* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Learning Science: The Very Idea
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA RUNNING HEAD: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA Learning Science: The Very Idea Liam Rourke Assistant Professor Learning Science and Technology Academic Group National Institute of Education Nanyang Technological University Singapore [email protected] (65) 6790-3349 Norm Friesen Applied Communication Technology Lab School of Communication Simon Fraser University Vancouver, BC [email protected] DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 1 Abstract Attempts to frame the study of teaching and learning in explicitly scientific terms are not new, but they have recently been growing in prominence. Societies, journals, conferences, handbooks, and centers of learning science are appearing with remarkable frequency. However, in most of these invocations of an educational science, the term science is itself understood in exclusively progressivist, positivistic terms. More recent theory, sociology, and everyday practice of science are ignored in favour of appeals to idealized scientific rigour and efficiency. We begin this paper by considering a number of examples of prominent scholarship undermining this idealization (e.g., Popper, Kuhn, Latour, Woolgar). We then argue that learning and education are inescapably interpretive activities that can only be configured rhetorically rather than substantially as a science. We conclude by arguing for the relevance of a broader and self-consciously rhetorical/metaphorical conception of science, one that would include the possibility of an interpretive human science. DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 1 Learning Science: The Very Idea In 1781, Kant surveyed the advances of mathematicians and geometers, and he compared their progress to the work of the philosophers with woe. He characterized all of metaphysics to that point as random groping and longed for certain, progressive knowledge (p. 17). In the late 1980s, a similar mood took hold among a group of educational researchers. Those who had embraced cognitive science felt their approach presented, as last, a way beyond the random groping of previous research on teaching and learning. Its certain and progressive nature, moreover, would lead to robust improvements to educational practice (Kolodner, 1991). In its current state, this movement is called the learning sciences. The Journal of the Learning Sciences (JLS) was established in 1991 as its principle forum, a handbook is forthcoming (Sawyer, 2006), and a handful of learning science programs have popped up in universities in the United States, Europe, and South East Asia. In this article we critique the effort to reconstruct educational inquiry as learning science. In it, we address four questions, 1) What is learning science in its current form 2) What is science, generally considered? 3) Is science something to which all educational researchers should aspire? And 4) What might we do instead? In addressing these questions, we argue 1) current understandings and practices of science, as revealed by philosophers, historians, and sociologists of science are quite different from the idealized version held by those most committed to learning science; 2) relapsing into a positivistic approach to the study of human action ignores major intellectual movements of the 20th century, and 3) movements underway in this century, including phronetic (i.e., socially responsible) DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 2 social science and hermeneutic psychology offer more promising ways to understand and affect educational practice. Science To understand the current popularity of learning science we are forced to rehearse a story that was told and retold frequently in the latter part of the 20th century. The story typically begins by identifying the attributes that comprise an orthodox definition of science and then follows the abandonment of each attribute as they were scrutinized by philosophers of science and sociologists --and in many cases, by scientists themselves. For Western chroniclers, the story of the scientific enterprise often begins in 15th or 16th centuries, and its function is to help us distinguish the Middle (or Dark) Ages from the Enlightenment (or the Age of Reason). In the former era, knowing and acting were informed by recourse to sacred texts and the interpreters of these texts. In the latter era, these endeavors came to be founded on increasingly formalized processes of observation (theory-driven and replicable), abstract representations (models, theories, and ontologies), and empirical verification. In this classical formulation, scientists had privileged access to the natural world, a world that was objective or pre-existing. Employing an agreed upon methodology, these trained practioners described and explained the phenomena that they discovered, and this enabled them to predict and modify outcomes. Learning science To what extent do these principles reflect the understanding of science propounded by learning scientists? As we await a canonical text and codified terminology (e.g., a ‘handbook of learning science’), we will induce this understanding DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 3 through a survey of their practice. Because science is often defined, at its root, in terms of the scientific method, we look for this definition in the methods of the learning sciences. Learning scientists employ several methods of inquiry, most of which have been borrowed from other fields and adapted to educational interests. One method however, is emerging within, and is unique to, the learning sciences. It is referred to variously as design research (Collins, Joseph, & Bielaczyc, 2004; Kelly, 2004; Reeves, 2000; Wang & Reeves, 2004), design experiments (Brown, 1992; Collins, 1992; diSessa & Cobb, 2004), design based research (Barab, & Squire, 2004; Dede, 2004) or developmental research (van den Akker, 1999; Ritchie, 1996). Design based research (DBR)—the term we settled on for this article—and learning science are reflections of each other, we argue, or mutually constitutive in the way that ethnography is of cultural anthropology or conversation analysis is of ethnomethodology. As with science, it is difficult to locate a concise, consensual definition of DBR. Separately, authors attend either to its goals, its epistemological commitments, or its procedures. Where these discussions overlap, there are tensions. To move our discussion forward, we offer our general and somewhat awkward definition: DBR is a method of inquiry whose goal is to contribute equally to educational practice and learning theory through formative case studies of interventions in naturalistic settings. Formalization of the method began with publications in 1992 by Collins and Brown, and much of our analyses will focus on Brown’s prescient article. Brown had been trained as experimental psychologist in the 1960s and had engaged subsequently in influential educational research programs. Moving across her career from behavioral to cognitive concerns, her early research designs embodied the social sciences’ DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 4 interpretation of natural science: a) experimental and quasi-experimental designs, which assured internal and external validity, b) laboratory studies, which allowed control and manipulation of variables, c) formulation and testing of hypotheses deduced from theories, which allowed advancement on prior work, and d) reliable and valid data collection procedures analyzed statistically, which demonstrated the experimenter’s detachment from the pre-existing reality under investigation. Eventually, several problems gave rise to discontent with these strictures. First, across their attempts to conduct a social science, many researchers realized that their endeavors lacked many of the defining features of the scientific method. Brown (1992) acknowledged that, unlike the natural sciences, much of educational research was not progressive. For a short time and within a particular community, successive studies build on previous ones, Brown maintained. However, after brief interludes of ‘progress,’ new theoretical perspectives take over, accompanied by new questions, research designs, and measurement instruments. These shifts derail the progressive sequence. Similarly, Brown questioned the utility of a reductionist approach to educational inquiry, which is also central to the scientific method. Reflecting on her studies of educational practice, Brown painted a holistic, rather than reductionist, picture: “Classroom life is synergistic,” she declared: Aspects of it that are often treated independently, such as teacher training, curriculum selection, testing, and so forth actually form part of a systematic whole. Just as it is impossible to change one aspect of the system without creating perturbations in others, so too it is difficult to DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 5 study any one aspect independently from the whole operating system. (Brown, 1992, p. 143) Brown described further problems in imposing the methods of social science on educational concerns. In her attempts to enhance learning theory and practice, she found that the antiseptic and contrived environments of the laboratory were altering fundamentally the phenomena she wished to study. In addition, the principles of teaching and learning produced in these settings did not transfer to classrooms. Moreover, these sites of educational practice were rife with conditions anathema to the researcher’s devotion to rigour and objectivity. Using cognitivist research on memory as an illustration, Brown reported, “These were issues of theory, attempts to unravel mysteries of the memory system. The work had nothing to do with theories about how to make a better learner. The players had absolutely no educational relevance in mind” (p. 145). As a reflective practitioner with a genuine interest in the welfare of students and teachers, Brown—and subsequently many educational researchers—found themselves studying teaching and learning in ways that systematically violated the tenets of social science research (cf. Campbell & Stanley, 1963). As Brown recalled, “My training was that of a classic learning theorist prepared to work with subjects (rats, children, sophomores), in strictly controlled laboratory settings. Those methods are not readily transported to the research activities I currently oversee” (1992, p. 141). Contributors to the recent JLS issue on DBR continue to grapple with the moral, epistemological, and methodological issues that originally effected Brown over a decade ago. Design based researchers traverse the line dividing two distinct orientations toward research: post-positivism (eg., Cook & Campbell, 1979) and interpretivism (eg. DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 6 Lincoln & Guba, 1985). Post-positivism maintains the values and processes of science that we described previously, but recognizes that there will be some slippage in the ability to realize these ideals when one studies human, agentive phenomenon rather than natural phenomenon. Post-positivists admit that the judgment of the researcher plays a role in interpreting of the results of experiments, and they have ritualized methods for correcting this bias, subjectivity, or error (Malhotra, 1994). Interpretivists, on the other hand, argue that this same interpretation on the part of the researcher is not an incidental or undesirable process, but one that is both unavoidable as well as central and foundational. Any study of human behaviour, they argue, is the active interpretation of phenomena that are themselves intentional --consequently well beyond the realm of the unproblematically “objective.” The oscillation of practitioners of DBR between these two, very different positions is widely evident in their writing. In the JLS special issue, readers encounter characterizations of DBR as an interpretivist, constructivist endeavor, but they are quickly referred to footnotes that return them to post-positivistic touchstones. Barab and Squire (2004), for instance, offer the following description of DBR: DBR focuses on understanding the messiness of real-world practice, with context being a core part of the story and not an extraneous variable to be trivialized. Further DBR involves flexible design revision, multiple dependent variables, and capturing social interaction. In addition, participants are not subjects assigned to treatments but instead treated as co-participants in both the design and even the analysis. The focus is on DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 7 characterizing situations as opposed to controlling variables. (Barab & Squire, 2004, p. 5) But hastily, they direct readers to this accompanying footnote: It is important to note that this is not meant to deride the importance of traditional psychological methods . . .. Design-based researchers should be asking how their claims would benefit from more rigorous testing within laboratory-based contexts. (Barab & Squire, 2004, p. 5) Similar vacillations between programmatic declaration and countervailing qualification appear throughout the special issue and elsewhere in related studies and discussions. Such researchers put themselves in a double bind, a term invoking not only paradox, but schizophrenic inconsistency (Bateson, Jackson, Haley & Weakland, 1956): Every move they make toward a deeper understanding of local practices is a move away from reliable, valid measurement and generalizable results. Conversely, assertions of the generalizability, objectivity and scientific validity of their findings removes them from their origin in situated, local and authentic practice. In all but one article in the special issue (Dede, 2004), we sense a desire to retain scientific terminology and the esteem, the hope of certainty, and the pursuant funding that it entails while letting go of the scientific method and its epistemological, methodological, and procedural commitments. Critiques of Science by Philosophers and Historians of Science Forty-three years after Kant offered his critique, Auguste Compte extended the vision: “I believe that I shall succeed in having it recognized that there are laws as welldefined for the development of human species as for the fall of a stone” (Compte, 1974 DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 8 cited in Frankel & Wallen, 2000, p. 431). Two centuries after this proposal for a social science put forward by the self-titled Pope of Positivism, efforts to formulate the equivalent of the law of gravity for one area of human activity—teaching and learning— have been elusive. Prior to the pragmatic critiques of science offered by researchers such as Brown (1992) who were interested human activities, foundational objections were being posed by philosophers and historians of science, and later by sociologists. One of these critics, philosopher Karl Popper (1959, 1963), took issue with the assertion that empirical verification distinguished science from other modes of inquiry. He argued that logically, no number of supportive experimental outcomes could confirm a theory once and for all, and instead, proposed falsifiability as a more apt criterion for scientific “truth.” Neatly summing up the difference, Einstein purportedly remarked, “No amount of experimentation can prove me right, but a single experiment can prove me wrong.” As this principle was ratified, Feyerabend (1975), a student of Popper’s (1959, 1963), pointed out that few theories are consistent with all experimental tests. Again, Einstein colloquializes the issue for us: “If the facts don’t fit the theory; change the facts.” Verification and falsification were categorical distinctions between scientific and other types of inquiry. Their dismissal was consequential. Even more consequential however were the challenges raised by another of Popper’s (1959, 1963) successors, Thomas Kuhn (1996), who questioned the progressive nature of scientific knowledge and its fundamental independence from its objects of study. Kuhn argued that scientific knowledge is cumulative only in a mundane or even accidental sense. Significant developments are revolutionary, he demonstrated, not DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 9 evolutionary, and they reflect dramatic breaks that are incompatible with previous research programs. Kuhn’s (1996) analysis also presents a challenge for another central tenet of science, that the natural phenomena it investigates are pre-existing, having a life apart from scientists’ interest in them. Kuhn’s tack was to draw on a concept rooted in structural linguistics, paradigm. Kuhn employed the term to reveal the arbitrary, contextual, and consensual meaning that objects have for an interested community pursuing a common goal. He then characterized these paradigms as having the tendency to undergo a seismic “shift,” in which one consensual frame of reference replaces another, and an area of scientific inquiry undergoes a sudden—rather than progressive or cumulative—change. Learning Science Paradigms: Shift Happens A number of aspects of Popper’s and Kuhn’s understandings of scientific paradigms can be readily illustrated by a cursory examination of two prominent attempts to understand teaching and learning in scientific terms: behaviourism and cognitive science. The first of these, behaviourism, had as its explicit goal to make psychology—a discipline at the time associated with non-experimental introspective methods—into a “real” science. It proposed to do so by emphasizing empirically and experimentally verifiable evidence at the expense of any theories or impressions about the mind or mental states. In this sense, behaviourism can be seen as taking Popper’s insistence on falsifiability very literally and seriously: The only valid knowledge available to psychological researchers, as the name behaviourism itself suggests, comes from behaviour, and from the stimuli (positive or negative reinforcement). Claims about the DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 10 role of the mind, about thought, or about free will cannot not be falsified, and are therefore outside of the bounds of a scientific psychology. As a consequence, research questions, problems and possible answers that this paradigm led researchers to were about ways of most effectively shaping behaviour through conditioning and reinforcement. Educational research itself was understood in terms of the observation of persistent changes in behavior through conditioning. Teaching was conceptualized as the provision of rewards for the successive approximation of target behaviors, and learning came to be understood as an enduring behavioural change achieved through these processes. The influence of this powerful paradigm lives on in our understandings of the importance of “positive reinforcement” or “stimulating environments” in fostering learning. The ability of this paradigm to satisfy consensual pursuit of scientific psychology met its limit quite abruptly in its attempt to account for language learning. In the late 1950’s linguist Noam Chomsky argued effectively that the ability of children to learn the vocabularies and grammar of their native language without formal instruction could not be explained through the laborious repetition of stimulus and response. As an alternative, Chomsky posited the existence of inherent, generative mechanisms of the mind --a conjecture expanded to become the founding hypothesis of the shifting psychological paradigm (e.g. see Bechtel, Abrahamsen and Graham, 1998). This paradigm, cognitivism, posits that computational structures, mechanisms and processes in the mind can be known. They can be the subject of scientific investigation by being modeled through the use of computer hardware and software. Cognitivism, in other words, proceeds from “the conjecture that every aspect of learning or any other feature of DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 11 intelligence can in principle be so precisely described that a machine can be made to simulate it" (McCarthy, et al 1955). This powerful hypothesis served as the basis for new and interdisciplinary orientations in linguistics (structural), computer science (Artificial Intelligence), philosophy (of mind), and explicitly “cognitive” orientations in neuroscience and education. Together, these were known as the “cognitive sciences” -constituting what has been called a “cognitive paradigm” (e.g. De Mey, 1992). This paradigm, in clear ascendancy in educational research since the 1970’s, has its own way of configuring educational research and practice. Learning is seen as changes in the way information is processed, represented and structured in the mind, and teaching becomes the effective support of these computational mental operations. Research, in turn, is centred around the discovery of mechanisms and processes such as those identified by Chomsky, and is also focused on computational modeling of such constructs as a kind of “existence proof” for these ideas (Gardner, 1987, 40). Cognitive science has produced ideas such as long- and short-term memory, or the educational value of advanced organizers which remain with us today. Recently, however, the cognitivist paradigm has itself shown signs of “shift:” “post-cognitivist” and “anti-cognitivist” schools of research and clinical psychology (e.g. Potter, 2000) have emerged over the last two decades. Within education itself, constructivist and situated variations on this paradigm have gained popularity—variations which are based on sociological, ethnographic and anthropological assumptions that differ radically from the a-social, mechanistic orientation of cognitivism in its early stages (e.g. Greeno, 1998; Salomon, 1998; Pea, 1994). It is in this context that the “learning sciences” --as an eclectic amalgam of schools and approaches-- appear to be DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 12 gradually taking the place of the more monolithic scientific paradigm provided by cognitivism. Critiques of Science by Sociologists Although the recent emergence of the learning sciences can certainly be understood as the latest in a procession of paradigms to gain prominence in educational research, it can also be understood in slightly different terms. These terms are also offered by the philosophy and sociology of science; specifically by more recent developments in the analysis of science as an everyday affair engaged in by people working in specific socio-historical contexts Whereas philosophers and historians of science such as Popper (1959, 1963), and Feyerabend (1975) and others (eg. Quine, 1951; Lakatos, 1970, 1976) dealt with Science as an abstract concept, Kuhn’s work precipitated an analysis of science specifically as sets of quotidian, situated and valueladen practices and contexts. This move was advanced by sociologists for whom the contingent nature of scientific procedures and the interpretive character of scientific facts were obvious. Latour (1979, 1987, 1988, 1992, 1999, 2005) for instance, employed ethnographic methods to study scientists at work. During prolonged engagements in the laboratories of primatologists and neuroendocrinologists, he witnessed an approach to inquiry that was very different from the disinterested, logical, and methodical reproduction of nature still dominant in orthodox understandings of the scientific endeavour. Like Feyerabend (1975) (and Lakatos, 1970, 1976), he dismissed the notion that theories stand and fall on the outcome of a single experiment. Rarely does an experiment provide anything more DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 13 than inconclusive data, he observed. He was equally unconvinced that the acceptance or rejection of scientific theories are decided entirely on evidence or reason. Others, such as Knorr-Cetina (1981, 1999), Gilbert and Mulkay (1990), and Woolgar (1988) supported Latour’s interpretations with similar types of studies. They argued that the objects of scientific study are socially constructed (to use a term now prominent in a number of educational and sociological research contexts) in the lab, and have no existence outside of the instruments that measure them and the minds that interpret them. By the latter half of the 20th century, any idealized notions of science and the scientific method as unquestionably privileged or impartial were in a troubled state. A picture of the natural sciences as not always, not only, or simply not progressive, objective, and explicitly logical prompted reflection among those interested in understanding human action and learning. This group, as Brown (1992) describes so well, were making major epistemological and pragmatic sacrifices in order to adhere to scientific principles, but these principles seemed more and more illusory. Lageman (2000) offers one possible rationale for this debilitative commitment. She demonstrates that the commitment to validity, objectivity and other trappings of natural science is a longstanding attempt by educational researchers to gain respectability and legitimacy. Flyvbjerg (2003), unfortunately, is pessimistic about this ever materializing, and he grounds his pessimism in a recounting of the recent science wars. He reminds readers of physicist Alan Sokal’s successful attempt to have a bogus article peer-reviewed and published in a leading social science journal. Of the many issues raised by the hoax, Flyvberg focuses on how it revealed the disdainful and dismissive DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 14 attitudes which many ‘hard’ scientists have for their ‘soft’ kin. He quotes from a Harvard biologist who cautions, “In pretending to a kind of knowledge that it cannot achieve, social science can only engender the scorn of natural scientists” (Lewonton, 1995, p. 28, cited by Flyvberg, 2003, p. 1). A further explanation for educational researchers’ detrimental commitment to the scientific method is found in a tangible correlate of esteem and respect: funding. In 2003, Burkhardt and Schoenfeld compared research funding in fields such as science, engineering, and electronics—5%-15% of their budgets—with funding for educational research—less than 0.01% of their budgets. Commenting on these figures, they note wryly that this is considerably less than Pfifer spends on R&D in its pet food division. Sroufe (1997) makes the connection between the perceived legitimacy of educational research and funding by quoting from a section of the 1997 Presidents’ Committee of Advisors on Science and Technology: “Education research is applied and anecdotal and permits gleaning to support one’s perspective” (President’s Committee of Advisors on Science and Technology [PCAST], 1997, p. 102; cited by Sroufe, 1997, p. 26). Therefore, as Sroufe reports incredulously, PCAST suggested that an outside committee, composed of unemployed graduates from science, math, and engineering programs, be enlisted to conduct educational research. Nonetheless, it is difficult to accept the argument that educational research needs to be more scientific if it is to receive more funding in our current epoch. To do so, we have to ignore the fact the a growing number of American’s do not believe in Darwin’s theory of evolution through natural selection (Orr, 2005), and that the Bush Administration, currently the ultimate arbiter of this funding, is regularly characterized as DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 15 “distorting science,” “stacking the deck against science” (Philipkoski, 2004a, 2004b), “misusing science,” “suppress scientific analyses” (Union of Concerned Scientists, 2004, 2005) and so on. A final rationale for the devotion to the scientific method is the hope nestled within science’s superordinate term positivism, which Toulmin (1990) characterizes as the quest for certainty. That hope, expressed by Kant (1781) in the introduction to our article, and later by Compte (1974, cited in Frankel & Wallen, 2000, p. 431), found its way into education in Royce’s (1891) contribution to the inaugural edition of the journal Educational Review. His article was titled Is There a Science of Education, and Lageman (2002) suggests that the answer he offered was something like, “no, but there should be”. Exactly 100 years later, the JLS began in the same manner. In its inaugural issue, the editor presents a list of problems with education, some dubious solutions, and writes: We simply do not have sufficiently concise theories of learning to be able to tailor curricula to the natural way that kids learn. Our best teachers follow their intuitions and provide wonderful opportunities for our kids, but . . . something more concrete than intuition is necessary. . . A major goal of the journal is to foster new ways of thinking about learning and teaching that will allow cognitive science disciplines to have an impact on the practice of education. We are interested in publishing articles that have the potential to make real world contributions (Kolodner, 1991, p. 4-6) Fourteen years later, this goal of convincingly uniting a science of education with its everyday application remains elusive. As an example, the upcoming International DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 16 Conference of the Learning Sciences (ISLS), subtitled “Making a Difference,” informs attendees: While learning scientists can present rich accounts of learning in complex contexts, convincing policy makers, teachers, and other researchers of the theoretical and practical value of our work is not a straightforward process. We must show impact at the local level while at the same time, work to have claims of more global significance. In other words, we must make clear that the learning sciences make a difference (¶ 3-4). The promise of a natural science of education, whose findings and hypotheses would enable “real world contributions” and “make a difference” in everyday practice apparently remains irresistible. However, clear and consistent evidence for such a science remains doubtful and unacknowledged, and the (hopefully transitory) antics of the Bush administration are not the only example. Miller (1999) provides examples of conclusions developed from lengthy, well-funded research programs that are consistently ignored or contravened by practice. The head of the Office of Educational Research and Improvement (OERI) enthusiastically described the series of What Work’s pamphlets produced by OERI in the late 80s, which synthesized robust research findings and presented them in an accessible way to practitioners. However, he lamented that, despite distributing over half a million copies, few practitioners had put them to use, or worse still, had even heard of them (Kaestle, 1993). Our experiences have been similar. A couple years ago one of us successfully bid on a government contract to conduct an evaluation of the use of Internet Protocol video conferencing in a few school districts. Briefly, our findings were no more enthusiastic than those presented by Fabos and Young DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 17 (1999) in their substantive and highly critical review of similar applications, and we cautioned the government about expanding the program. The day after we submitted our interim report, the government announced with fanfare six million dollars of funding to ensure that every school district in the province would have a video conferencing program (Alberta Government, 2004). We doubt there are seasoned program evaluators who have not had similar experiences. Experienced evaluators and researchers do not share the naïve belief that information, collected in a disinterested manner, is used objectively to make rational decisions. More often, we suggest, information is often collected selectively to legitimize decisions that have already been made. Among a broad range of stakeholders in the educational process, there is a consensus: Educational researchers, for the most part, have not been successful at emulating the processes, let alone outcomes, of natural scientists. Some, especially a growing community called learning scientists, argue that we should strive harder. If we do so, we will be able to develop robust theories and improve educational practice. We will gain legitimacy, and with it, funding. In this article, we have tried to demonstrate this argument is untenable, and that the same conditions that prompt the argument can be interpreted in different ways. In the final sections, we describe some alternatives including interpretive and phronetic (ie., socially responsible) educational research and development. What Might We Do Instead? Many learning scientists’ descriptions of DBR may suggest a gradual if not unequivocal turn toward interpretivist approaches to educational inquiry (eg., Brown, 1992; Barab and Squire, 2004). If this is also a turn away from post-positive DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 18 commitments --which are in any case incommensurable with interpretivism-- then it may also be seen as a most propitious shift of paradigms. As such, it may point to a possible way of reconstituting educational research in a different way. This would be a way of understanding the study and improvement of learning and learning conditions not as a “science” that would deny the reality of its own social construction, but that would be explicitly aware of the sociological and other conditions that inform it. This research would leverage this awareness, moreover, to its own advantage. It would utilize ways of understanding the constructed, debatable and interpretable nature of knowledge as a means of investigating its own subject matter. Such an approach would be associated with a number of methodologies and schools of thought. However, they all share the same underlying assumptions: That human phenomena, such as language, action and learning cannot be sufficiently understood as the outcome of rule-bound processes that can be predicted and controlled through research. These phenomena are instead understood as being in the realm of meaning and interpretation, rather than being subject to any ostensibly factual or scientific certainty. As such, human action, language and learning would be seen as necessarily occurring within a context --culture, society, institutions, history, groups-from which it cannot be separated. The nature of this context, moreover, is such that it can never be exhaustively articulated, modeled or even understood. As a further result of this fact, research cannot be understood as occurring at an objective remove from its object or its subject matter. The observation and manipulation of the researcher are themselves interpretable acts occurring in the context of the interpretable dimensions of culture, history, and other domains of human meaning and action. Examples of this kind DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 19 of research are provided by hermeneutic and post-cognitive forms of psychology (e.g. Martin and Sugarman, 2001; Potter, 2000), phenomenology and ethnomethodology (e.g. Dourish, 2001), and critical, historical, and genealogical methods (e.g. Holzkamp, 1992). A Different Take on DBR: Phronetic research Despite their mutually exclusive character, the process of relinquishing the postpositivistic elements of DBR while maintaining its interpretivist ones is not easy. Together, they can be seen as providing a sympathetic balance that would allow researchers to understand local practices while contributing to generalizable learning theories. This harmonious intersection of goals was presented persuasively in Stokes’ (1997) book Pasteur’s Quadrant. The eponymous quadrant refers to one cell of a two-bytwo matrix in which the goals of pure research are fused with the goals of applied research. The matrix has been so influential in the learning sciences that it requires little explanation (eg., National Academy Press, 2000; Reeves, 2000; Schoenfeld, 1999). However, this construction is deficient in an important way. The division of knowledge-seeking goals into two types originates with Aristotle (384/322 BC). He proposed that some of our efforts are directed toward episteme, pure research, or knowledge for knowledge’s sake. Other efforts, Aristotle suggested, are directed toward techne, applied research, the type associated with a Thomas Edison, rather than an Einstein or Bohr. However, Stokes’ and other differentiations between pure and applied science disregard a critical third category of knowledge proposed by Aristotle: phronesis. Aristotle defined this type of knowledge as “ a true state, reasoned, and capable of action with regard to things that are good or bad for man” (cited in Flyvberg, 2003, p. 2). The goal of a phronesis, as Flyvberg explains “is to help restore DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 20 social science to its classical position as a practical, intellectual activity aimed at clarifying the problems, risks, and possibilities we face as humans and societies, and at contributing to social and political praxis” (p. 4). These two alternatives—a wholly interpretivist and a phronetic approach to research—are already incipient, we think, in minor shifts from dominant orientations in learning science. Such approaches may certainly appear “unscientific” when compared to some of the methodological and other strictures that have been associated with the natural sciences and their methodology. However, this may simply be due to a very narrow understanding of science, not inherent to the pursuit itself, but reinforced by the way the term is used in many English-language contexts. In other linguistic contexts, the terms “science” and “scientific” are used to designate the broadly interpretive critical, hermeneutic and discursive methods enumerated above --and other possible approaches as well. These are often referred to as the Human Sciences. Such a designation would be appropriate to the kind of self-aware, consciously interpretive inquiry that is informed by 20th century theories of science --rather than one that harks back to the time of Kant and Compte. DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 21 References Aristotle, (384/322BC). Nichomachean ethics. (J. Thompson Trans.). London: Penguin. Barab, S., & Squire, K. (2004). Design-based research: Putting a stake in the ground. Journal of the Learning Sciences,13(1), 1-14. Alberta Government (2004). Alberta invests $6 million in provincewide videoconferencing initiative. Retrieved, December 13, 2005 from http://www.education.gov.ab.ca/news/2005/February/nr-VideoConferencing.asp Bechtel,W., Abrahamsen, A., and Graham, G. (1998). Part 1: The life of cognitive science. In Bechtel, W. (Ed.), A Companion to Cognitive Science (pp. 6-24). London: Blackwell Publishers. Brown, A. (1997). Transforming into communities of thinking and learning about serious matters. American Psychologist, 52(4), 399-414. Brown, A. (1992). Design experiments: Theoretical and methodological challenges in creating complex interventions. The Journal of the Learning Sciences, 2(É), 141-158. Burkhardt, H., & Schoenfeld, A. (2003). Improving educational research: Toward a more useful, more influential, and better funded enterprise. Educational Researcher, 32(9), 3-12. Campbell, D., & Stanley, J. (1963). Experimental and quasi-experimental designs for research. Chicago: Rand-McNally. Collins, A. (1992). Toward a design science of education. In E. Scanlon & T. O’Shea (Eds.) New directions in educational technology. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 22 Collins, Joseph, D., Bielacyzc, K. (2004). Design research: Theoretical and methodological issues. Journal of the Learning Sciences,13(1), 15-42. Cook, T. & Cambell, D. (1979). Quasi-experimentation: Design and analysis issues for field settings. Chicago: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1979. De Mey, M. (1992). The cognitive paradigm (4th ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Dede, C. (2004). If design-based research is the answer, what is the question? A commentary on Collins, Joseph, and Bielaczyc; diSessa and Cobb; and Fishman, Marx, Blumenthal, Krajcik, and Soloway in the JLS special issue on design-based research. Journal of the Learning Sciences,13(1),105-114. diSessa, A., & Cobb, P. (2004). Ontological innovation and the role of theory in design experiments. Journal of the Learning Sciences,13(1), 77-103. Fabos, B., & Young, M. (1999). Telecommunication in the classroom: Rhetoric versus reality. Review of Educational Research, 69(3), 217-259. Frankel, J., & Wallen, N. (2000). How to design and evaluate research in education. Boston: McGraw-Hill. Flyvberg, B. (2003). Making social science matter: Why social inquiry fails and how it can succeed again. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gardner, H. (1987). The mind's new science: A history of the cognitive revolution. New York: Basic Books, Inc. Greeno, J. G. (1998) The situativity of knowing, learning, and research. American Psychologist, 53(1), 5-26. DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 23 Holzkamp, K. (1992). On doing psychology critically. Theory and Psychology, 2, 193-204. Kaestle, C. (1993). The awful reputation of educational research. Educational Researcher, 22(1), 23-31. Kant, I. (1950). Critique of pure reason (N. K. Smith Trans). London: MacMillan (Original work published 1781). Kelly, A. (2004). Design research in education: yes, but is it methodological? Journal of the Learning Sciences, 13(1), 115-128. Kelly, A. (2003). Research as design. Educational Researcher 32(1), 3-5. Kolodner, J. (1991). The Journal of the Learning Sciences: Effecting changes in education. Journal of the Learning Sciences, 1(1), 1-6. Kuhn, T. (1996). The structure of scientific revolutions (3rd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lagemann, E. (2000). An elusive science: The troubling history of educational research. London: University of Chicago Press. Latour, B. (2005). Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network theory. London: Oxford University Press. Latour, B. (1999). Pandora's hope: essays on the reality of science studies. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Latour, B. (1993). We have never been modern. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 24 Latour, B. (1992). Where are the missing masses? The sociology of a few mundane artifacts. In W. Bijker & J. Law (Eds.) Shaping technology, building society: Studies in sociotechnical change. Cambridge: MIT Press. Latour, B. (1988). The pasteurization of France. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Latour, B. (1987). Science in action: How to follow scientists and engineers through society. Boston: Harvard University Press. Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1979). Laboratory life: the social construction of scientific facts. Los Angeles: Sage. Lewonton, R. (1995, April 20). Sex, lies, and social science. In The New York Review of Books 42(7). Retrieved, December 23, 2005 from http://www.nybooks.com/articles/ article_id=1923 Lincoln, Y., & Guba, E. (1985). Naturalistic inquiry. New York: Sage Publications. Malhotra, Y. (1994). Role Of science in knowledge creation: A philosophy of science perspective. Retrieved December 23, 2005, from the Brint Institute’s Web site: http://www.kmbook.com/science.htm Martin, J., and Sugarman, J. (2001). Interpreting human kinds: Beginnings of a hermeneutic psychology. Theory and Psychology, 11, 193-207. Miller, D. (1999, August 8)). The black hole of education research. Chronicle of Higher Education, 45(48), 17. National Academy Press (2000) How people learn. Bridging research and practice. Boston: National Academy Press. DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 25 Orr, A. (2005), May 23). Devolution: Why intelligent design isn’t. The New Yorker. Retreived, December 13, 2005 from http://www.newyorker.com/fact/content/articles/050530fa_fact Pea, R. D. (1994). Seeing what we build together: Distributed multimedia learning environments for transformative communications. Journal of the Learning Sciences, 3(3), 283-298. Philipcoski, K. (2004a, February 18). Scientists: Bush distorts science. Wired Magazine. Retrieved from http://www.wired.com/news/medtech/0,1286,62339,00.html Philipcoski, K. (2004b, February 3). Stacking the deck against science. Wired Magazine. Retrieved from http://www.wired.com/news/medtech/0,1286,62119,00.html Potter, J. (2000). Post-cognitive psychology. Theory & Psychology. 10 (1) 31-37. Presidents’ Committee of Advisors on Science and Technology. (1995). Report to the President on the effective use of technology to strengthen K-12 education in the United States. Washington DC: Author. Reeves, T. (April, 2000). Enhancing the worth of instructional technology research through design experiments and other developmental research strategies. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Educational Research Association, (New Orleans, USA). Reeves, T. (1999). A Research Agenda for Interactive Learning in the New Millennium. In Proceedings of World Conference on Educational Multimedia, Hypermedia and Telecommunications 1999 (pp. 15-20). Chesapeake, VA: AACE. DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 26 Ritchie, R., & Nelson, W. (1996). Developmental research. In D. Jonassen (Ed.) Handbook of research for educational communications and technology (pp. 1213-1245). New York: MacMillan. Salomon, G. (1998) (Ed.). Distributed cognitions. Psychological and educational considerations. NY: Cambridge University Press. Sawyer, K. (2006). The Cambridge handbook of the learning sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Schoenfeld, A. (1999) Looking toward the 21st century: Challenges of educational theory and practice. Educational Researcher, 28(7), 4-14. Seventh International Conference of the Learning Sciences (2006). Conference overview. Retrieved, December 12, 2005, from http://www.isls.org/icls2006/overview.html Stokes, D. (1997). Pasteur’s quadrant. Basic science and technological innovation. Toronto: Brookings Institution Press. Sroufe, G. (1997). Improving the “awful reputation” of educational research. Educational Research, 26(7), 26-28. Toulmin, S (1990). Cosmopolis: The hidden agenda of modernity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Union of Concerned Scientists (2005). Scientific Integrity in the News. Retrieved, December 13, 2005 from http://www.ucsusa.org/scientific_integrity/interference/scientific-integrity-in-thenews.html DRAFT: LEARNING SCIENCE: THE VERY IDEA 27 Union of Concerned Scientist (2004). Scientific Integrity in Policy Making Investigation of the Bush administration's abuse of science Available: http://www.ucsusa.org/news/press_release/preeminent-scientists-protest-bushadministrations-misuse-of-science.html van den Akker, J. (1999). Principles and methods of developmental research. In J. van den Akker, N. Nieveen, R. Branch, K. Gustafson, & T. Plomp (Eds.) Design methodology and developmental research in education and training (pp. 1-14). Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Wang, F., & Reeves, T. (2003). A critical review on teachers and technology. In Proceedings of World Conference on E-Learning in Corporate, Government, Healthcare, and Higher Education 2003 (pp. 1809-1812). Norfolk, VA: AACE. Woolgar, S. (1988). Science: The very idea. London: Routledge.