* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download The Missing Formal Proof of Humanity`s Radical Evil in Kant`s
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
Philosophical Review The Missing Formal Proof of Humanity's Radical Evil in Kant's "Religion" Author(s): Seiriol Morgan Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 114, No. 1 (Jan., 2005), pp. 63-114 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/30043651 Accessed: 04/10/2010 04:40 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://links.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://links.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://links.jstor.org ThePhilosophicalReview,Vol. 114, No. 1 (January 2005) The Missing Formal Proof of Humanity's Radical Evil in Kant's Religion Seiriol Morgan 1. Of all his texts in the area of practical philosophy, Kant's Religionwithin the Boundaries of Mere Reason has long been widely held to be the least satisfactory.1Quite at odds in tone with the bulk of his earlier work on the subject, in which he champions human freedom and exalts the dignity of rational agency and the nobility of the good will's commitment to morality, the Religionpaints a dark portrait of humanity as a race perpetually in bondage to its own sinful nature; its central claim being that all human beings possess a radical propensity to evil that makes evil deeds inevitable for us. The book has been attracting controversy ever since its publication, which notoriously was greeted with dismay by many of those who had previously been most enthusiastic in their praise of him. Goethe and Schiller, for example, both viewed the claims of the Religionas arbitrary and unjustified concessions to pre-Enlightenment prejudice in a particularly pernicious form, that of a broadly Augustinian theology of original sin, concessions entirely unmotivated by any consideration internal to the basic Kantian project. Nor, by and large, have more recent commentators been any more sympathetic. Their criticisms tend to be built less on a visceral opposition to the encroachments of an allegedly misanthropic Christianity, resting instead on a careful analysis of the particular claims Kant makes throughout the text. Nevertheless, the conclusion that again is most frequently reached is that Kant's position in the Religionis untenable. Numerous authors have accused him of trying to have his cake and eat it too, by attempting to squeeze into one position two incompatible theses, neither of which he can bring himself to give up. The result is predictably a hopeless confusion, they argue.2 Even more telling, perhaps, than the almost uniform verdict of failure handed down by those who have explicitly addressed the claims of the Religionis the widespread silence on the matter from those providing exegeses or defenses of Kantian moral philosophy in general. Clearly, if true, his assertions regarding a universal human propensity to evil could not but have significant implications for moral psychology and ethics in general. And yet numerous standard twentieth-century 63 SEIRIOLMORGAN textbooks on Kant's moral philosophy say nothing at all on the matter. Nor, by and large, has this changed over the last fifteen years or so, during which there has been a very significant upsurge of interest in Kantian ethics, with the rise to prominence of a number of Kant scholars responding on Kant's behalf to the anti-Kantian critique associated with the recent renaissance of virtue ethics. Although collectively these philosophers have offered a formidable arrayof sophisticated interpretations and defenses of various aspects of Kant's program in moral philosophy, the arguments of the Religionare rarely among them. Rather, these arguments are simply ignored in their work, or the pessimism of the text implicitly contradicted. It seems safe to conclude then that a large majority of Kantian moral philosophers of the last century and this agree with the explicit critics' assessment of Kant'sviews on radical evil, and treat the claims he makes there accordingly, as at best an eccentric and inessential addition to the fundamental Kantian project, and at worst an embarrassment, to be largely ignored either way.3 Perhaps the most obviously problematic aspect of the text is the yawning gap at the heart of the argument, at the point where solid argument is most needed. For, lacking as he obviously does empirical acquaintance with the behavior of each and every human being past, present, and future, Kant will need to present an a priori argument in order to earn the right to assert that all human beings have such a propensity. Indeed, since he thinks that this characteristic is necessary (R 6:32), even if he were per impossibile to have such an acquaintance, this would still not underwrite the modality of the claim. There are certainly various indications in the text that Kant is perfectly aware that some kind of formal argument will be needed to establish his position. For instance, at the beginning of part 1, he states that in order to call a human being evil, we must be able to infer a priori from her actions an evil maxim, and consequently an evil common grounding of all her particular evil maxims (R 6:20). And on pages 32 to 33 of the Prussian Academy Edition of the Religion,he clearly implies that such a proof is available. But famously he does so in the course of relieving himself of the burden of providing it, "in view of the multitude of woeful examples that the experience of human deedsparades before us." Two pages later, he tells us that the existence of the propensity to evil in human nature "can be established through experiential demonstrations of the actual resistance in time of the human power of choice against the law" (ibid., 35). But as many have indignantly pointed out, it cannot. All that the woeful parade of human deeds can show us is that there are evil 64 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILLVKANT'SRELIGION people, or at most, that evil is common and widespread. It would be an entirely reckless generalization to conclude from the undeniably extensive litany of the crimes that human beings have carried out that every single human being has a propensity to evil, and indeed actually is evil, and that the root of this evil lies in human nature. Furthermore, it is clearly a central tenet of the Critiqueof Pure Reasonthat transcendental propositions such as this cannot be confirmed by appeal to examples from experience (KrVA 554/B 582). So his claims are crying out for a transcendental deduction that he does not provide. Obviously the suspicion has to be that he does not do so because he has no such argument to hand. None of this bodes well, and I have considerable sympathy with the complaints of Kant's critics. The text of the Religionis convoluted and difficult, with inadequate exposition of central concepts and confusing articulation of important claims. And in fact matters are worse than this, because it does indeed turn out that the view outlined there is selfcontradictory. Unlike the critics, however, I will be attempting to provide a sympathetic reconstruction of Kant's argument. Whereas they almost alwaysthink that the very idea of incorporating a claim about an inherent human propensity to evil into the moral philosophy outlined in the earlier works is a grave error, I think the problem lies in Kant's execution. Despite the entirely natural suspicion his breezy assertion about sparing us the formal proof raises, I will be arguing that a synthetic a priori argument for a universal human propensity to evil is in fact available, at least within the bounds of the Kantian critical philosophy. Of course, I will not be able to defend every part of Kant's selfcontradictory position, but I will be arguing that granted this context a significant majority of Kant's claims can be defended. One important claim in particular cannot be vindicated, however, so it will turn out that the nature of the propensity cannot be understood in precisely the way Kant wants. 2. This much seems to be generally agreed about what Kant is claiming. According to Kant, every human being has a fundamental disposition (Gesinnung) towards either good or evil (R 6:22), which consists in the free adoption of a fundamental maxim, or "meta-maxim,"which regulates the adoption of the specific maxims that determine the agent's particular actions.4 These dispositions are mutually exclusive, so every- 65 SEIRIOLMORGAN one's willing is regulated in its entirety either by a commitment to good or a commitment to evil (R 6:25). This view is known as rigorism. Whether a human being's disposition is good or evil depends upon the relative priority he assigns to the two basic incentives that we all experience, morality as respect for the moral law as embodied in the Categorical Imperative, and self-love as the pursuit of happiness through maximal satisfaction of the inclinations (R 6:36). The good person subordinates the incentive of self-love to that of morality, permitting himself to act on inclination only when such actions do not conflict with the requirements of duty, though Kant thinks that when it does not so conflict the pursuit of happiness is good. The evil person subordinates duty to the gratification of his desires, acknowledging moral ends only insofar as they do not proscribe his pursuit of what he wants. So evil for Kant consists neither in the inclinations themselves (R 6:34), nor in any corruption of reason's ability to grasp what is morally required or a diabolical decision to take a maxim's morality as a disincentive (R 6:35), but in a free choice of the will (Willkiir)to prefer the self-centered realization of its own happiness to the moral actions it knows it is dutybound to perform. In Kant's view, all human beings have a general predisposition (Anlage) to good, which manifests itself in three particular ways (R 6:26-28). First,we have a predisposition to animality, a kind of mechanical self-love through which we are naturally inclined to take care of our interests as natural social beings- through self-preservation by the consumption of food and avoidance of harm, the preservation of the species through sexual congress, and the maintenance of our natural communities through an impulse to sociability. Second, we have a predisposition to humanity, an innate tendency to use our powers of reason to advance our interests. This tendency is displayed in our use of our intelligence in the pursuit of happiness, through the satisfaction of current desires and in our ingenuity in creating objects or devising activities that we think will bring us pleasure. Third, all human beings have a predisposition to personality. This is simply our susceptibility to the moral law as incentive, which gives us the ability to determine ourselves to action by the thought that something is morally required alone. According to Kant, all these predispositions belong essentially to human nature, so no human being could lack or lose them. And yet we are all also subject to a propensity (Hang) to evil. Unfortunately, it cannot be said that Kant is particularly clear on what exactly such a propensity might be, defining propensity cryptically as "the sub66 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION jective ground of the possibility of an inclination, insofar as this possibility is contingent for humanity in general" (R 6:29) before notoriously going on to illustrate the idea with the example of the alleged propensity of all "savage"people for intoxicants. This is quite unhelpful, since such a propensity would be the disposition to develop an ongoing desire for a substance upon experiencing its intoxicating effect for the first time. Evil however cannot lie in the inclinations, for then it would be a function of the causal laws of the world and not free choice, and consequently would not be imputable (R 6:21). Admittedly, Kant distinguishes between physical and moral propensities, with moral propensities attached to the faculty of choice (Willkiir) and hence outside the sphere of causality (R 6:31). But this just increases the mystery about how the example is supposed to be informative. What does seem clear is that Kant is claiming the following. The propensity to evil differs from a predisposition because even though it is innate, it is appropriately thought of as having been brought by the human being on herself (R 6:29). It is the ground of the possibility of our adopting specific evil maxims (ibid.). It is universal and "woven into human nature" (R 6:30), but nevertheless is rooted in the will's free choice, so despite being subjectively necessary for everyone, it must be thought of as an accidental property of the human being (R 6:32). The propensity is evil in itself (R 6:37), and it is inextirpable (R 6:31), but since it is rooted in our freedom, it must be possible for freedom to overcome it (R 6:37). In human action, the propensity manifests itself in three different degrees: frailty, impurity, and depravity (R 6:29-30). Kant takes the apostle Paul to be describing the phenomenon of frailty when he reported that "I do not do what I want, but I do the very thing I hate" (Rom 7:15). An individual manifesting frailty is someone who has adopted a good maxim, but finds himself acting counter to it because the incentive provided by the moral law that his will endorses is somehow weaker than that provided by cajoling inclination. In the case of impurity, once again the agent's fundamental orientation is good, in that his will endorses a maxim that aims at compliance with the moral law. But for such a person, the moral incentive is insufficient to determine the will by itself, and so in order to actually perform an action required by the Categorical Imperative, the agent needs some additional motivation from the inclinations, and so his performance of the right action relies on heteronomous considerations. Such an action would be an impure action; an agent's heart is impure when he fre67 SEIRIOL MORGAN quently or invariablyrequires this self-centered stiffening of his supposedly moral resolve. Finally, in depravity or corruption, the individual's descent into evil is complete. Here the maxim is not good at all, since the corrupt person has made a perverse choice to reverse the appropriate priority of the incentives, by subordinating the moral law to her own self-love, and simply acts accordingly. Kant characterizes the first two grades of the propensity to evil as unintentional guilt, but the final stage is clearly deliberate (if self-deceptive) guilt (R 6:38), and consequently those who perversely subordinate the moral maxim to that of self-love are to be designated evil people (R 6:30). As part 1 of the Religion continues, Kant's account becomes even more pessimistic, with its assertion at the beginning of section 3 that in fact all human beings are evil and are so by nature (R 6:32). That is, we are conscious of the moral law but nevertheless incorporate into our maxims deviations from it, and that we do so universally as a species, so that even the best of us can be presupposed to have on occasion subordinated morality to self-love in the manner of the depraved. So not only do we all have a propensity to evil, we all actuallyareevil on Kant's view. Indeed, on closer examination, there seems little to distinguish the propensity to evil from the state of being evil itself, since (at R 6:43) Kant explicitly states that the propensity to evil involves the adoption of an evil supreme maxim. Furthermore, this is a presupposition both of his argument against the suggestion that it is self-contradictory for such a propensity to be imputable (R 6:31), and his argument for the inextirpability of the propensity (R 6:37), as well as his claim that the common ground of particular evil maxims is itself a maxim (R 6:20). Yet this isjust what it is to possess an evil disposition, and so to be an evil person. Nevertheless, there is still moral hope for humanity, since, despite the inextirpable nature of the propensity, a germ of goodness remains in even the most depraved individual (R 6:45). Every human being is aware of the call of conscience (ibid.), and due to the predisposition to personality built into human nature, we all can at any time freely will to do what we ought to do, whatever the depth of our prior corruption. Since to do so requires adoption of a good maxim, one in which we have subordinated the incentive of self-love to that of morality,we must be able to embrace as a fundamental maxim the priority of morality. Consequently it is within our power to come to possess a good disposition. Hence we are all able by our own effort to restore ourselves to the rightful condition of humanity, though the effects of our former perversitywill still be present in our habits and sensibility, so that the moral 68 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION life from then on will at best be one of constant progress in the struggle to overcome and reform these acquired tendencies to evil (R 6:47-48). So much for the view Kant holds. It is easy to see that on the face of it there is much that is puzzling and problematic about it. For instance, one might well ask what the difference between a predisposition and a propensity is supposed to be, and how it could be possible for us to possess both a predisposition to good and a propensity to evil at the same time. But most centrally, it is difficult to see how something that is imputable to our power of free choice could be universal and necessary, even if merely "subjectively necessary" and hence not an essential property of the free being. For one would presume that we are to be held responsible only for things that we freely choose, and if we freely choose something, we must have been free not to choose it. So Kant seems to be claiming that we necessarily freely choose one way rather than another, whereas freedom and necessity surely exclude one another. Richard Bernstein expresses the worry well: Kant is at war with himself. For, on the one hand, he never wants to compromise the basic claim of his moral philosophy: that human beings as finite rational agents are free, which means that they are solelyand completelyresponsible for their moral choices and the maxims they adopt. If we become morally good or evil, this is our own doing and a consequence of our own free will (Willkiir). On the other hand, Kant also wants to affirm that all human beings have an innate propensity to moral evil. In order to have his cake and eat it too, he is then driven to claim that even though this propensity is woven into the fabric of human nature, it is a propensity that springs from our freedom, and one for which we are responsible.5 Nevertheless, as we will see, matters are actually more complicated than the critics make out. I will have to postpone discussion of this, since I need to do quite a bit of preliminary work to explain why. But it is certainly true that there is a muddle in his exposition, because the position he ends up producing is internally inconsistent. For (at R 6:31-32) he asserts that the propensity is universal and inextirpable, and he implies this at various other points in his discussion (for example, R 6:37). As we saw, Kant explicitly equates the propensity to evil with possession of an evil disposition. But he also claims that we can develop a disposition to good, claiming that arousing the mind's contemplation of "the sublimity of our moral vocation" is a means of awakening moral dispositions, thereby restoring the original ethical order among the incentives (R 6:50). He then goes on to assert that although the possibility of such a restoration is incomprehensible, granted the 69 MORGAN SEIRIOL depth of our corruption, such a restoration is indeed possible (ibid.). Yet if the propensity to evil is inextirpable, and the possession of such amounts to possession of an evil disposition, in such a circumstance a human being would possess both a good and an evil disposition. But this would be syncretist latitudinarianism, in flat contrast to the rigorism Kant insists upon. So whatever we end up concluding about Kant's overall position in the Religion,we will not be able to accept everything that he says there, since at least one of these claims will have to go. But once again, let me postpone discussion of which claim it should be. It seems to me that the best way to come to understand why Kant thinks there is a universal human propensity to evil is not to try to grapple head-on with this impenetrable text. Rather, we will achieve much better results if we begin with the earlier work, and ask whether we can construct anything that looks like an argument for a propensity to evil out of the materials available there. I am going to argue that we can, because the seeds of the formal proof are indeed already present in the writings of the 1780s, in particular, the Groundwork of theMetaphysicsof Morals. 3. is the highly ambitious one of providKant's project in the Groundwork what he takes to be the central commonvindication of a ing complete sense views about morality, both in terms of its content and its authority. To do so, he needs to show that moral obligation is an overriding rational requirement upon all human beings, or indeed any other beings who are like us in the relevant ways. His strategy is to work backwards, as it were, beginning with our ordinary everyday understanding of moral worth, and aiming to vindicate it step by step, by showing how this is implicitly grounded in a principle that rational beings such as ourselves are committed to acting upon. To this end, the is to outline and clarify the concept aim of section 1 of the Groundwork of duty as it is understood in everyday moral consciousness, and to bring to light the principle of action implicit within it. Kant proceeds by presenting us with a series of examples, some of morally worthy behavior and others where the action in question lacks moral worth, reflection upon which is supposed to assist us in systematizing our moral intuitions and grasping the reasons that implicitly underlie our judgments. He clearly thinks that there will be no serious disagreement about the results of this reflection, at least among those who have not 70 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION been corrupted by bad philosophy or self-centered rationalization (G 4:405, 409-10), which are that moral action must be based upon the motive of duty rather than inclination (G 4:397), the worth or otherwise of an action lies not in aiming at or achieving some purpose but in the principle of the will underlying it (G 4:394, 399-400), and that acting from duty requires acting out of respect for the moral law for its own sake (G 4:400-401). Kant then argues that the principle upon which the moral person acts is "never to act in such a way that I could not also will that my maxim should become a universal law" (G 4:402). This then essentially turns out to be the first formulation of the Cat2. Kant's strategy in egorical Imperative as it is derived in Groundwork this section is to overcome the sophistry of "popular moral philosophy," which pretends to find morality's ground in sundry loosely connected empirical considerations (G 4:410), and replace it with the firm foundations of an a priori metaphysics of morals. Insisting that a law must be universally valid for all rational beings in order for it to count as a moral law (G 4:412), Kant proceeds by searching for a principle of action which could have this universal validity. Since the inclinations of rational creatures vary (and even if they did not, this would be a merely contingent conformity), he concludes that no empirical consideration could possibly ground the universal necessity of moral requirements, since nothing could be a moral requirement if one could be exempted from it due to having or lacking a particular desire or nature. We are therefore obliged, Kant argues, to seek the principle of morality in the one thing we necessarily have in common as rational agents, which is pure practical reason itself. Such a principle could have no material component, and so can be valid solely in virtue of its form. The only principle suitable to command solely in virtue of its form is the first formulation of the Categorical Imperative, "Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law" (G 4:421). So the philosophical search for a principle which could be valid for rational beings as such converges on the same principle as that which is presupposed by our everyday idea of morality, so vindicating it. In what remains of Groundwork 2, Kant further elucidates the nature of the Categorical Imperative by outlining the two other formulations to which the Formula of Universal Law is equivalent, and shows that for an agent to act according to it requires autonomy as opposed to heteronomy of the will (G 4:440), and hence freedom. 71 SEIRIOLMORGAN So by the end of Groundwork2, Kant has demonstrated to his own satisfaction what morality must be and what it presupposes. But in terms of his overall project, he has merely demonstrated what morality would have to be and what conditions it requires, if there is any such thing as morality. He has not demonstrated that the concept is not a "mere phantom of the brain" (G 4:445). To achieve this, he needs to move from a metaphysics of morals to a critique of practical reason. What he still needs to do is show both that agents such as ourselves possess the freedom required for us to be moral agents, and that as free agents we do not merely possess the capacity to act in accordance with the Categorical Imperative, but are rationally committed to doing so, or as Kant puts it "a free will and a will under moral laws are one and the same" (G 4:447).6 Consequently Groundwork3 contains two subarguments. Much of this third section is taken up with the first question, containing an exposition of transcendental idealism aimed at demonstrating the possibility of our freedom, and an argument that freedom is required of us as a practical postulate. But it also contains an argument for the latter claim, and it is this argument that concerns me here. Once again it runs right through Groundwork3, and is unfortunately tangled up with the strands of the argument for the former. It is possible to tease them apart however, and a very compressed statement of it in full is presented at the beginning of the section. This is the passage: Since the concept of causality brings with it that of laws in accordance with which, by something that we call a cause, something else, namely an effect, must be posited, so freedom, although it is not a property of the will in accordance with natural laws, is not for that reason lawless but must instead be a causality in accordance with immutable laws but of a special kind; for otherwise a free will would be an absurdity.Natural necessity was a heteronomy of efficient causes, since every effect was possible only in accordance with the law that something else determines the efficient cause to causality; what, then, can freedom of the will be other than autonomy, that is, the will's property of being a law unto itself? But the proposition, the will is in all its actions a law unto itself, indicates only the principle, to act on no other maxim than that which can have as its object itself as a universal law. This however is precisely the formula of the categorical imperative and is the principle of morality; hence a free will and a will under moral laws are one and the same. (G 4:446-47) The passage makes his overall argumentative strategy clear. He is going to argue that a being with a free will must have its willing regulated by some law or principle. But obviously the principle by which its 72 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION willing is regulated must be one that it chooses for itself rather than one that is externally imposed, for otherwise it would not be free. The only principle that would be suitable then to regulate the willing of a free will is one that it would choose for itself. But any principle appropriate for it to choose itself must then be one which expresses its autonomy, its property of being a law unto itself. The only principle that does this is the Categorical Imperative. Therefore, the only principle that is suitable for the will to choose is the subordination of self-love to morality. Hence every free will is in some sense committed to choosing morality as its principle, and "a free will and a will under moral laws are one and the same." But what isn't at all clear at this point is why we should buy the two central steps in the argument, that the free will must be regulated in its willing by a law, and that the only law suitable for doing so is the Categorical Imperative. Indeed both these claims seem on the face of it counterintuitive. So why should we accept them? Let's take them in turn. Kant's official reason why the free will must be regulated by a law is that as it is a causality it would otherwise be a causality operating independently of laws, which is a contradiction. But actually Kant never substantiates this assertion, since he is relying on the argument he presents in the Second Analogy of the Critiqueof Pure Reason (A188/B232A211/B256). Unfortunately, all that the argument there purports to establish is that a materialcausality must operate according to a law, and he is not entitled simply to extend this conclusion without argument to free causalities. Indeed, we have every reason for thinking that any attempt to argue for such an extension will fail, since an argument which purports to tell us how objects must behave in the manifold of our experience will tell us nothing about things in themselves (G 4:459). So, to my knowledge, nowhere in Kant's work is a clear case made for this claim. But contemporary Kantians have stepped in to provide an argument on his behalf, which rests upon a claim about the necessary conditions of agency.7 The argument proceeds as follows. What one might be tempted to think is that freedom and this kind of regulation are incompatible, because the free will would be constrained by any kind of law, even if it gives that law to itself, because to the extent that it is regulated, it is not free. But if the will has no principle governing its willing, then it can't be thought of as acting for reasons, since reasons require consistency. To be responsive to reasons is to take various considerations to provide one with a reason whenever they occur, ceteris paribus. If there 73 SEIRIOLMORGAN were no principle regulating one's willing, this kind of consistency could not be expected. On some occasions, the will would take a set of considerations to count as a reason for action, on others that very same set to provide no such reason, or a reason against the action. This makes it very difficult to view any of the will's volitions as genuinely responsive to reasons at all, as opposed to mere whims. But if the will does not act for reasons, then it is hard to see how it can actively be making any real choices,rather than just "plumping" for one option or another through a random "volitional spasm." So the free will without a principle would not look like the will of an agent,but rather a site of uncaused happenings, and such "blind chance" would not be freedom (KpV 5:95). This argument seems to me to be a genuinely Kantian one, in that it appeals to considerations we would expect him to endorse. So let us grant for the sake of argument that the will must choose a principle to regulate its willing. Why is the Categorical Imperative the only principle it is suitable for it to choose? One would think that any number of governing principles would provide the consistency necessary for agency, most obviously the principle of self-love, which would be the subordination of considerations of morality to those of inclination. The problem, as Kant admits, is that it is difficult to see how the moral law can be practical, and, furthermore, on what ground the moral law is binding (G 4:449). What is it that motivates us to moral action, and why are we rationally obliged to act upon it? We can easily imagine, as Kant does (G 4:449-50), someone asking for the reason why he should make his maxim of action one which he could will as a universal law, the "interest"he should take in morality. Obviously, the interest we provide him with cannot be an appeal to any of his inclinations, for then ipso facto the action would not be moral. But if the incentive is not an inclination, what could it be? Kant then raises the suspicion that our belief that we have a reason to act morally involves covert circular reasoning. We take ourselves to be justified in acting morally because moral action is what makes us personally worthy. But the idea that moral action confers worth on an individual presupposes the validity of morality, which is precisely what the skeptic is putting in question. This time Kant does provide an argument, but it is cryptic and difficult. His solution is essentially to introduce the idea of the two standpoints, which he claims is easily grasped by common understanding, as it considers the difference between its passivity in reception of sensation and its activity in its production of ideas. This leads us to the dis74 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION tinction between the sensible and the intelligible worlds. The laws of nature in the form of causality apply to the sensible world, but the intelligible world is governed by the laws of reason. Since the human being is conscious of both his receptivity in his experience of sensation, and his spontaneity in his free operation of reason, we must conceive of ourselves as rooted in both the sensible and the intelligible worlds (G 4:451). As rational beings then, qua intelligence as Kant puts it, we must conceive of ourselves as part of the intelligible world and so as pure spontaneity, since anything with respect to which we are not spontaneous but receptive comes not from the free power of reason but the passive effect of sensibility. As such, our causality lies in reason's spontaneous action alone (G 4:452). But it is precisely this separation which indicates why freedom commits us to morality. Freedom requires autonomy, because if reason were not autonomous, then it would be determined not by itself but by some outside cause, and so would not be spontaneous. "Whatelse then can freedom of the will be but autonomy-that is, the property which the will has of being a law to itself' (G 4:446). So spontaneity's principle must be a principle of autonomy. But the only principle of autonomy is the formal one of the Categorical Imperative, since material maxims are rooted in the empirical world's causal contingencies. Hence reason commits us via spontaneity to morality, and to the extent that we conceive of ourselves as rational inhabitants of the intelligible world, we are required to embrace it. Of course, we can also conceive of ourselves as sensible beings subject to the causal laws of the world of appearances. But Kant argues that we must regard ourselves as belonging more fundamentally to the intelligible world. This is because the intelligible world contains the ground of the sensible world, he tells us, emphasizing the claim to stress its importance (G 4:453). He is referring here to his conclusion in the Critiqueof Pure Reasonthat causality is one of the pure concepts of the understanding, one of the categories by means of which (we know a priori) the mind must present the manifold of experience in order for a world to appear to a subject at all, rather than a feature of the world as it is in itself (KrV Bxxvi-xxviii, B233-34). His thought seems to be that our experience of the world of causality, and the sensible inclinations that it throws up in us, depends upon the spontaneous activity of the mind as prior to it. Unfortunately, it is not made too clear what the force of that observation is supposed to be. But one thing that is clear is that Kant insists that the intelligible, purely spontaneous aspect of the self is the "proper"self, and that the inclinations 75 SEIRIOLMORGAN cannot be imputed to this real, core element of our identities (G 4:457-58). Our free wills are our egos as they are in themselves (G 4:451), and their spontaneous activity expresses only the self's activity, whereas the inclinations are, from the point of view of that ego, a kind of alien effect of an external causality, tempting us to betray what we truly are by willfully rejecting our essence (G 4:454-55). Kant seems to think that we know this intimately, through our experience of reasoning on the one hand and both sensing and desiring on the other, and, in any case, that it is philosophically confirmed by the transcendental idealism of the first Critique.Consequently he takes himself to have shown that we must view our freedom, and hence its preservation through the choice of morality as the principle of autonomy, as trumping any consideration that sensibility might, on the face of it, seem to present to us as a reason for choice. If this extended argument goes through, Kant will have demonstrated the universal rational authority of morality. One could be forgiven for thinking that this does not make things a great deal more perspicuous. But consider the following thought experiment, which I think very effectively brings out the way we are meant to take these complicated considerations.8 Imagine the free will deciding before it enters the world how it's going to make its choices when it gets there. According to Kant, this means arriving at a principle upon which it will make its choices. This is because the will is a causality, and all causality acts in accordance with laws (KrV A539/B567). But since it is a will, it is a free and not a natural causality, and so cannot be determined to act according to any principle imposed on it by a force external to itself. Hence it must choose its principle for itself (G 4:446). In effect, the task the will is faced with then is choosing what is going to count as a reason for action for it when it gets into the world. Various reason-generating principles might spring to mind, but for the sake of argument let's confine ourselves within Kant's strictures and limit the choice to that of self-love or morality. So the will has to choose what will count as supreme reason for it when it arrives in the world, the satisfaction of its own inclinations or the conformity of its choices with the Categorical Imperative. In deciding which of the principles to give overriding status, it is deciding which to subordinate to the other. So the choice it has to make is one between a good and an evil disposition. But how is it to make the choice? Since it is deciding what is going to count as a reason for it in the future, what reason could it have to guide it now? Certainly no appeal can be made either to morality or self-inter76 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION est, conceived as the satisfaction of inclination, since any such appeal would be a circularjustification. So one might think that the will would be in a condition prior to all reasons, and that any choice it makes would simply be a random exercise of its spontaneity, an utterly unmotivated "leap of volition." This would obviously be unacceptable for Kant, partly because he shares the view of many in the philosophical tradition preceding him that a will possessing pure liberty of indifference would be unable to make anything that could be meaningfully thought of as a choice at all (KpV 5:95), but much more importantly because it would entirely undermine his project of grounding morality in bare practical reason. If the rational authority of morality were found to be contingent upon an unjustified leap of volition, it would have no rational authority at all. However, it is at this point that Kant really demonstrates his ingenuity, in making the most extensive possible use of the very limited resources available to him. The problem we face is that in imagining the will making a choice between morality and self-love, prior to its immersion in the world, we have pared away virtually every element of the self that might provide it with reasons-its desires, its emotions, its values, its membership in a society, its history, its individual identity. All that remains is the sheer power of choice, the will's spontaneity. And so it is precisely within spontaneity that Kant locates its reasons. Kant'sreasoning is that since all the will is is freedom, the only thing that can possibly provide the will with a reason is spontaneity itself. As freedom is its inner nature, the will has reason to choose the principle which best preserves and expresses it. Of course, according to Kant, this principle is the Categorical Imperative. The reason spontaneity provides the will with reason to choose morality as its principle lies in the nature of the alternative (G 4:462). Someone whose fundamental principle of action is self-love acts to secure her own happiness, that is, the greatest possible satisfaction of her inclinations. But as Kant conceives of the inclinations, they are a phenomenon of the sensible world, fundamentally external forces whose presence lies beyond the agent's control. Human inclination is a function of causalityjust as much as animal inclination, or indeed the behavior of ordinary physical objects. So what we desire is not chosen by us. It is a function of our animal bodies, our contingent history and socialization, and various other causal factors. Therefore, the agent who chooses self-love as her principle has no further input into the unfolding of her life. As the world generates desires in her, she will act 77 SEIRIOL MORGAN to satisfy them, and so her behavior is effectively determined by the causal mechanisms of the phenomenal world. She will consequently behave as though she were not the possessor of a spontaneous will at all. A choice of self-love is therefore the abrogation of freedom, something that it is quite unintelligible for the will to will. But this is not the case for morality. Even though morality constrains the will, it is not an infringement of the will's spontaneity, because this is a constraint that is a function of the will itself, and not a determination by some heteronomous cause external to it. The good person is not just determined by the world's causalityby wayof her desires. She makes use of the spontaneous capacity of reason, which allows her to step back from the promptings of desire and intervene to redirect the forces of causality when human dignity requires it. Her will uses its freedom to make a difference in the world, and so expresses its inner nature, whereas the heteronomous will does not. Hence if this argument works, any free being has reason to take the prescriptions of the Moral Law as authoritative. 3, that Assuming the success of the second subargument of Groundwork rational beings actually have free wills, the extended argument as a whole takes us to morality's universal authority for rational beings, which is what Kant is most fundamentally concerned to show.9 The thought experiment is a conceit, of course. There is no such thing as the will making decisions prior to its entrance into the world. But it is not misleading, since its elements mirror those of Kant's account appropriately. Kant sees the seat of our freedom as lying in the noumenal realm, and consequently outside the temporal order (KrV A34-36/B51-53). The agent freely chooses his fundamental disposition, but this is not something he does at any particular moment in time. Rather, the particular choices that the will makes at any particular time presume the disposition that is its fundamental object of choice. The inclinations are experienced in time, a function of causality. So although there is no time that the human agent actually lacks inclinations, their subjective normative force is alwayswhat the will chooses to allow them, and so whether an inclination presents itself to us as a reason requires a prior choice of maxim, and ultimately (conceptually but not temporally) of some meta-maxim. Hence they cannot sway the choice of disposition, and it wasjust this that the imagined pre-embodiment of the will of the thought experiment was intended to represent. 78 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION 4. Various objections to this line of argument might immediately spring to mind.10 But let's put these to one side, since Kant thinks it works, and our purpose is to try to understand Kant on evil and to produce the transcendental argument he alludes to but omits to provide. The important lesson to take from this argument for our purposes is that Kant thinks that the will can have reasons simply qua free will, and that any such reason is a function of its own nature. Of course, at root the free will only has one reason. Since only the preservation and affirmation of its spontaneity could provide it with a reason, the only reason it has is to choose morality as its unifying principle, since only morality preserves freedom. But weknowthat at leastsomewills do not choosemorality.Any such choice is clearly irrational, since the only thing that could provide the will with a reason is its spontaneity, and that is only respected by choosing morality. Hence choosing morality is what it has overriding reason to do, and a candidate reason that opposes an overriding reason is no reason at all. But nevertheless such choices are made, and the only way to account for this is to see the will as presented with an incentive to make a different choice, an incentive which it takes to provide it with a reason, but which is in fact merely a pseudo-reason. What might this incentive be? One might be immediately inclined to appeal to the pull of the individual's inclinations, the thought being that the evil will prefers the pleasure provided by their gratification to the autonomy it can achieve by disciplining them in accordance with the Categorical Imperative. This answer is strongly implied by some of the things Kant says in the Groundwork(for example, G 4:405). But it cannot be Kant's answer, because, as he explicitly states in the Religion (R 6:23-24), the inclinations only present themselves as reasons to the will insofar as the will has chosen to incorporate their satisfaction into its maxim. What we are looking for is an elucidation of what motivates the choice to make the inclinations legislative over morality in the first place, so any appeal to the pull of sensuality misses the point. Once again, the incentive that the will acts upon when it makes that choice can only be a function of its nature as pure spontaneity. As pure spontaneity is its nature, only freedom itself could be an incentive for it,just as only freedom can provide it with its genuine reason. So the pseudo-reason must lie in the will's erroneous representation of freedom to itself, in such a way that 79 SEIRIOL MORGAN it is tempted in pursuit of this freedom to make a choice that in fact selfdestructively renounces it. A clue as to how it does this is present in the contrast Kant draws between freedom conceived positively and freedom conceived merely negatively (G 4:446). Conceived negatively, freedom is simply the power of activity in the absence of alien determination; conceived positively, it is autonomy in the form of the Categorical Imperative. Kant then remarks that the negative idea of freedom, although not mistaken as such, is "unfruitful for insight into its essence" (ibid.). Someone understanding freedom merely negatively would possess only a partial conception of it, and so would have failed to understand it properly, because although she would have correctly grasped a necessary condition of being free, she would not have grasped what is additionally required for an agent to be fully or truly free. Clearly no one can be free if their actions are determined or restricted by alien causes, indeed; but neither are they genuinely free if they allowtheir actions to result from these causes, by embracing a heteronomous principle. So we see here how it might be possible to mistake what freedom really is, if one were to take what is necessary for it to be the whole of it. is the impersonal theoKant's perspective on this in the Groundwork retical perspective of the philosopher, and his characterization of the negative conception of freedom there is a metaphysical one. But the important question for our purposes is how freedom might be understood and misunderstood from the first-personal practical perspective. Clearly, if it is correctly understood from the first-personal perspective, it will be understood just as it is from the impersonal viewpoint, as autonomy, and the agent will affirm her freedom as autonomy in her choice of principle. But what of the agent conceiving of freedom merely negatively? How would she try to affirm her spontaneity? She cannot do so by affirming her spontaneity as freedom of action in the absence of alien causation, for that is a metaphysical condition her will is in whatever she chooses, and so would provide no positive criterion for making any particular choice rather than another. Rather, the incentive masquerading as a reason opposed to that provided by morality must be negative freedom presenting itself not in the form of lack of alien determination, but lack of restraint.A will embracing its self-affirmation in this way seeks like every will to express its spontaneity in the principle it chooses to regulate its willing. But the way it tries to do this is by affirming the unlimited indulgence of anything and everything it might will. Its principle is simply to do what it wills to do, and to treat 80 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION as an obstacle to be overcome any other will which stands in the way of its achieving it. Its choice is therefore untrammeled license. It is not difficult to see how the will could make such a choice under the aspect of securing its freedom, for doing so involves a subtle perversion of the truth that it can easily conceal from itself. This is because the absence of interference in one's choices by the agency of another is a genuine criterion of freedom. When an agent legitimately chooses to 4,if she is prevented from doing so by some other agent, then to that extent her freedom has been violated, and so the will of the other is an obstacle to her freedom. Indeed Kant actually defines freedom (Freiheit) as "independence from being constrained by another's choice (Willkiir)"in the Rechtslehre (MS 6:237). This can't be the whole of since there is a story course, very important sense in which heteronomous agents lack freedom, since they do not possess autonomy, and lack of autonomy can coexist with complete freedom from constraints arising from the wills of others. And indeed Kant is thinking of a very particular sense of freedom here, which he calls "outer freedom," contrasted with inner freedom, which is the exercise by the virtuous individual of his "capacity for self-constraint... by pure practical reason" is of outer free(MS 6:396). All discussion of freedom in the Rechtslehre dom, since the subject matter of this division of the MetaphysicsofMorals is the nature of our 'juridical obligations," that is the conduct that can be legitimately enforced by agencies such as the government, the courts, and so on. What Kant is doing in this division of the book is asking about the nature of the rules that are appropriate to govern a society that takes freedom to be the most important value to be respected in our social relations with one another, as of course any legitimate society should. His conclusion is that right actions are those that "can co-exist with everyone's freedom in accordance with a universal law" (MS 6:230). These are the actions that such a society is justified in legislating to ensure, and in totality they constitute the sphere of what then outlines what these Kant calls "legality."The bulk of the Rechtslehre specifically are. What is entirely irrelevant from the point of view of the doctrine of right is the moral worth of any particular action. Since the inner maxim underlying an action is always unknown to us, and it would be pointless to legislate that people behave in ways we could never in principle verify, the doctrine of right concerns only the performance of actions in accordance with the principle of right, not from the motive of duty.We can havejuridical obligations only to perform or not to perform observable actions, and so inner freedom through the 81 SEIRIOLMORGAN adoption of virtuous maxims is a matter of indifference as far as the question of right is concerned (MS 6:231). It is concerned only with the legality and not the morality of actions, though of course any action which does not fall within the bounds of rightness will be an immoral one. Consequently the discussion of freedom within the bounds of the Rechtslehre can understand the concept only negatively. Outer freedom may be an incomplete conception of freedom, but it remains a genuine condition for freedom for all that. Since interference by others reduces freedom, then, it seems clear that an agent's freedom is increased if such interference is removed. Kant agrees, claiming that hindering the hindering of freedom, as the state does when it lays down laws forbidding coercion, amounts to promoting it (ibid.). So the agent must become freer the more she is able to do what she chooses. The conclusion of this line of thought might seem to be that the agent is completely free if there are no such restraints at all. But this is true only insofar as the absence of restraint consists in the absence of the coerciveagency of others, since the increase in freedom with the will's increasing capacity to exercise its power of choice has its limits. If it were taken beyond the bounds of legality, then the drive for ever more freedom would undermine itself. This is because an illegal act cannot result from a universalizable maxim, and so the agent performing it must have acted upon a heteronomous principle. At least to that extent, the agent must therefore lack autonomy, and hence genuine freedom. So a condition of the agent's extending his "outer freedom" beyond the boundaries of legality would be the abandonment of his inner freedom, and since inner freedom as autonomy is freedom properly understood, it must trump any increase in outer freedom, and so the anticipated increase in freedom as such would be illusory. But this is of course what the evil will actually does. It pursues its whims whatever effect this may have on the legitimate choices of others, and we know that the incentive to do so is provided by its pure spontaneity. The evil will must therefore take freedom as such to be outer freedom, and complete outer freedom to be the absence of any and all restraints upon its willing. It does not demand just the removal of any unjustified interference in its own legitimate choices by others; it demands the removal of any restriction on its choices whatsoever, and takes itself to be free only if there are no restraints of any kind on what it might choose to will. Since any number of things it might will are restricted by the moral claims that the dignity of others as free beings confronts it with, a will single-mindedly determined to maxi82 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION mally extend its outer freedom must will to be free of the constraints of morality. So the evil will revolts not only against the overextension by others of the domain of their free choice, but against their freedom simpliciter, and hence against their very being, as the ends in themselves they most fundamentally are. This is why it is appropriately described as evil. Of course, from the perspective of the autonomous agent, the will that tries to affirm its spontaneity in this way is making a tragic blunder. Outer freedom only extends as far as the bounds of legality, and trying to push it any further is to become less rather than more free. But from the perspective of an agent who takes outer freedom to be freedom simpliciter, this latter fact would be quite invisible. Consequently he would see no reason when attempting to affirm his spontaneity as outer freedom to rein in his choices at the point at which they begin to conflict with those of others. The individual who fetishizes outer freedom and focuses his attention entirely on it in his attempt to be free will be led by a kind of confused but compelling dialectic to the embrace of license. It might be objected at this point that Kant himself denies this, since a fundamental claim of the Rechtslehre is that the principle of right can be derived analytically from the concept of outer freedom (MS 6:396). This might seem to suggest that reflection on the negative concept of freedom demonstrates that outer freedom extends only to the bounds of legality. But recall that the Rechtslehre is written from the impartial of someone to perspective aiming promote outer freedom as such, and how it can be done. The answer, which we arrive at a priori, is asking that it is promoted by allowing everyone as much freedom as possible compatible with an equal amount of freedom for all others. Therefore, it is a fact that Kantian legality is the way to promote outer freedom on the social plane. But analysis of the concept merely shows us what rightness is, and nothing about that fact itself compels anyone to take any practical interest in it, and govern his behavior according to the principle of right. Rather, the only thing that could motivate an individual to respect the outer freedom of the others with whom he interacts, besides fear of their personal power and that of punitive authority, is morality. From the amoral perspective of a particular agent considering his de facto relationship with other agents, rather than that of someone taking an abstract view of the de jure relations between agents in general, nothing about the idea of outer freedom itself calls for its restriction when it begins to encroach upon the choices of others. Kant is quite explicit about this: 83 SEIRIOLMORGAN Thus the universal law of right, so act externally that the free use of your choice can coexist with the freedom of everyone in accordance with a universal law, is indeed a law that lays an obligation on me, but it does not at all expect, far less demand, that I myselfshouldlimit my freedom to those conditions just for the sake of this obligation; instead, reason says only that freedom is limited to those conditions in conformity with the idea of it and that it may also be actively limited by others; and it says this postu- late is incapableof furtherproof.- When one's aim is not to teach virtue but only to set forth whatis right,one maynot and should not represent that lawof rightas itself the incentiveto action. (MS6:231) We have here then a clear statement by Kant that there is nothing in the idea itself which could present an agent with a reason to limit his outer freedom in accordance with the claims to freedom of others. On the contrary, the inner logic of the pursuit of outer freedom alone leads inexorably in the direction of license. Unlike the moral will, which values autonomy as such and its own freedom in doing so, the will taking freedom to be outer freedom cannot value spontaneity as such, since its own spontaneity and that of others are not in harmony, but frequently in conflict. Therefore, it can value only its own outer freedom. In pursuing its own outer freedom, itjust affirms its freedom from restraints upon the choices it might choose to make. Consequently it is difficult to see what could motivate it to curtail that affirmation at any point prior to complete affirmation of anything that it might choose. Any concession on its part that some set of choices that it might have some incentive to make are out of bounds for some reason beyond its own whim would have to look like a totally arbitrary renunciation of the principle that governs its existence, and so as unintelligible. Obviously, an acceptance that its freedom should be constrained by a requirement to respect that of others would be just such a concession. This is the dialectic, which is a term that in a context like this Kant alwaysuses negatively (for example, G 4:405), to mean a train of thought that takes us in the direction of a false but usually congenial conclusion, via a series of tempting missteps. Viewing outer freedom as the whole of freedom is a wholly erroneous conception of it. But someone single-mindedly wedded to this idea would quickly come, by seemingly rationally respectable steps, to the conclusion that freedom is the untrammeled license to do whatever one feels like doing. The mystery is beginning to unravel, then, as this line of reasoning provides as far as possible an answer to the baffling question of how the will could fail to respond to its one overriding reason. Motivated by the allure of a distorted picture of freedom, it is blinded to the reality of its 84 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION choice. But we are certainly not to conceive of the fundamental problem here as a kind of intellectual mistake, as if the evil will were the fruit of a confusion about a matter of fact. The evil person is not someone who has made a subjectively rational decision on the basis of false information, who at most we could convict of culpable ignorance. The evil person is someone who willfully does what in some sense she knows to be bad. But this is exactly how Kant conceives of her, because all free agents are presented with the incentive of morality, and they all know in their hearts that acting morally is what they should do. No one can escape the call of conscience (MS 6:400). We can refuse to heed it but not to hear it, and the most we can do to resist it is temporarily to dull our senses to it (MS 6:438). This is what the evil will does when it focuses its attention on the idea of outer freedom, and it does so not because it is ignorant of morality, but because it does not wish to be bound by it. So it is the will for the absence of restraint upon our willing that precedes our endorsement of the idea of it. We come to take outer freedom to be freedom because that is what we would like it to be. What the will really yearns for is the kind of freedom and power possessed by a very different kind of will, the infinite unlimited will of God. It wants unfettered power and choice. But as finite beings we can never have such a power, because our natures are not self-sufficient, and we find ourselves in the midst of a world not of our making that we do not control. At root then, the will's affirmation of license is a revolt against its own being, a futile attempt to be more than it is. There is a deep irony about this, of course, since in attempting to pursue its freedom at the expense of the freedom of others, the evil will ends up annihilating its own autonomy, in a self-imposed fall into causality.11 5. I think it is entirely appropriate to think of the propensity to evil asjust this incentive to embrace unrestrained license. The picture that emerges is of the human being as of her nature inclined to a kind of gratuitous willfulness, in which she simply fetishizes and elevates to a supreme value, trumping all other considerations, the unlimited indulgence of her whims. Put this way,it certainly sounds like such an incentive would draw us toward evil acts. Indeed, one might think it sounds too evil, for on the face of it the affirmation of license sounds very like the diabolical will that Kant explicitly rejects, rather than the mere subordination of moral concerns to ones of self-interest, which is what 85 SEIRIOL MORGAN Kant says evil consists in. But although it is not immediately obvious, in fact the incentive as I describe it gets the relationship between will and inclination exactly right. Kant wants to say both that evil is something actively perverted, the willful embrace of something that presents itself as transgressive of what we know in our hearts to be morally required, and that it consists simply in the pursuit of inclination on those occasions when inclination conflicts with morality. On the face of it, this looks once again like Kant trying to say two incompatible things at once. But the will's overabundant affirmation of its own freedom will mean, in practice, the subordination of morality to self-love. This is because the will cannot will anything unless it has some incentive to do so (R 6:35), and the will's licentiousness is not the source of specific incentives, only the general one to do what it wills to do. The bare power of choice can give the will incentive (and reason) to choose freedom over unfreedom, but it cannot provide it with incentive to choose to j rather than xy.So the only specific motives the will can have are the incentives presented to it from outside itself, from sensibility. It is for this reason that Kant remarks that if we were lacking in incentives of sensibility, moral considerations would inevitably function to determine the will (R 6:36). Therefore the licentious will ends up indulging all its whims by doing whatever the agent wants to do, just as Kant said, and license and self-love turn out to be identical. Furthermore, the argument I have provided is the formal one we have been looking for. Such an argument moves a priori from some accepted phenomenon to the reality of its conditions of possibility. The phenomenon in this case is the fact that human beings commit acts that are contrary to morality. In order to have performed an act that is morally reprehensible, an agent must be free, or else he would not be responsible for what he did. But in order to have made an imputable choice to flout morality's requirements, the agent must have had some incentive to do so, for the will can choose to do only what it has incentive to do, otherwise it would not be free but a locus of blind chance. The incentive for any particular evil act will be an inclination. But since a free will is not determined in any way, the fact that it is motivated by inclination means that it must have incorporated self-love as legislative into its maxim. Once again, it must have had incentive to do so, and this time the incentive can come only from the will's nature as pure spontaneity. The only way the will can have been motivated by its spontaneity to subject itself to causality in the form of the choice of self-love is through its representation to itself of freedom as the unlimited indul86 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION gence of all its whims. How else could freedom provide an incentive that in reality places the will into bondage when followed? The only empirical claim is the explanandum, that human beings perform immoral acts. That is hardly going to be controversial, at least on the assumption that we are free. Kant takes himself to have good reason for thinking this is the case, of course; in any case we are investigating whether Kant is entitled to his claim about the propensity to evil within the bounds of the practical philosophy as a whole, and if we are not transcendentally free then the whole project has failed. The argument that we are not determined by material causes is itself a formal one, and all the other steps are a priori. Consequently the argument also establishes the universality of the propensity. We know that at least some wills are attracted to evil, because some agents perform acts that clearly subordinate moral considerations to ones of sensibility. Since sensuous incentives cannot determine the will except insofar as the agent has incorporated them into his maxim, the evil will must have been presented with an incentive from its own nature to do so. But its own nature is pure spontaneity, a nature it shares with every other will. Hence if any will is motivated by its own nature as bare freedom to incorporate evil into its maxim, every will must present itself with incentive to do so (R 6:25-26). And since the incentive emerges from its innermost nature in this way, it does not seem unreasonable to consider it inextirpable, but possible to overcome in practice, again as Kant said. Compare it to the moral incentive that is the predisposition to personality, with which the will is presented simply as a consequence of its own nature. Kant is quite clear that this cannot be extirpated (R 6:35). It belongs with necessity to human nature, and so one could not be a human being if one lacked it (R 6:28). But of course it can be flouted, and usually is, since most human beings subordinate the moral incentive to incentives of self-love. So an inextirpable but combatable incentive to evil seems to be exactly what one would expect, as the appropriate mirror image of the moral incentive for the will. Of course, it must be frankly admitted that the argument I have presented is simply not present in the text of the Religion.But this can't be a surprise; if it had been, then Kant would not have been accused of lacking the necessary formal proof. And it does strongly chime with some suggestive remarks that he makes there and elsewhere. For instance, he respectfully criticizes the Stoics for mistaking and hence underestimating the enemy of morality, which on Kant's account they took to be the undisciplined inclinations of the unwise person. Kant 87 SEIRIOLMORGAN denies that evil can lie either in the inclinations themselves or in mere folly, insisting instead that it must lie in an active malice, which he describes as "an invisible enemy, one who hides behind reason" (R 6:57). Since the will is practical reason, this "hiding behind reason" appears to indicate that the enemy of morality is the will's misuse of its rational powers to conceal its freely chosen wickedness from itself. He then goes on in a footnote on the next page to state explicitly that evil lies in the perverted maxims of "freedom itself' (R 6:58). Granted that he hasjust described evil as the malice of the human heart, we can take him to have asserted that an impulse that is appropriately described as malice lurks within the human will. An incentive emerging from our spontaneity to embrace license, and with it the subordination of the wills of all others to one's own, strikes me as just the kind of incentive he might be referring to here. He also says a number of things in the Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of Viewthat strongly suggest the line of thought I have been outlining. For instance, when discussing the passions, which in their various ways are all deeply entrenched inclinations to subordinate the wills of others to our own (ApH 7:270), he says "the mere sensuous idea of outer freedom, by analogy with the concept of Law, raises the inclination to continue in it or extend it to the point of vehement passion" (ApH 7:269). The particular passion he is discussing here is the natural passion for freedom, which is precisely a generalized habitual desire to subordinate the claims of other people to the choices of one's own will. Consequently Kant seems to be saying here that those agents who develop such passions do so simply as a result of reflection on the idea of freedom as the ability to do whatever one wants to do. This is not quite an explicit endorsement of my claim about the nature of the incentive the evil will follows, since as an inclination a passion is a quality of sensibility rather than a disposition of the will, and he does not directly say it is the idea of an unlimited outer freedom which does the work. But this claim about the passions is one that someone who accepted the argument of section 4 would be likely to find very congenial. Later, in a discussion of the character of the species, he asserts that "man's self-will is always ready to break forth in hostility towards his neighbors, and alwayspresses him to gain unconditional freedom, not merely independence of others but mastery of other beings that are his equal by nature" (ApH 7:327). This statement is an even clearer indication that Kant holds the human will as such to be subject to an incentive to limitless self-assertion. 88 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION 6. In any case, understanding the propensity to evil as it is outlined above allows us to make good sense of a lot of what Kant does say in the Religion, including many of the elements that his critics have found most problematic. For one thing, the account nicely treads a fine line between doing too much and doing too little. Kant is adamant that evil cannot be explained, repeating the point like a mantra throughout part 1 (for example, R 6:21, 32, 39-40). To explain evil is to explain it away,since to explain it is to place it within the causal order. Hence to some extent, evil must remain a mystery. But this need not mean that everything about evil-doing must be utterly incomprehensible to us. I think we can draw a useful distinction between explainingevil, by giving some kind of rationalization of it, or a causal account of its origins, either of which would be self-defeating, and elucidating it, which is important and useful (R 6:31). To elucidate evil is to give an account of the psychology of the evil person in order to show what kinds of considerations attract her to wrongdoing, and what it is about human beings that make it the case that we can be attracted to it in this way.As long as no part of the elucidation implies that evil is determined by alien causes, we will not have explained away the responsibility that is essential to wrong-doing. The above account appropriately elucidates evil within the bounds of the Kantian framework. It describes the primal motivation of the evil person, the self-assertive determination that no limits be placed upon the choices the agent may make. It preserves freedom and responsibility by locating that insistence in a fundamental choice of a free will. It informatively locates the incentive for such selfassertion in the essence of freedom itself. But ultimately, it leaves the mystery of evil in place. No rationalization of evil is provided, because evil remains utterly without intelligible justification. Since all free agents have overriding reason to secure their autonomy by choosing the Categorical Imperative as their guiding principle, none have any reason to choose evil. Whatever reason freedom as self-assertion might present itself as providing, a putative reason that opposes an overriding reason is not a genuine reason at all. Hence self-assertion is self-defeating and its choice unintelligible. We know what it is that motivates us when we choose evil, but we don't grasp, except through a glass darkly, howit could be motivating. On the other hand, this account is not trivial, an accusation that has recently been leveled by Allen Wood against an alternative attempt to 89 SEIRIOLMORGAN outline a transcendental justification for the ascription of a universal propensity to evil.12 The argument is advanced by Henry Allison, who draws on an observation made by Sharon Anderson-Gold in a very influential paper.13 It proceeds as follows. As part of his account of humanity's predispositions to good, Kant asserts in the Religionthat all human beings have an inextirpable predisposition to personality (R 6:27), that is, we have the ability to move ourselves to appropriate action by the mere representation of its requirement by the moral law. This amounts to the same thing as the claim that there exists for everyone an incentive for the will to choose moral maxims, which receives its transcendental proof in Groundwork 3, as we saw. Since there is such an if there were no incentive, countervailing incentive then the will would adopt it automatically. But we know that the incentive is not automatically adopted, since we sometimes act contrary to morality. So there must be an incentive that functions as a counterweight to that of morality to explain how it is that many of us fail to act as we ought, for if the incentive to act according to the moral law were never actively opposed by some other incentive, then it would alwaysbe sufficient to motivate us to action. Therefore the will has within it an innate tendency to be drawn to flout the law, and it is this that is the propensity to evil. Allison then goes on to note that Kant equates the propensity to evil with the adoption of an evil Gesinnung. If moral propensities amount to the adoption of good or evil meta-maxims, then rigorism says that everyone must have either a propensity to good or a propensity to evil. The grounds for ascribing the propensity to evil universally to the human race can be seen when we imagine what it would be like for a human being to possess a propensity to good. According to Allison, an individual with a propensity to good would have a spontaneous tendency to subordinate the incentive of self-love to the moral incentive, and so would have no temptation to act wrongly. But there are no human beings in so fortunate a state (KpV 5:122). Hence no human being can possess a propensity to good, and so we all must possess one to evil. The triviality is supposed to lie in the alleged fact that Allison has demonstrated no more than that we are capable of doing wrong, or that when we don't do what we are morally required to do, somehow the will is attracted to perform the immoral action instead. At most this would rule out holiness on the part of the human will. Wood's criticism is that Kant clearly took himself to be advancing and defending a substantial thesis, not the uncontroversial claim that any one of us can be motivated to do wrong. To an extent, I think the triviality charge is 90 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION unfair, since the argument does succeed in showing that there must be something in the will's nature that provides it with incentives that actively run counter to the incentive provided by the predisposition to personality. This tells us something about the roots of wrongdoing, for instance, that it does not lie in a clouding of the intellect that allows an ordinarily unproblematic inclination to determine action in an inappropriate circumstance. Admittedly, it doesn't tell us very much, and is consequently rather unsatisfying. Nevertheless the problem seems to be one of incompleteness rather than triviality. But in any case, my argument supplies just what is needed to complement Allison's. It shows not only that we must be motivated in a way that actively runs counter to the moral incentive, it shows howwe are, as well as demonstrating why the motive must be universal to humanity if ascribed to any member of humanity. In addition, in providing an elucidation of the motive as the individual's willful self-assertion, my argument describes this motive in a way that gives some substance to the claim that the will is evil. Wood claims that Kant clearly wanted to do something more substantial than merely make the declaration that we are motivated to do wrong. My argument shows how the root of such wrongdoing is a deeply disturbing competitive standpoint taken by the agent towards the social world, and whatever the justice of the original charge, this is not an anodyne and uncontroversial claim.14 Finally,viewing the propensity to evil as freedom's inner incentive to self-assertion can allow us to make good sense of the claim that has been found most problematic by critics, Kant'sview that the propensity to evil is both innate and imputable. His problem is that he needs the propensity to be on the one hand universal, and on the other something we are responsible for in virtue of our freedom. But of course the idea of something being freely chosen seems to undermine the claim that it can be universal, because any particular individual could make the contrary choice. The propensity's universality suggests that it is part of human nature, and if so, it is difficult to see how it could be something we are responsible for. Kant does indeed insist that the propensity is rooted in or woven into our nature (R 6:30), but never clearly explains how something woven into our nature can simultaneously be a freely chosen deed (R 6:31). The confusion that inevitably results has led commentators to argue that Kant is trying to outline the nature of an incoherent entity, because he is attached to two incompatible theses and refuses to give up either one of them. But the problem can be resolved if we take the propensity to evil to lie in the self-assertive ten91 SEIRIOLMORGAN dency of the will. As we saw, the attraction to limitlessness is a function of its bare freedom, and consequently is a feature of the will as such and hence of every free will. So it is universal, and we can see how it can be described as innate. Nevertheless, the temptation is something that the will offers to itself. Through the idea of outer freedom, the will represents to itself the unlimited indulgence of all its whims, and it finds the idea attractive. This representation of an untrammeled self-indulgence in a positive light is precisely a kind of primal collusion with wickedness on its part. And the collusion is a consequence of its freedom, since if the agent were not free, there would be no such incentive. So the incentive bubbles up from freedom itself, and since it emerges from this source it cannot be caused, since freedom cannot be thought to deterministically cause anything without contradicting its essence as free. Hence the propensity is something it brings on itself. Nothing else in the world could be its source, so it can be imputed only to the will. Admittedly, many people will be inclined to view this as a sleight of hand. It's all very well to insist that the presence of the incentive is not the result of some causal factor external to the will; what matters for imputability is whether the agent had the freedom to do anything about it. Since Kant wants to insist that the propensity is universal, we must assume the agent did not have this freedom, and so we cannot be responsible for the propensity's existence, and hence neither it nor we can appropriately be thought of as inherently evil. Or so they will argue. But in my view we are justified in holding that Kant would reject this objection, since it rests upon a presupposition about the nature of freedom that he explicitly repudiates in TheMetaphysicsofMorals.15The argument he provides there draws on traditional philosophical discussions of freedom, which standardly distinguished two senses of freedom, "liberty of spontaneity" and "liberty of indifference." To possess liberty of spontaneity is to be oneself the cause of one's own actions; liberty of indifference is the power to do otherwise than one actually does, so that one can either n or not 0. The objectionjust mentioned assumes that the power to do otherwise is a necessary condition of any act or choice being free. But although Kant certainly holds that freedom very frequently manifests itself in the form of indifference, and that we do possess it with regard to the vast majority of our choices, he denies that it is necessary for freedom, or that freedom must be understood in terms of it: But freedom of choice cannot be defined-as some have tried to define it-as the abilityto makea choice for or againstthe law (libertasindifferen92 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION tiae), even though choice as a phenomenonprovides frequent examples of this in experience. For we know freedom (as it first becomes manifest to us through the moral law) only as a negativeproperty in us, namely that of not being necessitatedto act through any sensible determining grounds. But we cannot present theoretically freedom as a noumenon,that is, freedom regarded as the ability of the human being merely as intelligence, and show how it can exerciseconstraintupon his sensible choice; we cannot therefore present freedom as a positive property. But we can indeed see that, although experience shows that the human being as a sensiblebeingis able to choose in oppositionto as well as in conformitywith the law, his freedom as an intelligiblebeingcannot be definedby this, since appearances cannot make any supersensible object (such as free choice) understandable. We can also see that freedom can never be located in a rational subject's being able to choose in opposition to his (lawgiving) reason, even though experience proves often enough that this happens (though we still cannot comprehend how this is possible).-For it is one thing to accept a proposition (on the basis of experience) and another thing to make it the expositoryprinciple (of the concept of free choice) and the universal feature for distinguishing it (from arbitriobrutos. servo);for the first does not maintain that the feature belongs necessarilyto the concept, but the second requires this.-Only freedom in relation to the internal lawgiving of reason is really an ability; the possibility of deviating from it is an inability. (MS 6:226-27) The point Kant is making in this difficult passage is this. Human freedom is rooted in the noumenal world, since every phenomenon must be determined according to the laws of causality, and freedom and causal determination are incompatible. But as finite, sensible beings our natures straddle both the noumenal and the phenomenal worlds; we have active spontaneous powers in our reason and imagination, and are receptive to the effects of intuition and sensibility. Sensibility presents the will with incentives in the form of inclinations, and in doing so opens up the possibility of the will choosing to act to gratify them instead of following the moral law. As a result, human beings have a liberty of indifference that gives us the option of either conforming to the law or not, when some inclination provides an incentive to act in opposition to it. We are then naturally inclined to take this indifference to be the essence of freedom. But this is a mistake, because the true essence of freedom is not its manner of manifesting itself when it interacts with the unfree sensible aspects of our nature, but what it is in itself. This is "the ability of pure reason to be of itself practical" (MS 6:214), or what amounts to the same thing, our ability to determine ourselves to action through our own spontaneous activity, undetermined by any causal factor. Pure reason's capacity to be practical consists solely in its ability to 93 SEIRIOLMORGAN determine itself to action by the fact that its maxim qualifies as a universal law. Consequently the essence of freedom is the power to act according to the moral law, which can be possessed both by those who also have liberty of indifference with respect to their morally required actions, and those who don't. In the latter category, God for instance is literally incapable of acting contrary to the law, but this certainly does not mean that God is thereby unfree. On the contrary, he is as free as it is possible to be, since there is obviously no question of him betraying the principle through which freedom is actualized. By contrast, our own "power"to violate the law's dictates simply amounts to the possibility that any one of us may fail to achieve genuine autonomy. So Kant maintains a conception of liberty that allows for "originary" acts of freedom, acts that are free because they are spontaneous, even though we do not possess liberty of indifference with respect to them.16 The will's primal self-enticement to license can only bejust such an act. Hence the fact that we did not bring the propensity to evil upon ourselves through a choice we could have avoided does not mean that it is not our free doing, and so it is still something for which we can be appropriately condemned, as the epithet "evil" clearly indicates. Unfortunately, it is quite beyond the scope of this paper to provide a defense or even a discussion of the conception of freedom to which Kant subscribes. But this is not something I am strictly required to do, since my purpose here is just to show how an argument for a universal yet imputable propensity to evil is available within the bounds of Kant's critical philosophy. What I have to show is that granted his understanding of freedom, it makes perfect sense to say that the propensity is universal and yet imputable to each one of us individually, and this I take it I have done. 7. But the account of the propensity I have been sketching cannot be squared with everything Kant says about it, of course, since he asserts contradictory things. Recall that he wants to claim that all human beings have a propensity to evil, that the propensity consists in the adoption of an evil disposition, and that such a propensity is inextirpable, but also that human beings can come to possess good dispositions. This would imply that some human beings come to possess both good and bad dispositions at the same time. But rigorism denies that this is possible. Which of these claims then should we drop or modify? 94 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION The short answer is, whichever one we like, since when a philosopher presents us with an incoherent position, he cannot complain when we do our best to modify it so that it makes sense. We are entirely justified in experimenting, by exploring the implications of dropping any one or more of the conflicting propositions that seem to us could be sensibly denied, and seeing whether any resulting position strikes us as at all plausible. But if what we are trying to do is produce on behalf of the philosopher the best position available to him within the bounds of his philosophy as a whole, we need to be sensitive to questions such as whether a particular claim is central or peripheral to the main argument, whether its denial would cause the central argument to unravel, and so on. In what follows, I will try to be sensitive to these considerations, and I will suggest that certain commentators who have suggested resolving the problem differently have produced positions which are much more anti-Kantian than they think.17 Which claim or claims should be abandoned, then? Denying the universal propensity to evil will seem to many an attractive idea, and this is what in fact has been surreptitiously done by those Kantian ethicists who just say little or nothing about the claims of the Religion.But if my earlier argument is successful, we have a formal proof of the claim, so we can discount that possibility here. We might also like the idea of dropping the claim that the propensity is inextirpable. But once again, this would undermine the claim about our universal susceptibility to evil that Kant is set on making, and suggests the possibility of a kind of self-achieved moral purity that is entirely alien to the Christian tradition with which he is obviously trying to reach some kind of accommodation. Denying that anyone can develop a disposition to good seems a recipe for despair and threatens to annihilate moral responsibility. Not only that, but it flies in the face of our experience of our freedom and our consciousness of moral obligation (R 6:50). Our only real options then are to drop the claim that the propensity to evil amounts to the adoption of an evil disposition, or else to reject rigorism. The latter will probably strike most people as the more attractive of these two. But I think the former is actually Kant's best option. Kant argues for rigorism as follows. Against the indifferentists, who assert that a person may have a disposition committed neither to good nor to evil, he points out that the only way an incentive can coexist with the free spontaneity of the will is for that incentive to be able to determine the will only if the will incorporates that incentive into a maxim. But we know that the moral law serves as an incentive for the will, and 95 SEIRIOL MORGAN the will can only act upon those things for which it has some incentive. Therefore, if the agent acts in a way contrary to the dictates of morality, then not only must she have an incentive to do so, but she must have actually incorporated that incentive into her maxim. Presumably,indifferentists are committed to the idea that people sometimes act against the requirements of morality, since otherwise there would be no motivation for their position. Hence they must accept that agents incorporate incentives into maxims through the embrace of principles, which is what they wanted to deny (R 6:24). Against the syncretists, he argues that if an agent were actually to be genuinely good in some area of his life, he would have to have embraced morality by incorporating the moral law into his maxim. But genuinely to incorporate the moral law into one's maxim is to incorporate it universally, since morality claims universal authority over an agent's willing. Hence if the agent were also committing himself to evil in some other area of his willing, then he would have had to have embraced morality as both universal and yet particular, which is a contradiction (R 6:25). The arguments are once again brief and cryptic, but actually Kant has seen something important here. Returning to the thought experiment, let's ask whether it would be possible for the will to choose some latitudinarian mixture of principles as its fundamental ground of action. On reflection we will see that it could not, because from the perspective of the noumenal will such a compromise would obviously be self-defeating. This is because for each "standpoint," a compromise with the other would entirely undermine the goal it aims to achieve. Consider the point of view of the will as pulled towards morality. What attracts the will here is its freedom conceived positively, an affirmation of its nature in the rejection of determination by alien causes and a corresponding commitment to autonomy. For the will so minded, humanity acquires a dignity, morality acquires a sublimity, and the free wills of others acquire an absolute value placing them on a par with that which one values most highly in oneself. How could such a will take the attitude that it could be acceptable to endorse these ends in part?For if the will were to compromise on the Categorical Imperative, it would partially affirm its nature and partially affront it. It would partially express its essence and partially violate it, allow itself to be determined sometimes by alien causes, and sometimes take the autonomous agency of itself and others to be of absolute worth, and so on. But in trying to do so, the will would actually fail to achieve in any measure any of the things it half-heartedly attempted to commit to. You do not live up to 96 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION the demands of your nature at all by committing yourself to do so to a certain extent, and you cannot appreciate the sublimity and dignity of the ideal of humanity if you resolve to respect it only now and then. This wouldjust show that you had failed to grasp the importance of any of these things. So the attraction of the ideals of autonomy and morality disappears when they are compromised in this way. Neither could the will choose no principle, since it has incentive to endorse both selflove and morality, and a lack of a principle could not of course provide the necessary competing incentive. So indifferentism is ruled out also.18 So rigorism is actually firmly rooted at the center of Kant's moral philosophy, contra philosophers such as Stephen Engstrom, who have argued that it can and should be dropped in order to square Kantian moral theory with common sense.19 But if we must keep rigorism, what then are the implications of rejecting the claim that the propensity to evil consists in the adoption of the evil meta-maxim? I suggest that they are largely unproblematic, and that this is what we should do in order to make best sense of the Religion,and vindicate within the bounds of his framework as many as possible of the claims Kant makes. For one thing, such a rejection is intuitively well motivated, for it seems on the face of it odd and ultimately pointless to equate the endorsement of the subordination of morality to self-love as one's fundamental principle with the possession of a propensity to evil, since having an evil disposition just is what it is to be an evil person. A "propensity"ordinarily understood suggests susceptibility to a kind of behavior, some characteristic that makes it more likely that certain choices will be made by a particular person than by someone without the propensity. It does not suggest that a person is in a constant state of whatever kind. So someone who frequently resorts to violence when angered might be appropriately described as having a propensity to violence, but someone who is married is just married. She does not have a propensity to marriedness. Yet possession of an evil disposition is not something that happens to or is chosen by an agent from time to time. Gesinnungis a constant, an atemporal orientation providing us with the fundamental model for the regulation of our particular temporal choices. So even were we to take Hang to be a technical term badly translated by the English word 'propensity', there still seems to be no conceptual space for any distinction between having such a Hang, however we might conceive it, and simply being evil, if having it is taken to be equivalent to possession of an evil disposition. 97 SEIRIOLMORGAN Why then does Kant insist on what looks like a conflation of the two? His argument seems to rest on the imputability of the propensity, combined with the claim that the only thing that could be imputable to an agent is a maxim embraced by the will. Since the propensity to evil is imputable, and the only thing that is imputable is a chosen maxim, then the propensity to evil must be such a maxim, and the meta-maxim of subordination of moral considerations to considerations of self-love when they conflict seems like the only available candidate. So it turns out that having the propensity to evil just is being evil (R 6:31). Kant wants to say that the only thing that is imputable is one's own deed, and also that a propensity must be something that precedes a deed, in this case as a "determining ground." But this threatens a contradiction, as he acknowledges, because he insists that the propensity to evil is imputable. His attempt to escape it consists in the drawing of a distinction between two senses of deed, one sense as the choice of a meta-maxim and one as the choice of a particular action in accordance with it (ibid.). The particular evil deeds of the power of choice for which the propensity is the subjective determining ground are those particular evil maxims adopted by the agent. The determining ground of these maxims is the evil fundamental maxim, and so the propensity to evil must be the meta-maxim itself. But this is very unsatisfying, for at least two reasons. First, in stating that the concept of a propensity is that of "a subjective determining ground of the power of choice," hejust defines it in a way that stipulates Kant himself that it must be the meta-maxim. In the later Anthropology defines 'propensity' differently, as "the subjective possibilityof generating a certain appetite, which precedesthe idea of its object" (ApH 7:265); indeed, he even emphasizes the word 'possibility' when advancing the definition to stress it. This is a definition of a physical proAnthropology pensity, but the corresponding one for a moral propensity would be "the subjective possibility of eliciting a certain choice," and not "the determining ground of the power of choice." The subjective possibility of eliciting the choice of an evil action would be the incentive that motivates it, of course, which ultimately is freedom's willfulness. We never receive a proper explanation of why the concept of a propensity to evil is supposed to be that of the determining ground of evil actions, so it is not made clear in the Religionwhy we should accept the claim on which Kant tries to build a great deal. And on reflection the later definition has to be a better one, because there must be a gap between possessing a propensity to be or do something and being or doing that 98 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION thing, otherwise the concept of propensity is entirely redundant, as the ordinary understanding of the term suggests. Second, the requirement that the adoption of a maxim by an agent is necessary if anything is to be imputed to her is unmotivated in this special case. To see this, consider why maxims are required for imputability in the standard case. Most immediately, the maxim underlying an action is a statement of the general reason-generating principle accepted by the agent that elicits this action in these circumstances, and consequently of what she intended to accomplish by it. Thus they serve to distinguish a willed action from a mere bodily movement or something done by an agent who does not intend to perform an action falling under a particular description that nevertheless in fact applies to it. (The latter may still leave the agent the appropriate subject of blame, of course, if the ignorance itself is culpable; but the nature and probably the degree of the agent's culpability will be different.) But also, action upon freely chosen maxims is the only way that the will's freedom can coexist with our pursuit of self-love. Clearly, at least the vast majority of human actions are actions performed from the motive of inclination. As we know, were sensibility to determine the will, it would not be a true will at all, merely an arbitriumbrutum.Consequently for any desire that we gratify, it must have been the case that we need not have performed the action that aimed at doing so; that is, we must possess liberty of indifference with respect to the desire. It is the fact that a maxim stands between desire and action that guarantees this. The reason the action gets performed is not because I have the desire; it is because I have freely embraced a principle of taking the existence of such desires as a reason to act to gratify them in circumstances such as these. So the existence of the maxim serves to ensure the necessary element of indifference, which allows us to act on inclination without being necessitated by it, and hence be responsible for what we do in pursuit of it. However, as we saw, Kant must deny that we possess liberty of indifference with respect to the propensity, on pain of having to abandon his claim that it is universal. Whatever the propensity turns out to be, its genesis must be an "originary"spontaneous upsurge from freedom itself. So the propensity conceived of as evil meta-maxim would be a very unusual kind of maxim, and one that would not possess the property that makes maxims uniquely suitable to ground imputability in everyday cases. What Kant seems to have done then, in insisting that the propensity must be a maxim because it could not itself be 99 SEIRIOLMORGAN evil if it were not imputable, is to assume that because only a maxim can be imputable in standard cases, a maxim must be required for imputability in all cases. But this is illegitimate; an incentive cannot be imputable in the standard case because it is an incentive of inclination, and therefore external to the will, but the incentive to embrace license can arise only from freedom itself. An "originary" incentive to embrace license is therefore just as good a candidate for spontaneous generation by the will as an "originary"embrace of the evil meta-maxim, and consequently is something we could equally well be responsible for. So there is nothing in the nature of the evil Gesinnungthat gives it a better claim than the incentive to be the propensity to evil. Of course, I take my arguments earlier in the paper to have shown that a self-created incentive to license must exist in the will, as a condition of the possibility of wrongdoing. By contrast, there is no solid argument for holding that we all must have embraced an evil fundamental maxim; hence Kant's insistence that propensity and Gesinnungmust be one and the same is groundless. Since all the other claims that generated the inconsistency in his position are either firmly anchored in the Kantian system, or else fundamental to the very idea of radical evil, this then is the claim that should be abandoned. 8. If on behalf of Kant we dispose of the claim that the universal propensity to evil amounts to the same thing as the universal adoption of an evil disposition, we will have to tone down somewhat his indictment of the human race. What the formal argument I outline above demonstrates is not that all human beings have an evil disposition, but that all human beings are drawntoward evil by the will's inner yearning for limitless self-assertion. Since bare freedom is what makes wickedness attractive, it is attractive for every agent with such a will. But that the illicit exerts an inevitable pull on all human beings does not of course entail that everyone embraces evil as their fundamental commitment, merely that anyone may choose it, and we all feel an incentive to do so. Sensitivity to the lure of evil is an entirely different thing to its willful endorsement as one's meta-maxim, and so his Lutheran insistence on the ubiquity of human worthlessness must be abandoned. But this seems to me to be something we should be prepared to jettison on his behalf, granted that he cannot have everything he wanted to have. After all, the claim is intuitively highly implausible for post-Enlighten- 100 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION ment thinkers, and his threadbare defense of this particularly extreme claim does suggest just that uncritical adoption of Augustinian Christianity's misanthropy of which his entire project in the Religionwas accused. Nevertheless, Kant can hang on to his claim that the human being is by nature evil, as long as that claim is understood in the rather weaker sense that evil is a part of our nature. He is not entitled to maintain that we are all willfully committedto evil, but he can assert that there is something about the human will as such that is evil, both in that we are all attracted to it, and because inevitably we all succumb to this attraction from time to time, even if our general commitment is to the moral law. This latter suggestion in particular may immediately strike some as wrong-headed, as it is often assumed that the relationship between Gesinnungand the particular maxims underlying specific actions is one of governance; that is, the quality of the particular maxims is determined by the disposition, so that they all line up together in accordance with the meta-maxim. This would entail that if one possesses a good disposition, one performs only moral actions, and if one has an evil one, one performs only self-centered actions.20 And admittedly there are occasions where Kant says things that seem clearly to commit him to this view, such as when he asserts early on in the Religionthat in order to call a human being evil "it must be possible to infer a priori from a number of consciously evil actions, or even from a single one, an underlying evil maxim, and, from this, the presence in the subject of a common ground, itself a maxim, of all particular morally evil maxims" (R 6:20). The implication here appears evident, that anyone performing an evil act must be acting on an evil maxim, and hence must possess as a ground for it an evil meta-maxim. Rigorism then ensures that the exact contrary has to go for any action motivated by respect for the moral law, which entails that every agent performs actions of one kind or the other, but not both. But on reflection, this cannot be Kant's considered view. For one thing, he says things that appear to contradict it elsewhere in the book, asserting for instance that "between maxim and deed there is still a wide gap" (R 6:47). The context here makes it clear that Kant is talking about the moral meta-maxim, so this strongly suggests that he holds that we can be committed to good, and yet sometimes fail to act in the way that morality dictates; since all intentional action is on a maxim, this would mean that a good meta-maxim can coexist with an evil specific maxim on some particular occasion. But much more importantly, the notion that an agent's specific maxims 101 SEIRIOLMORGAN must all be a function of her fundamental maxim would make a nonsense of his account of virtue. Kant's discussion of virtue is rather unsystematic, and he uses the term (Tugend)in a number of different senses. For instance, in the Religion he distinguishes between virtus phaenomenon and virtus noumenon, empirical and intelligible virtue (ibid.). Intelligible virtue in this context just is the possession of a good disposition, whereas someone possessing empirical virtue has the entrenched habit of acting in a way that conforms to the requirements of the moral law. The empirically virtuous person thus presents the appearance of being a good person, to others and probably herself; nevertheless, she may not really be so, since her conformity to the moral law might be motivated by some other factor than respect for it, for instance, some settled pattern of inclination, such as a powerful desire to be thought well of by other people. As such, empirical virtue simply in itself cannot actually be genuine virtue at all; as Kant says, not the slightest change of heart in the evil person is needed to develop empirical virtue, merely a change of an account of virtue is provided mores (ibid.). But in the Tugendlehre, that gives the notion some content as virtue proper, distinct from the simple embrace of the moral meta-maxim. Here Kant defines virtue as "the strength of a human being's maxims in fulfilling his duty" (MS 6:394). The good agent requires strength of moral resolve (fortitudo moralis)because sensibility continually presents us with powerful forces acting as obstacles to our doing as we should (MS 6:380). Strength is plainly something that is a matter of degree, and indeed Kant makes clear that virtue understood this way is not an all-or-nothing matter: Virtue is always in progressand yet always starts from the beginning.-It is it is an ideal and unatalwaysin progressbecause, considered objectively tainable,while yet constantapproximationto it is a duty.That it always basisin human nature,which is startsfrom the beginning has a subjective affectedby inclinationsbecause of whichvirtuecan never settle down in peace and quiet with its maximsadopted once and for all but, if it is not rising,it is unavoidablysinking. (MS6:409) Elsewhere Kant similarly affirms that virtue in its highest form is an unobtainable ideal (MS 6:383), and says that while everyone has the capacity to resist inclinations running counter to the moral law, the capacity "asstrength" is something that must be acquired by enhancing the power of the moral incentive (MS 6:397). Since this is something that is achieved through contemplation and practice (ibid.), it must be something that is done over time, little by little. But of course the very 102 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION idea of virtue as a strength that one can have more or less of requires for its sense the possibility of those who possess some degree of it failing to live up to it. If anyone possessing virtue were guaranteed to perform all those actions that morality requires, then the idea of having more or less strength-and hence ultimately the idea of virtue as strength at all-would become meaningless. So it must be the case that virtuous individuals can nevertheless perform immoral actions; their degree of virtue is determined by the extent to which they succeed in maintaining their resolve to do only what duty allows and demands. Kant's whole discussion clearly presupposes that virtuous individuals possess good dispositions; in any case, it is hard to see how he could think anything else, for otherwise they would possess merely simulacra of virtue. Consequently he must hold that it is possible to possess a generally good disposition, and yet at some particular point fail to live up to one's commitment, acting instead on a specific evil maxim. As it turns out, this is precisely what we see in Kant's account in the Religionof the condition the good agent is in after undergoing the revolution in mode of thought (Denkungsart)that leads to his transformation from an evil person to a morally worthy one (R 6:47). The newly worthy agent becomes a subject "receptive to the good" (R 6:48), but does not enter into a state in which its pursuit is automatic or easy. Rather, he enters onto a path of "constant progress from bad to better," an "ever continuing striving" (ibid.) against an evil within him that is never totally defeated in the course of an earthly lifetime. Since evil actions presuppose a maxim on the part of the agent, Kant must think that although the will is committed to the Categorical Imperative, it is still perennially tempted to betray that commitment, and inevitably does so from time to time, succumbing to frailty,as it is described in the Religion,when it does so (R 6:29). So not only does Kant admit the possibility of moral lapses by the virtuous agent, he thinks that occasional failure of our strength cannot be avoided, no matter how robust our commitment to morality. Indeed, he thinks this an ever-present danger for the good person, and describes the life of the individual who has passed through the revolution in his cast of mind that is needed to renounce evil as one thereafter requiring "unremitting counteraction" against "a depravity of our power of choice" (R 6:51), as he fights against the traces remaining in his character of the corruption of his prior disposition. Although we can achieve increasing success in this endeavor, no human being will ever fully succeed in achieving the complete conformity of his will with the moral law (KpV 5:122). The 103 SEIRIOLMORGAN best we can do is continually to increase our virtue, which is simply to strengthen our resolution to do what is required of us (MS 6:390). So the moral life for the good person is a never-ending battle, in which her primary opponent is herself (MS 6:405). We see then in Kant a particular picture of the human being as a dangerous creature, one that can never be fully trusted. We can never be fully trusted because our wills never cease to be susceptible to the attraction of forbidden fruit, and anyone may find herself flirting with evil at any time. This freedom to misuse it is the price of a free will.21 Much of this pessimism rests on the claim that everyone committed to morality at any time in their lives will at some prior time have been an evil person committed to the pursuit of self-love at morality's expense. During that time, Kant thinks they will inevitably have acquired patterns of inclination and habits of perception, action, and affirmation oriented toward self-love-encrustations in reason, will, and sensibility-that will remain in place after the revolution in cast of mind that transforms the agent's fundamental commitment from evil to good. It is this after-effect of what the good person once was that Kant thinks the good person must combat, and it is because these aftereffects will inevitably be so pronounced that we will never be able to completely overcome them. If we deny that the propensity to evil is identical with possessing an evil disposition, then there will be good people who have not built up the habits, desires, and patterns of attention of the evil person, and so they will not have to combat these. If someone's disposition is good and she lacks the passionate nature and habitual willfulness of the reformed malefactor, we could surely expect her actions to be systematically good ones. How in the case of such a person could we hang onto the claim that the will alwayshas evil as part of its nature? Perhaps like this. Kant clearly thinks that the will is capable within time of choosing to act upon maxims that conflict with its fundamental commitment. Presumably,it must be necessarily typically the case, or at least necessarily increasingly typically the case, that the will chooses in accordance with its disposition. Since the will is transcendentally free, a systematic failure to act as it has resolved to act would cast serious doubt on the genuineness of the resolution. But because it is free, it can never bind itself, only continually maintain and strengthen its resolve. Considering the demandingness of the Categorical Imperative, the indeterminacy of our wide duties, and the sheer number of opportunities to fail to live up to the obligations each of us have 104 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION encountered, it is near enough unbelievable that there is anyone who has never, on any occasion, subordinated a requirement of morality to a consideration of self-love, if it is possible to do so while possessing a moral disposition. If all of us have performed some deed contrary to morality at some point in our lives, all of us have at some point implicitly asserted the priority of our freedom over that of others. Thus all of us have at some point said 'Yes" to evil, mimicking in the temporal moment the atemporal embrace of evil by the licentious will. Since in doing so we have responded to an incentive of the will, we have all experienced the dark pleasure that gratifying this incentive brings, and this experience will be lodged deep in the memory. So although such an agent will not be weighed down under the crippling legacy of former wickedness that Kant describes, the incentive to self-will still remains and can never be extirpated, and the temptation to gratify it is exacerbated by the will's memory of the pleasure it took in so doing, on those previous occasions on which the incentive was indulged. Given the temporal fluctuations of the will's resolve to abide by the commitment it has atemporally made, it would be a rash individual who denied that he or she would ever do wrong at any time in the future, or indeed that any good person is immune from moral failure. It seems to me that if this is the case, it is not only appropriate to describe human nature as containing an element of evil as such, but also that it would be prudent for us to be well aware of this uncomfortable fact, and remind ourselves of it often. As Kant's medieval predecessors knew well, one of the most insidious sources of moral danger is precisely the conviction that we are sufficiently good to be beyond the reach of temptation.22 9. Kant was trying to have his cake and eat it too, then, but to nothing like the extent usually assumed. His critics have standardly thought that when the internal tensions between the constituent parts of his position in the Religionare brought to light, his whole enterprise there must collapse. As we have seen, this is not the case. Instead of reading him as vainly attempting to articulate a necessarily incoherent combination of Enlightenment humanism and Augustinian pessimism, we should read him as having made a mistake in his attempt to outline the implications of his general ethical thought, by taking one step too many down the Augustinian road. This step was unmotivated by anything internal to 105 SEIRIOLMORGAN his system, and was probably actually motivated by the psychological effect upon him of the deeply misanthropic Lutheranism in which he was steeped from boyhood onwards. In comparison with Luther's insistence on the total depravity of humankind, an announcement of a universal propensity to evil as a mere inner yearning for unlimited license, and one that to boot we are able to combat from our own resources, might look like a pretty feeble indictment. It is not difficult to see how Kant, who was regularly confronted for much of his life with views of this kind, could have felt that a failure to assert a generalized commitment to evil would simply not do justice to the reality of human sinfulness. But it is precisely Kant's taking this step that involves him in the difficulties. Since the step is unmotivated by anything internal to his system, the best option for Kant was simply not to take it. Having said that, within the bounds of the general Kantian project in practical philosophy, the argument I have proposed on his behalf vindicates a very large number of the claims he makes in the Religion.It shows that there is a universal human propensity to evil, which is inextirpable and yet possible to overcome. It shows how the propensity can be both woven into human nature and something we have brought on ourselves. It explains how it is possible for us to have both the propensity to evil and a predisposition to good at the same time. It vindicates rigorism, and illustrates how it is possible that a commitment to evil can be both the pursuit of the incentives of self-love at the expense of those of morality and at the same time a deeply perverted attitude of the will. We can even hang onto, in modified form, the claim that the human being as such is actually evil. These amount to a substantial majority of the claims I attributed to Kant in section 2, and consequently I take the argument I have provided to amount to a vindication of the claims of part 1 of the Religionin broad outline, within the context of an assumed success of the Kantian practical project. Kant himself may have done a rather shoddy job of arguing for these claims, but he said there was a formal argument for a universal human propensity to evil available, and contrary to general expectation, it turns out that there is. Obviously this is of historical interest. But I think it has to have contemporary implications as well. My argument shows that far from being an unmotivated, late addition, inexplicably imported into a quite alien context, Kant's central claims about the propensity to evil are rightat the veryheartof his moral philosophy. Pessimism is therefore integral to his ethics, and this is something contemporary Kantians will need to address, now that the formal argument has come to light. Either they 106 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION will have to show how something like Kant's own pessimism is to be incorporated into neo-Kantian moral psychology, or they will have to distance themselves from Kant's arguments for the authority of morality, and probably from significant elements of his account of practical reason as well. I suspect that a consequence of doing the latter would be to make evident how oddly un-Kantian much of contemporary Kantian ethics actually is. The price of coming to understand better how the claims of the Religion relate to the practical philosophy as a whole may well be that we are forced to modify our view of the nature of the overall project in a way that makes it appear much less congenial to us, since it is actually considerably more alien to contemporary postEnlightenment liberal optimism than has standardly been thought. University of Leeds Notes Earlier versions of this paper were presented to the 2004 British Society for Ethical Theory conference at the University of Kent, the Historical Perspectives on Wrongdoing and Evil workshop at Leeds University, and to the Department of Philosophy at the University of Sussex. I'm grateful to the participants at each of these events for valuable help in developing the ideas in this article, and also to Nafsika Athanassoulis, Matthew Kieran, Andy McGonigal, Peter Millican, Dan Morgan, Martin Shaw, Roger White, and an anonymous referee for this journal. I'd also like to thank the PhilosophicalReview's very conscientious copyeditor, who has saved me from numerous errors of presentation. He bears no responsibility for those that remain, for which willfulness on my part is responsible. 1 I make reference to Kant's works in parenthesis in the text, citing the volume and page number of the Prussian Academy edition of Kant's gesammelte Schriften(1900-) and using standard abbreviations. The texts are the Critiqueof Pure Reason (KrV), Idea for a UniversalHistory with a CosmopolitanIntent (I), Groundworkof the Metaphysicsof Morals (G), the Critiqueof Practical Reason (KpV), Religion WithintheBoundariesof MereReason (R), TheMetaphysicsof Morals (MS), and Anthropology from a PragmaticPoint of View(ApH). I quote from the following translations: Religion within the Boundariesof MereReason,translated by George di Giovanni, in The CambridgeEdition of the Worksof Immanuel Kant: Religion and Rational Theology,ed. Allen Wood and George di Giovanni of theMetaphysics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996); Groundwork all translated Practical and The Reason, Morals, Morals, Metaphysicsof of Critiqueof Edition of the Worksof ImmanuelKant:Practical by Mary Gregor, in The Cambridge Philosophy,ed. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996); from a PragmaticPoint of View,translated by Mary Gregor (The Anthropology Martinus Nijhoff, 1974). Hague: 2 See, for example, Daniel O'Connor, "Good and Evil Disposition," KantStudien 76 (1985): 288-302, Gordon E. Michalson Jr., Fallen Freedom(Cam107 SEIRIOLMORGAN bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), and Richard Bernstein, RadicalEvil (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2001), 11-45, who, in spite of varying degrees of sympathy, all end up leveling this charge against Kant. 3 For instance, the following would clearly have to appear on any list of the most influential books or collections of essays on Kantian ethics published in English over the last twenty years: Onora O'Neill, Constructionsof Reason(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989); Thomas Hill, Dignity and Practical Reason (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1992); Barbara Herman, ThePractice of MoralJudgment(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993); Marcia Baron, Kantian EthicsAlmostWithoutApology(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1995); and Nancy Sherman, Making a Necessityof Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997). And yet not one of these books contains a reference to 'evil' in the index, and most lack any reference to related terms such as 'vice', 'passion', or 'self-love'. Even the small minority who have attempted to provide a qualified defense of Kant's arguments in the Religionhave sometimes felt the need to apologize on his behalf for the book's baffling obscurity, or to concede that much of its pessimism is unjustified. See, for example, Henry Allison, Kant's Theoryof Freedom(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 146-47. 4 The term 'meta-maxim' is Philip Quinn's. See "InAdam's Fall, We Sinned All," PhilosophicalTopics16 (1988): 89-118, at 110. 5 Radical Evil, 33. 6 Some commentators write as though Kant has already done the latter by the end of Groundwork 2, encouraged for example by Kant's asserting that he has shown "by developing the generally accepted concept of morality that autonomy of the will is unavoidably bound up with it or rather is its very foundation" (G 4:445), which can be read as saying that all we need to do is establish freedom of the will in order to give morality its foundation. See, for example, Paul Guyer, "Introduction," in Kant's Groundworkof theMetaphysicsof Morals:CriticalEssays,ed. Paul Guyer (Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998), xxxix, where he describes Groundwork3 as seeming to continue "the 'analytic' project of Section II, still trying to prove that the conception of free and rational agency really does give rise to the categorical imperative, or that a free and rational agent must act in accordance with that principle." I think this is a mistake, and that Kant was never trying to show in Groundwork 2 that a free agent is rationally committed to morality. Rather, he was trying to show that moral action requires acting on the categorical imperative, and that the categorical imperative presupposes autonomy of the will. It is true that the 3 contains an argument which is purely analytic, but early pages of Groundwork the concepts under analysis in the two sections are different; in Groundwork 2 it is morality, in Groundwork 3 it is freedom. Admittedly, Kant thinks that the two concepts reciprocally imply one another. But this biconditional is something he needs to demonstrate, and it seems to me that nothing he says in Groundwork2 is intended to do so. 7 See especially Christine Korsgaard, TheSourcesof Normativity(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 97-98, 219-33. 81 have borrowed this way of making the point from Christine Korsgaard's 108 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION essay "Moralityas Freedom," in CreatingtheKingdomofEnds (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996); see especially 164-67. I am greatly indebted to Korsgaard'swork throughout this article. 9Actually, as is well known, Kant never claims to be able to demonstrate that rational beings such as ourselves are transcendentally free. But since he takes himself to have arguments that no such demonstration is possible, he does not think this can be held against him. What he attempts to do instead is to show that freedom is possible, that it cannot be shown that we are not free (G 4:456), and that whatever the truth of the matter, we have no choice but to take ourselves to be transcendentally free from the practical standpoint (G 4:448). Furthermore, he demotivates determinism by showing how the arguments against freedom presuppose a mistaken understanding of the nature of causality, holding it be a noumenal reality rather than a category by which the mind structures the phenomenal world (G 4:459). If everything he attempts in the Groundwork succeeds, he will have shown that free beings are committed to morality as expressed in the Categorical Imperative, that it can't be shown we aren't free, that we know that freedom is possible, that all the arguments from the history of philosophy that purport to show we aren't free rest on a confusion, and that in practice we have no choice but to take ourselves to be free. This would clearly be a very substantial defense of morality. 10Most fundamentally, it rests on the presumption that the will has a choice of only two principles, morality and self-love. If there is any other purely formal principle through which the will's volition could be unified while preserving its autonomy, and Kant merely assumes, and does not argue, that there is not, then the will would have no more reason to choose the Categorical Imperative than that principle, and so the "leap of volition" would be reintroduced, and the rational authority of morality would vanish. 11The idea that evil has its roots in the will's perverted yearning to ape the power of God has an interesting history, much of which would have been familiar to Kant. It is of course suggested in the Bible (Gen. 3:5), then is explicitly advanced by Augustine and transmitted by him to the Christian tradition for which he was so influential. See, for example, The Cityof God 12.8 and, in particular, The Trinity12.11 (16): "For as a snake creeps along not with open steps, but by the most minute movements of its scales, so the slippery movement of falling away [from the good] takes possession of the careless little by little; and while it begins with the perverse desire of becoming like God, it arrives at the likeness of the beasts. Whence it is that they, who were stripped of their first garment, deserved by their mortality garments of skin. For the true honor of man is to be the image and likeness of God which is preserved only in relation to Him by whom it is impressed. Hence, he clings to God so much the more, the less he loves what is his own. But through the desire of proving his own power, man by his own will falls down into himself, as into a sort of center. Since he, therefore, wishes to be like God under no-one, then as a punishment he is also driven from the center, which he himself is, into the depths, that is, into those things wherein the beasts delight; and thus, since the likeness to God is his honor, the likeness to the beasts is his disgrace" (trans. Stephen McKenna (Washington: Catholic University of America Press, 1963)). We also 109 SEIRIOLMORGAN see from this quotation that Kant and Augustine share basically the same view about the fruits of evil as well. Although the specifics of their accounts reflect their individual metaphysical commitments, they agree that in pursuing unfettered power the will ironically subverts its own purpose, achieving the opposite of its aim. After Kant, the idea gets a subtle and psychologically acute development along broadly Augustinian lines in Kierkegaard; see in particular the section "In Despair to Will to Be Oneself: Defiance," from TheSicknessUntoDeath (vol. samledeVrker, ed. A. B. Drachmann,J. L. Heiberg, and 11 of SorenKierkegaard's H. O. Lange (Copenhagen: Gyldendal, 1901-6)), 178-85; marginal references to this edition are given in the English translation by Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980). Then, while continuing to appear in orthodox Augustinian form in more recent theologysee, for example, Emil Brunner, Man in Revolt (London: Lutterworth Press, 1939), 139-43-it also recognizably reappears in the work of thinkers such as Nietzsche and Sartre, having undergone a radical twist. For this kind of thinker, the attempt to secure a godlike, unfettered freedom is either the laudable aim of those who are to be admired, or an existential condition of being human, or (arguably) an unstable combination of both. See, for example, Sartre, Being and Nothingness:"(T)he best way to conceive of the fundamental project of human reality is to say that man is the being whose project is to be God...To be man means to reach toward being God. Or if you prefer, man fundamentally is the desire to be God" (trans. Hazel Barnes (London: Routledge, 1969), 566). We even see in Sartre (ibid., 615) a version of the idea that the project is self-defeating; this time however it is presented not as the wages of wickedness, but as a tragic truth about the human condition: "Thus the passion of man is the reverse of that of Christ, for man loses himself as man in order that God may be born. But the idea of God is contradictory and we lose ourselves in vain. Man is a useless passion." 12Kant's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 287 and the associated note on 402. 13Sharon Anderson-Gold, "Kant'sRejection of Devilishness: The Limits of Human Volition," Idealistic Studies 14 (1984): 38. Allison first presents his development of the argument in Kant's TheoryofFreedom,155-57 (and chap. 8 passim); see also his "On the Very Idea of a Propensity to Evil,"Journal of Value Inquiry36 (2002): 337-48. 14Indeed, we are now perhaps in a position to turn the tables on Wood, whose own "anthropological" account of radical evil has been both influential and controversial (Kant'sEthicalThought,283-90). This account offers a reductionist reading of the concept that identifies it with "unsociable sociability," the tendency, which Kant says that human beings in society have, to develop mutually antagonistic inclinations and ultimately downright malicious ones (I 8:20-21; R 6:27), in particular, the desire for power over others and the appearance of superiority to them (ApH 7:271-74). Wood's view is motivated in part by his conviction that Kant meant the account to be a substantial and contentious thesis, combined with pessimism that anything approaching a satisfying transcendental proof has been or is likely to be outlined. But in addi- 110 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION tion, his case rests heavily on some remarks of Kant about evil springing into being from a seemingly undemanding human constitution only upon the occasion of a person's immersion in society: "Envy,addiction to power, avarice, and the malignant inclinations associated with these, assail his nature, which on its own is undemanding, as soon as he is amonghuman beings.Nor is it necessary to assume that these are sunk into evil and are an example to lead him astray:it suffices that they are there, that they surround him, and that they are human beings, and they will mutually corrupt one another's moral disposition and make one another evil" (R 6:93-94). I agree that Kant takes the thesis to be a substantial one. Nevertheless, in my view the reductionist interpretation is a reading of last resort, since it threatens to make the phenomena Wood focuses on the unfortunate consequence of a natural process; in order for evil to be evil it needs to have its roots in the transcendental freedom of the will, and not in the physical propensity to develop inclinations. Fortunately, we don't need to accept it, since the social origin of the specific evils assailing human nature is exactly what we would expect if radical evil is as I have characterized it. On my account, the propensity to evil is the will's primal lust for an entirely unrestricted outer freedom. But it is precisely the wills of others that threaten restriction. On his own, man can do as he likes. He is in no danger of having his will bent to the service of another, nor does he encounter anything whose nature demands from him a respect that infringes upon self-love (KpV 5:75-76). Consequently it is no surprise that evil begins to wreak its effects only once he encounters others like himself. Since I have provided a formal argument that both gives substance to Kant's claims about radical evil and explains Kant's remarks about it manifesting itself only in society, I take the anthropological reading to be redundant. (This is not, of course, to say that Wood's eye-opening account of Kant's anthropology as a whole is redundant; on the contrary, I have learnt an enormous amount from it.) 15In what follows, I draw heavily on Wood's illuminating article "Kant's Compatibilism," in Selfand Naturein Kant'sPhilosophy,ed. Allen Wood (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1984), 73-101, especially 79-83. 16The term is Allison's; "On the Very Idea of a Propensity to Evil,"343. 17A reading of the Religionthat would resolve the inconsistency is presented in John Hare's book, TheMoral Gap (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996). Hare takes seriously both Kant's caveat (at R 6:37) that the propensity is inextirpable "through human forces," and his concession that divine assistance may be necessary for an agent's transformation from evil to good (R 6:44), and interprets him as holding that although we are unable to transform our evil dispositions by our own efforts, God can transform them for us, and when he does, we cease to possess an evil disposition. This reading is an interesting one, and admittedly there are passages where Kant does seem to be taking the idea seriously. Yet they are not without their difficulties since, as Hare sees, on these occasions the invocation of divine grace clearly fails to do thejob it is supposed to do. The ostensible problem is that since the ground of our maxims is corrupt (R 6:47), because of the will's embrace of the evil meta-maxim, it is impossible to see how we could ever come to make a morally worthy choice on our 111 SEIRIOLMORGAN own initiative. But even if there is a genuine problem here-and one might well question whether there is, since one would expect that the will's freedom should allow it unproblematically to choose to renounce former commitments and adopt new ones-Kant's semi-Pelagian insistence that in order for God to transform an agent's disposition the agent must first have done something to make himself worthy of it (R 6:44) ensures that the appeal to divine agency just recreates the problem one step down; it would be similarly mysterious how we could ever will anything making us deserving of that assistance, if corruption makes us unable to will the good. Hare thus reads Kant as ultimately producing an unstable position-torn as he is between the account of freedom and responsibility developed in the earlier work and his growing realization that radical evil cannot be overcome by human agency, he fails to take the required final step to the fully Augustinian position that Hare himself favors. I dispute this reading however, for the following reasons. First, Kant is equivocal about the claims upon which Hare places great weight, stating clearly elsewhere in the Religionthat the propensity is simply ineradicable (R 6:31), and refusing to commit himself to the claim that God's assistance is essential for us to will the good. He is absolutely adamant about going no further than semi-Pelagianism, and at various other places he insists without qualification that we are able to live up to our moral obligations (for example R 6:41, 50). And he does not talk about grace at all in the later MetaphysicsofMorals, something one would certainly expect if he had come to see it as central to any adequate account of how we develop virtue. Contra Hare, I think Kant is paying lip-service here to a facet of the Christian religion that is in significant tension with his views on agency and responsibility, but that has too central a place in Christian orthodoxy for him to simply dismiss. What Kant does clearly endorse is the claim that if the corruption of the ground of choice is such that we are unable by our own efforts to become good, then we are entitled to hope that the deficiency will be remedied by divine cooperation (R 6:52); essentially, we are to take it as a practical postulate (KrV 5:121) that the deserving will get whatever help they might need to achieve genuine goodness, whatever conundrums theoretical reason might present us with on the matter. But this is of course quite different from the claim that such assistance actually is required. Since the textual evidence against Hare's reading seems to me stronger than that in favor of it, and on his interpretation Kant is caught up in some similarly tricky entanglements, and furthermore none of the claims foregrounded by Hare follow from the earlier work, I'll put it to one side. 18Although Kant does not do so, the argument can be run from the opposing perspective as well, since a similar defeat of its own purpose also awaits the will inclined toward evil, if it attempts a compromise with morality. The evil will takes its essence as free to be expressed by its own unfettered power of choice, its willful celebration of the utter absence of restraints on its willing. From the standpoint of the will as drawn toward evil, any compromise with morality would be an entirely arbitraryrestriction on its project of self-affirmation. It would function as an admission by the will that aims to emulate God that it is not in fact godlike at all, which would lay bare the bankruptcy of its commitment and self-image. So from neither standpoint can the compromise 112 PROOFOFHUMANITY'SRADICALEVILIN KANT'SRELIGION be accepted. 19"Conditioned Autonomy," Philosophy and PhenomenologicalResearch48 (1988): 435-53. 20Engstrom appears to make just this assumption, since he attempts to provide a reductio of Kant's rigorism by arguing that when it is combined with what he calls his "purism,"the plausible contention that no one succeeds in fully living up to the demands of morality, it entails the unacceptable conclusion that we all possess an evil disposition and so are all morally on a par. "Conditioned Autonomy," 435-36. 21It is now possible for me to address the version of the formal proof advanced by Henry Allison, which I mentioned but put to one side earlier ("On the Very Idea of a Propensity to Evil";all page references in this note are to this article). Naturally I concur with his endorsement of Anderson-Gold's argument that since the moral law provides a positive incentive for us to act from duty, the possibility of acting contrary to duty requires an incentive that is actively opposed to the moral one (338). But recall that Allison wants to extend the argument in defense of Kant's claim that the propensity is to be understood as equivalent to an evil disposition. He begins by more or less taking as given Kant's identification of a moral propensity with Gesinnung(340), and goes on to argue that since rigorism is true of dispositions, any particular individual must possess either a propensity to evil or a propensity to good. Granted this, the obvious way to establish the universality of the propensity to evil is to rule out the possibility of anyone having a propensity to good (342). According to Allison, what a propensity to good would entail is a spontaneous preference for the impersonal requirements of morality over those of inclination, and an individual spontaneously inclined to prefer moral incentives to those of sensibility would not only perform only morally permissible actions, but would not find the moral law constraining (ibid.). But this would amount to possession of a holy will, which no human being can possess, since our sensuous natures present us with the claims of happiness as a necessary end. When those claims conflict with those of morality, as they certainly will from time to time, they will therefore inevitably generate an incentive in opposition to it. Allison's initial assumption would clearly be fully justified if he successfully established the universality of the evil disposition. But I don't think that he does. For one thing, it isn't clear to me why one would have to think that the embrace of the moral meta-maxim silencesthe claims of inclination when they conflict with morality, even if one thought that a good disposition would entail full conformity of the agent's actions with the moral law. After all, Kant clearly thinks that those of an evil disposition are correspondingly committed to giving precedence to the claims of self-love over those of morality, but this prioritization of self-interest certainly does not silence the demands of the law. On the contrary, he explicitly insists that conscience is an inescapable fact for all human beings (G 4:454; MS 6:400), and in any case, a will for which they were silenced would be a diabolical or brutal one. But even a weaker version of the argument-that no one can possess a propensity to good, because this would rule out the possibility of moral failure-would rest on the premise that 113 SEIRIOLMORGAN an agent's particular maxims must share without exception the moral quality of her meta-maxim (340), which I hope I have shown to be highly dubious. 22This is a favorite theme in Augustine's work; see for example his account of how Alypius's overconfidence in his own strength of will led him to succumb to the lure of the circus. Confessions6.8 (13). 114