* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Peter Sedgwick: mental health as radical politics
History of psychopathy wikipedia , lookup
Self-help groups for mental health wikipedia , lookup
Clinical mental health counseling wikipedia , lookup
Outpatient commitment wikipedia , lookup
Lifetrack Therapy wikipedia , lookup
Psychiatric rehabilitation wikipedia , lookup
Mental disorder wikipedia , lookup
Involuntary commitment internationally wikipedia , lookup
Psychiatric and mental health nursing wikipedia , lookup
Emergency psychiatry wikipedia , lookup
Community mental health service wikipedia , lookup
Mental health in Russia wikipedia , lookup
Causes of mental disorders wikipedia , lookup
Moral treatment wikipedia , lookup
Abnormal psychology wikipedia , lookup
Mental health professional wikipedia , lookup
Deinstitutionalisation wikipedia , lookup
History of psychiatric institutions wikipedia , lookup
Homelessness and mental health wikipedia , lookup
Critical Psychiatry Network wikipedia , lookup
History of mental disorders wikipedia , lookup
Anti-psychiatry wikipedia , lookup
Psychiatric survivors movement wikipedia , lookup
Thomas Szasz wikipedia , lookup
History of psychiatry wikipedia , lookup
Critical and Radical Social Work • vol 3 • no 1 • 103–17 • © Policy Press 2015 • #CRSW Print ISSN 2049 8608 • Online ISSN 2049 8675 • http://dx.doi.org/10.1332/204986015X14234701186107 pioneers of the radical tradition Peter Sedgwick: mental health as radical politics1 Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press Tad Tietze, [email protected] University of New South Wales, Australia This article examines the life, Marxist politics and critical psychiatric theory of Peter Sedgwick, author of Psychopolitics (1982). Sedgwick critically engaged with the ideas of key anti-psychiatric thinkers, including Goffman, Laing, Szasz and Foucault. His theoretical contribution – of the social construction of health and illness, mental and otherwise – underpinned a focus on the politicisation of medical goals within projects for social transformation. His ideas remain highly relevant to modern psychiatric debates and controversies. key words critical psychiatry • Marxism • anti-psychiatry • medicalisation • social construction Introduction Peter Sedgwick (1934-83) was a psychologist, academic, translator and revolutionary Marxist activist who lived in Britain through periods of progress, crisis and reaction – in both the field of mental healthcare and wider society – before his untimely death. While working in various health settings, Sedgwick pursued a sustained critical engagement with the ideas of thinkers associated with the anti-psychiatry movements of the 1960s and 1970s – including Erving Goffman, R.D. Laing, Thomas Szasz and Michel Foucault. He welcomed their critique of scientific positivism while rejecting a tendency to annex psychiatric problems from health and illness in general. In this article I outline Sedgwick’s personal story and his adult political commitments and achievements. I survey his critiques of the anti-psychiatric thinkers before elucidating his key theoretical contribution to critical psychiatry: the idea that all health and illness is socially constructed, and therefore that conflicts over normality, diagnosis and treatment can only be understood by locating their origins in conflictual capitalist social relations. I address more recent criticisms of his main positions and – through the example of the controversies surrounding the Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: 5th edition (DSM-5) – consider how his ideas help us to understand and orient thinking about the renewed crisis of mainstream psychiatry. Life of a radical Born in Southampton, England, in 1934, Sedgwick was brought up by his uncle and aunt after his mother’s death from breast cancer when he was just one year old. He was intelligent and studious as a child and went to Balliol College, Oxford, to read Greats. Sedgwick’s burning interest in questions of mental health and illness 103 Tad Tietze Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press was forged during his early years with his adoptive family. His adoptive mother ‘was admitted, in a condition of extreme dementia, into the charge of a crowded and custodial local mental hospital in which she quite shortly afterwards died’ (Sedgwick, quoted in Lukes, 1983). It was only after this that Sedgwick learned that he had been adopted. He later came to the conclusion that ‘the studious bookish part of me was constructed as an elaborate defence system against a fairly horrendous world’ (Kuper, 2013). Sedgwick also suffered from debilitating physical problems, including a bowed back and asthma (Mitchell, 2004). It was at Oxford that he became involved with the Communist Party, and in the aftermath of Khrushchev’s secret speech did not reject socialist values, instead moving towards a more questioning and non-dogmatic commitment to working-class self-emancipation. He became involved with the powerful movement for nuclear disarmament that swept Britain at that time. He joined the Socialist Review Group/ International Socialists (SRG/IS) in the late 1950s, remaining a member until 1976. Following his time at Oxford: He became a psychologist at Liverpool University but was forced out of this post when an article he had written about Durex’s monopoly of the contraceptive industry led to a confrontation with his professor (and support from his students). There followed jobs as a school teacher, an educational psychologist, tutor at a psychiatric prison and research psychologist at an Oxford hospital studying brain damaged patients. He then took up a politics lectureship at York University, spent a year in New York, and, finally, a post in both politics and psychiatry at Leeds University from 1974 until [his death]. (Lukes, 1983) While at Liverpool he met and married Edie in 1959. His daughter was born at the end of that year and his son was born in 1961. Despite his personal struggles, Sedgwick was widely considered to be an especially warm, generous and funny man, rarely allowing the darkness he carried to colour his professional and political activities. Sedgwick wrote for a wide variety of Left and mainstream publications, including New Society, International Socialism, New Left Review, The Observer, The Guardian, the Times Literary Supplement and New Statesman, as well as academic journals such a Salmagundi, Psychological Medicine and Psychiatric Bulletin. Compared with the overwrought stylistics of many writers on the revolutionary Left, Sedgwick’s prose had a literary elegance, densely packed yet frequently witty and ironic. He had a knack for puncturing received wisdoms, and would do so by mobilising an encyclopaedic knowledge of the history of the Left and the workers’ movement. That he was able to demolish One-dimensional man (Marcuse, 1964) when Herbert Marcuse was a darling of the New Left (Sedgwick, 1966) says much about his fierce intellectual independence. Even a cursory glance at the page dedicated to his work on the Marxists Internet Archive (https://www.marxists.org/) reveals his ability to intervene incisively in debates around the nature of Stalinism, nuclear disarmament, the travails of the British Labour movement and the New Left, socialist history and, centrally for this review, the politics of mental illness. He is also known for translating and editing Victor Serge’s Memoirs of a revolutionary (Serge, 1963) and Year one of the Russian Revolution (Serge, 1972), helping to edit Midnight in the century (Serge, 1981), and writing penetratingly on Serge’s politics (Sedgwick, 1984). 104 Peter Sedgwick: mental health as radical politics Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press While Sedgwick was for many years part of political currents that could broadly be described as ‘Leninist’, his own politics after 1956 were decidedly more libertarian. The SRG/IS was sufficiently open and inclusive that he was able to be a productive contributor to its activities not despite but because of the creative tension that flowed from such differences. The group’s founder and most prominent leader in that period, Tony Cliff, would later claim: ‘Every organisation should have one Peter Sedgwick, but no organisation would survive with two of them’ (Birchall, 2011: 175). It was only when the IS declared itself the Socialist Workers Party that Sedgwick believed that the group’s promise had been squandered by a grandiose turn to electoral work in an increasingly right-wing climate (Sedgwick, 1976). Following his departure he became involved in a number of Left regroupment efforts, including helping to organise the influential ‘Beyond the Fragments’ conference in 1980. However, as the impact of Thatcherism became obvious, he found himself fighting overwhelming depression, leading up to his premature death in September 1983. The challenge of ‘anti-psychiatry’ Sedgwick developed his critique of modern psychiatry in a series of papers and articles in the 1970s, several of which were revised, expanded and elaborated on with the help of editor Richard Kuper in the widely read Psychopolitics (Sedgwick, 1982). Perhaps surprisingly, his main foils in this process were not defenders of psychiatry but thinkers associated with the anti-psychiatry movement. While ‘anti-psychiatry’ refers to a heterogeneous and often contradictory set of ideas, politics and activities that rose to prominence in the late 1960s and early 1970s, it is possible to identify some common themes, highly critical of psychiatric theory and practice. First, there was a critique of psychiatry as being a branch of medicine that relied on low-quality or absent ‘scientific’ evidence when compared with the physical healthcare professions. Second, that mainstream mental healthcare was basically repressive in nature, robbing patients of their individual rights via mechanisms such as detention and forcible treatment. Third, psychiatric diagnosis was seen as fundamentally value-laden in the way it turned certain types of social deviancy into a poorly defined entity known as ‘mental illness’. Along with other political and social developments in Western capitalist countries at the time, these movements drew on and in turn influenced a series of scholars and thinkers who became associated with anti-psychiatry as a phenomenon (Tietze, 2011). Erving Goffman One of the earliest influences on anti-psychiatry was the work of American functionalist sociologist Erving Goffman, in particular with his books Asylum (1961) and Stigma (1963). Goffman employed an ethnographic approach to his study of psychiatric hospitals, coming to the conclusion that they were a type of ‘total institution’ in which brutal and ineffective treatments had a tendency to render patients ‘dull and inconspicuous’. However, Sedgwick noted, this apparently devastating critique of mental healthcare was undercut by the deeply conservative substance of Goffman’s theoretical stance, in which resistance to the social structures that oppressed people was little more than part of the way those structures reproduced themselves intact. 105 Tad Tietze Sedgwick reasoned: Goffman has no room for sense of the historical contingencies of social institutions. This deficiency makes it absolutely impossible for him to use his insights, either into particular local ‘settings’ or into the general quality of everyday life, in any way which is critical: which issues, i.e., a demand for change in a definite direction. (Sedgwick, 1974a: 38, emphasis in original) Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press Further, Goffman’s attention to micro systems of social interaction led him to a kind of ‘methodological localism’ that could not grasp the emergence of these specific interactions from broader social relations and conflicts. This meant that he accepted at face value various norms that were dominant in society in the United States in the post-war era, and therefore saw phenomena such as mistreatment of mentally ill people and stigma as merely the result of their deviancy from those norms. R.D. Laing Sedgwick’s approach to the Scottish psychiatrist and psychotherapist R.D. Laing – probably the most celebrated figure in anti-psychiatry – was quite different. This was in part because his subject’s oeuvre was marked by its frequent shifts in focus and theoretical position: ‘The texts of his works are like the old Egyptian palimpsests, manuscripts with the first draft rubbed away and, while still partly visible, written over by another scribe – in this case Laing himself in a different ideological phase’ (Sedgwick, 1982: 69). It was Laing’s ability to hold a multitude of quite dissonant critiques in tension that led many of those attracted to his ideas to see him as being especially committed to their own particular preoccupations. Thus, he could be republished uncritically in the Marxist journal New Left Review (Laing, 1962, 1964a, 1964b) at the same time as being seen as a guru of meditation. In The divided self (1960), Laing drew on a study of psychotic patients he cared for in Glasgow to declare that what others saw as symptoms and signs were in fact mental states and behaviours that had understandable personal meaning when seen in context. This relentless focus on individual experience soon made way for a concern with family systems, first emerging in his revisions to the manuscript for The self and others (Laing, 1961) that occurred in the light of working with families at the Tavistock Clinic in London, as well as a deep engagement with Jean-Paul Sartre’s existentialism. Laing argued that schizophrenia was the product of impossible ‘binds’ in which individuals were put by their families, to which the only rational response was descent into madness. Sedgwick noted that a lack of normal controls in his studies made it unclear whether Laing was tackling communication problems specific to ‘schizophrenogenic’ families or generally present in all families. But before such issues could be clarified, Laing was already moving back to the realm of individual experience in the mid-1960s, seeing psychosis as a ‘hyper-sane’ state of healing from psychic injury. This dovetailed with running the therapeutic community Kingsley Hall and was perhaps most fully summarised in The politics of experience (Laing, 1967). This represented a descent into mysticism that was, paradoxically, tied up with the period of Laing’s most openly anti-capitalist commitment. For Sedgwick the paradox is explicable in how Laing’s 106 Peter Sedgwick: mental health as radical politics Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press critique of a ‘crazy’ society leads there to be no social yardstick by which to judge the greater validity of ‘normal’ or ‘psychotic’ experiences. In the early 1970s, the Scotsman turned sharply ‘towards the criteria of everyday commonsense in his approach to drugs, the family and mental illness’, thereby creating the circumstances in which ‘the critic of Laing is now, indeed, faced with the task of defending those elements of his work which their author now wishes to repudiate or at least downgrade’ – especially his ability to undermine the ideologically loaded categories that informed the turn to a more mechanistic and biologically reductionist mainstream approach to mental disorder in the late 1970s (Sedgwick, 1982: 110). The thinness of the radicalism was unsurprising because: the main contention of Marx that ‘social being’ determines ‘social consciousness’ was never accepted by Laing: if anything, ‘social being’, the presence of structures of social organization which can be at odds with the consciousness of the individuals comprising these structures, is dismissed by Laing and his followers as the outcome of a plurality of ‘praxes’ or individualsubjective projects. (Sedgwick, 1982: 113-4) Thomas Szasz The Hungarian-born American psychiatrist, Thomas Szasz, meanwhile, took aim at the core pretensions of his own profession and its very raison d’être. His most celebrated work was an essay entitled ‘The myth of mental illness’ (Szasz, 1960), later republished as part of a book of the same name (Szasz, 1961). For Szasz, mental illness was a ‘myth’ because, unlike physical illness, there were no ‘anatomical and genetic’ contexts to judge someone ill, only ‘social and ethical’ ones. In this schema, physical medicine was counterposed to psychiatry by being focused on the discovery of a pathological ‘lesion’ requiring medical intervention, which psychiatry, by definition, lacked. Sedgwick pointed out that, in the original edition of The myth of mental illness, Szasz (1961) only attacks the ‘organicist’ faction of his profession, and even then mainly to put forward his preferred views on human behaviour, individual responsibility, and the benefits of private psychoanalysis. Yet in his later work, such as The manufacture of madness (Szasz, 1970), he posited a radical opposition between two types of psychiatry: The totalitarian pole is termed ‘Institutional Psychiatry’; it is characterised by involuntary incarceration in mental hospitals, the use of psychiatric concepts for the extralegal punishment of deviants, and the state’s investiture of publicly employed physicians as agents of social order rather than of their patients’ welfare. The opposite, benevolent extreme is offered in Contractual Psychiatry: an arrangement founded on an informed consensus between two freely choosing individuals, one a therapist and the other a client, the former providing a service in the unraveling of certain moral problems and the latter, in return, a monetary fee. (Sedgwick, 1982: 152) Sedgwick was scathing of Szasz’ critique at two levels. First, there was the unreal picture that Szasz painted of bodily medicine in order to sustain his extreme view of what defines its object of intervention. This fantasy was necessary to Szasz so that he could brush over the real-life complexities of institutional psychiatry, which even 107 Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press Tad Tietze in the least sympathetic assessment does not conform to his one-sided description of it, and which closely parallels the institutions and activities of physical healthcare. Second, he punctured Szasz’ right-wing libertarian view of market transactions as the apogee of therapeutic benevolence. Not only does the rejection of institutional psychiatry leave no place for a whole range of patients with a multitude of problems unable to afford to pay the cost of Szasz’ preferred model of care, but in many cases their mental infirmities would render them unable to enter into such exchanges as the informed equals that Szasz demands they must be. Finally, the shoehorning of all psychiatric care into the psychoanalytic model of the regular ‘hour’ of therapy makes little sense to many people’s problems. Szasz never faced up to the immense inequalities of power inherent in his preferred psychoanalytic encounter, nor the very real problems of psychotherapeutic coercion and exploitation, which have been a source of repeated scandal. Finally, Szasz’ hard-line rejection of ‘collectivism’ – dressed up in the form a rejection of ‘statism’ – denied the irreducibly social nature of health and illness, and evaded how society (as opposed to individuals) might do things differently in favour of a narrowly market-juridical schema. Michel Foucault A preoccupation with how society shapes both mental illness and responses to it did lie at the heart of French philosopher Michel Foucault’s (1961) pioneering work Folie et déraison: Histoire de la folie à l’âge classique (translated and abridged as Madness & civilisation; Foucault, 1965). For Foucault, concepts of mental health and illness were purely sociohistorical constructs that shifted and changed over time but always played a role in upholding existing power relations. In this view, the asylum and the analyst’s couch were equally parts of systems of repression and control, which Foucault later went on to explore in a variety of other social settings. While Sedgwick praised Foucault’s critique of existing liberal histories of psychiatry – which tended to see each new technical advance as bringing the field ever closer to perfection – he was less convinced by the coherence and validity of Foucault’s identification of ‘reason’ as the central driver of psychiatric advance. Madness & civilisation is replete with historical detail, yet it remains poorly grounded in material social facts in order to maintain its ‘overwhelming concern with the logic of “classical” (i.e. seventeenth-century) diagnosis’ (Sedgwick, 1982: 140). Because he needs to make the case for a ‘timeless bourgeois rationality which seeks the control of rebellious Unreason quite outside the complex of social contradictions characteristic of different periods’, Foucault misses minority psychiatric movements that contradict his central narrative, as well as being unable to acknowledge what might (ironically) be termed regressions to less mechanistic and more humanistic forms of treatment (Sedgwick, 1982: 142). In effect, the French thinker proposes a kind of anti-Whig history, ending up with ‘anti-psychiatric romanticism’ that celebrates madness as a genuine but always defeated enemy of irrational reason (Sedgwick, 1982: 147). The social construction of health and illness Underpinning such critiques was Sedgwick’s commitment to constructing a rigorous critical approach to mental health and illness based in close engagement with the 108 Peter Sedgwick: mental health as radical politics revolutionary theory of Karl Marx. He laid out the basic shape of this method in an article entitled ‘Mental illness is illness’ (Sedgwick, 1972a, emphasis in original), in which he argued that the anti-psychiatrists had made a great contribution in developing a ‘consistent and convergent tendency of opposition directed against positivist method in the study of abnormal human behaviour’. Sedgwick defined positivism as: Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press an approach towards the investigation of human pathology which, modelling itself upon antecedents which it believes to be characteristic of the natural sciences, (a) postulates a radical separation between ‘facts’ and ‘values’ (declaring only the former to be the subject-matter of the professional investigator) and (b) suppresses the interactive relationship between the investigator and the ‘facts’ on which he works. (Sedgwick, 1972a: 204) Yet for all their radical dissection of psychiatry’s claims about the nature of mental health and illness, ‘[i]t appears to me that none of [the critics] have begun by asking the question: What is illness? Only in the light of an answer to this question could we determine our answer to the question: Is mental illness really illness in the “medical” sense?’ (Sedgwick, 1972a: 196, emphasis in original). Further: The difference so forcefully argued by anti-psychiatric theorists, between the ‘biological norms’ to which physical medicine appeals and the ‘social norms’ which back up psychiatry, dissipates into nonsense as soon as we are brought to see that ‘the medical enterprise is from its inception value-loaded; it is not simply an applied biology, but a biology applied in accordance with the dictates of social interest. (Sedgwick, 1974a: 28) By broadening the scope of the entire inquiry, Sedgwick was following in the footsteps of the medical epidemiologist, René Dubos, who had explored how social and political change had historically produced the vast bulk of effective human responses to ill-health. Biotechnological medicine focused on individual treatment therefore formed merely a small (and not always successful) part of the overall story, yet one that had become pre-eminent in the modern industrial era (Dubos, 1959). By placing all of medicine (physical and psychological) in this context, Sedgwick could simultaneously blow apart the positivist claims of the biological psychiatrists and the shallow anti-positivism of the anti-psychiatrists. It may prove possible to reduce the distance between psychiatry and other streams of medicine … not by annexing psychopathology to the technical instrumentation of the natural sciences but by revealing the character of all illness and disease, health and treatment, as social constructions. (Sedgwick, 1972a: 210, emphasis in original) That is: ‘Outside the significances that we voluntarily attach to certain conditions, there are no illnesses or diseases in nature’ (Sedgwick, 1972a: 211, emphasis in original). Sedgwick provided a series of examples where analogous biological occurrences were differently categorised as illness or not depending on the social meaning ascribed to them. For example, a twig snapping off would not normally be considered a form of ‘illness’, while a human limb similarly broken would. Even within human society, 109 Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press Tad Tietze definitions of health and illness change over time: tooth decay was once considered normal yet now is seen as a disease process requiring both prevention and treatment. And various symptoms and physical signs depend on social context for the way they are defined: a man who finds himself increasingly weak and breathless on physical exertion is considered as ill when young, but simply ‘ageing’ when in his nineties. Thus, ‘all sickness is essentially deviancy’ from social norms, but of course only certain types of social deviancy are considered to be illness (Sedgwick, 1972a: 213). Sedgwick used these insights as part of arguing for the politicisation of medical goals. He wrote: ‘Mental illness, like mental health, is a fundamentally critical concept: or can be made into one provided that those who use it are prepared to place demands and pressures on the existing organisation of society’ (Sedgwick, 1972a: 222, emphasis in original). Such demands must not be limited to the reallocation of resources to overcome gross disparities in access to healthcare, but also they should posit what type of care would be needed. In a provocative review of Ken Loach’s film Family life, which rejected psychiatric treatment from a perspective aligned with Laing and David Cooper’s work, Sedgwick argued for ‘more and better mental hospitals, more and better doctors and nurses – at the expense of armaments and the profits of the rich’ (Sedgwick, 1972b). As Cresswell and Spandler (2009: 133, emphasis in original) contend, this goes beyond the bounds of narrow biotechnical conceptions of medical treatment: Sedgwick is pro-medicine precisely to the extent that he envisages a radically socialized medicine applicable equally to physical and mental health. Such examples of socialized medicine include, ‘[t]he insertion of windows into working-class houses’ and ‘the provision of a pure water supply and an efficient sewage disposal’. Sedgwick (1974b) was also sharply critical of how capitalism creates antagonism between medicine as legally inspired, contractual and individualistic on the one hand, and collectivist on the other. Writing in an era where the social provision of the post Second World War welfare state was starting to be unwound, he underlined the complicated double meaning of the word ‘collective’; that is, that due to collective struggles from below, and that provided by the state and its social agencies from above. As he addressed the Royal College of Psychiatrists, he presciently warned that the Thatcherite Right’s ‘libertarian’ critique of psychiatric authority was a way of breaking down collective provision without challenging the repressive authority of the state itself (Sedgwick, 1983). In the closing sections of Psychopolitics, Sedgwick (1982) reviewed the changing face of mental healthcare, considering these shifts in their national contexts and with careful attention paid both to wider political-economic changes and the specific political currents within clinician and patient social groups. The task for the Left was to find ways to creatively bring together these diverse currents, which he saw as already present in embryo, but which the Left had too often been at best inept at working with let alone providing relevant help to. 110 Peter Sedgwick: mental health as radical politics Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press Criticisms of Sedgwick Psychopolitics made a considerable impact on discussions of the politics of mental health and illness. However, while aspects of Sedgwick’s argument were often acknowledged and even appropriated (eg, Klerman, 1977), and continue to appear in influential critical psychiatry writings (eg, Greenberg, 2010, 2013), there have also been criticisms of his overall position. One objection to Sedgwick’s ‘terrible’ idea that all health and illness is socially constructed is that it ‘confuses the idea that we value something with the idea that our explanation of how it works is evaluative’ (Murphy, 2006: 83-4). Such a view falls prey to exactly the positivism that Sedgwick criticised more broadly – that the activity of science in elucidating how processes in nature work can be separated from the normative presumptions that lead scientists to inquire into these processes and then shape the methods of inquiry employed. A more sophisticated charge has been made by Wakefield (1992), whose influential ‘harmful dysfunction’ analysis of mental disorders treats these as existing ‘on the boundary between biological facts and social values’. Wakefield contends that ‘the fact that all disorders are undesirable and harmful according to social values shows only that values are part of the concept of disorder, not that disorder is composed only of values’. He argues that Sedgwick provides no consistent guide as to how to differentiate (health) disorders from other forms of social deviancy, and that this results in his being unable to critically analyse ‘incorrect diagnoses’ such as the historic labelling of runaway slaves and Soviet dissidents with mental illness. In addition, situations where there is an ongoing dispute about the disorder status of a particular problem (eg, attention deficit hyperactivity disorder [ADHD] or alcoholism), ‘[t]he complex factual arguments presented by both sides in these debates clearly indicate that judgments about disorder depend on much more than values’ (Wakefield, 1992: 375-7). Yet Sedgwick did not dismiss the facts presented in favour or against whether something is considered to fall within the health-illness spectrum and whether it represents disorder. Rather, as a historical materialist, he saw ‘facts’ as indissolubly bound up with the human social practices in which they were apprehended and ‘discovered’. He was making an ontological point: that human conceptions and the material reality they described were not the same thing. Thus, arguments about the ‘medical’ status of some social problem – or even if it is a ‘problem’ at all – can only be understood in a historically grounded appreciation of the society in which such debates occur. Sedgwick wrote of such definitions emerging because of the human interests they serve – but he also dissected the complex and often antagonistic ensemble of social interests that operate in any particular historical epoch. The implicit charge of relativism levelled at Sedgwick therefore does not apply. Unlike even an erudite analyst like Peter Conrad, whose accounts of medicalisation detail the competing social interests influencing such processes but refrain from making judgements about whether medicalisation is valid in each case (Conrad, 2008), Sedgwick based his judgements in an immanent critique of existing society. Except, perhaps, for his brief dalliance with a Kropotkin-influenced view of alternative healthcare systems at the end of Psychopolitics, his judgements are grounded in the impossibility of drawing up blueprints for healthcare in an idealised future social order. This does not restrain him from making judgements about, say, the extreme individual libertarian views of 111 Tad Tietze Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press someone like Szasz, on the basis that beneath the arguments lie determinate social interests, expressing themselves as absolute principles or objective facts when in fact they cannot be separated from the historically specific social purposes they reflect at the level of ideas, whether or not such mediations are consciously understood by those making them. In the end, Wakefield’s goal of a methodology that can come to objective conclusions about what is or is not a mental disorder cannot be satisfied precisely because he wrongly presumes that the answer can be judged independent of such interests. While standing against positivism at one level, Wakefield invites it back in at another. A very different kind of complaint comes from Cresswell and Spandler (2009), perhaps the key inheritors of Sedgwick’s psychopolitical approach, who argue that more recent struggles by psychiatric service users against the validity of ‘illness’ attribution undermine Sedgwick’s unitary, anti-dualistic conception of illness. In particular, they point to movements of people who self-harm and hear voices, and their struggle to de-medicalise their ‘symptoms’: The mobilization of such groups has revolved around the discursive ensemble ‘trauma/abuse/distress’ rather than the Sedgwickian ensemble ‘illness/ disease’. Such frameworks attest to the importance of personal histories of trauma and abuse, as well as iatrogenic degradations experienced within the mental health system itself. (Cresswell and Spandler, 2009: 138) This misses how Sedgwick explained why it is that ‘however illness is specified from culture to culture, the attribution of illness appears to include a quest for explanation’ and how illness arises historically alongside practice of treatment and is indissolubly tied up with it (Sedgwick, 1972a: 216). Even if illness is reframed as ‘trauma/abuse/distress’, as long as individuals seek to address their suffering through engagement with some kind of treatment process, the shift entailed in the renaming of their problems is at most a move away from dominant biotechnological medical paradigms to other healing paradigms, each with their own explanatory frameworks and treatment practices. Their critical rejection of mainstream psychiatry’s illness claims is thus coupled to uncritical belief that a terminological change breaks beyond socially constituted conceptions of health and illness in general. Cresswell and Spandler also argue that Sedgwick’s critique of Szasz elides how physical medicine and psychiatry are qualitatively different because determinations of health and illness are directly bound up with the state-sanctioned, coercive imposition of treatment in psychiatry. Yet this is unsustainable on two grounds. First, much of psychiatric practice has for decades expanded well outside the narrow remit of lockedward practice, with no clear boundaries between these realms. Second, their claim does not acknowledge the wide range of coercive practices in physical medicine, which Sedgwick already alluded to. From the impossibility of ‘informed consent’ when there are large asymmetries of knowledge and power between doctors and patients, to the informally non-consensual treatment of severely ill patients in emergency and acute medical settings, to the use of various legal instruments such as ‘guardianship’ orders to impose treatment and control on patients found to lack decision-making ‘capacity’, the individual freedom of patients being treated by physicians and surgeons is often only apparent and partial. The strength of Sedgwick’s critique is that he historicises these issues and forces us to think about the problems with modern healthcare in 112 Peter Sedgwick: mental health as radical politics general, and the society that spawns it, rather than a focus on the problems of the mental health field in isolation. Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press The DSM-5 and ‘the bereavement exclusion’ in Sedgwickian perspective The richness of Sedgwick’s contribution to the politics of mental health means that his work can be creatively applied to a wide variety of modern developments and issues, both strictly within disciplines of healthcare and in relation to wider social action. To conclude with one prominent example, while his work only hinted at the increasing centrality of diagnosis to the legitimacy of mainstream psychiatry, Sedgwick’s theoretical innovations provide a powerful framework for understanding controversies surrounding the recently released psychiatric ‘diagnostic bible’, the Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: 5th edition (DSM-5), published by the American Psychiatric Association – and for strategically orienting radical political projects in relation to such struggles over the boundaries of normality. (For other applications of Sedgwick’s ideas, see Spandler, 2007; Cresswell and Spandler, 2009; Tietze, 2011, 2014.) The revision of the DSM was initiated in 2002, with hopes that psychiatric diagnosis could move beyond the ‘atheoretical’, descriptive approach codified in the DSM-III (1980). Its protagonists naively imagined that advances in neuroscience would be robust enough to underpin diagnosis based on brain biology. As the revision process progressed, concern grew about the project’s lack of transparency, ties between the pharmaceutical industry and leading DSM participants, and the likelihood that the revision would broaden criteria to medicalise ever-more normal human traits. When the psychiatrist who had helmed DSM-IV, Allen Frances, broke ranks with his former colleagues and waged a public campaign against the ‘diagnostic inflation’ of DSM-5, he gave confidence to a wide range of patients, clinicians and professional groups to speak out against the manual (Frances, 2013). One of the especially contentious changes was the removal of the ‘bereavement exclusion’ from the diagnosis of major depressive disorder (MDD). Analysis, by members of the DSM-5 mood disorders workgroup, of scientific studies comparing episodes of MDD with episodes of low mood associated with the loss of a loved one indicated that there were no essential differences between the two presentations apart from the presence or absence of grief. That is, normal grief often met MDD criteria of five symptoms over more than two weeks. Once the proposal was publicised it became the subject of sharp criticism in the public sphere. Defending the proposed change, workgroup member Dr Stanley Zisook told The New York Times: ‘Depression can and does occur in the wake of bereavement, it can be severe and debilitating, and calling it by any other name is doing a disservice to people who may require more careful attention.’ In the same article, Wakefield countered that ‘[t]his would pathologize [millions of Americans each year] for behavior previously thought to be normal’ (Carey, 2012). Wakefield co-authored a scathing critique of the scientific papers the DSM-5 experts had been using to defend the proposed change (Wakefield and First, 2012). Lending its authority to the criticism, the leading medical journal The Lancet (2012: 589) would later editorialise that ‘grief is not an illness; it is more usefully thought of as part of being human and a normal response to death of a loved one’. One group of critics took the arguments to their 113 Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press Tad Tietze logical conclusion and stated that misery should be ‘de-medicalised’ and that ‘what are, frequently, essentially moral and political – not medical – matters [must be put] back at the centre of our understanding of human suffering’ (Rapley et al, 2011: 5, emphasis in original). Despite the controversy, however, the bereavement exclusion was ultimately removed in the DSM-5. An analysis of the dispute based in Sedgwick’s approach would have elucidated the social forces and interests at play: from pharmaceutical companies, psychiatrists and providers of psychological therapies seeking to expand their potential consumer base, to clinicians, patients, carers and employers wanting quick resolution of distressing symptoms, to clinicians and large sections of the public concerned that a normal process of grief would now be pathologised and treated as abnormal. It would note the institutional reasons for the American Psychiatric Association to press ahead with a new edition of its manual despite the lack of significant scientific advance to justify it, in particular the need for publishing royalties to prop up a professional body with declining membership and less access to industry sponsorship in the wake of scandals involving drug company payments to leading academic psychiatrists (Frances, 2013). Yet this would also warn against a simple rejection of the medicalisation of bereavement. As Sedgwick himself argued regarding previous debates on the issue: The example [of a bereavement causing symptoms] is revealing in several ways. A doctor may prescribe some form of minor tranquilliser to relieve some of the effects of a bereavement, even though depression of activity and feeling following the death of a close relative would scarcely be regarded as constituting a ‘mental illness’. Bereavement has, however, also been reported as a significant precipitating event in the onset of actual psychiatric illnesses.… The line of division between a ‘bereavement’ and a ‘psychiatric illness following bereavement’ would seem to depend on our culturallyderived expectations about how to mourn properly. (Sedgwick, 1974a: 33fn) For Sedgwick, an ever-present danger was the rejection of all ‘medical’ treatment of distress when the cause of such distress did not conform to the narrow biotechnical determinism that dominates medicine in late capitalism. The solution to the failures and contradictions of modern mental healthcare was neither to deny the illnessness of illness (ie, to ‘de-medicalise’ it), nor to technologise it further. Contra those who worry that the psychiatric relief of distress provides ‘analgesia at the expense of understanding’ (Jureidini, 2012: 190), Sedgwick argued: I myself am perfectly happy to see as many mentally-ill persons as possible treated, fully and effectively, in this society; for no matter how many maladjustments may become adjusted through expert techniques, the workings of capitalism will ever create newer and larger discontents, infinitely more dangerous to the system than any number of individual neuroses or manias. (Sedgwick, 1972a: 224) The politicisation of medical goals was for Sedgwick, therefore, a profoundly humanist orientation, one that demanded the greatest possible care for the suffering individual, indissolubly tied to a profoundly critical social practice. As the capitalist mode of production delivers social destruction worse than at any time since the 114 Peter Sedgwick: mental health as radical politics Great Depression, with healthcare facing devastating cuts while capitalist rationalities in medicine push technological rather than social remedies for people’s suffering, Sedgwick’s legacy is one worth preserving and extending in order to strengthen real-life political struggles over the future of health and illness. Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press Note 1 This article draws in part on Tietze, 2013, which was delivered as part of a panel on ‘Peter Sedgwick’s legacy: politics, psychiatry & freedom’. It has also been inspired by the contributions of my fellow panelists Ian Birchall, Mick McKeown and Richard Kuper. I would also like to thank Helen Spandler and Elizabeth Humphrys. References Birchall, I, 2011, Tony Cliff: A Marxist for his time, London: Bookmarks Carey, B, 2012, Grief could join list of disorders, The New York Times, 24 January, www.nytimes.com/2012/01/25/health/depressions-criteria-may-be-changed-toinclude-grieving.html Conrad, P, 2008, The medicalization of society: On the transformation of human conditions into treatable disorders, Baltimore, MA: Johns Hopkins University Press Cresswell, M, Spandler, H, 2009, Psychopolitics: Peter Sedgwick’s legacy for the politics of mental health, Social Theory & Health, 7, 129-47 Dubos, R, 1959, Mirage of health: Utopias, progress, and biological change, New York, NY: Harper & Row Foucault, M, 1961, Folie et déraison: Histoire de la folie à l’âge classique, Paris: Plon Foucault, M, 1965, Madness & civilization, New York, NY: Pantheon Frances, A, 2013, The new crisis of confidence in psychiatric diagnosis, Annals of Internal Medicine, 159, 3, 221-23 Goffman, E, 1961, Asylums, New York, NY: Doubleday Goffman, E, 1963, Stigma: Notes on the management of spoiled identity, Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall Greenberg, G, 2010, Manufacturing depression: The secret history of a modern disease, New York, NY: Simon & Schuster Greenberg, G, 2013, The book of woe: The DSM and the unmaking of psychiatry, New York, NY: Blue Rider Press (Penguin) Jureidini, J, 2012, Explanations and unexplanations: restoring meaning to psychiatry, Australian & New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry, 46, 3, 188-91 Klerman, G, 1977, Mental illness, the medical model, and psychiatry, The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 2, 3, 220-43 Kuper, R, 2013, Peter Sedgwick – introduction, paper presented at the conference ‘Historical Materialism, 10th Annual Conference’, 10 November Laing, RD, 1960, The divided self, London: Tavistock Publications Laing, RD, 1961, The self and others: Further studies in sanity and madness, London: Tavistock Publications Laing, RD, 1962, Series and nexus in the family, New Left Review, I, 15, 7-14 Laing, RD, 1964a, One-dimensional man, New Left Review, I, 26, 78-80 Laing, RD, 1964b, What is schizophrenia?, New Left Review, I, 28, 63-8 Laing, RD, 1967, The politics of experience, New York, NY: Ballantine Lukes, S, 1983, Obituary, New Statesman, 16 September, www.petersedgwick.org/ articles/biographical/NewStatesmanObituary.html 115 Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press Tad Tietze Marcuse, H, 1964, One-dimensional man: Studies in the ideology of advanced industrial society, Boston, MA: Beacon Press Mitchell, S, 2004, Oxford: Communist Party, www.petersedgwick.org/articles/ biographical/StanleyMitchell.html Murphy, D, 2006, Psychiatry in the scientific image, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press Rapley, M, Moncrieff, J, Dillon, J, 2011, Carving nature at its joints? DSM and the medicalization of everyday life, in M. Rapley, J. Moncrieff and J. Dillon (eds) Demedicalizing misery: Psychiatry, psychology and the human condition, London: Palgrave Macmillan Sedgwick, P, 1966, Natural science and human theory: a critique of Herbert Marcuse, Socialist Register, 3, 3, 163-92 Sedgwick, P, 1972a, Mental illness is illness, Salmagundi, 196-224 Sedgwick, P, 1972b, Who’s mad – you or the system?, Socialist Worker, 5 February, https://www.marxists.org/archive/sedgwick/1972/02/family.htm Sedgwick, P, 1974a, Goffman’s anti-psychiatry, Salmagundi, 26-51 Sedgwick, P, 1974b, Medical individualism, Studies – Hastings Center, 2, 3, 69 Sedgwick, P, 1976, The SWP fraud, Socialist Workers Party Bulletin, 1, http://marxists. org/archive/sedgwick/1976/12/fraud.htm Sedgwick, P, 1982, Psychopolitics, London: Pluto Press. Sedgwick, P, 1983, The fate of psychiatry in the new populism, Psychiatric Bulletin, 7, 2, 22-5 Sedgwick, P, 1984, The unhappy elitist: Victor Serge’s early Bolshevism, History Workshop Journal, 17, 1, 150-6 Serge, V, 1963, Memoirs of a revolutionary, 1901-1941, London: Oxford University Press Serge V, 1972, Year one of the Russian Revolution, London: Allen Lane Serge, V, 1981, Midnight in the century, London: Writers and Readers Publishing Cooperative Spandler, H, 2007, From social exclusion to inclusion? A critique of the inclusion imperative in mental health, Medical Sociology online, 2, 2, 3-16 Szasz, TS, 1960, The myth of mental illness, American Psychologist, 15, 2, 113-18 Szasz, TS, 1961, The myth of mental illness: Foundations of a theory of personal conduct, New York, NY: Hoeber-Harper Szasz, TS, 1970, The manufacture of madness, New York, NY: Harper & Row The Lancet, 2012, Living with grief, The Lancet, 379, 9816, 589 Tietze, T, 2011, Demanding ‘more and better’ psychiatry: potentially liberatory or worse than the disease?, paper presented at the conference ‘Alternative Futures & Popular Protest, 16th International Conference’, Manchester, 18-20 April, https://www.academia.edu/543824/Demanding_more_and_better_psychiatry_ Potentially_liberatory_or_worse_than_the_disease Tietze, T, 2013, ‘Neither psychiatry nor anti-psychiatry, but mental health as radical politics’, paper presented at the conference ‘Historical Materialism Tenth Annual Conference, Making the World Working Class’, London, 7-10 November Tietze, T, 2014, The Breivik controversy: politics, terrorism and psychiatry, Australasian Psychiatry, 22, 4, 383-5 Wakefield, J, 1992, The concept of mental disorder: on the boundary between biological facts and social values, American Psychologist, 47, 3, 373-88 116 Peter Sedgwick: mental health as radical politics Delivered by Ingenta to: Liverpool Hope University College IP : 194.81.33.118 On: Thu, 09 Apr 2015 14:56:43 Copyright The Policy Press Wakefield, JC, First, MB, 2012, Validity of the bereavement exclusion to major depression: does the empirical evidence support the proposal to eliminate the exclusion in DSM-5?, World Psychiatry, 11, 3-10 117