Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
MSc Anaesthesia Module: Basic Principles of Clinical Research 2004/05 Lecture 4 Causation in Epidemiological Research TITLE SLIDE In epidemiological research we often aim at showing causal relationships between risk factors and health. An understanding of the causes for disease is necessary for effective preventive, diagnosis and the application of correct treatment methods. But when can we actually say that an association is causal? SLIDE 2: LEARNING OBJECTIVES • Understand the definition of a causal factor for health and illness • Differentiate between causal factors and mechanisms for disease • Learn criteria how to practically determine causality • Be able to apply criteria for causality to an exampleSLIDE 3: WHY BOTHER? The aim of randomised controlled trials usually is to demonstrate that a particular treatment “causes” health improvements. Establishing causation is not only crucial for determining the best treatment it also proves the legitimacy for health protection policies. For example, the recently implemented smoking ban in workplaces was introduced on the grounds of epidemiological evidence that showed causality between environmental tobacco exposure and health. Also environmental standards such as prohibition of working with asbestos or special precautions when working with noxious agents are usually underpinned by epidemiological research evidence. Established causality can also guide disease prevention and health education programmes. For example, if we know what predisposes for disease we can screen for it in the population and can educate the general population about risk factors for specific diseases. Established causality might also have implications for legal action and litigation. Examples include law suits against tobacco companies in the United States by patients with lung cancer and against the company that runs the Sellafield nuclear power plant in the UK by patients with leukaemia. SLIDE 4: A CAUSE The most commonly used definition is provided by Rothman (1998) (see slide 4). One of the main components of the definition of a causal factor is that is must precede the disease event. This is sometimes self-evident, however sometimes not easy to establish because causation can go in both directions. For example, studies have found that unemployed workers are more likely to be depressed than employed workers. However, what came first? Did loosing the job precede the onset of depression? Or did workers loose their job because of depression? A naïve concept of causation states that there is just one causal agent, e.g. a bacteria, that inevitably causes the onset of a disease. However diseases are usually caused by a web of interacting causal factors, from which mechanisms of disease need to be differentiated. SLIDE 5: CAUSES OF CHOLERA For example, the exposure to contaminated water is not the only causal factor for the onset of cholera. Socio-economic conditions including poverty, malnutrition, crowded housing and in addition genetic predispositions lead to increased susceptibility for the cholera vibrio in infected water. In distinction to these causal factors, the biological mechanisms for cholera to develop after the risk factors are present include the ingestion of the cholera vibrio and its effects on the bowel wall cells. SLIDE 6: FACTORS IN CAUSATION Four types of factors play a part in the causation of disease. Usually the term “risk factor” is used for conditions that are associated with the risk of disease development. One risk factor alone is rarely sufficient to cause a particular disease or state. Predisposing factors such as age, gender and previous illness create a state of heightened susceptibility to a disease agent Enabling factors such as low income, poverty, poor nutrition, and poor medical care favour the development of disease. Conversely, circumstances that assist in recovery from disease or in the maintenance of good health can be called enabling factors. Precipitating factors such exposure to a specific noxious or disease agent may lead to onset of the disease Reinforcing factors such as repeated exposure to stress might aggravate an established disease or state SLIDE 7: THE WEB OF CAUSATION A cause is termed sufficient when it inevitably produces or initiates a disease. A sufficient cause is usually not a single factor but comprises different component causes. A cause is necessary if a disease cannot develop in its absence. Necessary causes usually include bacteria, viruses or noxious agents. For example smoking causes lung cancer; however smoking is not a sufficient cause in itself but a component of a sufficient cause. By itself it does not inevitably lead to lung cancer. Many smokers smoke heavily over 50 years without developing this disease, other components are required. However the cessation of smoking reduces the risk for lung cancer even if the other components cases are not altered. SLIDE 8: EXAMPLE Imagine you are presented with results of a case-control study showing that women hospitalised with breast cancer are more likely to have a family history of breast cancer as compared to women hospitalised for other reasons breast cancer. Can family history be considered as cause for breast cancer? SLIDE 9: ASSESSING THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN A POSSIBLE CAUSE AND A HEALTH OUTCOME When we find an association between a risk factor and a disease how do we know that the association is causal? Slide 8 shows an algorithm for examining associations. The questions are: Could this association be produced by selection or measurement bias? If not, could it be produced by confounding? If not, could it be a chance result? Only if all the above alternative explanations are excluded we can consider causality and apply specific criteria that establish causality (see next slides). For our example: First we have to take into consideration whether the association between family history and breast cancer could have been spuriously produced by bias. Selection bias could be present in this study because women with a family history of breast cancer may be more likely to conduct breast self-examinations and to seek medical attention as compared to women without such a family history. Thus breast cancer might be detected earlier and to a higher proportion in women with a family history. This bias would lead to an overestimation of the difference in breast cancer prevalence between the cases and the controls because some of the controls, although being ill, might not be diagnosed. Measurement bias could be present because women with a family history might be referred to elaborate diagnosis methods such as mammograms and biopsies by their GPs compared to women without such a family history. Thus the diagnosis of breast cancer would be more accurate and misclassification of symptoms as benign less likely in women without a family history. This differential measurement bias would also lead to an overestimation of the association between family history and breast cancer. The association could also be spuriously inflated by a confounder and be explained by nutrition or healthy life style. Since healthy diets and lifestyles run in families, these factors may be the “true” causes rather than family history in the sense of a genetic predisposition. Chance: The result of this one study could be just a chance finding. It needs to be checked whether the found association was statistically significant (p-value) and whether the estimate of the Odds Ratio was precise (confidence interval). If all the above alternative explanations can be excluded we may consider the association a causal one and can test the criteria for causation SLIDES 10-11: GUIDELINES FOR CAUSATION A commonly used set of criteria was proposed by Hill (1965); it was an expansion of a set of criteria offered previously in the landmark U.S. Surgeon General’s Report on Smoking and Health that officially established causality between smoking and lung cancer. These guidelines were subsequently slightly modified. The list provided here was taken from Beaglehole, Bonita and Kjellström (1993). Temporal relationship: Does the cause precede the effect? This is often self-evident, although difficulties may arise in case-control studies because risky behaviour is often altered if first pre-clinical symptoms show or upon onset of the disease. For example, patients might stop smoking when they have breathing difficulties, eventually resulting a high proportion of current non-smokers with lung cancer. Prospective cohort studies with repeated measurements can strengthen the evidence. Plausibility: Is the association plausible and underpinned by potential biological or psychological known theory and mechanisms? For example, laboratory experiments could have shown how exposure to the particular factor results in physiological changes that may lead to a particular illness. However, lack of plausibility may simply reflect lack of medical knowledge. Consistency: Is the association consistent with associations found in other studies? The more studies in different settings and with different populations show similar results the less likely it is that all studies are making the same mistake. However lack of consistency does not exclude a causal relationship since differences in exposure levels and settings might have reduced produced differences in results. Using systematic reviews and meta-analyses is a way of examining the consistency of the evidence of studies addressing the same hypothesis. In meta-analysis, welldesigned studies with a strong study design are given the greatest weight. Strength of the association: The magnitude of an association between a potential cause and an effect is usually measured by a relative risk ratio or an odds ratio. A strong association is more likely to be causal than a weak association, which could be influenced by confounding or bias. However the fact that an association is weak does not preclude it from being causal. Some causal factors are very difficult to measure. For example information about diet or alcohol consumption are usually based on selfreports, which are often biased. In additions, these factors vary considerably over time, which dilutes the association with a health outcome. It is also important to review what is considered a strong association. Some textbooks suggest that Relative Risk Ratios or Odds Ratios below 2 should be dismissed. This is misleading because the magnitude of effect size needs to be judged in the context of the unit of measurement. Even small ratios can be of high clinical importance. For example, an Odds Ratio of 1.14 between age and hypertension means one-year age increase multiplies the odds of hypertension by a factor of 1.14 or by 14%. This is substantial considering the small unit of analysis of one year. If we had measured age in 10-year increments, the odds ratio would have been 3.6 indicating that growing 10 years older multiplies the odds of hypertension by a factor of 3.6. Dose-response relationship (biological gradient): A dose-response relationship refers to the presence of a monotonic (unidirectional) dose-response curve indicating a heightened disease risk with heightened exposure levels, or a heightened disease risk with decreasing exposure levels. For example, more smoking means more carcinogen exposure and more tissue damage, hence more opportunity for carcinogenesis. Slide 12 shows an example of a biological gradient. Reversibility: When the removal of the risk factors results in a reduced disease risk, the likelihood of the association being causal is strengthened. For example, the cessation of cigarette smoking is associated with a risk reduction of lung cancer relative to people who continue smoking. If the cause leads to irreversible changes that produce disease, then reversibility cannot be a condition for causality. Study design: Is the evidence based on studies using strong study designs? Usually experimental research is considered the strongest design for establishing causation. However experimental designs are not always feasible. Slide 13 shows the ability study designs to demonstrate causation. SLIDE 11: JUDGING THE EVIDENCE No empirically found association between a potential causal factors and an effect will completely satisfy all criteria mentioned above. The evidence for a causal relationship is heightened if many lines of evidence lead to the conclusion. Causal inference is usually tentative and implies judgement of the scientific community. The judgement must be made based on the available evidence, however uncertainty always remains. In judging the different aspects of causation referred to above, the correct temporal relationship is essential, especially if reverse causation is a possible alternative explanation. The importance of the other criteria depends on the risk factor and the outcome under investigation. For example, a gradient between the risk factors and the disease outcome (dose-response relationship) does not make sense for some associations. In new areas of research, consistency of results might not be an issue due to lack of publications addressing the same issue. Also the strength of associations found in different studies need to be judged taking measurement difficulties for some exposures and outcomes into account. Initially Hill had included the criteria “specificity of association”, “coherence with existing knowledge” and “analogy” into the guidelines. They were omitted here, because they have proven less useful. SLIDE 12: EXAMPLE FOR A DOSE-RESPONSE RELATIONSSHIP SLIDE 13: ABILITY OF STUDY DESIGNS TO ESTABLISH CAUSATION SLIDE 14: CAUSAL FACTOR, CAUSAL LINK OR MECHANISM? In some research areas it is difficult to differentiate between a causal agent, a causal link or a disease mechanism. Ultimately it depends on the theory and the conceptual framework of the researchers. For example we know that arteriosclerosis is a risk factor for heart disease. Is arteriosclerosis a causal factor or a mechanism of disease? We could take a wider perspective and postulate that a smoking is a causal factor leading to arteriosclerosis, which is in turn the mechanism of disease leading to heart disease. We could even go one step further and hypothesize that smoking is caused by other factors such as stress. In the latter model stress is considered as the causal factor, whereas smoking constitutes a causal link in the association between stress and arteriosclerosis. This example shows that it is essential to clearly conceptualise all potentially contributing factors and specify their potential relationship with the outcome. Assignment questions: 1. Results obtained in a cohort study suggest that persons regularly smoking marihuana are more likely to develop schizophrenia than persons who do not smoke marihuana. Discuss how the results could have been affected by measurement bias, selection bias and confounding. 2. Take an example of an association between a risk factor and a health outcome in anaesthesiology and discuss causality using 3 of the Hill criteria for causality.