Download Reservation and Social Mobility : Theoritical Construct

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Self-categorization theory wikipedia , lookup

Social tuning wikipedia , lookup

Social dilemma wikipedia , lookup

Social perception wikipedia , lookup

Group dynamics wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
RESERVATION
AND SOCIAL MOBILITY:
THEORETICAL CONSTRUCT
Author:J. PRABHASH
ABSTRACT---Theory building occupies an important place in Social Science research. It helps
one to grapple with social realities, to relate the seemingly unrelated and isolated social
phenomena with each other and establish their causes and effects. The primary task here is to
comprehend and put in a proper perspective the existing body of thought in the field of
investigation and beat them into a desired shape to suit one's enquiry. This paper seeks to relate
reservation with social mobility and develop a theoretical framework to analyse their dialectical
interaction.
Theory building occupies an important place in Social Science research. For, it helps one to
grapple with social realities, to relate the seemingly unrelated and isolated social phenomena
with each other and establish their causes and effects. The primary task here is to comprehend
and put in a proper perspective the existing body of thought in the field of investigation and beat
them into a desired shape to suit one’s enquiry. In the process new theoretical insights emerge.
This paper attempts at such an exercise. It seeks to relate reservation with social mobility and
develop a theoretical framework to analyse their dialectical interaction.
Reservation is considered as the best tool in ameliorating the lot of the disadvantaged
sections in a society. The disadvantaged are those who suffer multiple deprivations, economic,
political and social. They have little or no means of subsistence, no representation in the power
structure and hence lag behind in social esteem. Reservation targets at drastically altering this
existential reality by improving their economic condition, giving them greater share in power and
thereby enhancing their social status. In this way the social rejects are made social acceptables
and are further encouraged to integrate progressively with the mainstream society. In this sense it
promotes social cohesion.
Democratic justification for reservation lies in its majoritarian principle and concern for
equality. It may be remembered that the bulwark of democratic governance is majority support.
As such the State primarily directs its energy to cater to their needs and interests. Needless to
say, in every society it is the disadvantaged who form the largest chunk of the population.
Therefore, it is only in the fitness of things that democratic governance postulates special care
strategies for the upliftment of such individuals
Reservation could also be justified in terms of equality, which is the very basis of
democracy. In fact, as Sunitha Pathania had pointed out, reservation is a catalytic agent of social
justice (“ Is Reservation the Solution?” The Hindu. th 29 Dec. 1996). It is the modem refinement
of the concept of equality, one based on the premise that strictly equal treatment meted out in
inherently unequal 1 situations can hardly be considered equitable . It, thus conflates equity with
justice and paves the way for equi-justice, a concept which denotes not equal justice but adequate
justice determined on the basis of one’s existential conditions with the worst off being offered
preferential treatment over the better off. Conceived in these two senses, reservation fosters the
greatest good of the society and informs the principle of equality with a new dynamism, which
enables it to winnow the most deserving from the non-deserving/least-deserving and accordingly
hammer state policies into desired shapes. Viewed thus, the theoretical underpinnings of
reservation could be traced to the principles of Utilitarianism and John Rawls’ Theory of Justice.
Reservation, Utilitarianism and Rawls’ Theory of Justice
It is a little noticed fact that the Utilitarian theory justifies the cause of reservation. Based as
it is on pleasure-pain theory, it measures utility in terms of the greatest happiness of the greatest
number. It believes in distributing the good things of life according to the above principle
(Faundez 7). In relation to state policy this means that its intrinsic worth depends on the
population size it seeks to serve or on whom it wants to confer its beneficial attributes.
Accordingly if the social benefits brought about by reservation out-weigh the harm to which it
gives rise, then under utilitarian approach such a measure would be justified.
(Faundez 7).
In the specific context of India, it won’t be difficult to understand that reservation policy
seeks to protect the interests of the Backward Classes who constitute a large majority of the
country’s population. Apart from this, it also generates much good for the society as a whole.
One could very well imagine the social turmoil it would have created had these people continued
as social rejects. By providing them a share in state power, reservation tries to prevent such a
contingency. In this sense it furthers social cohesion and integration by reducing socio-economic
inequalities (Faundez 7). Thus reservation becomes the catalyst of the greatest happiness of the
greatest number.
However, the best defence for reservation, it seems, comes from John Rawls. His Theory of
Justice is moderately equalitarian, reformist in nature, progressive in outlook and social in
consciousness (R. Sushila, “Rawls and his Critics” Unpublished Ph. D thesis, Delhi: Department
of Political Science, University of Delhi, 1987, 467). It is true that he never argues for a nonstratified, non-hierarchical society. Neither does he envisage the abolition of inequality as such.
All the same, it shouldn’t be overlooked that he also advocates the redressal of socio-economic
inequalities by elevating the worst-off (R.Sushila 211). Here he is not merely rationalising the
need for economic justice, but goes beyond and argues for the equal sense of worth of each and
all; for afterall man does not live on bread alone (Allan Bloom 650)
Rawls’ Justice stands on the tripod of equal liberty, fair equality of opportunity and the
maximin or difference principle. According to him, in matters of liberty every individual has to
be placed on an even keel, irrespective of his natural assets or initial position in society. Each is
to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with
a similar system of liberty for all (Rawls 302). This could well be interpreted to mean that in a
caste-based stratified system, the birth of an individual in a particular caste (in Rawlsean sense,
natural asset or initial position in society) should not come in the way of computing his social
status or economic and political positions in society. Constructed reversely, it means that a
person who is subjected to discrimination on that very basis be treated equally and at the same
time accorded certain preferential consideration as compensation for the ill-treatment suffered by
him. In this perspective Rawls’ equal liberty principle is not a sterile one standing for same
treatment under all circumstances. This would be clearer as one examines the other two legs of
the tripod.
For Rawls, Justice further means providing fair equality of opportunity. Under this, positions
are to be not only open in a formal sense but all should have a fair chance to attain them (Rawls
73) Here one should take serious note of the fact that what Rawls emphasizes is not equal
opportunities but fair equality of opportunities. The two propositions differ fundamentally. The
former is a sterile and negative concept as it considers individuals as equals without any regard
for their differential endowments. Fair equality principle, on the other hand, is dynamic and
positive as its focus is on the individual with all his advantages and disadvantages and hence
justifies providing differential opportunities depending on one’s needs. Thus fair equality of
opportunity means adequate opportunity or as stated in the Indian Constitution ‘equal protection
of the laws’. Opportunity provided to an individual is linked to his special circumstances, the
disadvantaged being provided with preferential treatment while the same being denied to those
placed in vantage positions. Only in this way the equality of opportunity provision be saved from
usurpation by those who have an initial advantage over others by virtue of birth and social
stratification (Rawls 75)
Here one comes across the much controversial issue of merit and talent. What is the position
of these attributes in Rawls’ scheme of Justice? He cautions us in laying too much emphasis on
these qualities. He says:
…merit and desert are social attributes [than individual and hence
are] to be harvested for society as a whole. It is just a matter of
chance or a natural lottery that these talents are so randomly
distributed in individuals. [As such] . . . individuals do not have
a prior right to use these talents to their own advantage. As society
has decided that certain attributes are important the fortunate
individuals who have these talents cannot claim them all for
themselves. (Rawls 72 – 74 )
Roland Dworkin succinctly presents Rawls’ contention in this regard and shows how it
could be used as a justification for reservation. Like Rawls, Dworkin too believes that what
counts for merit cannot be decided in the abstract but in terms of what society values and
considers relevant.In other words:
It all depends upon what society thinks should be cherished and the kind of institutions that
it would like to uphold. Therefore, nobody has a prior right to go to Medical College or become a
lawyer. Society will decide which mix of attributes it considers suitable for admission into
medicine and law. Admission may not be only on the basis of marks scored, but on the additional
basis of, say, colour of skin or caste background. As one’s attributes do not belong to the
individual but to society, it is up to [it] to decide which attribute, or bundle of attributes, it
considers relevant. At a certain point in time society could decide that being black or belonging
to an ex-untouchable caste is a socially useful colour in which case, then, academic Merit alone
will not count. (Roland Dworkin, cited in Dipankar Gupta’s “Positive Discrimination and the
Question of Fraternity: Contrasting Ambedkar and Mandal on Reservation” )
This, then, makes it clear that the quest for merit and deserts has to be kept in check. This,
however, does not mean that Rawls rejects them altogether. He only pleads that the basic
structure be arranged in such a manner that these contingencies work to the benefit of the least
advantaged (Rawls 102) This he terms as the difference principle. When applied to Government
policies it means that they ought to be formulated keeping in mind the interests of the worst off.
Utilitarians and Rawls thus become the best exponents of the policy of reservation, of course
indirectly.
The aforesaid exposition of reservation and its theoretical underpinnings clearly establishes
the organic linkages it has with the concept of social mobility. Reservation in the broadest sense
is a process of social churning as it attempts at restructuring the existing system on an
equalitarian basis. It shakes the privileged position of the dominant sections and offers the
disadvantaged a helping hand to intrude into the hitherto denied social, economic and political
slots in the system. The net result is intra-stratum movement or social mobility. Once this linkage
is established, the next logical course is to develop a theoretical framework to comprehend the
intricacies of the process of mobility.
Social Stratification and Mobility
In every society, ancient or modern, democratic or otherwise, the positions, which
individuals come to occupy, vary very much in terms of power, privilege and status. This has its
definite impact on the dialectical interaction among individuals, their social prestige, influence
and importance. In Sorokin’s phraseology its essence consists of unequal distribution of rights
and privileges, duties and responsibilities, social values and privations, social power and
influences (Sorokin 11).The fundamental basis of this phenomenon inevitably lies in the manner
in which societies are lacerated into layers and their hierarchical ordering. Thus social
stratification becomes an important field of investigation in Social Science. More often than not,
primary focus of attention here is on social formations with which various strata are composed
and the manner and degree of movements among them.
One confronts different philosophical conceptions regarding the above problematic. Take for
instance the issue of social formations. Here one usually comes across much of a juxtaposing of
the uni-dimensional construct of Marx and Engels with the multi-dimensional analysis of Weber
and others of his ilk, Runciman and Sorokin in particular. For Marx and Engels stratification
rests on the pedigree of class i.e., place of individuals in the system of production and property
relations. Weber while accepting the class conception of Marx and Engels brings in two
additional categories - status groups and parties - and thereby provides a social and political
dimension to an otherwise economic 3 construct . Runciman more or less follows the Weberian
typology with a slight modification. He introduces the concept of power instead of parties,
though in 4 reality both stand for the same thing . To Sorokin, economic, political and
occupational are the three principal dimensions of stratification (Sorokin 12)
A hindsight however reveals that there is a common thread that runs through and binds all
these schools of thought. Nobody from Marx and Engels down to Sorokin, seems to be in doubt
about the centrality of economic factors, or class formations to be more precise, in social
stratification. Also it won’t be far-fetched to maintain that other factors, be they status, party or
power, about which Weber or Runciman is specific are laced firmly with class. This, however,
should not be construed to mean that one is denying the salience of other factors or the
differential contributions of Weber et al to the study and analysis of social stratification. But the
purpose is rather a restricted one, to point out the significance of economic interest in the
formation of social collectivities.
Linked to the above, but much more important than it, is the effort at theorising the process
of the movement of individuals from one stratum to the other or change in placement within the
same stratum. A rich but variegated body of literature already exists in this realm, of course with
the usual contradictions inherent in the analysis of such complex social phenomenon.
Literature on social mobility relates the phenomenon with social change and/or movements
of individuals in social space. Theoretically the first proposition is valid as all social changes,
violent or peaceful, induce structural changes in varying degrees resulting in greater inter-and
intra-stratum traffic. However it has one important lacuna as it is couched in general terms
ignoring the specificities of such changes. The second formulation sounds better, though it also
has certain shortcomings on closer scrutiny. Sorokin, for instance, defines mobility as
transmission of an individual or social object or value-- anything that has been created or
modified by human activity — from one social position, economic, political and occupational, to
another (Sorokin 133). While this covers a lot of ground lost sight of by the first proposition,
applying this in societies with caste-based stratification system becomes problematic. This is
more so in the case of upward mobility. It may be noticed that mobility for an individual in the
final analysis becomes meaningful only when his elevation to a higher slot and consequent status
change is accepted by the larger society and his peers in the new stratum. For instance, in India
an individual belonging to Scheduled Castes who is inducted to a higher position (professionwise) may not be acknowledged by his official subordinates or his peers or even the clientele
belonging to the upper or intermediate castes. Sorokin misses situations like this.
It would be appropriate here to introduce Lipset and Zetterberg who view social mobility to
be the product of shift and ranking of occupations, consumptions, social power and social class
composed of individuals who accept 6 each other as equals and qualified for intimate association
. We could beneficially use this with some modifications to the latter part. For, qualifying for
equal treatment and intimate association alone won’t suffice our need. It is also crucial that the
mobile individuals are accepted and accorded due respect befitting their newly acquired positions
by their subordinates in the official hierarchy and the larger public outside, irrespective of their
caste status. This may be termed as social acceptance . Social Mobility, thus, means positional
shift of individuals in the social, economic, occupational and political structures in such a
manner that the new incumbents qualify for social acceptance irrespective of their caste or
ascriptive ties.
The linkage between social and political mobility also assumes salience here. The two are
inter-linked processes with social mobility leading to political mobility and this in turn leading
back and inducing greater social mobility. For instance, Verba et al hypothesize that social
mobility leads to political participation and activity (Verba et al. 69) and Barbara Joshi considers
it (political mobility) as a means of greater social and economic mobility (Barbara R Joshi 25).
Political mobility is a broader concept, which stands for greater political power and role in
the decision-making process, both at the party and governmental levels. It has also a social
acceptance dimension when applied in a caste-linked stratification and status system. Like the
socially mobile individual the politically mobile should also be accepted by the society. To be
more specific, his authority and status should be accepted and respected by his subordinates and
accorded due regard by his peers and superiors, both in the party as well as in the Government.
And this should come irrespective of his ascriptive identity.
Further, social mobility also influences political preference. This has been accepted by both
Instrumental and Expressive Theories. According to Lipset, intergenerational mobility affects the
relation between social class and political preference . Hence it is held that the political
preference of a mobile person will be more or less the same as the class of his destinations
(Newbeerta and Graaf 30, 48). As his class position changes upward, his political preference
oscillates between left-wing radicalism to right-wing conservatism. By implication this means
that a person in a lower position has a higher chance of having a left-wing political preference
than someone in a high-class position whose leniency will be towards right of centre political
formations. Abrams and Rose have proved this point while investigating the reasons behind the
Labour Party’s defeat in three successive General Elections (1949, 1954 and 1959) in England.
Their conclusion is that the Labour voters failed to identify with the party because of their
relative affluence (M.Abrams and R.Rose 484). The theory is that as a community experiences
material prosperity, it develops a vested interest in maintaining the status quo in property
relations and this in turn leads to its opposing activities, adversely affecting its material interests
(T.K. Oommen 166) Consequences of social mobility on political mobility and preference thus
become a focal point of attention in mobility studies.
Types, Directions and Mechanisms of Mobility
Viewing mobility as positional shift brings to the fore two crucial aspects of the
phenomenon, types and directions of the shift, and the process through which individuals seek
elevation to higher strata.
Four types of mobility are commonly identified; Ritual and Secular, and Contest and
Sponsored. Ritual Mobility is often initiated through group efforts aiming at a higher ritual
position or rank in a society where ritual status forms one of the important criterion of social
stratification (Chandrashekhar Bhat 124) Secular Mobility, on the other, is movement in public
sphere-- particularly educational, occupational and political-- and deals with the exercise of state
power. Owen Lynch points out political participation as an important channel of this type of
mobility (Owen M..Lynch 8 )
The second typology -- Contest and Sponsored Mobility is a distinct contribution of Ralph
Turner. When mobility is the product of open competition between individuals it becomes
Contest Mobility. The contest is judged to be fair only if all players compete on an equal footing
and victory here is solely by one’s own effort . Under Sponsored Mobility, however
competitiveness as well as own effort are at a discount. Here the mobiles are chosen by the
established elite or their agents and is like entry into a private club where each candidate must be
sponsored by one or more of the members.In other words here, for mobility to take place,
sponsorship or sympathetic disposition of the establishment becomes a sine qua non. Turner
points out the recruitment to the Catholic priesthood in US as a typical example of this type of
mobility. Recruitment of Scheduled Castes and other Backward Classes to the Government
service under the Indian Constitution also, in a sense, belongs to this category as they enjoy the
sponsorship of the State in the form of reservation.
From typologies of mobility as one moves on to its directions, one comes across two
principal dimensions with the possibility of each getting further fragmented into a series of subdivisions. Sorokin analyses it in terms of Horizontal and Vertical forms. Horizontal Mobility
means hopping of individuals along the surface i.e., movement within the same stratum and level
with hardly any ups and downs in status. Contrariwise in Vertical Mobility status shifts stand out
in bold relief. Vertical Mobility thus is the relations involved in a transition of an individual from
one social stratum to another (Sorokin op.cit) Theodore Caplow’s description seems to be more
crisp — movement of individuals upward or downward with a gain or loss in social
rank.(Theodore Caplow 59)
Turning back to Sorokin, it could be discerned that he divides Vertical Mobility into
ascending and descending currents. While the former denotes social climbing or ‘Upward
Mobility’, the latter points towards social sinking or Downward Mobility. Each of these, in turn,
is divided into two categories depending on the individual or collective nature of the mobiles
(Figure 1) (Sorokin 133— 34). In both currents there is the possibility of stray individual or
whole groups being catapulted to a higher plane or ejected out of it to a lower one.
Source:Pitrim A.sorokin,social and cultural mobility,Illinois:the free press of glencoe, 1959,p. 136.
Two other classifications that could be progressively adopted in analysing the direction of Social
Mobility are the ones presented by Melvin Tumin and Ray Collins, and K.L. Sharma. Tumin and
Collins identify four types of mobility situations by co-relating the status of parents and their
progeny: High Stationaries (high status children of high status parents) – horizontal. Upwardly
Mobile (high status children of low status parents— vertical; Downwardly Mobile (low status
children of high status parents)— vertical; and Low Stationaries (low status children of low
status parents)— horizontal.1 (Melvin M. Tumin and Ray C. Collins, “Status Mobility and
Anomie: A Study in Readiness for Desegregation”, British Journal of sociology, Vol. 10, No. 3,
1965, p. 161.)Sharma concentrates on Downward Mobility (Decline) and in the first instance,
classifies it into two (Figure2).
Source: K L sharma,social stratification and mobility, Jaipur:rewat publications, 1994, p. 216
General Decline (Total decline of a unit of society-individual, family etc.) and Domain
Specific (Downward mobility of the above units in a particular aspectoccupation, economic etc.).
Generalised Decline in turn comes for a two-fold classification-Structural Decline (Changes in
the organizational principle of the society) and Positional Decline (Movement of persons within
a continuing structure of society). The classification finally ends with the division of Structural
Decline into Primary Structural Decline (radical change which may be due to pressure from
above, for example, from the threat of war by a big power and/or from elites and reformative
policies or pressure from below, for instance, a Maoist revolution) and Secondary Structural
Decline (indirect and immediately less effective changes to which individuals and groups are
exposed) (K.L. Sharma 211— 25). Sharma considers Domain Specific Decline as the one to
affect the depressed classes very much since all their attempts at mobility in caste hierarchy are
frustrated by the forward castes consequent to which they lose their traditional occupation and
find themselves in a state of unemployment (Sharma 225). Parenthetically speaking, it may be
noted that it is Vertical Mobility and its various forms which are more important than Horizontal
Mobility.
Merton’s Reference Group Theory and Srinivas’ Concept of Sanskritization
Another important problem in the study of social mobility is the identification of the process
or mechanism through which individuals/groups seek upward mobility and theorizing it.
Merton’s and Srinivas’ are two valiant attempts at this.
Merton tries to weave his theory of mobility with the help of three conceptual categoriesRelative Deprivation, Reference Group and Anticipatory Socialization. It aims at systematizing
the determinants and consequences of those process of evaluation and self-appraisal in which
individuals take the value or standards of other individuals and groups as comparative frame of
reference (Robert K. Merton 234). The theory is premised on: a feeling of deprivation by
mobility aspirants relative to some dominant groups (Relative Deprivation); an endeavour to
identify a group/groups whose behaviour is considered worthy of emulation (Reference Group);
and finally the adoption of its/their norms and values in anticipation of its acceptance by the
referent group/ groups (Anticipatory Socialization). In his framework Merton develops four
types of Reference Groups: Normative-group/groups providing a frame of reference;
Comparative-group/groups providing a comparison relative to which one’s deprivation is
evaluated; Positive-group/ groups involving the ‘motivated assimilation of norms or standards of
the group as a basis of self-appraisal; and finally the Negative Reference Group - one involving
motivated rejection and the formation of counter norms (Merton 300) He also acknowledges the
possibility of plurality of Reference Groups, more so in the case of Normative and Comparative
Groups.
Two conditions, however, are stipulated for the theory, particularly anticipatory
socialization, to become functional stratification system should be under dispute, and the society
should be open. In Merton’s own words:
If the structure of a rigid system of stratification is generally
defined as legitimate, if the rights, perquisites and obligations of
each situation are generally held to be morally right, then the
individuals within each stratum will be less likely to take the
situation of the strata as a context for appraisal for their own lot.
They will, presumably, tend to confine their comparison to other
members of their own or neighbouring social stratum. If however,
the system of stratification is under wide dispute then members
of some strata are more likely to contrast their own situation with
that of others and shape their self-appraisal accordingly. It appears
further that anticipatory socialization [and therefore of the
Reference Group Theory] is functional for the individual only
within a relatively open social structure providing for mobility.
For, only in such a structure would such attitudinal and
behavioural preparations for status shifts be followed by actual
changes of status in a substantial proportion of cases. By the
same token, the same pattern of anticipatory socialization would
be dysfunctional for the individual in a relatively closed social
structure where he would not find acceptance by the group to
which he aspires . . .. (Merton 267— 68)
But it seems that Merton is over-stating his case. For, in the first instance, openness or
closeness of a society is relative than absolute. Therefore, anticipatory socialization rather than
becoming dysfunctional would be functional relatively. Further even in the so-called ‘closed
societies’ reference group theory has its relevance. Speaking about the rigid caste-based
stratification system in India, Damle clearly states this:
The paradox of caste lies in the fact that although lower caste
persons cannot expect to be included in a higher caste (Jati) and
also because higher caste persons need not fear their exclusion,
positive orientation for reference and imitation is permitted and
even encouraged. Anticipatory socialization can thus occur and
even if it does not ensure ultimate absorption or inclusion ... it
can be functional for the persons concerned ... where a higher
varna is used as a reference model.
Many studies have also shown the utility of this theory even in relatively closed societies.
K.C. Alexander’s study of the Pulayas of Kerala, Owen M. Lynch’s study of the Jatavas of Agra,
Chandrasekhar Bhat’s study of Waddars of Kamataka, all stand testimony to this. More than all
these, Srinivas’ concept of Sanskritization clinches the issue in favour of this argument. This is
exactly what he does by establishing the possibility of the lower castes emulating the behavioural
pattern of the twice born castes and thereby trying to move up, though the conceptual framework
he uses and the social reality he seeks to encapsulate are distinct.
Srinivas endeavours to analyse the mobility of ascriptive categories in the specific context of
India. He finds the middle castes moving along the ritual axis and attributes this to their
propensity to imitate Brahmanical values. He calls this process Sanskritization. To quote him:
The caste system is far from a rigid system in which the position
of each component caste is fixed for all time. Movement has
always been possible and especially so in the middle region of
the hierarchy. A low caste was able, in a generation or two, to
raise to a higher position in the hierarchy by adopting
vegetarianism and teetotalism, and by sanskritizing its ritual and
pantheon. In short, it took over as far as possible the customs,
rules and beliefs of the Brahmans and the adoption of the
Brahmanic way of life by a low caste seems to have been frequent,
though theoretically forbidden. (Srinivas. The Cohesive Role of
Sankritization and other Essays. Delhi : Oxford University Press,
1966)
Later he has amended the ‘Brahmanical model’ of emulation and stated that any superior
caste could be taken up for the purpose.
Srinivas further identifies three fundamental traits of the process: it is a group process not
strictly applicable to individuals; it is a long and protracted one, some times taking generations to
meet the target; and finally it is unhelpful for the untouchable groups below the ritual barrier of
pollution.17 Besides, a minimum of economic and political power is alsoneeded for the caste to
move up (Andre Beteille 120) By implication this means that Sanskritization as a concept is not
applicable to movement in the secular status hierarchy. It becomes operational only when an
intermediate caste after gaining economic and political mobility attempts at corresponding
change in the ritual hierarchy. In other words it is only useful for a caste whose economic or
social rank has improved and is therefore out of place with its low ritual rank and through
Sanskritization that is also raised (Lynch 11). Here it is also worthwhile to remember that
Sanskritization accepts the legitimacy of the caste system. Social mobility takes place only
within its parameters and not outside it. Viewed thus, it does not lead to any structural change.
In retrospect, it could be seen that though Reference Group Theory and Sanskritization help
a great deal in analysing the process of social mobility, still both leave a lot of ground uncovered.
The consequence of a failed attempt at mobility— for instance a person who lacks social
acceptance— best illustrates this point. In this case there is no congruence between the achieved
status and accorded status. This may create disillusionment in him. Neither of the theories is
equipped to meet such contingencies with the result that one is forced to seek the support of
other theories. Homans’ Theory Of Status Congruence, Oscar Lewis’ Culture of Poverty, Milton
Gordon’s Ethclass and Paranjpe’s Ethnocentric and Contra-identification are some useful
theoretical and conceptual categories in this regard.
A person who feels status discrepancy is an aggrieved person. He is anxious about his slot in
the society. Homans seeks to explain this in terms of status congruence/incongruence and status
anxiety (Homans 98). He has developed his theory in the specific context of acquired statuses in
a work organization (Nandu Ram 27) Congruence (inness) between statuses creates satisfaction
whereas incongruence (outness) between them breeds anxiety. To Homans, for the person
concerned inness is the symbol of distributive justice and the contra position that of injustice
(Homans 168 ).
The consequence of status incongruity for a person also needs investigation. Any one of the
following situations unfolds in such an eventuality: one may resign to one’s fate and
progressively get alienated. Oscar Lewis terms this as culture of poverty. He uses it in the
context of a class stratified and highly individuated capitalist society and considers it as ‘an
effort to cope with the feeling of hopelessness and despair which develop from the realization of
the improbability of achieving success in terms of the values and goals of the larger society. 18
The second situation is a little bit complex. Needless to repeat, a person lacking in social
acceptance is the one who attains mobility in the achieved status but wanting in mobility in the
accorded status. This means he had already moved away from his primary membership group
(in-group) but denied access to the group of destiny (out-group). He thus remains suspended
between the two. In such a contingency he might be forced to interact with his ethnic-class group
i.e., those members of his ethnic/caste group belonging to the same class status as his. Here one
finds a new group emerging at the confluence of class and ethnicity/caste. Milton Gordan calls
this Ethclass. According to him:
With a person of the same social class but of a different ethnic
group one shares behavioural similarities but not a sense of
peoplehood. With those of the same ethnic group but of different
social class one shares the sense of peoplehood but not behavioural
similarities. The only group which meets both these criteria are
people of the same ethnic group and same social class.
In the above group one feels at home and can interact with greater ease. The last situation is
one in which one identifies with his own ethnic/caste group. The issue raised above could be
analysed with the help of Paranjpe’s Theory of Ethnocentric and Contra-identification as
modified by Nandu Ram. Paranjpe visualises two situations of identification-one in which the
individuals identify with their ethnic/caste group (ethnocentric identification) and the other in
which they identify at the class level (contra-identification) (Paranjpe 106— 14). Nandu Ram
adds a third dimension of identification: non-caste class level. This situation arises as they may
not believe in any identification whatsoever in the stratification system and may have a frame of
reference of non-stratificational identification (Nandu Ram 15). This he considers as another
dimension of Paranjpe’s Contraidentification.
Integration of the Theoretical Framework
Social Mobility of Scheduled Castes is analysed in this study by lacing together the
following theoretical formulations: Lipsets’ and Zetterberg’s theory of Social Mobility, Srinivas’
Theory of Sanskritization, Homan’s Theory of Status Congruence, Gordon’s Theory of Ethclass
and Paranjpe’s Theory of Ethnocentric and Contra-identification.
The organic linkage between the reservation policy adopted in India and Utilitarianism and
Rawis’Theory of Justice is transparent. True to Utilitarianism, it also facilitates the greatest
happiness of the majority of the populace. Similarly like Rawlsean justice it is also one of the
fairest ways to uplift the worst off. Further, as is already made clear, the leitmotif of reservation
is social mobility of depressed classes. It is believed that once their stigmatised identity is
removed by changing for the better their social, economic and political lot, these people would
get progressively integrated with the rest of the society qualifying for intimate association and
social acceptance. Lipset’s and Zetterberg’s theory of social mobility with some modification as
already stated will suit our purpose here. However, social power and consumption dimensions of
their theory have been dropped as both are beyond the purview of this study. At the same time,
the concept of social acceptance is brought in to see whether their assimilation with the rest of
the society and thereby their mobility has been complete. Thus social mobility here is considered
as a multi-dimensional concept involving changes in education, occupation, political power and
income and social acceptance of the mobile (both social and political) persons. Sanskritization
will help to grapple with this dynamic process.
However the Scheduled Castes who may attain mobility in terms of education, occupation
and income or political mobility may not be accorded social acceptance by the rest of the society
because of their low caste status. Such people, at least a section among them, may find
themselves suspended between the two worlds, neither in the primary group nor in the fold of the
upper caste/ class. Harold Issacs calls the situation as one of ‘semi-limbo. With whom does such
a person identify himself in Caste? Class? Caste-Class level or non-Caste-Class level? Will he
become resigned to his fate and get alienated from the system? Paranjpe’s ethnocentric and
contra-identification theory, and Gordon’s Ethclass concept become crucial in analysing the
situation.
Notes
1.G. Patel, ‘Equity in a Modem Society’, Mainstream, Vol. XXII, No. 11, 29 January 1994, p.
53. Also see Charles
Valentine, Culture and poverty:- Critique and Counter Proposals,
Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1969.
2.Dipankar Gupta, “Positive Discrimination and the Question of Fraternity: Contrasting
Ambedkar and Mandal on
Reservation”, Economic and Political Weekly Vol. XXXII, No.
31, 2-8 August 1997, p. 1972.
3.Though Weber is in considerable agreement with Marx in this regard— for example he accepts
the latter’s proposition that
social stratification is a phenomenon closely linked to the distribution of and struggle for
power – he also differs from him
in several respects such as the conception of power, assessment of the course of European
history and the conception of
what constitutes a satisfactory explanation in Sociology to this
phenomenon. For details see Max Weber, The Theory of
social and Economic Organization, (Trans. A. M. Henderson and Talcot Parsons) New
York: Oxford University Press,
1967 and H. H. Gerth and C. Right Mills, From Max Weber, Essays in Sociology, New
York: Oxford University Press,
1959. Also see James Little John, Social Stratification, London: George Allen and Unwin,
1972.
4.For details see W. G. Runciman, “Class, Status and Power” in J. A. Jackson.(ed.), Social
Stratification, London:
University Press, 1968.
5.S.M. Miller, “Comparative Social Mobility: A Trend Report and Bibliography”, Current
Sociology, Vol.1X, No. 1, 1969,
n. pag. in Dr. Leela Viswanathan, Social Mobility Among Scheduled Caste Women in India
(A Study of Kerala), New
Delhi: Uppal Publishing House, 1993, p. 36.
6.S.M. Lipset and Hans L. Zetterberg, “A Theory of Social Mobility” in R. Bendix and S. M.
Lipset (eds.). Class, Status,
and Power, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1966, p. 563
7.This differs fundamentally from Earl Hoppers concept of Legitimization. For, it consists only
of adjusting one’s status
position to a level that approximates one’s new economic position and realizing the potential
prestige to which one
hasbecomebr ‘entitled’ through having changed one’s occupation by becoming a member of
the relevant core status
group. This is primarily because he focused his attention only on class-stratified societies
where social acceptance of
one’s position is not a problematic. However the two concepts are also related in a way. For,
to get social acceptance
of one’s status and authority one should oneself realize it. In this sense status legitimisation
precedes social acceptance.
For details see his Mobility. A Study of Social Control and Instability, Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1981, p. 150.
8.The basic idea here is that voting behaviour is rational and has an economic purpose. People
within a certain class are in the
same economic and social position and have the same
interests. Consequently people within a certain class will vote for
the same party that serves their interests best. For details see Paul Nieuwbeerta and Nan Dirk
de Graaf,
“Intergenerational Class Mobility and Political Preferences Between 1970 and 1986 in the
Netherlands”, Netherlands
Journal of Social Sciences, Vol 29, No. 3, June 1993.
9.The theory perceives voting as a social rather than an economic act. The assumption is that
one’s political attitudes and
preferences are influenced by the people one associates with. For details see Ibid.
10.For details see S. M. Lipset, Political Man, New Delhi: Arnold Heinemann India, 1973
11.Ralph H. Turner, “Sponsored and Contest Mobility and the School System” in Celia S. Heller
(ed.), Structural Social
Inequality: A Reader in Comparative Social Stratification, New York: Macmillan Co., 1969,
p. 354.
12.Ibid.
13.Ibid. p. 362.
14.Y. B. Damle, “Reference Group Theory with Regard to Mobility in Caste” in James
Silverberg (ed.), Social Mobility
in the Caste System in India, The Hague: Mouton, 1968, p. 98.
15.Today there is a proliferation of terms arising on the Sanskritization analogue such as
Kulanization, Kshatriyaization,
Desanskritization, Palianization etc. depending on the particular caste chosen for emulation.
In regard to
Kshatriyaization a different interpretation is also presented by Hermann Kulke. According to
him, in its functional sense
the concept denotes social change from above, ie., a process initiated in tribal areas by
Kshatriyas, Zamindars, Chiefs or
Rajas to strengthen their claim to legitimacy in the society
and to broaden the basis of economic and political power.
For a discussion in this regard see his work “Kshatriyaization and Social Change: A Study in
Orissa Setting” in
S. Devadas Pillai (ed.), Aspects of changing India: Studies in Honour of Prof. G. S. Ghurye,
Bombay: Popular
Prakashan,1976. For Sanskritization analogue refer Narmadeshwar Prasad, The Myth of the
Caste System, Patna:
Samjna Prakashan, 1957; S. K. Srivasthava, “The Process of
Desanskritization in Village India” in Bala Ratnam (ed.),
Anthropology on the March,
Madras: The Book Centre, 1963; and Eleanor Zelliot, “Buddhism and Politics in
Maharashtra” in Donald E. Smith(ed.), Religion and Politics in South Asia, Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1966.
16.Srinivas used the term Sanskritization instead of Brahmanization, as the customs and habits of
Brahmans were different.
Had that term been used, it would have been necessary to specify which particular Brahman
group was meant and at
which period of its recorded history. For details see his “A Note on Sanskritization and
Westernization” in Bendix and
Lipset, op. cit.
17.Srinivas, “A Note on Sanskritization and Westernization” in Bendix and Lipset, op. cit., p. 58.
18.Here it may be remembered that Lewis differentiates between Poverty and Culture of Poverty
and observes that ‘While the lower castes in India may be desperately poor, they are not certainly
afflicted by the disease of the culture of
poverty. [This is because] ... most of them are
integrated into the larger society and have their own Panchayat organs
which cut across
village lives and give them a considerable amount of power. In addition to the caste system,
which gives the individuals a sense of identity, and belonging there is still another factor, the
class system. Wherever there are unilateral kinship system or class, one would not expect to find
the culture of poverty because a class system gives people a sense of belonging to a corporate
body with a history and a life of its own thereby providing a sense of continuity, a sense of past
and of a future.
Ramashray Roy and V. B. Singh fault Lewis on several counts: First the sense of
continuity in respect of the
Scheduled Castes is also a sense of degradation. Their history and their life are nothing but
an unending series of
misery, woe and frustration. They do not represent anything to be proud of unless the way of
life thrust upon them by the
larger society is felt by them to be not only proper but also
edifying. This, however, is not the case. Secondly, it is true
that the class system gives a sense of belonging to a corporate body. However, this corporate
body along with the
Caste Panchayats Lewis talks of, have usually been the instruments for safeguarding
traditional caste norms. Even in
recent times when their functioning might be said to be influenced by a new consciousness,
they have neither been able to
wield political leverage nor offer a reliable base for political
mobilization and action. For a detailed discussion see Oscar
Lewis, La rida: Puerto Rican
Family in the Culture of poverty San Juan and New York, New York: Random House,
1966;
Ramashray Roy and V. B. Singh, Between the Two Worlds: A Study of Harijan Elites, Delhi:
Discovery
Publishing House, 1987.
19.Milton M. Gordon, Assimilation in American Life, New York: Oxford University Press,
1964, pp. 46-54. Also see Celia
S. Heller, “Ethnicity, Race and Class” in Heller, op. cit.
20.The theory was originally propounded by W. G. Sumner. Social Psychologists like Adorno T.
Wetal, G. W. Allport, Robert A. Levine, Donald T. Campbell et al. have also made notable
contributions in this field. According to the theory, an individual or a group identifies with an
ethnic group and claim ethnic superiority in comparison to other ethnic groups.In some cases,
one hates and takes revenge on them. If in certain cases an individual or a group does not
identify at the ethnocentric level, then identification may be at a level other than ethnocentric.
For details see W. G. Sumner, Folkways,New York: Mentor, 1965; Adorno T. Wetal, The
Authoritarian Personality, New York: Harper -Collins, 1950; G. W.Allport (ed.), The Nature of
Prejudice, New York: Doubleday, 1955; Robert A. Levine and Donald T. Campbell,
Ethnocentrism.. Theory of Conflict, Ethnic Attitudes and Group Behaviour, New York: John
Wiley, 1971; Paranjpe Caste Prejudice and the Individual, New Delhi: Lalwani, 1970; and
Nandu Ram, op. cit.
21.Harold R. Isaacs, India’s Ex-Untouchables, Bombay: Asia Publishing House, 1965. pp. 12842; Marc Glen, Johnson
and Sipra Bose, “Social Mobility Among Untouchables” in Giri Raj Gupta (ed.), Main
Currents in Indian Sociology-III:
Cohesion and Conflict in Modern India, New Delhi: Vikas
Publishing House, 1978, p. 10.
REFERENCES
Abrams, M and R.Rose. Must Labour Lose? New York: Free Press, 1959. Alexander, K.C.
Social Mobility in Kerala.
Poona : Deccan College, 1968. Beteille, Andre. Caste : Old and
New : Essays in Social Structure and Social
Stratification. Mumbai: Asia Publishing House,
1969.
Bhat, Chandrashekhar. Ethnicity and Mobility : Emerging Ethnic Identity and Social Mobility
among the Waddars of South
India. New Delhi : Concept Publishing Company, 1984.
Bloom, Allan. “Justice : Rawls Vs The Tradition of Philosophy”, American Political Science.
69.16. 1975.
Caplow, Theodore. The Sociology of Work. New York : McGraw Hill Book Co., 1964.
Taking Dworkin, 331 . Reservation London Rights :Duckworth, Roland. and Seriously Social
Mobility: 1977. A Theoretical
Construct
Faundez, K. Affirmative Action— International Perspective. Geneva : International Labour
Office, 1994. Gordon,
M. Milton. Assimilation in Ameerican Life. New York : Oxford University Press, 1964 .
Homans, G.C. Sentiments and Activities: Essays in Social Science. London : Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1962.
Joshy, R. Barbara. Democracy in Search of Equality: Untouchable Politics and Indian Social
Change. Delhi: Hindustan Publishing Co., 1982.
Lynch, M. Owen. The Politics of Untouchability (Social Mobility and Social Change in a city of
India). Delhi : National Publishing House, 1974.
Merton, K. Robert. Social Theory and Social Structure. Glencoe : The Free Press, 1957.
Nieuwbeerta, Paul and Nan Dirk de Graaf. “Intergenerational Class Mobility and Political
Preferences between 1970 and 1986 in the Netherlands”, Netherlands Journal of Social
Sciences. 29.3. June 1993.
Oommen, T.K. From Mobilization to Institutionalization : The Dynamics of Agrarian Movement
in Twentieth Century Kerala.
Bombay : Popular Prakashan, 1985.
Ram, Nandu. The Mobile Scheduled Castes : Rise of a new Middle Class. Delhi : Hindustan
Publishing Corporation, 1988.
Rawls, John. The Theory of Justice. Oxford : Oxford University Press, 1972. Sharma, K.L.
Social Stratification and
Mobility. Jaipur : Rawat Publications, 1994.
Sorokin, A Pitrim. Social and Cultural Mobility. Illinois : The Free Press of Glencoe, 1959.
Srinivas. The Cohesive Role of Sanskritization and other Essays. Delhi : Oxford University
Press, 1989.
Verba, Sidney, Bashiruddin Ahmed and Anil Bhatt. Caste, Race and Politics: A Comparative
Study of India and United
States. New Delhi : Sage Publication, 1971.