* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Draft Conference Paper - Inter
Social group wikipedia , lookup
Social development theory wikipedia , lookup
Symbolic interactionism wikipedia , lookup
Frankfurt School wikipedia , lookup
Sociology of terrorism wikipedia , lookup
Development theory wikipedia , lookup
Public sociology wikipedia , lookup
Postdevelopment theory wikipedia , lookup
Sociology of culture wikipedia , lookup
Structural functionalism wikipedia , lookup
Index of sociology articles wikipedia , lookup
Sociology of knowledge wikipedia , lookup
History of sociology wikipedia , lookup
Sociological theory wikipedia , lookup
Suffering as Capability Deprivation: A Capabilities-Based Sociological Perspective Spiros Gangas 1.INTRODUCTION Sociology’s normative focus has been confirmed at several turns of the discipline. The Marxist school, as well as normative functionalism, has set the parameters for an identification of sociology with key normative issues and concerns (Strasser 1976). Mills’ (1959) clarion call for ‘sociological imagination’ has inspired many current sociologists to regenerate this committed focus (Burawoy 2005). Thus social problems are now addressed in ways that address the social causes of diverse forms of suffering, with a view to understand such painful realities and to contribute to possible repairs and therapies. Latest innovations in the discipline emerge from reclaiming ‘suffering’ and ‘evil’ as topical areas of sociological focus (Alexander 2013; Pía 2001; Wilkinson 2005). If sociology is drawn, as much of its history and contemporary efforts illustrate, to the plight of many of our fellows, then this shift towards suffering raises issues of categorial and explanatory adequacy. Without wishing to challenge the achievements of sociology in this mission (see, for instance, Wilkinson and Pickett 2010), I shall argue that in order to accomplish this goal sociologists need to revisit some of their central categories. ‘Agency’ is one of these categories and it seems to be normatively truncated through discourses that play up meta-theoretical problems and antinomies (Archer 2000; Holmwood and Stewart 1991). Whilst such debates are worthy at the epistemological level they often assume esoteric conceptual juggling and thus push the discipline away from a major goal of its mission, namely the practical engagement with social institutions, processes and actions in terms of normative validity. My working hypothesis thus is that this normative deficit can be revoked if sociology becomes attentive to the ‘capabilities approach’. In order to defend this claim, I will, briefly, advance the following theses: (1)Sociology’s current notions of agency are normatively wanting. (2)The meaning of suffering can be theorized more fruitfully if sociology addresses capabilities. And, (3) Sen’s notion of ‘capability deprivation’ improves our understanding of actual sufferings in society. 2. SOCIOLOGY, AGENCY AND SUFFERING Sociology’s heritage, particularly the normative functionalism of Durkheim and Parsons, envelops agency in institutional arrangements which are held to provide normative templates for mitigating suffering. Whilst these traditions have been much contested, their fundamental premise, namely the imperative of building morally infused institutions, is hard to discard.1 This important insight can be supplemented by a new notion of agency and the normative foundations which fortify it against suffering. If, for example, we locate suffering as a deprivation of agents’ ability to make valued choices, or even of their cognitive capabilities (learning opportunities, education, access to information), we can provide a new twist to agency. This new twist can take many forms, but two which are important, even if they appear at first glance mutually exclusive, pertain to the ‘ethical institution’ thesis advocated (the ‘Hegel-Durkheim-Parsons’ paradigm), and at the other end to the concrete patterns of choice that enable the agent to minimize suffering and the social scientist to offer relevant problem-solving aid in a piecemeal and corrigible fashion. The latter normative standpoint is based also on pragmatism’s influence on sociology and it already constitutes an emerging strand in linking capabilities to sociology (Zimmerman 2006; Holmwood 2013). Without wishing to underestimate the considerable strengths of the latter position, I propose instead that for ‘capabilities’ to become operative in sociology we need to trace the areas where capabilities converge with agency. One way to achieve this partnership is to conceptualize suffering as a deprivation of basic capacities for agency. To be sure, this is not the place to embark on a review and reconstruction of sociological theories of agency. We need, however, to recall that ‘the capacity to act’ had always played a major role in the formation of sociology and still constitutes an opportunity for further theory-building. I will thus briefly mention only one instance of sociology’s concern with ‘capabilities’, although others may be mustered (e.g. Giddens 1984). One such case is the use of the notion of ‘capacity’ in the normative functionalism of Talcott Parsons. The term ‘capacity’ ranges from cybernetic and systemic usages but it ultimately leads to the agent and her normative uplifting via ethical institutions. For instance, Parsons writes that social rights do not “concern the opportunity to express and implement the rights derived from the societal values so much as the resources and capacities necessary for this implementation. In this connection the societal community defines and presents standards for the allocation of resources to the community as a whole and to its various subsectors. The obverse of this allocative function, is the definition of the terms on which capacities, as matched with opportunities, can be involved in the process of inclusion” (1969: 260). A clarification is necessary at this stage. It concerns the transition from the idea of ‘capacity’ to the more normatively loaded idea of ‘capability’. Moral philosopher Alan Gewirth warrants this transition claiming that, capabilities denote ‘capacity-fulfillment’ (1998: 119), a nuance neutralized in the anthropological and formal notion of ‘capacity’. Moreover, capability conveys basic values of humanness and is thus better suited to be retranslated to actual functionings in society (1998: 63, n.5) The normative thrust of Parsons’ concept is directed also at his critique of utilitarianism and is evident when he connects it to discussions about social rights. However, the concept’s force is compromised given its placement in Parsons’ analytical scheme of society as a social system, which prevents it from addressing adequately instances of concrete deprivation and suffering. Despite his formalism, Parsons adds to ‘capacity’ an intriguing dimension when he connects it to suffering and evil. He writes: “If the problem of suffering comes to focus in human exposure to the impact of deprivation independent of individual agency, and that of evil, in exposure to that of consequences independent of active intentions, that of capacity focuses on the fact that, however much we may want to do something, we may be prevented to incapacity from actually doing it” (Parsons 1978: 79). This is a powerful intuition on Parsons’ part that sets the stage for sustaining the ‘capacity’ – ‘capability’ transition in sociology. 3.THE CONTRIBUTION OF THE ‘CAPABILITIES APPROACH’: SUFFERING AS ‘CAPABILITY DEPRIVATION’. In an important attempt to systematize suffering from a sociological standpoint and to offer plausible grounds for inter-disciplinary linkages, Wilkinson (2005) makes only passing reference to the capabilities approach. He refers selectively to Nussbaum’s views on compassion in orderto gather further evidence for the thesis he proposes, namely that there is always a residual and recalcitrant dimension to suffering that eschews rationalization. This view captures indeed a major difficulty with regard to explaining evil and suffering, let alone mitigating it. Yet, Wilkinson fails to do justice to the reverse standpoint shared by the advocates of the capabilities approach. This is no other than the belief that much suffering can be comprehended rationally, and addressed with adequate theoretical and policy tools. Wilkinson thus locates the promise of a sociological response to human suffering to the following requirement: “that we amplify unsettling questions of meaning and morality, that we work to expose the apparent senselessness of the experience of injustice, violence and oppression, and that we make abundantly clear the terminal failure of understanding that takes place under the attempt to render the cultural grammar of suffering accountable to the rationality of scientific analysis” (Wilkinson 2005: 45). Wilkinson’s thesis certainly raises important questions about the adequacy of current notions of suffering and the tensions in our theoretical categories. What remains doubtful, however, is whether Wilkinson has exhausted the potential of the available tools that make us comprehend suffering and work towards its therapy. The capabilities approach is virtually ignored by Wilkinson and thus, as I argue, its claims to offer a diverse inventory of concepts and policies that mitigate suffering, becomes neutralized. But what are the main tenets of the capabilities approach? Briefly put, the capabilities approach puts to the fore the agent’s ability to have the ‘substantive freedom’ to achieve ‘various lifestyles’ (Sen 1999: 75). ‘Capability’ thus conveys the freedom that the agent has to achieve alternative functional combinations (. Sen expands the notion of capability and supplants it with the normative and empirical idea of ‘agency’. ‘Agency’ permits Sen to conceptualize action within a wider set of institutional arrangements contrary to rationalchoice theory. Sen writes: I am using the term ‘agent’ […] in its older-and “grander”-sense as someone who acts and brings about change, and whose achievements can be judged in terms of some external criteria as well. This work is particularly concerned with the agency role of the individual as a member of the public and as a participant in economic, social and political actions (varying from taking part in the market to being involved, directly or indirectly, in individual or joint activities in political and other spheres). (Sen 1999: 19). What is clear from this indicative statement is that agency’s empowerment is premised on the realization of basic capabilities. The set of basic ‘capabilities’, which signal achievable benchmarks on the basis of which communities and individuals canreflect and pursue the lifechoicesthey have reason to value, include the capabilities of: 1. Life; 2. Bodily Health; 3. Bodily Integrity; 4. Senses, Imagination, and Thought; 5.Emotions; 6. Practical Reason; 7. Affiliation; 8. Other Species; 9. Play; 10. Political and Material Control over one’s Environment (see, for example, Nussbaum 1992: 216-223; 2000: 78-80). It is important to stress at this stage that although capabilities may raise the normative bar too high (a source of dispute between Sen and Nussbaum), even if we take this assumption, we need to point out that its approach to combating suffering and deprivations is a modest one, but not for the reasons Wilkinson advocates. Rather, the ‘modesty’ of this research program stems from affirming both the complexity and the indeterminacy of certain contexts where policies become an urgency and duty, as well, from an imperative to secure the voices of those who suffer from calamities, famines and other evils. Whilst this may not always be possible, the focus on capability-empowerment constitutes a core value of the program. Thus it preserves some of the ‘recalcitrance’ of suffering that Wilkinson recognizes, but is free of the quietism that less generous critics may see lurking in his approach to suffering. That Sen’s approach is animated by a passion to contribute to combating diverse sources of suffering in society is nothing novel. What, however, is not immediately obvious is the source for this normative passion. Because Sen’s intellectual backdrop stems primarily from economics, the ‘scientific’ outlook of the capabilities approach provides few opportunities for giving to suffering per se amajor role. Yet, suffering retains a prominent position in his writings in at least two major ways. The first seems to fulfill a trope that plays up lived experience linking the man to his ideas, supplanting Sen’s scientific prose with an evocative and moving autobiographical icon. This is no other than the recurring story of Kader Mia, a daily laborer, who had come to Dhaka to seek work and a bit of earning to feed his family. Although warned by his wife not to seek work in a Hindu area, particularly dangerous then due to communal riots between Hindus and Muslims, Kader Mia had no alternative but to take that risk. Chased by communal thugs he was eventually stabbed, in front of Amartya Sen’s eyes who was ten at the time, and died later in the hospital (Sen 1999: 8). In another book that deals more directly with suffering, Sen invokes this episodeagain and confesses that “the terrible connection between economic poverty and comprehensive unfreedom (even the lack of freedom to live) was a profoundly shocking realization that hit my young mind with overpowering force” (2006: 173). Through this personal recollection Sen infuses his programme with one of the countless disturbing images of suffering that many have encountered. He manages, however, to connect economic unfreedom with political deprivations that stem from all sorts of identity-particularisms and nominal affirmations of collective and group identity. Such vivid imagery is theorized by a neighboring voice, economist Vivian Walsh (1961), who is among the first to connect evil and suffering to the problem of scarcity. Inspired by an episode from D.H. Lawrence’s The First Lady Chatterley, Walsh confesses: “to see someone dying slowly for want, as it were, of some constituent of the air a human being needs to breathe […]; to watch helplessly the slow dying of such an expiring spirit is to be acquainted with scarcity. Once seen, it is never forgotten” (1961: 31). Marx, for his part, presents the case of Mary Anne Walkley who having “worked uninterruptedly for 26½ hours, with sixty other girls” in factory rooms which provided “only ⅓ of the necessary quantity of air, measured in cubic feet” died of apoplexy from overwork in crowded and poorly ventilated rooms (Marx [1867] 1990: 364-365). Wilkinson proposes “that we take the ongoing difficulty of ‘making sense’ of human suffering not as an indication of the requirement for a more coherent rationalization of the specific components of this experience, but rather as an involvement with what suffering ‘is’ in human experience” (2005: 44). Unlike him, but in the spirit of Marx and Walsh, Sen refused to see in Kader Mia’s death the ‘inexplicable’ essence of suffering that sociologists, like Wilkinson, render an aporia that may keep social science active in combating ‘suffering’. The second suffering motif turns such episodes into a narrative and a category wide enough to encompass normative justification, explanatory force and policy relevance. ‘Capability deprivation’ captures suffering in terms of scarcity and want; however, its function in Sen’s program is not confined only to the domain of identifying and combating major deprivations. It also contains an enabling dimension that addresses human potentialities and thus bears direct relevance to Marx’s defense of species-being potential against alienation (Bull 2007; Dean 2009, Gangas 2014; Nussbaum 1990). Suffering conceived as capability deprivation ‘tweaks’ the murky notion of alienation and clarifies much of what was latent in Marx but was compromised from the moment the suffering from alienation became a grand-narrative for modernity’s pathologies; a notable case in point is the Frankfurt School’s tendency to subsume agency under the grip of instrumental rationality (e.g. Horkheimer 1974). Instead of getting trapped in the ‘system’-‘anti-system’ logic of total alienation and radical resistance, Sen opts for a research programme that openly confronting sufferings of all kinds, responding to local, regional, national and global challenges. Its ‘radical’ reformism bears on dissociating policies for capabilityempowerment from prevalent binary logics. 4. CONCLUSION In this paper I have tried to create some space for introducing the research programme of ‘capabilities’ in sociological theory through the discourse on suffering. I defended the position that this discourse, which under the umbrella of suffering includes inequality, injustice and all sorts of deprivations–relative and absolute–, is part and parcel with the capabilities approach. But as the recent turn of sociology to ‘public’ sociology demonstrates, what animates such a trend reveals an endemic concern with normative issues many of which bear on suffering. In this call for a capabilities-based approach to suffering, I part with grand narratives of modernity’s pathogenies (Alexander 2013, Mann 2004), although I acknowledge their force and appeal. The problem with such approaches is that they reify contradiction. Jeffrey Alexander’s claims, for instance, that ‘the values of civil society are as bad as they are good’ (2013: 111) sanctioning simultaneously integration and exclusion (hence, yielding inevitable suffering for some), is a case in point. If this is the case then one can expect suffering to reemerge from any sort of social arrangements, which seem to have inbuilt and insurmountable antinomies. Regardless of the validity of such approaches to modernity, a capabilities-based approach in sociology would be geared towards mitigating suffering, empowering the agent’s ability to make valued choices across fields that remain obfuscated by the so-called ‘discontents’ of modernity thesis. Repairing suffering is a feasible undertaking via capabilities because focusing on what a person can actually achieve in specific contexts and arrangements generates policies that improve people’s lives without being based on some algorithm solution that precedes the application of policy, thus taking place exclusively behind the back of the people involved. Moreover, such correctives and ameliorations to suffering run the risk, for the advocates of radical politics, of being seen as ‘reformist’ since they cannot penetrate into the heart of capitalism’s crisis, of fundamentalism’s Manichean world-view or of the deeper reasons that cause the depletion of the planet (for a ‘crisis-running-berserk’ critique of most ‘systemic’ flaws in the current politico-economic order, see Beck 2012). This short presentation suggested that a shift towards capabilities has the advantage of attaching to various sufferings an explanation which tends to give a voice to the suffering person, rather than filtering this voice through ideological codes (i.e. ‘progressive-conservative’, ‘radicalreformist’, ‘capitalist-socialist’, ‘libertarian-communitarian’ among others)2 which often perpetuate the very false-consciousness of the suffering agent whose potentialities they wish to restore. The capabilities approach does not uphold such facile utopianism. Avoiding doing so, it approaches suffering with weapons gathered from an open-ended inventory of diverse agents, groups, collectivities and organizations.3 Notes 1 Hegel remains the exemplar of this paradigm basically through his assumption and systematic analysis of ‘suffering from indeterminacy’. This pathology stems when the moral point of view, already within the matrix of ethical modern institutions, becomes detached from its wider moral network of social relations and thus, as Honneth argues, leads to ‘an inability to act’ (Honneth 2010: 41-2), damaging the cognitive and moral capacities of social actors. The corrective that Hegel offers can lead to a theory of intersubjectivity, in line with Sen (see Allen 2006). 2 A forceful critic of such stringent codes is Luhmann (1982: 166-189). Luhmann, however, works his theory of society through the antinomic codes that are also palatable to Alexander (2013: 125). In an essay on barbarism, Luhmann at his most normative, and scarce, moments, mocks attempts at ‘all-inclusion’ of the causes of suffering and cautions the ‘defender’ of existences ‘reduced to the bodily’ of smuggling ‘bourgeois’ codes (capabilities perhaps?) to those who are by definition excluded from ‘bourgeois’ values (Luhmann 1999: 269-70). This criticism could have the capabilities approach as its target; what Luhmann seem to bracket is the fact that within the capabilities approach the transpositional scrutiny of one’s precarious and damaged life is, has indeed, been possible (the Kader Mia incident is a familiar confirming instance of countless that can be mustered). 3 This is a modification of Feyerabend’s (1978) epistemological position of ‘anything goes’. Seeking synergies may not involve an indeterminate range of allies: fascists, communist tyranny sympathizers, fundamentalists cannot, by definition, be considered as ‘allies’ in this effort to strengthen capabilities and these categories would, in all likelihood, be omitted in Feyerabend’s call to openness. So my invocation of Feyerabend has little, if anything, to do with endorsing epistemological or moral relativism. Bibliography Alexander, J., The Dark Side of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity, 2013. Allen, M.P. ‘Hegel between non-domination and expressive freedom: capabilities, perspectives, democracy’, Philosophy and Social Criticism, 32(4): 493-512, 2006. Archer, M., Being Human: The Problem of Agency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Beck, U., Twenty Observations on a World in Turmoil.Cambridge: Polity. Bull, M. ‘Vectors of the biopolitical’, New Left Review 45: 7-25 (May-June), 2007. Burawoy, M., ‘For Public Sociology’, American Sociological Review 70(1): 4-28, 2005. Dean, H., ‘Critiquing capabilities: the distractions of a beguiling concept’, Critical Social Policy 29(2): 261-278, 2009. Feyerabend, P. Against Method. London, Verso, 1978. Gangas, S. ‘Alienation as capability deprivation: reconstructing a sociological concept’, Social Science Information 53 (1), forthcoming March 2014. Gangas, S. ‘Values, Crisis and Resistance: Prospects for Freedom Reconsidered’. Roots, Rites and Sites of Resistance: The Banality of Good. Cheliotis, L.K. (ed.), Houndmills, Basingstoke: Palgrave 2010. Gewirth, A., Self-Fulfillment. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998. Giddens, A. The Constitution of Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984. Holmwood, J. ‘Public Reasoning without Sociology: Amartya Sen’s Theory of Justice’, Sociology (forthcoming), 2013 (available online at: http://soc.sagepub.com/content/early/2013/03/11/0038038512470767) Holmwood, J. and Stewart, A., Explanation and Social Theory.Houndmills, Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1991. Honneth, A., The Pathologies of Individual Freedom: Hegel’s Social Theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton and Oxford, 2010 (2001). Horkheimer, M. Critique of Instrumental Reason. NY: Seabury, 1974. Luhmann, N.The Differentiation of Society. NY: Columbia University Press, 1982. Luhmann, N., ‘Beyond barbarism’. In Luhmann Explained: From Souls to Systems by HansGeorg Müller. Chicago and La Salle, Illinois: Open Court. Mann, M., The Dark Side of Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005. Marx, K. Capital. Volume I. Penguin, London, 1990 (1867). Mills, C.W. The Sociological Imagination. Harmonndsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1983 (1959). Nussbaum, M.C., ‘Aristotelian Social Democracy’, Liberalism and the Good, Douglass, R.B., Mara, G.M., and Richardson, H. S., (eds),New York and London: Routledge, 1990. Nussbaum, M. C. ‘Human Functioning and Social Justice. In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism’, Political Theory 20(2): 202-246, 1992 Nussbaum, M. C. Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. Parsons, T. Politics and Social Structure. NY: The Free Press, 1969. Parsons, T. Action Theory and the Human Condition. NY: The Free Press, 1978. Pía, L.(ed.) Rethinking Evil: Contemporary Perspectives.Berkeley: The University California, of Press, 2001. Sen, A. Development as Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. Sen, A., Identity and Violence: The Illusions of Destiny. London: Penguin, 2006. Strasser, H. The Normative Structure of Sociology: Conservative and Emancipatory Themes in Social Thought. London: RKP, 1976. Walsh, V. Scarcity and Evil.Englewood-Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1961. Wilkinson, I. Suffering: A Sociological Introduction. Cambridge: Polity, 2005. Wilkinson, R. and K. Pickett.The Spirit Level: Why Equality is Better for Everyone. London: Penguin,2010. Zimmerman, B. ‘Pragmatism and the Capability Approach: Challenges in Social Theory and Empirical Research’, European Journal of Social Theory 9(4): 467-484, 2006.