* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download The heritage of german idealism in Kierkeggard`s Either/Or
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
The heritage of German idealism in Kierkegaard’s Either/Or by Kresten Lundsgaard-Leth I. Preliminary remarks Søren Kierkegaard’s authorship is often considered the critique par excellence of the German idealism in general and its systematic-speculative version with Hegel’s philosophy in particular – and this reputation is by no means entirely unfounded. Nonetheless, it remains an interpretive task to investigate, how and why the Kierkegaardian alternative articulates itself. Is the Christian leap of faith (qua »the highest paradox of thinking«) nothing but a theological (or existential) polemic against idealism through idealism-external criteria? Or could it be that Kierkegaard’s thought (in a very certain way) actualizes the dissolution of German idealism itself by means of idealism-internal criteria? This question is obviously a delicate matter. Still, through a careful reading of Kierkegaard’s early magnum opus, Either-Or from 1841, I suggest the following thesis: The critique of idealism in Kierkegaard’s authorship actually comes into being through a tense unity of diverse, idealistic motives, which mutually exclude each other. Thus, the influence(s) of Kant, Fichte and Hegel are all of them present in the investigations of Either/Or - as well as the apparent tension between their philosophical key-concepts. Negatively, the description (or diagnosis) of the aesthetical point of view in its various modes draws on the Kantian notion of heteronomy as well as the Hegelian polemic against the irony of romanticism. Positively (and probably more important) the ethical position of Wilhelm is presented as a conspicuous mixture of idealistic thought-figures: Firstly, (i) Kant’s accentuation of the importance of the motive (rather than the consequence) founds the normative intuition of the ethical letters. Secondly, (ii) Fichte’s depiction of faith (as articulated in Die Bestimmung des Menschen (1800)) inspires, how the ethical motive (i. e. the choice) must be understood. And finally, (iii) the immanent-dynamical dialectics of Hegelian spirit determines – so to speak – the content (or the what) of the ethical choice – as will be shown. And as already mentioned, this complexity of transcendental, subjective and absolute idealism cannot be coherently conjoined within one single position. There may have been biographical circumstances in the mix, but the idealistic tension of Kierkegaardian ethics is, philosophically, the primary explanation for the necessary move towards religion. II. The immediate aesthetical as Kantian heteronomy Roughly, the aesthetical stage in Kierkegaardian thought must be divided in (at least) two versions of aesthetical consciousness: Firstly (i), the immediate aesthetical consciousness lacking awareness of itself as aesthetical and therefore without aesthetical self-consciousness. Secondly, (ii) the highly self-conscious point of view of A (the supposed author of the first volume of Either/Or) could be described as an aesthetic-subjectivist irony. It is fundamentally valid for both positions that – in Wilhelm’s expression – »the aesthetical in a man is that by means of which he immediately is, what he is«; but in a rather dissimilar fashion – as we shall have a closer look at. To begin with, let us consider the first aesthetical stage: In Wilhelm’s formulation, every aesthete believes that »one should enjoy life […] but he [i. e. the aesthete] always makes a condition, which is either outside of the individual or in the individual in such a way that it is not made by the individual himself«. It is easily comprehended, following some of Wilhelm’s examples, in what sense phenomena such as wealth, fame or everlasting love are conditions of enjoyment external to the individual him- or herself. But for what reason do not – in Wilhelm’s opinion - talent and the ambition of personal beauty qualify as conditions made by the individual him- or herself? Here, the etymological origin of aesthetics in the Greek expression for sensation (i. e. aisthesis) has a significant role to play: Exemplified, it may be the individual him- or herself who is beautiful or have an inclination towards x (e. g. a cookie) but, as immediate facts of sensation, both of these can immediately change – into ugliness (after a car-crash, for instance) and the inclination towards not-x or y, respectively. In this sense, the sensually conditioned happens to us »in such a way that is not made by the individual himself«. We cannot freely choose it – only take note of its factuality as it comes over us. The determination of the sensually conditioned – and sensual inclinations in particular – as not being a part of the individual’s genuine self clearly draws on the Kantian distinction between heteronomy and autonomy as presented in The Foundation for the Metaphysic of Morals (1785). As it would be well known, these Kantian terms are intimately related to the concept of the will. The will determined through heteronomy is enthused through sensual inclination (and eo ipso non-moral), whereas the autonomous as well as moral will constitutes its own end. Negatively, Kantian morality must be considered as freedom from sensual heteronomy and the conception of heteronomy as an alien (or self-external) determination of the will arguably provides the framework for the aesthetical stage in Either/Or qua conditioned by something »which is either outside of the individual or in the individual in such a way that it is not made by the individual himself«. For both Kant and Wilhelm, the ethical and moral freedom, respectively, implies a suspension of the necessity of natural causality. Positively, on the contrary, the story is quite another. The moral will in Kantian morality is free to the practical selfdetermination of reason (acting upon the ends made by reason itself), which has very little to do indeed with the passionate ethical choice suggested by Wilhelm. Both of them, still, are more concerned with how we act as opposed to what we actually do when acting – which will be addressed later on. III. Wilhelm’s critique of A’s aesthetics as Hegelian criticism of romanticism So far, let us get back to the aesthetical stage, which is not exhausted with the immediate aesthetical consciousness and which (therefore) cannot be contained within the framework of Kant’s distinction between autonomy and heteronomy. Thus, the much more sophisticated and reflective aesthetical point of view – as articulated by A in the first volume of Either/Or – cannot be comprehended as an immediate consciousness following sensual inclination. More likely, it is a mode of romantic irony, the critique of which draws on Hegel’s judgment towards this exact movement (i. e. romantic irony) in contemporary intellectual history. Between the lines, this attack on the ironical aesthete implies a critique of Kantian morality – as we shall see. Wilhelm depicts (and addresses) A in the following manner: »There is not actual despair, but despair in thought. Your thought has hastened ahead, you have seen through the vanity of everything but you have not moved on […]. You are constantly beside yourself, namely, in despair«. Thus, A has seen through the vanity and perishable nature of the aesthetical stage itself (in Danish these two words, forfængelighed and forgængelighed, sound very much alike). As we already know, the conditions of enjoying one’s life are sensually conditioned and not in the individual’s power – and to truly realize this equals to despair – or with an utterly famous depiction: The aesthete is always already in despair, whether he (or her) knows it or not. Having realized this, he does not participate in his own existence – but has become a mere spectator (or voyeur) of it. But what sense does it make (what regards A’s reflective despair) that – as was initially stated »the aesthetical in a man is that by means of which he immediately is, what he is«? In a way, it does not make sense. A has once and for all invalidated the vanity of aesthetical existence and negated all value founded on sensual conditions. In this self-reflective negativity, however, A remains dependent on the very thing he negates (namely the perishable nature of everything immediate). In what way? Well, because he has no positive alternative to put forth. He can see through the untenable heteronomy of aesthetical value but is totally incapable of presenting a sound substitute, wherefore radical negativity must be the inevitable outcome. There are apparent common features between Wilhelm’s depiction of A’s aesthetical despair and Hegel’s description of romantic irony. In Hegel’s Philosophy of Right (1821), irony is presented as nothing less than the highest form of evil. Irony, according to Hegel, actualizes the annihilation of everything objectively normative, which it replaces with the artistic creation of subjective norms. Like J.-P. Sartre will accordingly suggest in the twentieth century, it is a self-deceiving illusion to believe in the objectivity of normative validity. Thus, values are analogous to works of art rather than to the categorical dictates of reason. Interestingly, Hegel argues that the romantic irony is essentially the ultimate consequence of Kantian autonomy with its appeal to what the human subject can will (qua reasonable) should become a universal law. The problem is – in Hegel’s opinion – the following: When nothing is left other than subjectivity to appeal to, the apparent moral agent will not only see through the perishable nature of sensation – but furthermore the abstract emptiness of Kantian morality. Thus, purely subjective validity equals no validity whatsoever, as both Hegel and A have apparently recognized. As an immanent critique of Kantian moral philosophy, Hegel’s objection probably will not hold water. However, this consideration will be bracketed in the following. What is of importance here is the concluding ironic-aesthetical nihilism of the romantic irony as well as A. Both positions are ambivalently torn (or dispersed) between the excessive creation of interesting states of affairs, on the one hand, and always already to have seen through the emptiness of this design, on the other. As we have witnessed, Wilhelm’s diagnosis of the aesthetical stage in toto is thoroughly encouraged through motives of German idealism (namely Kant’s distinction between heteronomy and autonomy and Hegel’s polemics towards romantic irony, respectively). Furthermore, and as a result of this, there is already an inherent tension to be found within the mentioned diagnosis. That is, the tension between the philosophies of Kant and Hegel. In the ethical alternative to aestheticism, which we will now take into consideration, the same tension and incommensurability becomes all the more obvious. IV. The Ethical choice as Hegelian dialectics In order to vanquish his nihilistic despair, Wilhelm tells A to choose himself ethically. To choose one self is intimately related to the concept of spirit. In the aesthetical stage (in both of its versions) the spirit is hysterical. Wherefore? Well, for reasons inherited from German idealism: As we have learned from The critique of pure reason as well as The Phenomenology of spirit, the spirit demands the absolute (or the unconditional), which by no means can ever be satisfied through sensual (and eo ipso finite) conditions. Just as the immediate aesthetical consciousness, A is negatively dependent on the finality of sensation, wherefore he has not exceeded the boundaries of immediate sensation (or finality) – but merely seen them through. Thus, the negative infinity of the ironical nihilism (and its accompanying despair) must be replaced by a positive infinity of the spirit, which has to go through to negative movement of despair in order to, positively, arrive at itself. But how? Well, it (i. e. the spirit) must return to finality and manifest itself concretely and positively herein. Furthermore, this movement is a twofold actualization: (i) It is an activity of the spirit (i. e. a performance performed by the spirit) and (ii) it is the actual realization (in the Aristotelian sense of actuality) of the spirit. The spirit must give up its immediate immediacy in an infinite negation (such as A’s despair) and return to an infinitely re-qualified version of immediacy (in the ethical choice). Only then is spirit really spirit – or in Wilhelm’s own formulation: »I posit the absolute and I am the absolute, but as totally identical with this I must say: I choose the absolute that chooses me and I posit the absolute that posits me […] It is the most abstract of all, which is also in itself the most concrete of all«. With a trivial example: My identity is not exhausted in my mere subjective possibilities as well as it not exhausted in any factual actuality (e. g. being a student of philosophy). The immediate aesthetical consciousness has confused its identity with just its sensual features (i. e. factual identity) whereas A has mistaken his negative reflection and unqualified possibility with himself. However, none of these positions are adequate: My identity is the dynamic-dialectical identity of the identity of identity and difference. But still, this is admittedly a highly formal characterization in – in terms of Hegelian dialectics – of the double-movement of the ethical choice. V. Fichte’s faith as how of the ethical choice contra Hegelian mediation Although there is an apparent structural analogy between the ethical choice and Hegelian dialectics, the specific how of Wilhelm’s choice is clearly inspired by Fichte’s concept of faith (as a matter of fact, we do know that Kierkegaard has been reading Die Bestimmung des Menschen). With Fichte, the »inner voice of conscience« articulates the demands of moral freedom as opposed to the natural mechanics of inclination. This delineation still seems rather Kantian - but there is an imperative and vital difference. In the Foundation for the Metaphysic of Morals a moral action is described as (i) subjectively motivated by respect for the moral law and (ii) objectively determined by the moral law itself. Practical reason – in Kantian morality - has to postulate a pure feeling – namely the respect – which can be motivated exclusively intelligibly. Otherwise, the normative ought of morality cannot be acted upon, in which case morality in toto would be absurd. Thus, respect is a practical conditio sine qua non for practical imperatives. This argument, however, arguably is either (i) begging the question (that what ought to be done actually can be done) or (ii) a terribly formal argument (and here, we cannot get into details). Fichte, on his side, apparently senses this difficulty when he proclaims how »I cannot think anything outside of my thought«. Ethical motivation must necessarily manifest itself in a factual reality outside the realm of pure thinking (or knowledge), wherefore it seems utterly insufficient for practical reason merely to postulate its own conditions of possibility (such as the moral agents capability of acting out of respect for the moral law). Morality is not simply a matter of coherent reasoning but must be actualized in the factual world. Otherwise, moral philosophy is no less abstract than romantic irony and we will have no reliable way of telling the difference between the creations of ironic reflection and the postulations of pure practical reasoning. The answer to this challenge, as Fichte puts it, is »not knowledge, but a decision of the will […]. All of my conviction is just faith and it originates from the character (or the disposition) – not from the understanding«. Thus, the freedom of the moral (or ethical) act is a matter of decision not the necessary self-legislation (i. e. autonomy) of reason. Admittedly, a thorough reading of Fichte’s relation to Kant would have to be way more nuanced. For now, however, we just wish to point out a genuine idealistic inspiration for Wilhelm’s concept of choice. Wilhelm’s formulations on the subject are in each case close to Fichte’s: Thus, the ethical realization of the spirit is not an activity of thought or contemplation, but a choice of the will. Although the Kantian notion of freedom means (as we just mentioned) a necessary selflegislation of practical reason, it is not necessary (in the eyes of Kant) - but only possible - that moral actions will actually be carried out. Human beings are namely very likely to act from heteronomous motives and inclinations, wherefore we (in this sense) can choose not to obey the necessary imperatives laid upon by practical reason. Following this line of argument, Wilhelm’s choice does not primarily oppose the Kantian conception of autonomy. Instead, it attacks the Hegelian notion of »Sittlichkeit«, the metaphysical radicalism of which by far outbids that of Kantian morality. For Hegel, not only the imperative demands of morality must imply necessity. The realization of freedom and morality is itself a necessary dialectical movement of the »Weltgeist« (i. e. the absolute spirit). »That which is reasonable is actual; and that which is actual is reasonable« - as Hegel puts it in his Philosophy of Right. As the core metaphysical principle of reality, the Hegelian spirit assures that the factual reality will actualize the abstract reason; thereby – by means of this institutional concretization - realizing reason itself (very much like the dialectical structure of the ethical choice). Thus, true reality (and freedom) is a dynamical synthesis (or mediation) of »the concept and its realization«. In practical philosophy, the state is such a reasonable unity of concept and reality through which Hegel can dismiss the inherent dualism of Kant’s morality. Wilhelm furiously and consistently opposes this Hegelian framework – for instance in this concise passage: »If mediation is admitted, there is no absolute choice […]. [The] difficulty […] lies therein that one confuses two spheres with each other, that of thought and that of freedom […] in the logical, in nature [!] […] necessity rules, wherefore the mediation has its validity […] With history, on the other hand, there is a difficulty, because, as you say, here freedom rules«. Wilhelm – as well as Hegel – understands both movements dialectically. Nonetheless, he distinguishes rigidly between (i) the epistemological doubt as impetus in the necessary dialectics of logic on the one hand and the existential despair as the catalyst in the free dialectics of the ethical choice. Hegel, indeed, does not distinguish between the two – as a reading of the opening chapter of the Phenomenology of Spirit would reveal. In Wilhelm’s articulation: »Doubt is the despair of thought, despair is the doubt of personality«. Despair is existentially involved (something is at stake) – whereas doubt is an indifferent epistemological mode of thought. And it is only what concerns the existential despair that the either/or of the book title finds it application. Either A will choose himself in his despair (taking over his factual existence in freedom) – or he will not. Tertium non datur. No mediation is possible here. VI. Kant versus Hegel: The motive or the what of the ethical choice? As we have seen, Fichte’s concept of faith has inspired the how of the ethical choice thereby trumping Kantian autonomy and Hegelian mediation. Nonetheless, the basic understanding of normativity on the whole draws on Kant’s deontological focus on the motive rather than consequences. With Wilhelm: It is not as much about »choosing what is right, as it is about the energy, the earnestness and pathos, with which one chooses«. This mixture of Kant and Fichte within the ethical stage of Either/Or has already been confused by the involvement of Hegelian dialectics in the existential sphere. And the eclecticism of Wilhelm goes even further: Thus, the content of the dialectical double-movement of the choice is a concretization and identification of abstract self-consciousness in its factual circumstances. In practice, the individual must realize the universal – as both Wilhelm and Hegel put it – and be able to re-identify itself with its actual profession (as carpenter or student of philosophy) without (as the immediate aesthetical consciousness) losing hold of itself (i. e. its self) in its factuality. Still, Wilhelm accuses Hegel of having confused the spheres of existential freedom and logical necessity. No mediation of absolute spirit can bring about the ethical choice, which will always have to be a concrete choice of a concrete individual (or in Danish: hin enkelte). VII. Rounding: The dissolution of the ethical position »If there must be mediation, then one could say that it is repentence, but repentence is not mediation […] and if I cannot repent the past then freedom is but a dream«. But what does this say. Well, in order to choose oneself freely one must repent oneself. To repent oneself is to be able to reidentify with an aesthetical facticity, which is more than oneself, indeed, which is ultimately the entire stock (or generation). Every individual is always already something actual (formed by its history and its predecessors), which must be taken over in a free choice. But does the idea of repentence as some sort of existential necessary condition for the ethical choice seem somewhat preposterous? Can anybody choose so much? The problem is – in my reading - that Wilhelm copies Hegel’s idea of a concrete realization of the moral will without accepting the metaphysical concept of the spirit, which would assure a necessary mediation between the reflective self and the positive reality. Thus, Wilhelm demands an objectification of morality solely by means of a decision of the subjective individual and this presents an exceedingly tense juxtaposition of Kantian autonomy, Fichtean faith and Hegelian »Sittlichkeit«. In Either/Or Wilhelm still presupposes that the ethical individual is up for the task; that he or her can »reconcile man with life«. Nonetheless, the following questions (just to mention a few) are already present between the lines: (i) how can subjective repentence contain the objective guilt of the stock? (ii) How can the individual ever choose something right here right now, if it must continually repent the past? How can I know, whether or not I have repented adequately or in the right way? Is this consideration not anxietyprovoking (to point to a later work of Kierkegaard)? Must we not presuppose a metaphysical »order of things« as a precondition for the meaningfulness of the ethical choice? As we know, Kierkegaard will ask those questions with full-blown radicalism in his later writings. He moves on to religion – in other words – but only (or philosophically) because of the dissolution of the ethical stage from idealism-internal motives. Religion, shortly explained, will bring about a complex atonement through the absurdity of faith – or in the words of Vigilius Haufniensis (i. e. the watchful Copenhagener): »The only thing that is truly capable of disarming the sophism of repentence is faith, the courage to faith […] This only faith can do, for only in faith is the synthesis perpetual and in each moment possible.« But this – I am afraid – I quite another story. It starts nonetheless, with the dissolution of the ethical stage qua a manifestation of problems inherent to German idealism and some of its most prominent representatives.