* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Joint Actions, Stories and Symbolic Structures: A Contribution to
Situated cognition wikipedia , lookup
Style (sociolinguistics) wikipedia , lookup
Social Bonding and Nurture Kinship wikipedia , lookup
Social psychology wikipedia , lookup
Social theory wikipedia , lookup
Unilineal evolution wikipedia , lookup
Social history wikipedia , lookup
George Herbert Mead wikipedia , lookup
Social network analysis wikipedia , lookup
Postdevelopment theory wikipedia , lookup
Social group wikipedia , lookup
Structuration theory wikipedia , lookup
Universal pragmatics wikipedia , lookup
Nazareth-Conferences wikipedia , lookup
Sociology of terrorism wikipedia , lookup
Community development wikipedia , lookup
History of the social sciences wikipedia , lookup
Joint Actions, Stories and Symbolic Structures: A Contribution to Herbert Blumer’s Conceptual Framework Abstract Despite its centrality in Blumer’s conceptual framework, the notion of joint action remains theoretically underdeveloped and empirically underutilised. To fill this void, the present article focuses on the dynamics inherent to the formation of joint action, and highlights actors’ deployment of available symbolic rules and resources for constructing the legitimising accounts that normally accompany their lines of action. The construction of such accounts, or stories, is viewed here as the prime means of reducing the intrinsic contingency of joint action and determining its content and terms as well as its direction and prospects. The article concludes by underscoring the importance of the suggested theoretical input for tapping some of the potential of Blumer’s approach, especially the one regarding its capacity to address subtle forms of power. Keywords Control, Defining Activities, Joint Action, Meaning, Social Contingency, Symbolic Resources, Symbolic Interactionism Introduction Herbert George Blumer (1900–1987) is certainly among the major sociologists who have exerted a noticeable influence on the shaping of the discipline. An ardent interpreter and proponent of George Herbert Mead’s legacy, he was one of the leading figures of the Chicago School style of symbolic interactionism and made a significant contribution to the development and consolidation of this tradition – a tradition which after decades still finds its clearest and ‘most parsimonious formulation’ in his work from 1969 (Craib, 1984: 72). To a great extent Blumer’s prominence is due to his well-known methodological outlook, consisting of an uncompromising rejection of the idea of sociology as a positivist science and a solid advocacy of more empathetic and participant modes of inquiry which, in his view, better fit the particular nature of the subject matter of the discipline. Hand in hand with this methodological outlook is his theoretical framework, which stems from a novel ontological stance and which – as many observers have pointed out – is the main source of Blumer’s influence on the discipline (Becker, 1988; Fine, 1993; Hall, 2003; Kuhn, 1964; Lal, 1995; Lauer and Handel, 1983; Manis and Meltzer, 1972; Meltzer et al, 1975; Plummer, 1990; Reynolds and Heman-Kinney, 2003; Sandstrom et al, 2002; Shalin, 1986; Shotter, 1980; Stryker, 1980; Warshay, 1975). Within this theoretical framework, however, the notion of joint action occupies a central position. As shown below, this concept captures Blumer’s particular image of social 1 reality, and encapsulates many of the essential features of his brand of symbolic interactionism with its characteristic emphasis ‘on the flow of interaction and interactive processes, looking at the way in which meanings develop and change’ (Craib, 1984: 74-75). Despite its obvious centrality, however, this concept has hitherto received relatively little theoretical attention (Baugh, 1990; Forte, 2001; Halas, 2012; Harvey, 1987; Low, 2008; Lyman, 1984; Lyman and Vidich, 1988 and 2000; Maines, 1988; McPhail and Rexroat, 1979); and as its articulation falls short of specification in some important areas, many of its potentials remain unexploited. Given the rather scarce supply of work specifically devoted to Blumer’s key concept, the main purpose of the present article is to contribute to its theoretical elaboration and highlight the crucial role this concept can potentially play in addressing the question of power from a symbolic interactionist point of view. More specifically, the main rationale of this undertaking has less to do with a purely scholastic interest in the history of symbolic interactionism than with a concern for the potential and prospects of this tradition with regard to the treatment of issues that are of crucial importance to sociology, notably those concerning the more subtle, discursive forms of power and domination which – by no means novel – become increasingly prevalent in contemporary societies (Hardy et al, 2000; Schiffrin et al, 2003; Seidel, 1987). To serve this purpose however the article begins with a brief presentation of the concept and some of its main properties. It then continues with an identification of the areas where – due to the vagueness of Blumer’s own articulation of the notion – some clarification and elaboration is needed. In the next step the article targets the core of the formation process of joint action, notably the participants’ ‘defining activities’ (Blumer, 1969: 5), and draws on some of the ideas put forth by Harrison White (1992) and Anthony Giddens (1984) in order to elaborate theoretically on the participants’ efforts at defining, interpreting and making sense of the interaction situation in which they are engaged, as well as their attempts to determine the content, terms, direction and prospects of the joint action that is in the making between them. Finally, the article discusses some of the implications of the suggested theoretical specifications and elaborations. Definition and Properties Building on, and presenting a substitute for, Mead’s idea of ‘social act’ (Blumer, 1969; Blumer and Morrione, 2003; Collins, 1988) the concept of joint action has an almost allinclusive empirical referent, and denotes any case of social interaction where the participants’ 2 individual courses of action cross and fit into one another, for instance in ‘a trading transaction, a family dinner, a marriage ceremony, a shopping expedition, a game, a convivial party, a debate, a court trial, or a war’ (Blumer, 1969: 70). Among its various characteristics there are a few distinct but closely connected features that are of particular relevance to the purpose of this article. First, essential to the constitution of a joint action is ‘the fitting together’ of the separate and distinct acts of the individual parties, each party occupying a different position and launching his or her act from that position (Blumer, 1969: 70). Being more than the sum of the individual acts of its participants, joint action is conceived by Blumer as ‘a societal organization of such acts (Blumer, 1969:17, italics added), and as such it is an ‘emergent’ (Cuff et al., 1998: 135) phenomenon in that ‘while made up of diverse component acts that enter into its formation, [it] is different from any one of them and from their mere aggregation’ (Blumer, 1969: 17).1 The second property is the inbuilt interdependency amongst the participants in a joint action, as each constantly seeks to work out his or her own line of action by noting, recognising and interpreting what others are doing and by adjusting own action to their doings. This interdependency is emphasised by Blumer when he (1969: 97), for instance, asserts that ‘what one’s associates are doing becomes the context inside which one’s own developing act has to fit;’ or when he on another occasion (1969: 8) maintains that …the activity of others enter as positive factors in the formation of [the actor’s] own conduct; in the face of the actions of others one may abandon an intention or purpose, revise it, check it or suspend it, intensify it, or replace it. Finally, far from being a straightforward response to stimuli or a smooth enactment of predefined social roles, joint action in Blumer’s view is a contingent accomplishment, taking shape through the ongoing mutual fitting attempts of its participants and through the interlocking of their courses of behaviour. For instance, he (1969: 72) underlines the uncertainty that characterises joint action by asserting that although …usually the course of a joint action is outlined in advance […], there are many joint actions that encounter obstruction, that have no preestablished pathways, and that have to be constructed along new lines. On other occasion he – in refuting the presumed causal relationship between attitudes and behaviours – maintains that human action is not an expression of a predisposed ‘already 3 organised tendency’ but a ‘construction’ (Blumer, 1969: 94) that takes shape in an ongoing interactive process into which the actor enters only with an ‘initial bid for a possible line of action’ (Blumer, 1969: 97) without any certainty about its development. Therefore, as the interaction among the participants unfolds, …given lines of action may be started or stopped, they may be abandoned or postponed, they may be confined to mere planning or to an inner life of reverie, or if initiated, they may be transformed (Blumer, 1969: 16). In fact, Blumer (1969: 72) goes even further, and proclaims that ‘uncertainty, contingency and transformation are part and parcel of the process of joint action.’ In the face of this feature, it is therefore ‘a sheer gratuitous assumption’ in his (Blumer, 1969: 72) view to believe that ‘the diversified joint actions which compromise a human society are set to follow fixed and established channels;’ and it is to capture this feature that he (1969: 72) underlines the incremental character of joint action, pointing out that …just because [a joint action] is built up over time by the fitting together of acts, each joint action must be seen as having a career or a history. In having a career, its course and fate are contingent on what happens during its formation. …The career of joint actions also must be seen as open to many possibilities of uncertainty [italics added].2 Voids and Remedies So conceptualised, the notion of joint action of course encapsulates, and is in full agreement with, the fundamental elements of Blumer’s sociological thought. On one hand, it reflects his position that social interaction is inherently indeterminate and that its outcomes are contingent upon the specific ways in which it unfolds. Blumer’s conception of joint action, in other words, expresses his basic vision of human actors as active interpreters, planners and schemers, and mirrors his uncompromising rejection of the over-socialised (Wrong, 1961) conception of human action as it is typically pictured from structural-functionalist perspectives (Stryker, 1988). Moreover, Blumer’s conception of joint action lays the conceptual foundation of his root image of empirical social reality as an ever-changing web of ongoing, developing interaction, which in accordance with the Simmelian vision (Low, 2008), constantly changes formation. Furthermore, this conception underpins his rather harsh criticism of the ‘mechanistic’ sociological explanations based on the ‘simplistic cause and effect mode of reasoning’ and associated with the conventional mode of inquiry known as variable analysis (Shibutani, 1988: 29); and naturally this conception also fits his own 4 alternative notion of proper sociological method well, with its typical emphasis on the indepth exploration of the meanings created in and conveyed through interaction. In short, Blumer’s conception of joint action as the emergent and unpredictable product of the interactive processes that are ceaselessly in the making is thus indispensable to his approach, and reflects the coherence of his entire system of thought. Nonetheless, Blumer’s account of this notion lacks sufficient specification and lucidity in several important regards. This theoretical deficiency comes to the surface, for instance, when he only in the passing highlights general reasons why actors, especially in the highly diversified and heterogeneous contemporary social settings, seek to align their lines of action. For instance, he (1969: 76) only briefly mentions that in such settings …the participants may fit their acts to one another in orderly joint actions on the basis of compromise, out of duress, because they may use one another in achieving their respective ends, because it is the sensible thing to do, or out of sheer necessity. This is particularly likely to be true in our modern complex societies with their great diversity in composition, in lines of interest, and in their respective worlds of concern.3 Yet he leaves the matter at that, and declines to offer any specified account of the social forces and processes which bring these actors together and which induce them to try to fit their lines of action. Or to take another example, on several occasions he refers to two distinct steps in the formation of joint action, notably ‘first identifying the social act [with which the participants] are about to engage and second, interpreting and defining each other’s acts’ (Blumer, 1969:70). Yet, he does not elaborate on the issue, and makes no effort to specify these steps any further. However, the theoretical deficiency of joint action considers in particular what constitutes the core of this phenomenon, namely the participants’ defining activities. According to Blumer, as actors are called on to act in given situations they have to ascertain the meaning of the actions of others and design their own lines of action in light of such interpretations. In his view the participants’ ongoing defining activities constitute the essential property of human interaction, present and observable in all cases of joint action. The point is repeatedly underlined by Blumer (1969: 67), who, for instance, asserts that …in the flow of group life there are innumerable points at which the participants are redefining each other’s acts. Such redefinition is very common in adversary relations, it is frequent in group discussions, and 5 it is essentially intrinsic to dealing with problems (and I may remark here that no human group is free from problems.) Moreover, in his view the description of the interactive process in terms of participants’ ongoing defining and redefining activities holds true even for actions unfolding along established paths, as in individual occasions of institutionalised interaction situations such as weddings or funerals. In his (1969: 18) own words, this kind of action is …just as much a result of an interpretative process as is a new form of joint action that is being developed for the first time. …[the] meanings that underline established and recurrent joint action are themselves subjective to pressure as well as to reinforcement, to incipient dissatisfaction as well as to indifference; they may be challenged as well as affirmed, allowed to slip along without concern as well as subjected to infusions of new vigour. In fact, it is on the basis of the significance ascribed to such activities that Blumer (1969: 3) asserts that their thorough investigation constitutes the ‘very distinctive position [of symbolic interactionism]’ and that this kind of investigation draws a ‘major line of difference’ between this brand of sociology and other approaches which normally take meaning for granted. Yet despite the significance that Blumer evidently attaches to the ongoing mutual defining activities of actors, and despite an explicit ambition to bring them to the fore, he fails to specify the issue sufficiently; and, more concerned with drawing attention to their mere existence rather than exploring in detail their various aspects, he leaves us only with a few, embryonic comments on what, in his view, represents the most characteristic feature of symbolic interactionism. What is particularly missing from Blumer’s treatment are specified accounts of the questions about how the fitting of the participants’ individual lines of action occurs or through which mechanisms the participants jointly produce the alignment of their behaviour. That is, Blumer makes it clear that the arrival at common definitions and meanings is central to the formation of any joint action and obviously, in his view, arriving at such common definitions and meanings represents the very source of the participants’ interdependence and the ensuing contingency of the joint action unfolding between them. Nonetheless he leaves untouched the question of how the participants jointly determine and endorse the meanings of the situation in which they find themselves. Nor are there, in his account, any specifications regarding the particular forms that the defining activities of the participants take, and the 6 interactional resources, skills and strategies they use to secure their individual projects and steer the process of interaction in the desired directions and towards the intended outcomes. Against this unfortunate omission, however, the present article takes the view that due to the weight ascribed to the defining activities of actors, Blumer’s approach represents a theoretical framework with significant potential for an adequate and insightful investigation of very subtle forms of power, influence and domination in society. This quality is, however, admittedly only a potential one, meaning that Blumer’s approach provides only a fertile soil in need of much theoretical cultivation in order to grow into a fully-fledged framework for addressing power issues; and it is out of this conviction that an attempt at such theoretical cultivation is made below – an attempt that, targeting the core of joint action and the dynamics of its formation, is carried out in three steps, all in line with the main tenets of Blumer’s perspective. First, the contingency that, according to Blumer, is constitutive of joint action induces the participants to seek efficient control regarding its career, that is, the directions it might take and the outcomes it might generate. Second, such attempts normally permeate the very core of the unfolding joint action – the participants’ defining activities – and are carried out in the form of the legitimising narratives or stories (White, 1992) that normally envelop any purposeful line of action – be it motivated by material interests, emotions, and values or otherwise. Finally, in constructing their stories participants typically draw on the symbolic rules and resources available (Giddens, 1984), which are provided by the symbolic structures prevailing in wider society. These steps are unpacked sequentially below. Contingency and Control As mentioned above, the very construction of joint action entails interdependency among the participants in that each one’s behaviour is interlocked to those of the others and takes shape only within the interactive context that is made up of these others’ behaviours. Thus, as none of the participants is in the position to pursue his or her initially chosen course of action independently from the lines of action that others might choose, the direction, path and form that the joint action eventually takes are most likely to differ from the trajectories outlined by the participants. No matter how carefully designed in advance, the actual course of the unfolding interaction can, in other words, derail from the ones that any of the participants initially had in mind and develop in unanticipated directions and produce unexpected results – sometimes even beyond the participants’ perceptual horizons. The career of any joint action is therefore inevitably bound to be uncertain in that the participants can seldom predict with 7 sufficient certainty which results the ongoing process will eventually generate and with what probability. What is crucial here is that this open-endedness turns continuity, preservation and fulfilment of the chosen line of action the key concerns of the participants, and induces them to try to reduce as far as possible the contingency involved. In other words as the joint action unfolds the participants face the risk of their schemes being upset, and the need to cope with this challenge generates reasons to gain and exercise efficient control over the course that the interaction may take and the outcome it may produce. Indeed, the inherent interdependency and uncertainty that, especially in heterogeneous settings, characterise joint action make it an inevitable condition for any of the participants to try to secure his or her individual project and steer the unfolding interaction into preferred routes and towards the projected outcomes; and in the face of such inbuilt social contingency ‘control attempts’ (White, 1992) become imperative for the achievement of any objective that triggers any line of action, be it an instrumental and strategic action in the narrow sense, or communicative, emotional, value-laden etc. Regardless of the driving forces, the purposes at hand and the outcomes in view, such attempts in other words represent a universal and omnipresent element in all kinds of purposive action, which are mainly fuelled by the participants’ pervasive need to narrow the range of the possible directions and outcomes of the joint action, and which are launched to restrict the array of possible paths. Constantly and mutually undertaken, such control attempts are instigated and carried out mainly for the purpose of setting the stage for the actual unfolding of the interaction, for confining the potentially openended situation, and for preserving the continuity of their own line of action and securing its accomplishment. As such they therefore constitute an integral, ever-present element of any designed and purposeful action, and are essential to its fulfilment. Control and Construction of Stories Once it is granted that the contingent nature of joint action makes control efforts necessary, the question that arises naturally is as to what specific form these efforts take. The answer suggested here is that it is primarily through the construction of stories – and counter-stories – that actors seek to determine the state of the interaction situation as well as the conditions and terms of the joint action that is unfolding; or as White (1992: 68) puts it, ‘stories come from and become a medium for control efforts: that is the core.’ To unpack this ‘core’ we need to recall that in developing the notion of joint action Blumer starts out with the distinctive assumptions of the hermeneutic perspective, 8 according to which human beings invariably assign meaning to their own actions and to those of others, and that such meanings constitute the basis on which they relate themselves to these others (Bauman, 1978; Ricoeur, 1981). As he repeatedly emphasises, however, human actions do not carry a baggage of invariable meanings once and for all attached to them. Their meanings are instead open to actors’ creativity and adaptability, and are determined contextually. They can therefore be best understood as jointly generated social products. That is, the actual meanings that human actions assume emerge only out of the particular unfolding interaction processes; Or, as Blumer (1969: 110) puts it, they arise out of the ‘ceaseless movements of definition and redefinition’ in which participants constantly interpret own actions and that of the others by ‘arresting, recognizing or adjusting their own intentions, wishes, feelings, and attitudes’ as well as assessing ‘the fitness of norms, values and group perceptions for the situation being formed by the acts of others’ (Blumer, 1969: 70) – a task that becomes increasingly challenging as the whirl of modern life brings together many actors from distinct regions of the highly differentiated contemporary social landscape who need to fit together and reconcile their diverse, heterogeneous and often conflicting perceptions regarding the reasonable, legitimate and acceptable mutual rights and obligations, as well as expectations and claims. The openness of joint action with regard to its meaning – and thereby the indeterminacy of its career – presents participants with the opportunity to carry out their mutual control efforts in subtle forms through purposefully constructed representations of their lines of action, however. More specifically, it gives rise the possibility of each participant making his or her line of action appear in a certain way and loading it with certain values and assessments, while simultaneously portraying the behaviour of others in certain other ways and assigning certain other meanings to it. That is, the absence of intrinsic meanings and interpretations turns the participants’ lines of action potentially subjected to a range of possible constructions and representations and – not given prior to the unfolding interaction – the actual meanings that the participants’ courses of conduct assume become dependent on how they succeed in articulating their individual lines of action (Hall, 2006; Laclau and Mouffe, 2001). Therefore, the activities through which the meaning of the joint action takes shape become the key control issue, their determination becomes the main target of the participants’ mutual control attempts, and their construction becomes the focal site at which these efforts are typically carried out – with the effect that the career of the joint action inevitably becomes a negotiated outcome emerging from and determined by the ongoing mutual control efforts of its participants. 9 It is against the background of such dynamics that the significance of the participants’ stories and their functions stand out. The concept of story – which is basically a generalisation of the notion of account (Scott and Lyman, 1968) – refers to the organised and explicit narrative which encapsulates the actor’s perceptions, definitions and interpretations as well as his or her assessments and evaluations of the situation that it covers. Broadly speaking, a story is a narration constructed for ordering the experience and for conferring meaning to it. As such, it is an act of organising what might otherwise be perceived as an experiential chaos, giving it a more-or-less coherent decipherable semblance. Reporting on the actor’s experiences and understandings of the state of the social situation and of the conditions and terms of the interactions unfolding there, the construction of such a story involves a selection of what is to be included or excluded, emphasised or downplayed, celebrated or rejected – all woven together more or less skilfully according to the context. Regardless of their specific make-up, however, stories perform vital functions. That is, a story is primarily a justifying narrative told by a participant in a given situation to furnish his or her purposeful line of action with valid representations that are contextually familiar to the listeners, and that underpin the aptness, adequacy, and above all the legitimacy, of the behaviour in question. The prime purpose of its construction is to endorse the expectations and claims that the chosen line of action entails – a purpose which is typically materialised through favourably influencing others’ perceptions of one’s own action. Moreover, in the face of the inbuilt indeterminacy of joint action and the need to reduce contingency and gain control over its career, it becomes imperative for the participants to seek to exercise efficient control over the unfolding situation and increase the probability of the desired outcome; and stories are the main devices used for this purpose. In other words, it is through the construction of stories and counter-stories that participants in a joint action seek to determine the kind of situation that is unfolding, and the issues that are at stake. By deliberately assigning meaning and conferring value to their own actions and to those of the others, the participants mutually try to bestow legitimacy over their own intentions and objectives while simultaneously trying to discharge the validity of the interests and expectations of the others; and by doing so they pursue to enlarge their own manoeuvring space and enhance their own action capacity, while at the same time attempting to limit the options open to the others by narrowing the range of possible interpretations, meaningassignments, and the responses that these others can invoke when constructing their stories. Stories from Structures 10 As Mills (1940) and others have pointed out, such justifying narratives do not arise from within the participants. Stories, in other words, are by no means the results of purely individual imagination and never take shape according to the actors’ entirely individually devised preferences in a socio-cultural vacuum where society has vanished in ‘the universal solvent of definitional and interpretative processes’ (Stryker, 1988: 38). On the contrary, when constructing their stories actors find themselves invariably within specific universes of meaning, which provide them with a menu of perspectives, definitions and interpretations that they can call into play. Put differently, rather than being totally sealed off from the larger social settings, actors are normally embedded in generic and relatively durable symbolic structures (Giddens, 1984), which consist of institutionalised – that is socially endorsed and sanctioned – schemes of perception and appreciation that vary considerably across the spheres and regions of highly differentiated modern societies. Similar to the ways in which the generalised grammatical procedures of a language (langue) generate the concrete and particular use of spoken words (parole), these symbolic structures are generic schemes ‘instantiated in action’ (Giddens, 1984: 6), in that they make their presence felt as transposable principles that enter, guide and discipline the defining activities of actors in the form of current normative conventions (such as reciprocity or solidarity), taken-for-granted common-sense conceptions (of fairness or civic manner for instance), and dominant principles and styles of action (such as economic rationality or rule of law). ‘Picked up’ from various social settings and internalised by actors as their stock of interactional dispositions and skills, these rules and resources are facilitating devices which are actualised whenever necessary, enabling actors to decipher their social situations relatively effortlessly. They are the ready ‘…recipes for interpreting the social world and for handling things and men in order to obtain the best result in every situation with a minimum of effort’ (Schutz, 1964: 95). In that capacity these rules and resources underpin the practical mastery of actors (Bourdieu, 1977), and function as formulae for interaction or as ‘instruments for guidance and formation of action’ (Blumer, 1969: 5). Put differently, the widely sanctioned and frequently invoked rules and resources embedded in symbolic structures guide actors in their interpretations of social situations and help them to go along the flow of everyday life. As such they are contingency reducing devices, without which actors would lose direction and their interactions would come to a halt, as they would lack reliable cues regarding the suitability and/or legitimacy of their lines of action. It should also be emphasised, however, that the relationship between the available symbolic rules and resources on the one hand and the actors’ deployment of these 11 devices on the other hand is the kind of ‘loose coupling’ that Goffman (1983: 11) speaks of, in that there is no strict one-to-one correspondence and no rigid and mechanical ‘gearing’ of these devices ‘into interactional cogs.’ Instead, actors enjoy a considerable degree of freedom in weaving together their stories, which allows them to ‘…select, check, suspend, regroup and transform the meanings in the light of the situation’ (Blumer, 1969: 5) and which enables them to make new adjustments whenever they face disruptions. That is, due to their creative and performative abilities, actors can actively choose and purposefully combine the various symbolic devices available to them on the basis of the ‘interest prevailing at the moment’ – the interest that ‘determines the elements which the [actor] singles out to define his [their] situation thinkingly, actingly and emotionally, to find his [their] way in it, and to come to terms with it’ (Schutz, 1966: 123). Needless to say, there are no standard or prescribed patterns of how actors come to construct their stories, as their defining activities vary from one stance of joint action to another – sometimes producing ‘fresh action’ (White, 1992) with unprecedented and groundbreaking outcomes. Yet, neither the variability of stories across social realms nor their adaptability alters the fact that – despite the openness of meaning to the participants’ creative defining activities – stories and counter-stories are never designed without substantial reference to external auspices. Although stories are worked out in the actual process that unfolds ‘then’ and ‘there’, and are shaped according to the actual characteristics of the situation, the participants do not enjoy an absolute, limitless and unconfined freedom in making them. On the contrary, the participants’ stories are essentially social in their origin, content and design. They emerge from the unfolding interaction, and originate from sources that are socially provided. Their utility as an efficient means of affecting the career of joint action comes from their reliance on existing rules and resources, and they owe their legitimising properties to the social forces beneath and behind these symbolic devices. Actors’ story construction can therefore more advantageously be viewed as a relatively bounded social practice which is both made possible and constrained, both endorsed and curbed, by the symbolic rules and resources which, in each segment of the social world, provide the dividing line between what is socially possible, plausible and permissible, and what is not. Leverage The incorporation of the ideas presented above into Blumer’s conceptualisation of joint action has several pay-offs, some of which are highlighted below. As mentioned at the outset, the articulation of this concept suffers from an insufficient specification with regard to the 12 participants’ defining activities – for which Blumer himself bears a good deal of the responsibility. As result, the notion has until now remained largely equivocal and, subsequently, difficult to bring into touch with empirical experience. Indeed, it seems rather ironic that Blumer, who ‘believed that ambiguity was the basic problem with [many important] social psychological concepts’ (Tucker, 1988: 108) and who revealed ‘the deficiencies of most concepts in the social sciences’ (Tucker, 1990: 1326), would decline to fine-tune the key concept of his own framework and leave behind an imprecise and ‘tremendously abstract’ (Becker, 1988: 18) theoretical perspective. The theoretical input presented above, on the other hand, enables us to examine in detail how actors in any given situation purposefully deploy the symbolic rules and resources at their disposal to construct legitimising veneers for their own action, how they confront the counter-stories of other participants and adapt their own stories according to the unfolding interaction, and how the actual career of the joint action is determined through such processes. In doing so the suggested specification helps us remove some of the ambiguities that until now have hampered both the application and validation of this central concept, and facilitates a more effective and mutually fruitful interrelationship between the concept of joint action and its empirical referents. In addition, the proposed elaboration also offers the opportunity of addressing a number of important substantive questions, among which the potential of Blumer’s conceptual framework for the analysis of crucial power issues stands out in particular. Recently it has been suggested that Blumer’s brand of symbolic interactionism is essentially based on the principle of sociality rather than domination, and that it is not conceptually fit for addressing power issues (Athens, 2009).4 The main argument of the present article however is that there is nothing in Blumer’s theoretical framework that necessarily commits it to the vision of society as an entirely harmonious and smoothly functioning system (Layder, 2006). Conversely, as some observers have pointed out, Blumer’s approach to social reality embraces conflict as an indispensable feature of dynamic contemporary social settings (Tucker, 1990). Indeed, this feature of Blumer’s approach is to be found in the very premises of his conceptualisation of human action, as he avoids the ‘fallacy of roles’ (Bourdieu 1977) and discards the ‘over-socialised’ conception of actors (Wrong, 1961) according to which people merely enact their internalised social roles in full agreement with the prevailing cultural prescriptions. Instead, as indicated by his uncompromising advocacy of the characteristic contingency of joint actions, Blumer allows for frictions and clashes among actors who – encountering and interacting in the highly heterogeneous social settings of our 13 time – design their individual lines of action according to different logics, standards and criteria. As shown above, at the heart of these conflicts and clashes stand the defining activities of the actors who – ‘each occupying a different position and launching his or her act from that position’ (Blumer, 1969: 70) – are creative authors of their individual lines of action, and who are capable of making strategic use of the available symbolic rules and resources in order to determine the definition of the situation and the appropriate line of action. As this feature of Blumer’s approach remains underdeveloped, however, the ideas suggested above can contribute to the advance of his approach towards a fully-fledged framework for addressing power issues from a symbolic interactionist point of view. More specifically, as the present article has tried to demonstrate, through the deployment of the concept of story, Blumer’s approach can fruitfully be used for addressing adequately subtle and yet fundamental forms of conflict, power exercise and the uneven distribution of symbolic devices in larger society, as well as the systematic effects of this unevenness on the ability of actors to determine the fate of the joint actions in which they voluntarily or otherwise partake. By specifying the participants’ defining activities through the notion of story, the theoretical contribution suggested above puts us in a conceptually better position to map out, in any given situation, the relative availability of symbolic rules and resources to the participants, as well as these participants’ capacities and skills to invoke these devices when articulating their courses of action. Subsequently, the suggested theoretical input allows for empirical studies of subtle power exercise in various social settings across levels and realms, and enables us to explore in detail important questions regarding the asymmetries that usually prevail among various groups of actors with regard to their access and their capacity to use the existing and potentially available symbolic rules and resources to affect the content, terms, directions and outcomes of their interactions. Looking Ahead In the light of the ideas presented above it seems only reasonable to stress what others have pointed out earlier, notably that although ‘one might expect that everything worth saying about the work of Herbert Blumer has already been said [it] is not true’ (Tucker, 1990: 1326), and that it may still be ‘too early for a final assessment of [his] work’ (Shibutani, 1988: 30). In this spirit the present article finds it rewarding to view the key element of the formation of joint action – the defining activities carried out in the form of stories – as a relatively bounded social practice that is both made possible and constrained by symbolic 14 rules and resources. More specifically, the theoretical elaboration of this notion along the lines suggested above can help us bring out the potential of Blumer’s approach regarding the detailed and empirical enquiry into the ways in which subtle discursive modes of power and domination enter the interaction situation and decide its fate – the modes of power which stem from and rest on the definition of social categories and relationships among them, and which operate through the placement of events, actions and individuals in symbolic hierarchies or ‘regimes of representation’ (Hall, 1997). By the same token, the theoretical elaboration suggested above helps us materialise the potential of Blumer’s approach so as to account for the kind of social order that is generated, sustained and reproduced through the asymmetric distribution of access and ability to deploy symbolic rules and resources to construct legitimising stories. That is, the theoretical input proposed above provides us with the first necessary conceptual tool needed to explore the forces and the mechanisms through which the bulk of inherently contingent and potentially open-ended situations grow regular, patterned and predictable in their outcomes, and how diverse joint actions fall in and evolve within institutionalised frameworks, and thereby largely unintentionally generate and sustain the regularity and the stability that is easily observable in society at large. An example of this possibility prefigures already in Blumer’s (1985a, 1958b, 1965a, 1965b) own series of work on race relations in the United States. At the heart of the race system lies, in his view, a fundamental structure which represents a historically rooted hierarchical social organisation and which embraces and brings together various racial groups, positioning them in relationship to one another and regulating the flows of interaction among them. This hierarchical social organisation is institutionalised in time and space and derives from the collectively endorsed definitions of social groups and shared conceptions of the appropriate relative positions of these groups and relationships among them. From this underlying, institutionalised definition of social categories then stems the fundamental asymmetries among the country’s various racial groups, with regard to their access and ability to draw on the available pool of symbolic rules and resources which can be used for constructing their legitimising stories, endorsing their lines of action and determining the fate of their inherently contingent and potentially open-ended interactions. The adequate treatment of these topics of course requires much more theoretical elaboration, as well as empirical validation, which is well beyond the scope of the present article. However, what has been put forth above should suffice to substantiate the statement that many sociological insights are still to be tapped from Blumer’s heritage and how such an endeavour can enhance the capacity of symbolic interactionism to explore both 15 theoretically and empirically the link between social production – the process of creation of meaning in the flows of interaction – and social reproduction – the process through which various forms of social order persist despite the creative and transformative capacities of actors (Giddens 1976). References Athens L (1997) Violent Criminal Acts and Actors Revisited. Champaign, IL: University of Illinois Press. Athens L (2007) Radical interactionism: going beyond Mead. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 37(2):137-165. Athens L (2009) The roots of radical interactionism. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 39(4): 387-414. Athens L (2012) Mead’s analysis of social conflict: a radical interactionist’s critique. The American Sociologist 43(4): 428-447. Athens L (2013) Radical and symbolic interactionism: demarcating their boundaries. Radical Interactionism on the Rise (Studies in Symbolic Interaction) 41(1): 1-24. Baugh K (1990) The Methodology of Herbert Blumer: Critical Interpretation and Repair. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bauman Z (1978) Hermeneutics and Social Science: Approaches to Understanding. London: Hutchinson. Becker H (1988) Herbert Blumer’s conceptual impact. Symbolic Interaction 11(1): 13-21. Blumer H (1958a) Race prejudice as a sense of group position. Pacific Sociological Review 1 (Spring): 3-7. Blumer H (1958b) Research on race relations: United States of America. International Social Science Bulletin 10: 403-447. Blumer H (1965a) The future of color line. In: McKinney J, Thompson E (eds) The South in Continuity and Change. Durham: Duke University Press, 322-336. Blumer H (1965b) Industrialization and race relations. In: Hunter G (ed.) Industrialization and Race Relations: A Symposium. London: Oxford University Press, 220-253. Blumer H (1966) Sociological implications of the thought of George Herbert Mead. American Journal of Sociology 71(5): 535-544. Blumer H (1969) Symbolic Interactionism: Perspective and Method. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall. Blumer H and Morrione T (2003) George Herbert Mead and Human Conduct. Walnut Creek, CA: AltaMira Press. Bourdieu P (1977) Outline of a Theory of Practice. London: Polity. Collins R (1988) Theoretical Sociology. Orlando: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Craib, I (1984) Modern Social Theory from Parsons to Habermas. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf. Cuff E, Sharrock W, Francis W (1998) Perspectives in Sociology. London: Routledge. Fine G (1990) Symbolic interactionism in the post-Blumerian age. In: Ritzer G (ed.) Frontiers in Social Theory: The New Syntheses. Ney York: Columbia University Press. Fine G (1993) The sad demise, mysterious disappearance, and glorious triumph of symbolic interactionism. Annual Review of Sociology 19: 61-87. Forte J (2001) Theories for Practice: Symbolic Interactionist Perspectives. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. 16 Giddens A (1976) New Rules of Sociological Method. London: Hutchinson Giddens A (1984) The Constitution of Society. Cambridge: Polity Press. Goffman E (1983) The interaction order. American Sociological Review 48(1): 1-17. Halas E (2012) Herbert Blumer on the interactional order of the democratic society. Polish Sociological Review 1(177): 3-18. Hall P (2003) Interactionism, social organization, and social processes: looking back and moving ahead. Symbolic Interaction 26(1): 33-55. Hall S (1997) Representation: Cultural Representations and Signifying Practices. London: Sage. Hall S (2006) The re-discovery of ideology: the return of the repressed in media studies. In: Storey J (ed.) Cultural Theory and Popular Culture: A Reader. London: Pearson Education. Hardy C, Palmer I and Philips N (2000) Discourse as a strategic resource. Human Relations 53(9): 1227-1248. Harvey L (1987) Myths of the Chicago School of Sociology. Aldershot, UK: Avebury. Kuhn M (1964) Major trends in symbolic interaction theory in the past twenty-five years. The Sociological Quarterly 5(1): 61-68. Laclau E, Mouffe C (2001) Hegemony and Socialist Strategy. London: Verso. Lal B (1995) Symbolic interaction theories. American Behavioral Scientist 38(3): 421-441. Lauer R, Handel W (1983) Social Psychology: The Theory and Application of Symbolic Interactionism. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall. Layder D (2006) Understanding Social Theory. London: Sage. Low J (2008) Structure, agency and social reality in Blumerian symbolic interactionism: the influence of George Simmel. Symbolic Interaction 31(3): 325-343. Lyman S (1984) Interactionism and the study of race relations at the macro-sociological level: the contribution of Herbert Blumer. Symbolic Interaction 7(1): 107-120. Lyman S, Vidich A (1988) Social Order and the Public Philosophy: An Analysis and Interpretation of the Work of Herbert Blumer. Fayetteville: University of Arkansas Press. Lyman S, Vidich A (2000) Selected Works of Herbert Blumer: A Public Philosophy for Mass Society. Champaign, IL: University of Illinois Press. McPhail C, Rexroat C (1979) Mead vs. Blumer: the divergent methodological perspectives of social behaviorism and symbolic interactionism. American Sociological Review 44(3): 449-467. Maines D (1988) Myth, text, and interaction complicity in the neglect of Blumer’s macrosociology” Symbolic Interaction 11(1): 43-57. Manis J, Meltzer B (1972) Symbolic Interaction: A Reader in Social Psychology. Boston: Allyn and Bacon. Meltzer B, Petras J, Reynolds L (1975) Symbolic Interactionism: Genesis, Varieties and Criticism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Mills C W (1940) Situated actions and vocabularies of motives. American Sociological Review 5(6): 904-913. Plummer K (1990) Herbert Blumer and the life history tradition. Symbolic Interaction 13(X): 125-144. Reynolds L, Heman-Kinney N (2003) Handbook of Symbolic Interaction. Toronto: AltaMira. Ricoeur P (1981) Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences: Essays on Language, Action and Interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sandstrom K, Martin D, Fine G (2002) Symbolic interactionism at the end of the century. In: Ritzer G, Smart R (eds) Handbook of Social Theory. London: Sage, 216-231. 17 Schiffrin, D, Tannen, D and Hamilton, H (eds) (2003) The Handbook of Discourse Analysis. Malden, MA: Blackwell. Schutz A (1964) The problem of rationality in the social world. In: Brodersen A (ed.) Collected Papers Volume 2 Studies in Social Theory. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 64-88. Schutz A (1966) Some structures of the life-world. In: Schutz I (ed.) Collected Papers Volume 3 Studies in Phenomenological Philosophy. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Scott M, Lyman S (1968) Accounts. American Sociological Review 33(1): 46-62. Seidel, G (1987) The white discursive order: the British new right’s discourse on cultural racism with particular reference to Salisbury Review. In: Zavala I, van Dijk T and Diaz-Diocratez M (eds) Approaches to Discourse, Poetics and Psychiatry. Amsterdam: Jon Benjamins Publishing Co. 39-66. Shalin D (1986) Pragmatism and social interaction. American Sociological Review 51(1): 929. Shibutani T (1988) Herbert Blumer’s contribution to twentieth-century sociology. Symbolic Interaction 11(1): 23-31. Shotter J (1980) Action, joint action, and intentionality. In: Brenner M (ed.) The Structure of Action. Oxford: Blackwell, 28-65. Stryker S (1980) Symbolic Interactionism: A Social Structural Version. Menlo Park, CA: Benjamin/Cummings. Stryker S (1988) Substance and style: an appraisal of the sociological legacy of Herbert Blumer. Symbolic Interaction 11(1): 33-42. Tucker C (1988) Herbert Blumer: a pilgrimage with pragmatism. Symbolic Interaction 11(1): 99-124. Tucker C (1990) Review of “Social order and the public philosophy: an analysis and interpretation of the work of Herbert Blumer” by Lyman S and Vidich A (1988) Social Forces 68(4): 1325-1327. Warshay, L (1975) The Current State of Sociological Theory: A Critical Interpretation. New York: David McKay. White H (1992) Identity and Control: A Structural Theory of Social Action. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Wrong D (1961) The over-socialized conception of man in modern sociology. American Sociological Review 28(2): 183-193. 18 Notes 1 Blumer occasionally elaborates on this emergent character of joint action by, for instance holding that In my judgment, the most important feature of human association is that the participants take each other into account. …Taking another person into account means being aware of him, identifying him in way, making some judgment or appraisal of him, identifying the meaning of his action, trying to find out what he has on his mind, or trying to figure out what he intends to do. … Taking each other into account in this mutual way not only relates the action of each to that of the other but intertwines the actions of both into what I would call, for lack of a better word, a transaction – a fitting of the developing action of each into that of the other to form a joint or over-bridging action. …[Such a] transaction is something other than an addition of the actions of the two individuals; these two line of action in their developing inter-relationship constitute a singleness, such as we recognize when we speak of an argument, a debate, a discussion or a fight (Blumer, 1969: 108-110, italics in the text). 2 He (1969: 71-72) also makes an attempt to pin down the factors that cause the uncertainty: Let me specify the more important of these possibilities. One, joint actions have to be initiated – and they may not be. Two, once started a joint action may be interrupted, abandoned, or transformed. Three, the participants may not make a common definition of the joint action into which they are thrown and hence may orient their acts on different premises. Four, a common definition of a joint action may still allow / wide differences in the direction of the separate lines of action and hence in the course taken by the joint action: a war is a good example. Five, new situations may arise calling for hitherto un-existing types of joint action, leading to confused exploratory efforts to work out a fitting together of acts. And six, even in the context of a commonly defined joint action, participants may be led to rely on other considerations in interpreting and defining each other’s lines of action. 3 Of course, it also should be mentioned that Blumer (1969: 115-6) does emphasise that ‘there are cases of human associations which are heavily ritualized, as in a stylised religious ceremony, wherein each overt action of each participant is definitely prescribed at each given point…’ but he nonetheless is quick to point out that ‘such instances are relatively infrequent in human group life and should not be used as prototype of human group life.’ 4 Such assessments have recently been voiced particularly within the nascent current known as radical interactionism which emphasises the impact of domination on social interaction and which takes as its main task the examination of how power is exercised in and through everyday encounters (Athens, 2007, 2009, 2012 and 2013). Although this current highlights some much-needed modifications with considerable potential for the revitalisation of symbolic interactionism, it excludes Blumer from its perspective, with the argument that his 19 approach is essentially based on the principle of sociality rather than domination (Athens, 2009). 20