* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download INTELLECTUAL AUTONOMY
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
Philosophical Issues, 23, Epistemic Agency, 2013 INTELLECTUAL AUTONOMY Linda Zagzebski University of Oklahoma 1. Introduction According to a standard interpretation of philosophical history, Immanuel Kant revolutionized ethics by making the ultimate moral authority one’s own rational will. I take that to be the heart of the idea of autonomy. In this essay I will describe a view of the self according to which autonomy properly applies in the intellectual domain on the same grounds as it applies in the practical domain. I will explain why I believe that the power of reflective self-consciousness is more basic than any epistemic reasons—anything that indicates to a reasonable person that some proposition is true. The argument is epistemological, not moral. The conclusion is that what we mean by reason in its theoretical sense derives from reflective self-consciousness. The authority of the self over the self is the natural right of the self to reflect, which is to say, the natural right of the self to be a self. The authority of reason over a person’s belief-forming activities, like the authority of reason over a person’s practical action, is derivative from the natural authority of the self. 2. Autonomy 2.1. A very short history of autonomy In contemporary discourse, autonomy can mean a number of different things, but I assume that the dominant idea is that of rational self-governance. Autonomy has sometimes been identified with the different notion of independence, especially in political discussions, and that is one of the reasons for the vilification of autonomy by those opposed to the individualism of our Intellectual Autonomy 245 times. When autonomy is applied to the epistemic domain, it has sometimes been equated with epistemic self-reliance, the analogue of political independence. For instance, Elizabeth Fricker describes intellectual autonomy as follows: “This ideal type relies on no one else for any of her knowledge. Thus she takes no one else’s word for anything, but accepts only what she has found out for herself, relying only on her own cognitive faculties and investigative and inferential powers (2006: 225).”1 This ideal raises a number of issues, but I find it particularly interesting that intellectual autonomy should be identified with epistemic self-reliance when it is far from obvious that autonomy and self-reliance are identified in the practical domain. My purpose in this essay is to present a view of intellectual autonomy as a form of autonomy, not simply self-reliance by another name. In my opinion, autonomy is most interesting if it is a value that is pre-moral. What I mean is that the idea of autonomy does not rest upon any moral value, and it might be strong enough to be a constraint on our understanding of what morality is. If I am right about that, that would explain why the idea of autonomy can support the modern shift from viewing morality as obedience to law to understanding morality as self-governance. Self-governance was arguably an important value since the ancient Greeks, so that is not what was new in the modern era.2 What Kant gave us was the idea that morality is self-governance, the rules by which a rational being governs itself. The additional premise is that morality comes in the form of a command; it is the product of a will. So if morality comes in the form of a command, and a person should not submit to any will but her own, it follows that morality is a command I give myself. It gets its authority from myself. The Kantian position on the nature of morality, then, follows from the nature of autonomy as self-governance combined with the view that morality comes in the form of a command. Why would modern philosophers think, either on moral or pre-moral grounds, that I should not submit to anything but my own rational will? In the ancient and medieval periods, philosophers recognized two grounds for authority—one Greek, one Judeo-Christian, both of which were modified or even rejected in the modern West. The first way to ground authority was in God, who created and governs the universe. The second way to ground authority was in reason. For the Greeks, reason is intrinsically authoritative; the authority of reason is self-evident. A person is self-governing in so far as she has a share in the force of reason that governs the universe. But since an individual person’s reason is limited, her authority to govern herself is also limited. In the last several centuries before Kant, I see two shifts in the way philosophers thought of the ground of authority. The first shift was from reason to the will. In the later Middle Ages there was a dispute between those who accepted the ancient view that the source of authority is in the divine reason, and those who claimed that the source of authority is in 246 Linda Zagzebski the divine will rather than the divine reason. Duns Scotus was one of the earliest proponents of the latter view.3 The shift from reason to will as the ground of authority had significant consequences since the relation between the divine and human wills is quite different from the relation between the divine and human reason. Our reason is arguably a share in the divine reason, which is why a measure of self-governance for the ancients and medievals is compatible with being governed by God. In contrast, our wills obviously do not share in the divine will. A will by its nature is individual. The focus on will cannot help but be a focus on the individual. In the century leading up to Kant, there was a second shift—from the idea of the natural authority of reason to the idea of the natural authority of the self. Kant brilliantly combined (a) the modern idea of the authority of the self, (b) the ancient idea of the authority of reason, and (c) the later medieval view that authority resides in a will. He argued that to be governed by oneself and to be governed by reason are the same thing because the true self is one’s own rational will. But that does not yet tell us which is more basic. Is the point of the Kantian view of autonomy that I should not submit to anything but my rational will, or is it that I should not submit to anything but my rational will? If it is the former, reason is still the primary authority, and there is no explanation for why it should be my will that governs me rather than any other rational will. If instead, autonomy means that I should not submit to anything but my own rational will, my rationality is not sufficient to explain why other wills do not have authority equal to or greater than mine. Many modern philosophers will say that I do not need a justification for the authority of my own will, but since philosophers before the modern period did not see it that way, we need a defense for the shift from the idea that the authority that needs no justification is reason to the idea that the authority that needs no justification is the authority of the self over itself. Christine Korsgaard offers such a defense. She argues that Kant’s answer to our question is that the self’s authority over itself does not derive from the authority of a rational will; rather, reason is authoritative because it is the rules that the self must set to govern itself (Korsgaard 2009: xi). The self just is a being with an executive function. It must take control of itself because of the operation of self-consciousness. The rules of reason are the rules of a self-conscious being. Korsgaard interprets the authority of reason as derivative from the authority of the self-conscious self, the reverse of the traditional view. As I interpret the historical development of the idea of autonomy, then, there was a progression from the ancient idea that authority over me resides in reason, to the idea that authority resides in the rational will, to the idea that authority resides in my rational will. The first two were rooted outside the individual person, generally in the divine reason or will, with human authority based on the human being’s submission to or imitation of the Intellectual Autonomy 247 divine ground of authority. The third constituted a radical shift, although Kant did not give up the idea that authority is grounded in universal reason. What was radical was the idea that universal reason is attached to my own will. I surmise that it was that feature that permitted later degeneration into the view that my will, unconstrained by anything, including reason, is the only authority over me.4 2.2. Intellectual autonomy and heteronomy Let us now begin to look at what all this has to do with autonomy in the intellectual domain. First, I think it is fair to say that even if the ultimate bearer of practical or moral authority is someone’s will, nobody but Hobbes would say that the ultimate bearer of intellectual authority is a will.5 Nevertheless, we would expect there to be a close connection between intellectual autonomy and autonomy of the will, and a corresponding connection between intellectual authority and practical authority. Notice first that autonomy of the will presupposes autonomy of the intellect. It is unlikely that we can autonomously make a choice unless the beliefs upon which the choice is based are autonomous. This point does not depend upon any particular view of autonomy, but only on the assumption that choices depend upon beliefs. If it is good that acts are autonomous, at least some of our beliefs ought to be formed autonomously. The conditions of the mind upon which choice depends must be autonomous. Notice also that the ways in which a will can be heteronomous according to Kant have a parallel in the formation of beliefs. A will is heteronomous in one way when it is controlled by a will outside of it. Similarly, an intellect can be too greatly influenced or even controlled by someone else’s will. It is plausible to say such an intellect is heteronomous. Intellectual coercion is generally thought to be impossible, as Locke observed (see note 5), but commercial and political advertising are common ways of pressuring people to form particular beliefs even though the beliefs are not literally coerced. It is understandable that people sometimes complain that their autonomy is violated, at least to some degree, by the use of such methods of influencing belief. An amusing and more extreme view on coercion over belief is Robert Nozick’s claim that rational persuasion is coercive, and philosophers are guilty of coercing people’s minds. Nozick says: The terminology of philosophical art is coercive: arguments are powerful and best when they are knockdown, arguments force you to a conclusion, if you believe the premises you have to or must believe the conclusion, some arguments do not carry much punch, and so forth. A philosophical argument is an attempt to get someone to believe something, whether he wants to or not . . . Why are philosophers intent on forcing others to believe things? Is that a nice way to behave toward someone? (Nozick 1981: 4–5) 248 Linda Zagzebski We may not all agree on whether anyone is entitled to influence the beliefs of others by rational argument or any other method, but fortunately, we do not have to settle that issue because the first kind of intellectual heteronomy is relevant either way. Surely another person can unduly influence my beliefs, and that can happen even when the other person is not claiming authority, is not attempting to coerce my belief or to persuade me, and may even be unaware of my existence. Of course, we will want to know what undue influence is, but it is plausible that it exists and that it is problematic for roughly the same reason Kant gives for thinking that the first kind of heteronomy of the will is problematic. If we are not fully rational when our wills are pushed around, then we are not fully rational when our intellects are pushed around, whatever “pushed around” amounts to. At least, there is a prima facie case for the equivalence. A will is heteronomous in the second way, according to Kant, when it is determined by forces within the self other than reason—by inclination or fancy. An intellect also can be determined by inclination or fancy, or something other than reason, and there is a prima facie case for calling such an intellect heteronomous. The value of intellectual autonomy that contrasts with a heteronomous intellect in this sense is not very controversial. Nobody denies that reason is good for the intellect, and that forming beliefs by inclination or fancy is a bad idea. I think that we can expect, then, that if autonomy is valuable, intellectual autonomy is also. Both of the ways in which a will can be heteronomous according to Kant probably apply to the intellect, and both ways are disvaluable. So far we have nothing more than a couple of hints about the nature of intellectual autonomy. In the next two sections I will return to the view adopted from Korsgaard that reason derives from self-consciousness. Rather than to give a Kantian argument for that position, I will give an epistemological argument that epistemic reasons derive from the powers of a self-reflective being. This will lead to a view of intellectual autonomy that connects it with autonomy in the practical domain. 3. The primacy of conscientious self-reflection 3.1. The exercise of self-reflection What I mean by a self is the inner world of a person. When a self is conscious, it is aware of the distinction between the subject and object of consciousness, and in self-consciousness the subject is able to direct consciousness to itself. To be conscious of oneself includes consciousness of a variety of mental states, including beliefs, desires, emotions, sensations, attitudes, judgments, and decisions, as well as imaginary versions of each. Some of these states occur naturally. For instance, I think there is a natural desire Intellectual Autonomy 249 for truth and a natural belief that the natural desire for truth can be satisfied, so basic epistemic self-trust is natural. I think it is natural to have many other beliefs, such as the belief that there are other persons with conscious states similar to mine. Many emotions are no doubt natural as well. But most of our particular beliefs, desires, and emotions are acquired. Our mental states can sometimes conflict with one another. We experience conflict between our mental states as dissonance. It seems to me that the experience of dissonance is basic. It cannot be explained or analysed in terms of some other experience. I do not mean that conflict is defined by the experience of dissonance since there can be conflict that is unconscious, but we detect conflict through the experience of dissonance. Many times when there is dissonance, the self automatically adjusts by giving up one of the states that conflict. This often happens when there is conflict between a belief and a perception. I believe that I turned off the watering system, but then hear the sprinklers go on. I give up my belief without any attention to the conflict. The conflict is short-lived and psychic harmony is restored effortlessly and without conscious attention. I think that the awareness of dissonance resolved without effort gives us our initial model of what rationality is. I say that because I think that rationality is a property we have when we do what we do naturally, only we do a better job of it. To be rational is to do a better job of what we do anyway—what our faculties do naturally. Sometimes there is conflict that is not automatically resolved. If we are aware of dissonance, we typically feel a need to resolve it by giving up one of the components of the self that creates the dissonance, and we may not want to do so. Some forms of dissonance do not need to be resolved; we can get along well enough with the dissonance. This often happens with conflicting desires, or with a desire that conflicts with a belief. I believe that I will go on a trip tomorrow, but I do not want to go. I am aware of the dissonance between the belief and the desire, but I do not feel an urgency to give up either the belief or the desire the way I do when I am aware of conflicting beliefs. Nonetheless, it is better if dissonance is resolved. Conflict between desires or between a belief and a desire can also be resolved unconsciously, and the experience of the resulting harmony gives us a model of a kind of rationality that is desirable for the same reason we desire harmony in our beliefs: We naturally desire and attempt to achieve a harmonious self. When we are aware of a conflict within the self, we might find it hard to give up either side to the conflict, but may make the judgment that a certain one ought to be given up. This situation often occurs when a decision conflicts with a set of beliefs. We may judge that we ought to change the decision, but find it difficult. Perhaps we are able to do so after a struggle; we call that continence. Perhaps we are not able to do so and we call that incontinence or akrasia. Akrasia is often called moral weakness, but the weakness need not have anything to do with morality. Indeed, one can be akratic when what 250 Linda Zagzebski one judges one ought to do is opposed to morality (Davidson 1970). A mild form of akrasia exists as long as the conflict exists and we are aware of the dissonance but do not resolve it. A stronger form of akrasia occurs when we resolve the conflict in favor of the wrong side to the conflict—what we judge we ought not to do. I have proposed that we begin reflection with a model of what we ought to do to resolve conflict, which is, very roughly, what we would do if we were doing it automatically and without effort. What we do reflectively builds upon a base in what we do pre-reflectively. Of course, part of the point of reflection is to change some of what we do pre-reflectively, but reflection operates on processes that already exist in our pre-reflective state. We judge ourselves reflectively with the pre-reflective experience of successful resolutions of conflict. My position, then, is that there is a connection between rationality and our reflective judgment of what produces harmony in the self. I have added the idea that there is a connection between rationality and what people do automatically. I think we would have a lot of trouble distinguishing rational from irrational behavior were it not for the experience of making an automatic adjustment when there is dissonance in the states of the self. Of course, I am not suggesting that rationality should be defined by such behavior. But what we do automatically gives us our initial standard of rationality, a standard for what it is to make the adjustment in the self correctly. The criterion works only if there is a close connection between the way the self naturally operates and what the self ought to do. That means that there is a connection between the natural and the normative, in particular, a connection between the self as it naturally operates and the way it should operate. When parts of the self adjust automatically, no executive is needed. The self exercises its executive function when we have to make up our mind. Choice in action involves an executive function, but other changes in the self do also. Sometimes resolution of dissonance within the self requires the exercise of the executive function of the self. It does so when the resolution of dissonance does not occur automatically. The executive self can also be called an agent. The self is an agent in its role of taking charge of itself, correcting itself, and thereby becoming a more harmonious self, and hence, in some deeper way, more of a self. A self-conscious being has an executive function in virtue of being a self. This is the sense in which the self has natural authority over itself. I have no objections to someone who says that the reflective ability of the self to monitor and change in the way I have described shows the centrality of the will in our psychology, but I find it misleading to use the term “will” for the executive function I have described. I do not maintain that the self-reflective regulation of the self involves changing states of the self “at will,” and I think that our power to act is not a good model of the reflective powers of the self, which are broader and generally weaker than Intellectual Autonomy 251 the power to perform basic acts. My preference, then, is not to say that the ultimate authority over a self is the will. Rather, the natural authority of the self over the self is the power of the executive function of self-reflective consciousness. 3.2. Beliefs and the reflective self Let us look now at a deep kind of dissonance produced by reflection upon our beliefs as a whole. Many philosophers who have rigorously reflected upon their beliefs notice the phenomenon of epistemic circularity, or what Keith Lehrer (1997) has called “the loop of reason.” The problem is that there is no non-circular way to determine that the natural desire for truth is satisfiable, or to put the claim in the preferred idiom, there is no non-circular way to tell that our belief-forming faculties are reliable as a whole. Richard Foley (2001) links the phenomenon of epistemic circularity with the lack of answers to the radical skeptic and the failure of the project of strong foundationalism. We can do everything epistemically that we are supposed to do, including following the evidence scrupulously, but we have no assurances that the results will give us the truth or even make it more probable that we will get the truth. Foley concludes that we need self-trust in our epistemic faculties taken as a whole, together with our pre-reflective opinions. Self-trust is necessary, and further, he argues that it is rational in that it is a state to which we are led by the process of rational self-criticism. One is rationally entitled to self-trust, and therefore one is rationally entitled to the degree of confidence one has in one’s opinions and faculties when one has trust in the self since it is critical reflection that leads to self-trust. (25, 47). Foley’s model is one in which it is rational to do what self-reflective beings do. That seems to me to be right. William Alston offers a more detailed argument for a related conclusion about circularity in his final book, Beyond Justification (2005), which modifies an argument in Alston (1986). Alston argues that we cannot justify any belief arising from a basic practice of belief-formation (perception, memory, introspection, rational intuition, induction, and others) without justifying the well-groundedness of the practice, but we cannot do that without using that same practice. For instance, I cannot justify my belief that a dive-bombing hawk just swooped by my window without a justification of the reliability of my perceptual faculties, but I cannot justify my belief in the reliability of my perceptual faculties without using perception. This is a stronger claim than the one made by Foley. Alston argues that circularity arises in the attempt to establish the reliability of individual basic sources of belief such as perception, memory, and deductive reasoning, whereas Foley claims only that circularity arises in the attempt to establish the reliability of our epistemic faculties and beliefs taken as a whole.6 252 Linda Zagzebski It does not matter for my argument whether Alston’s stronger view on the extent of circularity is correct. Either way, circularity is a problem that reflective beings notice. But there is an interesting difference between Alston and Foley that I think is important. Alston does not think that the problem of epistemic circularity is necessarily tied to the threat of skepticism. He says that the spectre of skepticism is a dramatic way to put the issue, “but it is not necessary for a calm, fully mature consideration of the problem” (2005: 216).7 The problem as Alston sees it is that the fact that the justification of our beliefs is ultimately circular prevents us from being “fully reflectively justified” in our beliefs. We need not be especially worried about evil geniuses and brains in vats to notice circularity, and we need not think that the alternative to full reflective justification is skepticism. I think Alston is right about that. A problem arises as soon as a person reflects upon her desire for truth and carries reflection upon that desire as far as she can. She is doing what every self-reflective being does, only more thoroughly and scrupulously. She feels dissonance when she lacks full reflective justification for her beliefs, and that is a problem even if she does not fear skepticism or even pays any attention to skepticism. Alston and Foley think of self-trust as the rational outcome of a sophisticated line of argument. It is an end state, not the state from which we start. I differ from them on this point since I have suggested that there is pre-reflective self-trust. Before we reflect upon the justification of our beliefs or the reliability of our faculties, we already trust ourselves and our environment, including other people. The difference is that awareness of epistemic circularity forces us to confront the pre-reflective trust we have in ourselves at the reflective level. Is it rational to have self-trust after reflection? That depends upon whether reflection creates dissonance between our natural pre-reflective trust, and beliefs that result from reflection on our total set of beliefs, including the belief that full reflective justification is impossible. Foley and Alston say that self-trust is the rational result of reflection upon beliefs. But even if someone is not convinced by their arguments, surely the rational result of self-reflection is not to give up pre-reflective trust. There is no dissonance between self-trust and our total set of beliefs, including the belief that full reflective justification is impossible. On the contrary, there is less dissonance between self-trust and our total set of beliefs than there is between the belief that full reflective justification is impossible and the rest of our beliefs. But there is another way to resolve the latter dissonance: one could become a skeptic. One could give up both natural self-trust and one’s previous beliefs, but not give up the belief that full reflective justification is impossible. To prevent dissonance with the natural desire for truth, the skeptic would have to give that up also, if possible, or else live with permanent dissonance. I have my doubts that there are such persons, but if such a radical skeptic exists, she does not have the irrationality of dissonance, but she attains harmony Intellectual Autonomy 253 by foregoing much of what we do naturally. I have suggested that rationality is, roughly, doing a better job of what we naturally do. The skeptic I have described is not going a better job of what we do naturally because she is not doing what we do naturally. However, I am not going to critique skepticism. My conclusion in this section is that when a person carries self-reflection as far as she can, and does it honestly and rigorously, she will do the best job of maintaining harmony in the self—one of the principal goals of the executive self, by maintaining a great many of her pre-reflective beliefs, and bringing her trust in herself to reflective consciousness. That is, the result of rigorous self-reflection is to become consciously aware of her natural self-trust and accepting of it. 3.3. The conscientious believer and the nature of reasons The function of self-trust in our epistemic lives leads to a way of thinking about reasons for belief that makes them derivative from what we do when we bring our desire for the truth to reflective consciousness. When we want our questions answered, what we typically do is to look for what we call reasons. Something is a reason because, upon reflection, it can be put together with other reasons in such a way that they seem to support a given conclusion, a conclusion that we then take to be true. What we call justification (in one of its senses) is the state we are in when we succeed in finding reasons of that kind. The desire for truth in a self-reflective person leads to the search for reasons in this way, and the arguments for epistemic circularity by Foley and Alston make this assumption. We trust that there is a connection between the possession of reasons for belief and getting the truth. A self-reflective person who desires truth may not search for reasons for every belief. The issue of whether there are beliefs that a self-reflective person accepts without reasons is an important one, and I am not assuming that there are no such beliefs. What is not disputable is that a self-reflective person looks for reasons for many of her beliefs, and she considers it a good thing to have reasons for any of her beliefs. I do not think there is any explanation for why she does that or what would justify her in doing so except that that is what self-reflective persons who desire truth do. To have reasons for her beliefs produces psychic harmony, and to fail to have reasons produces psychic dissonance. This leads to the question whether we have reasons to think that our reasons for belief lead to the truth. The same question can be posed in terms of the related notion of evidence.8 Do we have evidence that evidence leads to truth? In any sense of evidence that would eliminate the need for trust in the relation between evidence and truth, the answer is no. For one thing, we do not have evidence that evidence leads to truth. What we have is evidence that evidence for p leads to more evidence for p, enough that at some point we 254 Linda Zagzebski declare p true. But in any case, why should we pay attention to the evidence that evidence leads to truth unless we trust the connection between evidence and truth? No matter how much evidence we have, its connection to truth will always be something that cannot be established without circularity. The answer to the question of why it is rational to trust evidence is the same as the answer to the question of why it is rational to trust reasons. Trusting the connection between evidence and truth is something rational people who desire the truth do. Even the skeptic trusts this connection. In fact, it is because the skeptic trusts this connection that the skeptic becomes a skeptic. It is the failure to complete the search for evidence that leads her to skepticism. Circularity is relevant to the desire for truth because we make certain assumptions about the nature of mind and the universe. We want truth—our questions answered correctly, and we notice that the process of attempting to answer those questions can never be completed. But this is a problem because we assume (a) there is a connection between successfully getting the truth and what we do when we attempt to answer our questions (what we call finding reasons or evidence), and (b) what we attempt to do can never be completed. The discovery of epistemic circularity discussed by Alston and Foley is the discovery of (b), but what about (a)? We do not discover (a); we trust it. The need for trust in (a) is independent of (b), and we can see that by looking at what our situation would be like if, per impossibile, we were able to complete the search for reasons in a non-circular way. We would still need trust that there is any connection between reasons and truth. Whether or not we have the reasons we seek, we need to trust that reasons are the sorts of things that give us the answers to our questions, that connect us to truth. So even if strong foundationalism had succeeded, we would need trust that we identified the foundation correctly and that the foundationalist structure reliably gives us truth. This is no less the case if the foundation is certain. We would still need trust in the connection between the state of certainty and truth. We get the same conclusion no matter what notion of evidence or reasons we use. Evidence can be understood as something internal to the mind— generally, a phenomenal experience or a belief. In contrast, evidence is sometimes understood as public property, the sort of thing to which scientists or lawyers can point in the common project of attempting to answer questions. If reasons are public, they can be either objects, such as fingerprints, or facts (true propositions).9 Alternatively, reasons could be some combination of the public and private, such as facts known by the subject. There are many variations, but in every case, trust is needed. If a reason for belief is internal to the mind, the need for trust in the connection between a reason and something external to the mind is clear. If instead a reason is defined from an external perspective, what in fact indicates truth, that means that what we do when we are attempting to get truth may not be having a reason in the Intellectual Autonomy 255 sense defined. That does not remove the need for trust, it just backs it up a step to trust in the link between what we do when we are trying to get truth and having a reason from an external perspective. The same point applies to evidence. Whether or not we define evidence in a way that builds a reliable connection to the truth into the concept, we need to trust the connection between (a) what we do when we make a fully conscious effort to use our faculties the best way we can to get truth and (b) success in reaching truth. Using an externalist notion of reasons or evidence therefore does not remove the need for trust in the connection between our faculties and getting the truth. The fundamental reason we trust evidence or reasons is that looking for evidence is what we do when we are self-reflective, and we trust that. I call the quality of using our faculties to the best of our ability in order to get the truth epistemic conscientiousness. I think of this quality as the self-reflective version of the natural desire for truth. It is a natural desire brought to selfreflective consciousness and accompanied by the attempt to satisfy it with all of one’s powers. I have argued that we need trust that there is a connection between the natural desire for truth and the satisfaction of that desire using the faculties that any person has, reflective or pre-reflective, but once a person becomes reflective, she thinks that her trustworthiness is greater if she summons her powers in a fully conscious and careful way, and exercises them to the best of her ability. What I am calling conscientiousness is the state or disposition to do that.10 Conscientiousness is important because we do not think that we are equally trustworthy at all times. We trust that there is a connection between trying and succeeding, and the reflective person thinks that there is a closer connection between trying with the full reflective use of her powers, and succeeding. Conscientiousness comes in degrees. There is a probably a degree of conscientiousness operating most of the time since we have some awareness of ourselves and the exercise of our powers most of the time. But higher degrees of conscientiousness require considerable self-awareness and self-monitoring. A conscientious person has evidence that she is more likely to get the truth when she is conscientious, but she trusts evidence in virtue of her trust in herself when she is conscientious, not conversely. Her trust in herself is more basic than her trust in evidence, and that includes evidence of reliability. The identification of evidence, the identification of the way to handle and evaluate evidence, and the resolution of conflicting evidence all depend upon the more basic property of epistemic conscientiousness. I think, then, that evidence is what we take to be indicative of truth when we are conscientious, and we trust that that is identical with what is indicative of truth. Norms of reasoning such as the rules of probability are tools for helping us figure out what is most conscientious to believe.11 Likewise, I think that intellectual virtues are qualities that arise out of epistemic conscientiousness. These qualities are those that epistemically conscientious persons endorse and attempt to 256 Linda Zagzebski acquire. But we would not treat them as virtues unless we thought that our cognitive and sensory faculties are generally trustworthy because these qualities are useless in a being whose faculties are not naturally conducive to reaching their end.12 It follows from what I have argued that there are two levels of selftrust, both of which are more basic than any reasons or evidence we can identify. First, there is the general trust in our faculties that I argued is the most rational response to epistemic circularity. Second, there is the particular trust we have in our faculties when we are conscientious—exercising our truth-seeking faculties in the best way we can. Our identification of reasons for belief, norms of reasoning, and the qualities we think are intellectually virtuous are all derivative from what we do when we are epistemically conscientious. My judgment that the evidence supports some proposition p is not trustworthy without trust in my faculties, in particular, the conscientious use of my faculties. That means that trust in my faculties is always more basic than any judgment about the evidence and what it supports. Trust in myself is more basic than trust in my judgment of the reliability of myself or anyone else. This line of reasoning has the consequence that ultimately our only test that a belief is true is that it survives conscientious reflection. That includes reflection on future experiences, and future judgments about the past and present. At any one time, of course, we cannot know what our future experiences will be. Norms of reasoning are the norms that have been adopted by the conscientious judgment that following them makes it likely that beliefs will survive without dissonance into the future—that they will survive with changes in experience and changes in other beliefs. In section 3.1, I proposed that the experience of dissonance unconsciously resolved gives us our first model of what rationality is. Given what I have argued in sections 3.2 and 3.3, the experience of the conscientious self resolving dissonance gives us our second model of what rationality is. It is rational to trust when it is needed to resolve dissonance, and epistemic self-trust is rational in this sense. The foundation of rationality is the conscientious self reflecting upon itself in order to resolve dissonance. 4. Intellectual autonomy In section 2, I suggested that the rise of the idea of autonomy can be understood in terms of a double shift in the answer to the question, “What has ultimate authority over me?” Before the modern era there were two answers to that question that were not perceived as conflicting, and for the most part, were blended into one answer. The ultimate authority is God, and the ultimate authority is reason, but reason is the divine in the human. I proposed that the two-part shift in the answer to the question, “What has Intellectual Autonomy 257 ultimate authority over me?” included a shift from the (divine) reason to the (divine) will, and a second shift from reason to the self. Kant did not reject the authority of reason, but he accepted both the shifts from reason to will and from reason to the self, yielding the view that the ultimate authority over me is my own rational will. The defense of this view, according to Korsgaard, is that the norms of reason are the rules of self-governance. It is important that the rules of self-governance are not the rules that they are because they are the norms of reason. Rather, the norms of reason are what they are because they are the rules of self-governance. The self governs itself because of the self-reflective structure of the self. The self is more basic than reason, and the will directs the self. What makes the will crucial for Kant is that the norms of morality come in the form of commands. In my view of autonomy, there are some features of this picture that need to be clarified, and possibly modified. First, the ability of the self to command itself is just a special case of the more general capacity of a self to reflect upon itself and to make adjustments, some of which are unconscious, some of which are conscious but effortless, some of which require effort, and some of which are intended, but the self is powerless to make the change. I see all of these processes as occurring because of the natural desire of a self to be harmonious in its states—to resolve dissonance, and to adjust in a way that is intended to survive future self-reflection without dissonance. It is not obvious that it is the will that performs all these functions. Rather, the self performs these functions upon itself. What gives the self authority to do so is just that that is the nature of the self. It cannot do otherwise than to be a self. I think that also means that the term “self-governance” is misleading since that term can be interpreted as suggesting that there is an issue that can be answered in more than one way: Does the self govern itself or is it governed by something outside the self? In the sense in which I think the self is self-governing, there is no alternative, so the question of who governs the self does not arise. In the sense in which I have argued that the self is self-governing, governance by anything other than the self is an impossibility. We can now see how the problem of epistemic circularity reveals the relationship between the authority of reason over our beliefs and the authority of the self to direct itself. As I argued in section 3, trust in ourselves when we are conscientiously directing the self is more basic than anything we call evidence or reasons to believe some proposition. From my first person perspective, I will always need to trust the connection between (a) what I do when I make a fully conscious effort to use my faculties the best way we can to get truth, and (b) success in reaching truth. I am rationally forced to accept that trust in my powers is prior to trust in reasons. That does not mean that I am more authoritative than reason. It just means that my ability to use reason is always derivative from the self-directing function of my self. 258 Linda Zagzebski The authority of the self also does not mean that I could decide otherwise than to adopt the norms of theoretical and practical reason. The norms of reason are the norms I must use in order to reflectively adjust the self. It is not an accident that the rules I must use in self-direction are the same as the ones every other self must use. Reason is the set of rules of any self-reflective being. Finally, the sense in which the self has authority over itself is compatible with governance by God or by another external authority for the same reason it is compatible with being governed by reason. The self is a constantly changing entity that develops under its own direction, but there is nothing in that function that rules out accepting beliefs or directives from authority. In fact, I have argued elsewhere (Zagzebski 2012) that the acceptance of both epistemic and practical authority is a rational requirement of a consistently self-directing self. The modern shift from the authority of reason to the authority of the self therefore does not diminish the authority of reason, but it does show us that the effective use of reason by one self can differ from its use by another self because of differences in the states of the selves upon which the norms of reason are applied. I think also that the argument of section 3 shows us the fundamental significance of the self’s management of itself, even in the intellectual domain. I think that autonomy is this capacity for self-management and its exercise. Autonomy is sometimes described as a right that can be violated, and sometimes as an ideal to which we should aspire. Both ways of speaking of autonomy make sense on the picture I have described. I have proposed that the basic norm of self-direction is conscientious self-reflection. Conscientiousness comes in degrees, and I suggested that it takes a high degree of self-reflection to use our faculties to the fullest extent of our powers in our attempt to reach the ends of those powers. Self-direction is also a right that a self has in being a self, and there are ways that that right can be violated, either from the inside or from the outside. As I mentioned in section 2.2, Kant argued that a will is heteronomous in one way when it is controlled by a will outside of it. In my picture, a self is heteronomous in this way when there is outside interference in the capacity or exercise of self-direction. Someone is intellectually heteronomous in this way when there is outside interference in the self’s direction of its pursuit of truth or other intellectual goods. According to Kant, a will is heteronomous in another way when it is unduly influenced by inclination, or what he called “empirical” causes. In my picture, a self is heteronomous in this way when it is not properly self-reflective, thereby permitting states of the self to change or continue without conscientious self-reflection. The self is intellectually heteronomous in this way when it permits states of belief to change or continue without conscientious self-reflection. Conscientious self-reflection can be hampered by both internal and external influences. Intellectual Autonomy 259 In my view, autonomy is the right or ideal of managing all parts of the self, not just decisions to act, in order to achieve a harmonious self. Intellectual autonomy is the right or ideal of self-direction in the acquisition and maintenance of beliefs. The basic ends of acts and beliefs are given by natural desires. I have mentioned the natural desire for truth in particular, but I do not wish to deny that there are other intellectual goods, such as knowledge and understanding. Desire for these goods is probably acquired by the experience of self-reflection. The foundation of rationality is the conscientious self attempting to resolve dissonance and produce harmony in the self. I argued in section 3 that the self cannot resolve the dissonance that results from conscientious reflection on one’s total set of beliefs without epistemic self-trust. Since intellectual autonomy is the exercise of self-management in one’s beliefs, then epistemic self-trust is a necessary condition for intellectual autonomy. I think that this point can be generalized. Autonomy requires trust in the connection between the conscientious use of all of one’s powers—perceptual, epistemic, affective, conative—and success in reaching the basic ends of those powers. Self-trust is a necessary and critical condition for autonomy, and for the same reason it is a necessary and critical condition for being a self.13 Notes 1. The identification of intellectual autonomy and epistemic self-reliance has also been made by some who are opposed to epistemic self-reliance. For instance, Benjamim McMyler (2011, ch. 1) says he is opposed to intellectual autonomy, but he makes it clear that that is because he equates it with epistemic self-reliance. 2. Anthony Flood (2003) argues that there are numerous ancient sources of the idea of self-governance stretching back to Socrates, and that Aquinas had a robust notion of self-governance in his moral philosophy. 3. See Schneewind (1998 ch. 2, sec. iii) for an historical overview of voluntarism,or the view that moral authority is grounded in a will. For a history of Divine Command theory, see Idziak (1980). 4. For an interesting discussion of the culmination of the idea of authority in the individual will, see Taylor (1976: 288–94). 5. In Behemoth, Dialogue 1, Hobbes argues that the Sovereign is the intellectual authority in the State, holding authority over the Church in its teachings. He argues that the universities need to be disciplined so that they teach what the sovereign wants since the universities are the core of rebellion, as happened in the English civil war. This part of Behemoth includes a long diatribe against the Catholic Church and the Presbyterian Church for their “pretensions” to authority. In contrast to Hobbes, Locke denies that authority over religious belief is possible. He says: “ . . . the care of souls cannot belong to the civil magistrate, because his power consists only in outward force: but true and saving religion consists in the inward persuasion of the mind, without which nothing can be 260 Linda Zagzebski 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. acceptable to God. And such is the nature of the understanding, that it cannot be compelled to the belief of any thing by outward force. Confiscation of estate, imprisonment, torments, nothing of that nature can have any such efficacy as to make men change the inward judgment that they have framed of things.” (Locke 2009: para 16). Rousseau (1968) seems to have an intermediate position. He agrees with Hobbes that the sovereign should fix the articles of faith, but he says it cannot compel a citizen to believe them, although it can banish whoever does not believe them as an anti-social being. (The Social Contract Book IV, chap 8). I thank Zev Trachtenberg for conversation on these passages. Alston’s position on the circularity of justifying basic sources of belief has an interesting twist. He argues that circularity does not prevent us from using an inductive argument to establish the conclusion that a doxastic practice such as sense perception is adequately grounded (1986: 202–3). An inductive argument of this sort is not logically circular, given that the conclusion does not appear in the premises, but it is epistemically circular in that one’s confidence in each premise depends in practice upon the assumption of the reliability of sense perception (SR). Nonetheless, epistemic circularity does not prevent us from being justified in believing each of the premises in the argument, nor does it prevent us from being justified in believing that SR follows from the premises. And so epistemic circularity does not prevent us from being justified in believing the conclusion, SR. He says, however, that he will pursue the discussion in the following pages in terms of the “more dramatically attractive” skeptical challenge. His response to epistemic circularity two pages later is therefore framed as a reply to the Pyrrhonian skeptic. The notions of reasons and evidence are closely connected, but there are some differences. One difference is that we usually speak of reasons for a given belief, whereas evidence can be gathered when any belief for which it is evidence is not yet in play. So we would not normally speak of having reasons without indicating what the reasons support, whereas we might say we have evidence when we have no idea what the evidence indicates. Some philosophers make evidence a narrower category than reasons, limiting evidence to reasons of a certain kind—e.g., propositional beliefs. For instance, Plantinga (1983) does this in his well-known attack on evidentialism. In this terminology, an experience can give a person a reason to believe a proposition, but it is not evidence. Another difference is that evidence is sometimes thought to be objects that point to truth, such as fingerprints. A fingerprint could be evidence, but it is not a reason. I mention evidence in this sense below. See Kelly (2006) for an excellent summary of the various senses in which people speak of evidence. Note that as I define conscientiousness, it does not have any relation to duty. For this reason, trusting my faculties as a whole cannot mean trusting that, taken as a whole, using my faculties makes it more probable than not that I get the truth. That would make it too easy to convince myself that most of my beliefs are true. Believing a faculty is trustworthy does not include making a judgment of probability. My position is that judgments of probability depend upon a prior belief in the trustworthiness of my faculties. Intellectual Autonomy 261 12. In Zagzebski (2012: 82) I argue that qualities like intellectual attentiveness, carefulness, thoroughness and openness to new evidence are forms of epistemic conscientiousness. But it does not do us any good to be careful, thorough, etc. unless our faculties put us generally on the right track. So we assume the general trustworthiness of our faculties when we treat these qualities as virtues. 13. Parts of this paper are taken from Zagzebski (2012, chapters 1, 2, and 11). Bibliography Alston, William P. 1986. “Epistemic Circularity.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47, pp. 1–30. Alston, William P. 2005. Beyond Justification: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. Davidson, Donald. 1970. “How is Weakness of the Will Possible?” in Moral Concepts, edited by Joel Feinberg. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Flood, Anthony. 2003. “Self-Governance in Aquinas and Pre-Modern Moral Philosophy.” Dissertation in Philosophy, University of Oklahoma. Foley, Richard. 2001. Intellectual Trust in Oneself and Others. N.Y.: Cambridge Universitiy Press. Fricker, Eizabeth. 2006. “Testimony and Epistemic Authority.” in The Epistemology of Testimony. Edited by Jennifer Lackey and Ernest Sosa. N.Y.: Oxford University Press. Hobbes, Thomas. 2010. Behemoth, or the Long Parliament. Edited by P. Seaward. N.Y.: Oxford University Press. Idziak, Janine. 1980. Divine Command Morality: Historical and Contemporary Readings. N.Y.: Edwin Mellen Press. Kant, Immanuel. 1997. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated and edited by M. Gregor. N.Y.: Cambridge University Press. Kelly, Thomas. 2006. “Evidence.” in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by E.N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/arhives/fall2008/entries/evidence/. Korsgaard, Christine. 2009. Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lehrer, Keith. 1997. Self-Trust: A Study of Reason, Knowledge, and Autonomy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Locke, John. 2009. A Letter Concerning Toleration: Humbly Submitted. N.Y.: Classic Book America. McMyler, Benjamin. 2011. Testimony, Trust, and Authority. N.Y.: Oxford University Press. Nozick, Robert. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, M.A.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Plantinga, Alvin. 1983. “Reason and Belief in God.” in Faith and Rationality. Edited by N. Wolterstorff and A. Plantinga. Notre Dame, I.N.: University of Notre Dame Press, pp.16–93. Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1968. The Social Contract. Translated by M. Cranston. N.Y.: Penguin Press. Schneewind, J.B. 1998. The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Taylor, Charles. 1976. “Responsibility for Self.” in Identifies of Persons. Edited by Amelie Rorty. Berkeley, C.A.: University of California Press. Zagzebski, Linda. 2012. On Epistemology. Belmont, C.A.: Wadsworth/Broadview Press. Zagzebski, Linda. 2012. Epistemic Authority: A Theory of Trust, Authority, and Autonomy in Belief. N.Y.: Oxford University Press.