* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Struttura del volume
Social Darwinism wikipedia , lookup
Social Bonding and Nurture Kinship wikipedia , lookup
Developmental psychology wikipedia , lookup
Postdevelopment theory wikipedia , lookup
Other (philosophy) wikipedia , lookup
History of social work wikipedia , lookup
Sociology of the family wikipedia , lookup
Social exclusion wikipedia , lookup
Sociology of knowledge wikipedia , lookup
Social development theory wikipedia , lookup
Differentiation (sociology) wikipedia , lookup
Children's geographies wikipedia , lookup
Social group wikipedia , lookup
Social contract wikipedia , lookup
Structural functionalism wikipedia , lookup
Social theory wikipedia , lookup
Unilineal evolution wikipedia , lookup
Children rights and contemporary sociological perspectives of childhood GUIDO MAGGIONI - CLAUDIO BARALDI Summary. The aim of this paper is to summarize recent developments in two perspectives on children and childhood which in recent years have come simultaneously to the foreground in social sciences and law. In social sciences, a growing consensus has developed in considering children as active social agents and as agents of change in society. Sociologists developed new conceptual frameworks and appropriate research methods to explore children’s experiences, some authors advocating the need to take a child’s perspective. At the same time, sociological studies have moved away from a developmental socialization perspective and searched for deeper insights in childhood, mainly viewing it as a social construction and children as a permanent structural part of society. In law, the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child, finalized in 1989, has constructed moral precepts concerning the well-being of children in the form of legal or quasi-legal rights. The language of rights has met in recent years with wide acceptance as a means to empower the powerless, and children have been typically viewed as a separate group needing rights to rescue them from “evils” of contemporary society. Without taking sides in the political and ideological debate which opposes child “savers” and child “liberationists”, the authors examine the links between the view that children are active social agents and the widespread support for children rights and child citizenship. The former trend in the social sciences is similar in content and aims to the latter in law: they are both connected to the idea of the autonomy of childhood and of individual children, but they are both ridden with paradoxes which may undermine this latter idea. 1. In recent years a growing consensus has emerged in the social sciences on the consideration of children as active social agents and as agents of change in society. In the last two decades sociologists have tried to develop new conceptual frameworks and appropriate research methods to explore children’s experiences, some authors advocating the need to take a child’s perspective. At the same time, sociological studies moved swiftly away from a developmental socialization perspective and searched for deeper insights into childhood, mainly viewing it as a social construction and children as a permanent structural part of society. In law, in the same years, the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child has been adopted and then ratified by the overwhelming majority of the countries of the world. The 1989 Convention constructs moral precepts concerning the well-being of children in the form of legal or quasi-legal rights. The child is viewed as a person who is endowed with a panoply of rights, in a perspective that has met an incomparably 1 bigger success, and a much broader media recognition, than the self-determination vindicated by the now defunct children’s liberation movement of the Seventies. In this essay we will summarize how both these perspectives on children and childhood almost simultaneously came to the fore in recent years in social sciences on the one hand (paragraph 2), and in law on the other (paragraph 3). We'll suggest that the contemporary picture in sociology and in law is ridden with such openly conflicting perceptions of children and childhood, which reflect paradoxes of contemporary society. First of all, we'll suggest that in both these domains the “older” perspectives on children and childhood have not disappeared. In the social science, and in public opinion as purported by mass media, a developmental view of childhood is still holding its own, that can be linked with the socialization approach to the sociological study of children. In law and social policy the “child best interests”, as they are perceived by relevant adults, are still held as the principle of paramount importance for public action involving children and the promotion of children’s welfare, much more than children "rights" . Even without dealing with different perceptions of children and childhood maintained in religion, morals, economics and so on, and restricting ourselves to sociology and law, we'll suggest that late modernity account of children is not to be described in terms of a radical paradigm change. It's true that some new elements are added, but at the same time most of modernity basic tenets on children are confirmed, and are narrated in the language of autonomy. It will then be suggested that the perception of children as social actors and the relevance acquired by the idea of children's rights are not distinct and independent developments (paragraph 4). While the social constructionist perspective is the foundation for a new sociology of childhood, the notion of children as autonomous social actors is the main support for the declaration of the universal rights of children . The two perspectives have been gradually unfolding in close connection, through significant, if not continuous, relationships. In fact, they represent distinct ways to observe the modern aspects of childhood. Autonomy, ambiguously presented both as a fact and as a goal to be achieved, is a normative ideal perpetually undermined by concomitant anxieties, old and new, about children and their fate. Theory and ideology are confusedly associated in this perspective, as it shifts between two opposite social representation : that of a strong child in command, and that of a weak child at risk. The paradox arises from the evolution of modern society, increasingly producing the conditions for autonomy, in spite of the persisting relevance of integration. 2. In the last two decades a momentous shift seems to have occurred in the sociological approaches to childhood, which some would describe as a complete U-turn. The allpervasive notion of the child as a socialized personality system who internalizes social roles and values, seems to have been replaced by the conceptualization of the child as an active subject, co-constructing sociality together with other agents. As a consequence of 2 this radical redefinition, a new map of the territory of childhood would have to be drawn. If this description probably overemphasizes change, it must be admitted that in the past not many theorists, in general sociology, came to terms with childhood and children as a theoretically challenging issue. Those theorists who did (Mead, Parsons) considered it as a reflection of the more general problem of the relationship between individuals and society. They developed a socialization perspective which stimulated research almost exclusively bent on studying children development and socialization, with an emphasis on the interiorization of social norms and values on the path to adulthood. This approach required a thorough analysis of the social structure as it surrounds children, influencing their development and affecting their behaviour in a variety of ways and patterns. The focus was not so much on childhood itself as in the reproduction of social conformity, in how society reproduces and strengthens itself by the transmission of social values and norms through generations. This choice of observing socialization processes was consistent with a sociological approach primarily interested in society as its own object. The child as an active social agent was not conceptualized, as the socialization process was broadly perceived as a linear course along which the child passively acquires social knowledge and adapts itself to society. In the socialization approach, children are observed as socially determined through internalization of roles and values, but in spite of this they are also observed as autonomous personality systems, that is as "persons in roles" (Parsons and Bales, 1955, Parsons, 1977). Contemporary critics claim that this approach subordinated sociology to the paradigms dominating (then as now) in psychology and pedagogy, which understand childhood in terms of developmental stages and ignore it as a social category. In more recent years the active agent perspective has attracted widespread support, and it can be recognized as the trade-mark of the so-called “new” sociologists of childhood, albeit somewhat different emphasis can be detected accordingly to the different sources these “new” sociologists base their work on: some of them adopt an interaction perspective (Denzin 1979), others give more weight to agency (Giddens 1984, 1991), or, again, stress other conceptual elements like social actors, coconstruction . This new trend in childhood sociological studies also dictates that the context of children’s everyday life experiences should be given special attention, and that children should be understood as co-agents in the construction of social reality. The focus is now on the correlations between individual action and social reproduction (Qvortrup et al. 1994). An example of this kind of theory is Corsaro's interpretative reproduction (Corsaro, 1997). In a different but closely linked perspective, this very aim to "give voice" to the child as an autonomous social agent, is adequately achieved in the theory of the social agent which appears to be held as a general framework for analysis in research concerning children in families (Thompson 1997). Contemporary social studies on children are not so neatly split in two unambiguously distinct and conflicting approaches. Far from being the utterly separate worlds they sometimes are purported to be, symbolic interactionism, phenomenology 3 and social constructionism are strongly intertwined, as can easily be seen in the results of theorethically grounded research. Above all, at the level of “pure” theory, the social constructionist approach, in some cases relying on Vygotskij's suggestions (Harré 1984, Shotter, 1984), seems to be linked to Parsons' theory, with which it shares the view of children's persons as social products. For the new sociology of childhood, socialization may still have partial validity as a theoretical tool only as a process in which children actively respond to adult effort to pattern their life and shape their future. In a different but closely linked perspective, this very aim to portrait the child as an autonomous social agent is achieved in the theory of the social agent by Paul Thompson (1997), who emphasizes children competence in constructing the meanings of adults actions and behaviour inside family networks depicted as systems of emotional and social relationships. Children's decisions, preferences and choices strongly influence intergenerational cultural transmission and generational differentiation. However, the new paradigm of the sociology of childhood can be perceived as an attempt to integrate the concepts of intepretation and active social construction with the analysis of social categorization: children are seen both as actors engaged in social constructions for themselves and others, and as a normatively determined social category (childhood). Hence a new tension between autonomy and dependence, in continuity with the old sociological theme of socialization, but in a new constructivist mould. Social structures influence children, and in so doing they operate for the consolidation of society. The focus seems to have been readjusted again, but with the same attention for the reproduction of social conformity. This connection is not new. These same themes of social construction and social membership were seen in the light of the polarity autonomy-dependence in the pioneering and seminal work of Philippe Ariès (1960). Ariès main thesis, and the one which met with more widespread acceptance, is that childhood is a social and historically constructed category, as demonstrated both by different representations of children in different societies, and by the far from universal recognition of childhood as a distinct social category. Superseding individualistic and developmental perspectives, Ariès opened the door to a new conceptualization of childhood as a permanent structure of modern society (Sgritta 1988). Ariès also added that in modern Europe the "discovery" of childhood, while stimulating growing concern and more attentive care for children, for quite the same reason produced their total inclusion in the context of the family and gave birth to a segregative educational system. As a result of these trends, social control was strongly increased, children were assigned, as individuals, to a marginal role in society and made more dependent from the adult world. In this way, also the new sociology of childhood is involved in paradoxical outcomes: children are considered as both endowed with, and deprived of, personal autonomy. The social constructivist-interactionist approach observes children as socially active but also as social constructions: they can manage social action (they are competent in agency), but they are also reproduced through society. Socially active children are also members of a socially constructed social category known as childhood, 4 which varies enormously in space and time in its definition and scope, as childhood is itself a socially constructed entity. 3. Approximately at the same time as the “new” sociology of childhood firstly emerged and then asserted itself in mainstream sociological studies of children, after long and protracted negotiations and debates between representative of states and nongovernmental organizations, the 1989 United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child was born. For many active participants and commentators alike, the Convention amounted not only to a revolution in the history of law perception of the child, but also to a turning point in the very history of childhood. It has been claimed that it would be wrong only to perceive it as a new step in the long process, which began over a century ago, of extending the protection of the law on the child to advance its best interests. Rather, the Convention brings to a “higher” level, in the realm of rights, the new faith in the power of the law to protect children and their future well-being. The Convention truly contains an impressive set of “legal” rights, which can be summarized as follows: 1) General rights, as the right to life, freedom of expression, thought and religion, the right to information and privacy; 2) Rights concerning the civil status, including the right to acquire nationality, to preserve one’s identity, to remain with parents (unless their best interests dictate otherwise) and the right to be reunited with their family; 3) Rights requiring protective mesasures, to protect children from economic and sexual exploitation, prevent drug abuse and other forms of neglect and abuse; 4) Rights concerned with development and welfare, including the right for a reasonable standard of living, to health and basic services, to social security, education and leisure; 5) Rights concerning children in special circumstances (refugee children, orphans, etc.) and / or with special needs (Freeman, 1996). As it can easily be seen by the last three group of rights in the list above, the language of rights has been used also to cover what could more exactly be described as obligations, of specific adults with a parenting responsibility or of welfare agencies, or ultimately the state. While actually maintaining an emphasis on protection and welfare, the Convention articulates those issues in the language of rights. Taken all together, these rights seem to be constituted in a confusing and not coherent matrix of ideas concerning survival, protection, development and participation. However, what is clear is that a discursive space has been established within which children are now seen as individuals whose autonomy should be safeguarded and fostered (James et al. 1998). Some commentators have questioned the wisdom of this unlimited and admittedly confused extension of children’s rights. Some pro-rights activists would answer their critics saying that whether such rights are good or not to children, is beside the point : children should be granted rights for the same reason that adults were. By being presented with rights with which to defend themselves and promote the 5 fulfillement of their desires and needs, children for the first time in history could be recognized as complete human beings, with integrity and personality, and with the ability to fully participate in society. But here lies a paradox: giving children specific rights has the effect of drawing attention to the fact that children cannot expect to have equal rights to adults. It serves to reinforce the adult\child distinction, while at the same time defines children privileged, but also discriminated citizens. Children have “their” rights because they do not have, and cannot be expected to have, full citizen’s rights (King 1997). The very fact that a Convention declaring the rights of children was so strongly felt to be needed, emphasizes the difference between children and adults. If children’s rights are stated as not being the same as those of adults, then children are confirmed in a minority status which clearly requires interpreters of their needs and wishes, not too different in their position and function to the guardians or tutors of the past. Therefore, not only through the survival of almost intact welfare protective policies, but also through the notion of separate children’s rights the Convention refrains from a clear-cut and radical assumption on the self-determination of children, distancing itself from the liberationists utopia of the Seventies. Unconvinced by the heroic view of childhood and children which this choice would imply, the Convention, together with prevailing public opinion and expert advice, including social scientists, seem to rely on the same image of the child as a weak powerless human being, which was at the bottom of the protectionist account. Potential victim of adults neglect and abuse, children still need the support of adult advocates that really know what is best for them. The ideal of protection that has been articulated in the language of rights on account of the very wide acceptance this form of expression has met in recent years. Rights as a means to empower the powerless, are seen as instrumental to the betterment of the conditions of separate, minority group and children have been typically viewed as such, needing rights to protect them from the “evils” of contemporary society. The image of the suffering child has come to symbolize all the injustices of the world, and giving rights to children has been stated as the way to protect children against all those injustices. It is not by chance that the children’s rights movement has put so much faith in the transformation, both nationally and internationally, of children’s rights into legally constituted rights. They are formulated as law, because there is no other code for modern society to openly state its fears and hopes for children and their future, and at the same time to hold out the possibility of alleviating those fears and realizing those hopes (King 1997)1. However, this is unlikely. In fact, while the entire framework of the Convention is built upon concepts of freedom, the prevailing view of the child is still that of a subject to be protected, first of all from the potentially negative consequences of his\her “immature” and “unwise” acts, choices and behaviour (Ronfani 1997). The child continues to be seen as an imperfect human being, in a developmental perspective which tends to describe it as a weak subject, with limited autonomy, slowly 1 This faith in the power of law probably stems from a disillusionment and a lack of faith in other system (such as politics, economics, science and religion) to protect children and their future well being, more than from a positive appreciation of law. 6 developing under adult guidance from a primary dependency to the final achievement of adult rationality and, as a consequence, independence. Two seemingly contradictory regulatory codes are thus embodied in the Convention: the one seeks to grant them autonomy, the other seeks to protect children and promote their welfare through paternalistic measures. Programmes of protection from abuse and programmes of promotion of rights lead to very different directions: how is it possible to combine a request for increasing protection with the expectation that children should be given their own public voice and be liberated from adults overwhelming power of direction ? As a consequence of this paradoxical construction, pretended rights endlessly proliferate, while the problem of the entitlement to their use is not consistently tackled with. As it contradictorily describes children both as passive victims of society and as makers of their own destiny, the Convention seems to be in touch with contemporary opinion, where children are regularly observed not only as weak, immature, not capable of decisional autonomy, but also as potential victims of adults' action from which they must be protected . Actually, at the same time as there is a dynamic towards autonomous children, other contemporaries social practices point in the opposite directions, emphasizing children’s separateness, difference and need to be guided and tutored. Children are arguably now more closely surrounded by surveillance and social regulations than ever before: <<Childhood is the most intensely governed part of personal existence.... the modern child has become the focus of innumerable projects that purport to safeguard it from physical, sexual and moral danger, to ensure its “normal” development...>> (Rose 1989, 121). The ideology of child protection and the concomitant attempt to increase the regulation of children’s behaviour certainly dates back to early modernity, but in late modernity it has taken new meanings and directions. In the risk society (Beck 1992) parents increasingly identify the world outside the home as one from which their children must be shielded and in relation to which they must devise strategies of risk reduction. Even the boundaries of the family are held to be at risk of penetration by insidious alien technologies, like the Internet (James et al.1998). At the same time, they are also thought of as responsible subjects capable to decide for themselves. And in some areas of late modernity society other new descripitions of children are being drawn : a heroic social representation of the child as an independent being, capable of self-development, albeit with some help from adult experts who write guide-lines for their self-care, teaching them how to behave when parents and teachers are too busy to take care of them. Latch-key children are tentatively presented as children in self-care, what was perceived as adult neglect might now be reshaped as a condition consistent with the development of a competent child (Hochschild 1995; Kyllönen 1997). The paradox must go on. The paradoxical unity of children's autonomy and children's protection is enhanced by the inclusion of every individual under 18 in the catch-all category of childhood. It is not necessary to share a developmental approach, to observe that fundamental characteristics are sharply differentiated in adolescents and in young children and that they are commonly expected to enjoy quite different degrees of 7 personalization and rights. The combination of promotion/protection and age differences creates further problems. It seems obvious that in our society young children must be considered relatively dependent from a social and material point of view, so that protection is particularly relevant for them, while adolescents can be considered largely autonomous, so that any expansion of the potential for autonomy is of the utmost importance for them. However, while the promotion of personalization and autonomy in the first phase of childhood is strongly asserted, society seems to need a strict and controlled welfare protection for an ever-growing number of adolescents. In this view, children should coherently be denied the ability to autonomously claim their own rights. When they are too young to speak for themselves, because of their biologically or socially constructed inability to do so, adults should take it upon themselves to speak for them. Even if some children are deemed to be old enough to speak their minds as individuals, they could not be taken seriously as a group able to promote the common interests of children as a social category. Given this kind of paradoxes, the Convention creates an uneasy relationship between welfare rights and autonomy rights . While autonomy rights directly pertain to children's actions, welfare rights pertain to adults' actions, first of all to parenting and caring . The attempt to formulate in the language of rights both the emancipation of children from adults, on one side, and the attribution of educational responsibility and control power to adults, on the other side, is an excessively ambitious and confusing project. The paradoxical construction of rights makes it even more difficult to determine the content of the needs that should be protected and of their corresponding interests. It is, therefore, an extremely arduous task to turn them in legally constituted rights, as it is their application in national law systems: in contemporary society it is unlikely to achieve consensus on the definition of normal and legitimate practices and deviant and illegitimate ones. A universal moral code which can be used for evaluation of social events is not a viable proposition anymore, if ever it was2. In this context, the child's interest may justify very different and arbitrary evaluations and practices (Ronfani 1997). It may become a means for the imposition of ideologies about familial and parental relations and about educational and pedagogic patterns, as children's interests are not self-asserted . It is true that some adults feel entitled to articulate them in detail, perhaps while listening to the voice of their “inner child”. As it is well known, in the last couple of centuries there has never been any shortage of self-appointed child advocates ready and willing to state what is good for the child and what is not. In short, the concept of rights implies the ability to use them, while the concept of protection is linked to notions of weakness and immaturity. A contradiction surfaces between children's spontaneous actions and adults' actions interpreting, orienting and channeling desires, i.e., using power. It is very difficult to imagine the exercise of individual rights by agents who are considered as only potentially autonomous. 2 Typically, in their efforts to achieve these ambitious aims, advocates of children's rights are frequently accused to impose western values on different cultures and traditions: the survival of aboriginal and immigrant minorities is thought to be endangered when western-inspired policies undermine traditional cultural traits or economic functions deeply embedded in the basic structure of society. 8 4. Moving to a second order observation of the recent trend towards children rights, it is possible to identify close links between the growing acceptance of the view that children are active social agents and the widespread recent support for children rights. The former trend, which has developed in the social sciences, is similar in content and aims to the latter which has emerged in law. The recognition of children’s rights is leading social scientists to believe that children are active social agents, creating and recreating the social world they live in: as a German writer puts it, we understand children as independent social actors and we cannot consider them as objects of adult’s actions or victims of social processes not only for scientific reasons, but also because this perspective can not be politically justified in the terms of children’s rights (Zinnecker). Of course, the connection is working also the other way round, and the influence can be reciprocated. The law system must likewise construct its own theory of childhood to support its view of children’s rights, and for this purpose it can avail itself of recent developments in sociological theory. The scientific notion of the child as a social agent can easily open the way to ideological assumptions concerning the autonomy of the child and its competence to handle complex situations without (or even against) parent or adult advice. The image of the child as a strategic social actor is coherent with the post-anti-parsonsian sociology of action and is strictly linked to the notion of a strong, competent child which from a comparatively early age can claim the rights set out in the more “advanced” parts of the Convention. In attempting a description of the structural foundations of children's observations and conditions, we have to start from the notion that the connection between the theory of the child as a social actor and the ideology of children's rights is mediated by the concept of autonomy. A full citizenship requires autonomous social actors, capable to express themselves in multifarious social contexts, in economy, education, politics, law and so on. For this reason, society creates the structural conditions conducive to an increasing social importance of autonomy. It is a paradoxical relevance, because of the simultaneous attempt to preserve integration and normative expectations of membership. From a structural point of view, the interest in autonomy and the following paradoxes are connected to the personalizaion process in modern society. Personalization is a consequence of an important structural change in Western society, which began to take place in the sixteenth-seventeenth century: with the growth of a functional differentiation inside society, individuals become persons. They can no more primarily be thought of as members of groups and families: they must rely on themselves, constructing self-confidence and self-identity. In the different forms and contexts of societal communication, they are treated as autonomous, i.e., as unique and specific human beings, fully responsible for their choices. The paradoxical result of the modern social construction of persons in communication is the socialization of a individualized mind, giving an increasing importance to the sense of autonomy and selfrooting. The social construction of individuals as persons is functional to a society requiring each of its members to be a competent and a responsible participant in multiple and differentiated social contexts. Personalization entails a loss of 9 exclusiveness in social membership and engenders multiple inclusions in differentiated social systems. Consequently, an individual can no more rely on his/her membership of a group or a category: as a person, each individual, singled out in society, can trust only in himself (and, later, in herself), to be available for partial inclusion in different contexts, in different times and in different ways. Obviously, the personalization process is full of ambivalences. In spite of the evolution towards personalization, pre-existing features of society are still positively evaluated, such as group membership, identification in communities and significant others. Furthermore, protection and obligations are considered crucial issues in stating and implementing children's rights. Consequently, the action of society is full of paradoxes: lack of personalization is increasingly observed as a serious problem. While the social sciences can consider autonomy as a false or insignificant problem, at the core of children's condition in our society is the aim to promote and protect their personalization, and at the same time supply them with adequate provisions enabling them to attain personal autonomy, the most important goal of child development. Fundamental personal rights are the product of contemporary culture, crossing all the social systems, because personalization is a general problem for all the social systems in modern society. In our times the most important and delicate context in which personalization takes place is childhood, a phase in the life-course in which individuals are perceived as humans in development, who are controversially defined either as persons or as persons to be. The construction of children's personal rights results from a process of combining the observation of individual cognitive, normative and emotional development, with relationships with the different social systems (family, school education, caring services, social policies, law system). This is the framework producing the paradox: personalization is simultaneously promoted and protected; individual persons are emancipated and controlled at the same time. Deviant outcomes and repression must both be avoided, as they are perceived as a threat to society. It has been suggested that parallel trends towards increased autonomy and increased regulation are not as contradictory as they might first appear. They would prove the extent to which children are at the centre of political strategies in late modernity, designed to govern the individual through the capture of the inside, rather than constraint of the outside (James 1998). If this is true, the western political systems are using paradoxical arguments in order to guide and perhaps control the personalization process. This is a very risky strategy, as paradox can easily create serious problems in the observation of social as well as individual systems and, consequently in socialization and participation processes. The discipline which has the task of the second order observation, that is sociology, seems also unable to observe the paradoxes and the risks in their use. Bibliography Alanen, Leena. 1990. Rethinking socialization, the family and childhood, <<Sociological Studies of Child Development>>, vol. 3, Connecticut, JAI Press. 10 Ambert, Anne-Marie. 1995. Sociological Theorizing on Children: Concluding Thoughts, <<Sociological Studies of Children>>, vol.7, Connecticut, JAI Press, pp. 247-256. Ariès, Philippe. 1960. L’enfant et la vie familiale sous l’Ancien Régime, Italian translation Padri e figli nell’Antico Regime. Roma - Bari, Laterza. Baraldi, Claudio. 1996. Sistema giuridico, servizi sociali e famiglie “problematiche”: l'enigma della tutela dei bambini. In G. Maggioni (edited by), Come il diritto tratta le famiglie, QuattroVenti, Urbino. Baraldi, Claudio. 1997b. L’età dell’innocenza. Autonomia e cittadinanza dei bambini, in Cittadinanza dei bambini e costruzione sociale dell’infanzia, edited by G. Maggioni e C. Baraldi, Urbino, QuattroVenti. Baraldi Claudio. 1998. Infanzie a San Patrignano, in La comunità capovolta, edited by Claudio Baraldi and Giuliano Piazzi, Milano, FrancoAngeli. Becchi, Egle. 1994. I bambini nella storia. Roma - Bari, Laterza. Becchi, Egle, Julia, Dominique. 1996. edited by. Storia dell’infanzia, vol. 1. Dall’antichità al Seicento ; vol. 2. Dal Settecento a oggi, Roma - Bari, Laterza Beck Ulrich. 1992. Risk Society, English translation, London, Sage. Boggi, Ornella. 1997. La sociologia alla scoperta dell’infanzia: un problema di ridefinizione teorica, in Cittadinanza dei bambini e costruzione sociale dell’infanzia, edited by G. Maggioni e C. Baraldi, Urbino, QuattroVenti. Chisholm, Lynne; Büchner, Peter; Krüger, Heinz-Hermann; du Bois-Reymond, Manuela. 1995. Edited by. Growing up in Europe. Contemporary Horizons in Childhood and Youth Studies, Berlin-New York, de Gruyter. Corsaro, William A. 1997. The Sociology of Childhood, California, Pine Force Press. Cunningham, Hugh. 1995. Children and Childhood in Western Society since 1500, Essex, Longman. DeMause, Lloyd. 1974. Edited by. The History of Childhood, New York, Harper & Row. Denzin Karl. 1979. Childhood Socialization, San Francisco, Jossey-Bass. Freeman, Michael. 1996. Edited by. Children's Rights: A Comparative Perspective, Aldershot, Dartmouth. Giddens Anthony. 1984. The Constitution of Society, Bekeley-Los Angeles, University of California Press. Giddens, Anthony. 1991. Modernity and Self-Identity. Self and Society in the Late Modern Age, London, Polity Press. Harré, Rom. 1984. Personal Being. A Theory of Individual Psychology, Cambridge (Ma), Harvard University Press. Hochschild, Arlie Russell. 1995. The Culture of Politics: Traditional, Postmodern, Cold-modern, and Warm-modern Ideals of Care, <<Social Politics>>, Fall, pp. 331-346. James, Allison; Prout, Alan. 1995. Hierarchy, Boundary and Agency : toward a Theoretical Perspective on Childhood, <<Sociological Studies of Children>>, vol.7, Connecticut, JAI Press, pp. 77-99. James, Allison; Jenks, Chris; Prout, Alan. 1998. Theorizing Childhood, Cambridge, Polity Press. 11 Jenks, Chris. 1996a. Childhood,. London, Routledge. Jenks, Chris. 1996b. The Postmodern Child, in Children in Families, edited by Julia Brannen e Margaret O’Brien, London - Washington, Falmer Press, pp.13-24. Jensen, An-Magritt. 1994. The Feminization of Childhood, in Childhood matters. Social Theory, Practice and Politics, edited by Jens Qvortrup, Marjatta Bardy, Giovanni Sgritta, Helmut Wintersberger, Aldershot, Avebury, pp.59-75. King, Michael; Piper, Christine. 1995. How the Law Thinks About Children, 2nd Ed., Aldershot, Arena. King, Michael. 1997. A Better World for Children? Explorations in Morality and Authority, London, Routledge. Kyllönen, Riitta. 1987. Le costruzioni sociali del bambino nel rapporto di cura, in Cittadinanza dei bambini e costruzione sociale dell’infanzia, edited by G. Maggioni e C. Baraldi, Urbino, QuattroVenti. Maggioni, Guido. 1996. Edited by. Come il diritto tratta le famiglie. QuattroVenti, Urbino. Maggioni, Guido; Baraldi, Claudio. 1997. Edited by. Cittadinanza dei bambini e costruzione sociale dell’infanzia , Urbino, QuattroVenti. Newson, John; Newson, Elizabeth. 1963. Patterns of Infant Care in an Urban Community, London, Allen & Unwin. Newson, John; Newson, Elizabeth. 1968. Four Years Old in an Urban Community, London, Allen & Unwin. Newson, John; Newson, Elizabeth. 1976. Seven Years Old in the Home Environment, London, Allen & Unwin. O’Neill, John. 1995. On the Liberal Culture of Child Risk : a Covenant Critique of Contractarian Theory, <<Sociological Studies of Children>>, Connecticut, JAI Press, vol.7, pp.1-18. O’Neill, Onora. 1992. Children’s Rights and Children Lives, <<International Journal of Law and the Family>>, 1, pp. 26-43. Parsons Talcott. 1977. Social Systems and the Evolution of Action Theory, New York, Free Press. Parsons Talcott, Bales Robert. 1955. Family, Socialization and Interaction Process, New York, Free Press. Pilcher, Jane; Wagg, Stephen. 1996a. Edited by. Thatcher’s Children? Politics, Childhood and Society in the 1980s and 1990s, London - Washington, Falmer Press. Qvortrup, Jens; Bardy, Marjatta; Sgritta, Giovanni; Wintersberger, Helmut. 1994. Edited by. Childhood matters. Social Theory, Practice and Politics, Aldershot, Avebury. Roche, Jeremy. 1996. The Politics of Children’s Rights, in Children in Families, edited by Julia Brannen e Margaret O’Brien, London - Washington, Falmer Press, pp.2639. Ronfani, Paola. 1995. I diritti del minore. Cultura giuridica e rappreentazioni sociali, Milano, Guerini scientifica. 12 Ronfani, Paola. 1997. L’interesse del minore nella cultura giuridica e nella pratica, in Cittadinanza dei bambini e costruzione sociale dell’infanzia , edited by G. Maggioni e C. Baraldi, Urbino, QuattroVenti. Rose, N. 1989. Governing the Soul, Routledge, London. Shotter John. 1984. Social Accountability and Selfhood, Oxford, Basil Blackwell. Sgritta, Giovanni B. 1988. La condizione dell’infanzia. Teorie, politiche e rappresentazioni sociali, Milano, Franco Angeli. Zinnecker, Jürgen. 1995. The Cultural Modernization of Childhood, in Growing up in Europe. Contemporary Horizons in Childhood and Youth Studies, edited by Lynne Chisholm, Peter Büchner, Heinz-Hermann Krüger, Manuela du BoisReymond, Berlin-New York, de Gruyter, pp.85-93. 13