Download FIRst-PeRson MoRALIty AnD tHe RoLe oF ConsCIenCe

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Philosophy of artificial intelligence wikipedia , lookup

Enactivism wikipedia , lookup

Conscience wikipedia , lookup

Other (philosophy) wikipedia , lookup

Direct and indirect realism wikipedia , lookup

Internalism and externalism wikipedia , lookup

Moral psychology wikipedia , lookup

Embodied cognitive science wikipedia , lookup

Ethics of artificial intelligence wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Massimo Reichlin
Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
[email protected]
First-Person Morality and
the Role of Conscience
abstract
I build on Baker’s insight concerning the relationship between having a robust firstperson perspective and being a moral agent in order to show the defects of some recent
projects of naturalisation of morality. I argue that morality depends upon having
conscience, and is an inherently first-personal experience. I then move on to criticise
Baker’s too neat distinction between a rudimentary and a robust first-person perspective,
and suggest that Baker excessively downplays the role of embodiment in her account of
what it is for the same first-person perspective to be instantiated across time.
keywords
First-person perspective, conscience, embodiment, natural kind
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
1.
In Naturalism and the First-Person Perspective (2013) Lynne Baker convincingly
argues that the first-person perspective (FPP) is an irreducible element of a
complete ontology, and one that cannot be accounted for in terms of neural
processes. I agree with this important conclusion, and with the idea that the
possession of a FPP accounts for many relevant aspects that distinguish the
lives of persons and make them peculiarly valuable and important.
In the first part of this article, building on Baker’s insight, I will stress
the peculiar link existing between moral experience and the FPP: I will
suggest that we cannot adequately explain morality unless we acknowledge
the peculiarity of the FPP. In the second part, focusing on human infants’
early capacities for social relations, I will suggest that Baker excessively
downplays the role of embodiment in her characterisation of the FPP, and
that her neat distinction between the rudimentary and the robust FPP
might be revised. I will conclude suggesting that Baker’s theory suffers
from a difficulty in the definition of what counts as an instantiation of the
same FPP across time, and that this depends on her view of the relationship
between persons and their bodies.
2.
One central contention in chapter 9 of Naturalism and the First-Person
Perspective is that “nothing can be a moral agent without a robust firstperson perspective. Since only persons can have robust first-person
perspectives, only persons can be rational or moral agents” (Baker 2013, pp.
192-193). This point, I think, is well taken. At the same time, it runs against
some recent views coming from empirical studies of moral judgment.
In these studies, it is suggested that morality is a much less complex
phenomenon than we usually think; particularly, that moral judgment
is inherently based on our emotions (Dalgleish 2004), and that all beings
showing some form of empathy or possessing a system of unreflective,
automatic emotions (the so called system 1) can roughly be considered
moral agents. Research on the neuroscientific bases of moral judgments,
as well as on the psychological and neuroscientific dimensions of empathy
(Moll, de Oliveira-Souza, Zahn & Grafman 2008), have contributed much to
these developments, and to the considerable revival of Humean views on
morality (Nichols 2004 and Prinz 2007). According to these views, moral
judgments are nothing more than gut feelings, or emotional, automatic
reactions mediated by our ‘sentimental’ brain (Haidt 2001 and 2007);
135
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
alternatively, they can be reconstructed as the outcome of a double level of
processing by different areas of our brain, that is, the automatic reactions
by system 1, as corrected and integrated by the reflective, computational
processes of system 2 (Greene 2008 and 2009).
While it would be wrong to neglect the importance of the neuroscientific
findings for an adequate understanding of morals, it must be stressed that
reconstructions such as these account in a very partial way for the whole of
moral experience. The lesson to be learned, no doubt, is that morality has its
roots in the deep structures of our ‘sentimental’ brain; however, the recent
focus on emotive, automatic processes, leaves much out of consideration.
The concept of morality with which these studies are working is in fact
centred on swift judgments in very specific, often dramatic and sometimes
bizarre quandary situations, such as those dealing with ‘trolley cases’,
crying babies and the like (Greene, Sommerville, Nystrom, Darley & Cohen
2001). But this focus fails to account for the perhaps most important part of
morality, i.e. the one that has to do with the development of more general
patterns of reaction and disposition to act, patterns which crucially involve
an idea of oneself. To put the point somehow more bluntly: an account of
moral experience centring exclusively on the generation of outputs, in the
form of third-person judgments on the rightness or wrongness of some
considered course of action, misses most of what morality is all about.
And, following Baker’s point, I would like to say that most of what such an
account misses has to do with the FPP.
The basic fact about the moral point of view, I would say, is that it is not
third-personal, or at least, that it cannot be wholly accounted for in thirdpersonal terms; it is an essential element in moral evaluation that rightness
and wrongness cannot be defined from a spectator’s viewpoint on the facts
of the world (not even on ‘moral’, or ‘axiological’ facts there to be valued),
but involve the adoption of a FPP. When I ask myself what is it right to do, I
am not contemplating this question from an external viewpoint, I am not
asking what would be the best thing to do ‘from the point of view of the
Universe’, as it were: what I am actually asking is what I should do, what
are the best reasons on which I may act, and therefore on which I ought
to act. Of course, my gut feelings, or emotional automatic reactions, may
mark the beginnings of a moral response, and may suggest the adoption of
an attitude: what is crucial, however, and distinctive of an authentic moral
judgment, is the fact that I decide to endorse that reaction. I stop for a while,
reflecting on what are my best reasons to act on in the circumstances, and
end up with the decision that that reaction is the most appropriate way to
face the situation. This decision involves the consideration of my practical
136
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
identity as a moral subject, that is, the consideration of my personal values,
commitments and ideas of the good life (Reichlin 2014).
Baker aptly suggests that the possession of a rudimentary FPP does not
enable the adoption of this specifically normative perspective, since moral
reasons are always reasons bearing on the relationship between myself
and others: therefore, in order to make moral judgments, I must have some
image of myself as myself, and of myself in the web of my relationships with
others. To eliminate or reduce the FPP, therefore, is also to reduce moral
decision-making to the image of an evolutionary mechanism wired into our
brains in order to produce useful behavioural outputs, as judged from the
evolutionary viewpoint of the reproductive fitness of the individual and
of the social group. Alternatively, it is to reduce it to the consequentialist
image of a tool for correcting our biased automatic reactions with a view
to maximising utility, thanks to our reflective, computational inputs
from system 2. I am not suggesting that these processes play no part in
the complex phenomena of our moral experience: rather, that they do not
capture the whole of it, nor its main core.
A robust FPP is needed to account for a plausible view of morality. Living a
moral life primarily has to do with constructing one’s character or moral
personality, that is, with developing habits and dispositions to feel, judge
and choose according to an ideal image of oneself and an ideal of a good
life. Morality, therefore, is first-personal in its essence: it does not have
to do only (nor, I would say, mainly) with producing consequences (even
though, of course, consequences too matter in a moral decision); its main
core concerns establishing relationships with other people, and adopting
principles to shape our treating one another with respect. Morality has
to do with the contribution that I* – a symbol that Baker uses to refer to
our capacity to think of ourselves as ourselves – give to the state of the
world, through my choosing the kind of person that I* want to be, in my
relationship with others. As Thomas Nagel famously put it, morality cannot
be entirely accounted for in terms of agent-neutral reasons, that is, of
reasons that are valid and applicable whoever is the agent (Nagel 1986);
there is a fundamental aspect of morality in which agent-relative reasons
are involved, that is, moral rightness and wrongness also depend on the
fact that it is me who will be doing x, or producing consequence y. And the
fact that I will be doing the action bears on my self-image, it is mirrored in
it and will accompany my self-conception from this moment onwards. If
the ‘naturalisation’ of morality is the project of translating this basic firstperson experience of the commitment to moral principles and to an idea of
the good life in a wholly third-personal language, then it means to miss the
137
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
main point of morality, or to explain it away.
The Western philosophical and theological tradition has an apt word to
capture this specifically first-personal character of moral experience: this
word is ‘conscience’. Conscience is perhaps no longer a fashionable word in
philosophical language; nonetheless, we can say that morality depends on
having conscience, in the precise sense of having a first-personal view on
our agency and relationship with others. The etymology of the word tells
us this very clearly, for conscientia refers to a peculiar kind of knowledge.
It is knowledge (scientia) of something that is not entirely separated from
the knower, since it is knowledge that, at the same time, involves an idea of
oneself (cum-scire): knowledge that binds the knower, that directly involves
the one who has it. Conscience, therefore, is not equivalent to moral sense,
if this is conceived in the standard Humean meaning, according to which
all that there is to morality is feeling some pleasurable or unpleasurable
sentiments with reference to actions and characters. Conscience, in fact,
has to do not with simple ‘moral perceptions’, but with the progressive
structuring of one’s framework of attitudes and patterns of reaction, in
the light of our experience of interhuman relationships and aided by the
internalisation of other people’s looks and judgments on ourselves.
Friedrich Nietzsche once famously wrote that conscience depends on
authority and therefore “it is not God’s voice in man’s breast, rather the
voice of some men in man” (Nietzsche 1996, II, 2, § 52). He was partly right,
because the authority of conscience depends in part on internalising others’
reactions and judgments, so that their voice resonates in us and their gaze
on us shapes the way in which we look to ourselves. But of course, he was
also partly wrong, because our conscience is the form of our practical
identity, that is, of that conception of virtue and of the good life that we
define for ourselves and we aim to instantiate in our choices and actions.
In Baker’s terms, we can say that conscience is also a product of our FPP.
This is therefore my conclusion for this first section: there is a relationship
between having conscience and having the capacity to conceive of oneself as
oneself; the two are generated in a common process and mutually support
each other.
3.
I have suggested that there is an important and reciprocal relationship
between conscience and the robust FPP, and that this is why some recent
projects of naturalisation fail to grasp what really is at stake in morality.
I now want to show that this is no reason to forget the close relationship
pointed out by empirical research between the emotional experience of
human relationships and morality; moreover, that we should also take into
138
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
account the role played by very early experiences of sociality in establishing
both conscience and the robust FPP.
One important conclusion of contemporary studies in developmental
psychology is that infants show very early signs of the distinction between
themselves and the others, and very rapidly set out for the development
of a sense of agency. For example, infants in the first hours of their life
already distinguish their body from others’, as shown by their reacting
more vivaciously to the experimenter’s stimulation of their cheek, than to a
similar self-stimulation (Rochat & Hespos 1997). An analogous observation
is provided by the fact that four-month old babies try to reach for objects
that are being shown to them only within the sphere of their grasp, and
show much hesitation when the object’s distance is such that the attempt
would endanger their bodily equilibrium. This body-scheme, of course, is
subpersonal, but it is nonetheless a very early sign of the beginnings of the
consciousness of oneself.
Moreover, infants also show very early signs of agency, as evidenced for
example by experiments in which two-month old babies modulate their
way of sucking a ‘musical’ dummy, according to the different sounds that
it produces (Rochat & Striano 2000). These findings suggest that there is
a very early experience of one’s body that is a constitutive element in the
concept of oneself as a distinct and original source of action. Moreover, it is
well known, as mentioned by Baker herself, that humans possess a unique
capacity for social interaction, cooperation and mind-reading (Tomasello
1995 and 2009), as it is shown, for example, by their very early capacity
to imitate and to distinguish facial emotions. We can also add that, in a
few months from birth, infants start to develop attitudes of reaction to
other’s actions that are clear forerunners of social and moral behaviour. For
example, two-month old babies react negatively to the sudden interruption
of an interaction by an adult, as if there was a sort of ‘breach’ of an implicit
rule (Rochat 2001), and seven-month old babies differentiate their social
expectations according to the fact that they are interacting with some
privileged person, or with an unknown one (Layton & Rochat 2007).
The lesson that can be drawn from these data is that infants learn to
identify themselves through the relationships with others: it is through the
experience of the others’ gaze, and the very implicit realisation of being the
object of others’ representation and care that the sense of oneself emerges.
Self-consciousness, and the future development of the capacity for moral
agency are rooted in our very early, and peculiarly human, interest for
reputation, that is, for the way in which others see us. We can say that the
emergence of the self is tied to the social interactions of the human infant
139
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
with other people: in fact, there is a sort of co-emergence of the ideas of the
self and of the others.
Now Baker is of course aware of these data. Her strategy to mark the
peculiarity of persons, as distinguished from human biological organisms,
is to establish a distinction between a rudimentary and a robust FPP: human
babies are provided with a rudimentary FPP, but what makes us unique
and places us above the animal kingdom is the possession of a robust FPP,
which does not emerge until the kid possesses language and the capacity for
I-thoughts. This distinction is fairly persuasive, but I suggest that it should
not be taken as marking a neat boundary. In fact, since the acquisition of
a robust FPP is the acquisition of a sense of oneself as oneself, the infants’
early capacities to distinguish themselves from others, and to interact
with them in significantly complex ways, can be considered as early steps
on the way to the development of a robust FPP. As a matter of fact, it would
be implausible to suggest that the robust FPP ‘magically’ emerges with the
appearance of language; it is much more plausible to say that the sense of
the self is largely acquired through very early experiences of oneself as
oneself in a non-linguistic dimension, and that the acquisition of language
completes and perfects the process, enabling a much wider experience
of one’s agency and relationships with others. To put it bluntly: it seems
possible to have a very robust sense of oneself without having developed
those complex verbal capacities that eventually enable the individual to
express one’s self-awareness.
This, of course, is not meant to suggest the existence of any kind of protomoral behaviour in very young infants; as already noted, I accept Baker’s
view that only individuals with a robust FPP can be full-blown moral agents.
However, the preceding observations show that the early social interactions,
essentially mediated by the experience of a lived body and characterised
by an emotional load, are vital elements in the formation of a robust FPP,
which – as we saw – is intertwined with the generation of conscience
and moral agency: as Philippe Rochat put it, the process through which
children attract the gaze of others, while independently exploring their
environment, is a seminal element that leads them to become increasingly
self-conscious, and represents “the ontogenetic roots of the human moral
sense” (Rochat 2012, p. 390). It can be added that this progressively emerging
conception of oneself as oneself is mediated by some specifically moral
behaviour, that is, by the adults’ behaviour of caring for the infant. In this
sense, we can say that the child acquires the conception of herself partly by
learning to be the object of a loving relationship for her mother and other
privileged persons. The co-emergence of the sense of oneself and of the
140
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
sense of others is mediated by experiences of care and affection, so that we
may say that the primordia of conscience – i.e. the implicit notion of being in
an ethical relationship with others, and of laying claims to others’ attention
– are one basic factor in the emergence of a robust FPP.
Baker rightly insists on the fact that it is the robust FPP that makes morality
possible: but it is also clear that some causal work goes in the opposite
direction. Though the definitive acquisition of a robust FPP is the result
of acquiring language, the early experiences of one’s lived body and of
being thrown from the start into the basic forms of ethical relationship
contributes much to that result. As noted by Baker, the robust FPP implies
acquiring the empirical concepts expressed by a public language, and this
implies “to have social and linguistic relations” (Baker 2013, p. 139). What I
want to stress is that social and linguistic relations of a specifically ethical
kind are present in early infancy, and help the construction of the child’s
sense of oneself as oneself long before the child acquires the active use of
language. This may suggest that the distinction between rudimentary and
robust FPP should not be overemphasised, and the continuity between the
two should be given proper recognition.
4.
I have argued that there are reasons to doubt that the acquisition of
cognitive abilities (i.e., the use of a syntactically complex language) is the
only means through which a robust FPP becomes effective, for the prelinguistic, lived experience of embodiment in a biological organism, with
the emotional experiences that this allows, is a relevant step towards
the establishment of a robust FPP. Before the acquisition of the concept of
oneself, the fact of being situated in a bodily condition, of experiencing
one’s body as a causal factor in effecting changes in the world of things and
persons, and of experiencing a complex set of perceptions and emotional
reactions associated to this embodied situation, are vital contributions
to reaching a sense of oneself, which in turn is a major contribution to the
establishment of a robust FPP. In other words, I have argued for a softening
of the distinction between the rudimentary and the robust FPP. Now, I
wish to give a look at the consequences of these observations for Baker’s
definition of the boundaries of personhood.
Baker does not assume that the possession of a robust FPP, with the
associated linguistic competence, is a necessary condition of personhood,
and of the full moral status that is proper to persons: she subscribes to the
view that human children, also at an age at which they certainly lack a
robust FPP, are already persons. The reason she gives for this view is that
human infants have a rudimentary FPP essentially: and the reason why they
141
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
have it essentially is that they are “of a kind that develops robust first-person
perspective” (Baker 2013, p. 44, emphasis added). This makes a difference
with other mammalians who have rudimentary FPP: these are of kinds that
do not develop robust FPP, and therefore have the rudimentary FPP only
contingently. Now, this seems to mean that, according to Baker, there is
no need to presently possess the capacities for a robust FPP in order to be a
person; it is enough that you have the capacity to develop a robust FPP in the
ordinary history of development that is proper of your natural kind. And in
fact, in the paper read at the Summer School on “Naturalism, First-Person
Perspective and the Embodied Mind”, Baker writes that the dividing line
between a human infant, who is person, and a nonhuman organism, who is
not, is that the first, but not the second, “has a remote capacity to develop
a robust first-person perspective” (Baker 2014, p. 22-23); and, as defined by
Baker, a remote capacity “is a second-order capacity to develop a capacity”
(Baker 2014, p. 23).
I see two possible objections to this. The first is that, in the light of the
scientific evidence very sketchily summarised in the preceding section,
this capacity can hardly be said to be remote: infants in the first years of
age are in fact actively making their way on the road that brings to the full
possession of a robust FPP, and their level of individual agency and social
interaction is so high that they can fairly be said to possess a stable sense
of themselves, in a way that cannot be said of most nonhuman animals.
There is in fact much more continuity between human infants and grown
children than Baker seems willing to allow: specifically, it seems that we can
justifiably say that pre-linguistic infants enjoy some relatively complex form
of inner life, so that Baker’s contention according to which “without a robust
first-person perspective, there would be no inner life at all” (Baker 2013, p.
140) is highly questionable.
The second, and more important, objection is that, if being of a kind that
naturally develops a robust FPP is a sufficient condition in order to be
recognised as a person, even though the relevant capacities are still in the
process of construction, than it is not clear why a sentient human foetus
should not be considered a person as well. The two conditions that Baker
stipulates for having a rudimentary FPP are the possession of consciousness
and of minimal agency: now, there is convincing evidence that a foetus with
a sufficiently developed cortical function (starting from about the 24th week
of pregnancy) does satisfy the first condition for it (Lagercrantz 2014), and,
depending on how minimal agency can be, it might be said to partly satisfy
the second as well. Therefore, since a sentient foetus is likely to possess a
rudimentary FPP, and is a being of a kind that naturally develops a robust first142
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
person perspective, it should be considered a person, according to Baker’s
criterion.
But, even though we should accept that a sentient human foetus does not
satisfy the second condition, the mention of the concept of a natural kind
invites the following line of argument: if being of a kind that naturally
develops a robust FPP is sufficient in order to be considered a person, than
being of a kind that naturally develops first rudimentary, and then robust FPP
should be taken as sufficient ground for personhood as well. To stress the
role of being an individual of a certain natural kind, in order to grant the
human newborn the status of a person, is to accept – at least implicitly –
that there is some ontological significance in being human, that is, in being
a living organism “of a kind that typically develops a robust first-person
perspective” (Baker 2013, p. 148). Therefore, one might be tempted to say
that, at the time that the human individual is present, what you have is a
biological individual of a kind that naturally develops a rudimentary FPP,
at some time (perhaps late) during pregnancy, and then a robust FPP within
the first three years after birth. Where should we stop this regress? Probably
at the time when a human organism is present, which can safely be said
some two weeks after fertilisation, when the cells’ totipotency is lost and
twinning can no longer occur (Ford 1991). This move would partly reconcile
Baker’s view with animalism, in that it would acknowledge the relevance of
human biology among the conditions that account for what we essentially
are: it would acknowledge that embodiment in a biological organism is
a basic condition for the future emergence of the robust FPP, i.e., of the
distinctive mark of full-fledged personhood.
Baker comes close to recognising the importance of biology for persons
when she objects to Descartes’ conception of the self as a solitary thinker,
with no hands, nor flesh, nor blood (Baker 2013, p. 140). However, her
recognition of our necessary embodiment is limited by her insistence that
our body might be substituted by a bionic, wholly engineered one, while we
continued to exist so long as we had our FPP. Baker’s confidence in asserting
this view is based on the well-known cases of the implantation of artificial
limbs and other prosthetic parts that can be meaningfully integrated into
our bodily scheme. I agree that an individual with an artificial arm is still
the same person, because – among other things – she exemplifies the same
FPP: but I think that there are limits to the alteration of our bodily image,
beyond which a bionic body, made up of entirely engineered parts, can no
longer support the same FPP.
Baker’s view greatly underestimates the connexion between my having this
body and my having my FPP. My body is not a mere biological object, it is
143
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
a lived body and the very condition of my being open to the outside world,
that is, of my having consciousness and a FPP: what does the fact that my
FPP is the condition of my persistence mean, if it does not mean that such
perspective emerges from this particular body? If the single fact that accounts
for your being the same person that you were as an infant is that “there is a
single exemplification of the dispositional property of having a first-person
perspective both then and now” (Baker 2014, p. 2), is it not the case that such
a FPP can be the same because it is a dispositional property of the same
body? In particular, it might be said that I can be the same individual and
have the same FPP only so long as I have the same brain; but we may also
add, so long as I conserve the experience of looking at the world from the
same bodily perspective, of acknowledging myself as the bearer of certain
expressions and the user of certain gestures that mirror my inner life. It is
the importance of our embodiment for our sense of ourselves that makes
cases of deep and persistent disfigurement so dramatic, and imaginary tales
such as Kafka’s The Metamorphosis so irretrievably tragic. It is simply the fact
that the alteration of our body affects our sense of ourselves, and we cannot
exemplify the same FPP while inhabiting an utterly different body.
It is true, of course, that my body is ever in the process of changing, and
the cells that constituted it years and even months ago, are no longer those
that constitute it now; and my brain, that coordinates all living functions
and enables consciousness, is constantly changing its neurons as well.
But it is also clear that a form or some other principle of unity testifies to
the permanence of the same organism across the changes of its material
constituents. If it is not this continuing human organism that displays the
dispositional property of conceiving oneself as oneself, who or what does?
If the ‘miness’ of the FPP across time is not accounted for by my biological
continuity, than it can only be linked to my psychological continuity, as in
standard psychological views of identity. But this conclusion would run into
the difficulties that Baker herself raises against psychological views (Baker
2000).
5.
For all her insistence on the anti-Cartesianism of her position, a slight
element of dualism still lingers in Baker’s view: once severed from its
emergence in my specific bodily condition, my FPP seems an analogous
either of a Cartesian soul, that might be transferred in a different, non
biological body, or of a Parfitian collection of connected mental states that
might be teletransported into another planet. Baker surely is not willing
to accept either view: and she would also reject the partly ‘animalistic’ one
I suggested. But has she the conceptual resources to avoid this move? And
144
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
more importantly, does the reconciliation so accomplished of the FPP with
the relevance of embodiment in a biological organism necessarily condemns
its defender to naturalism? In other words, is the irreducibility of the FPP
necessarily tied to the constitution view and to the denial of the role played
by our biological bodies in shaping our identities as persons? I do not think
so. It is persons – I concur – not brains nor minds who “are subjects of
experience, or are rational or moral agents” (Baker 2013, p. 142): however, we
persons cannot think of ourselves as ourselves outside this organic body, for
a non organic, bionic body would not be me, in that it would not support my
FPP. Perhaps this is only an intuition, but it is a very robust one.
145
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
References
Baker, L.R. (2000), Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge;
Baker, L.R. (2013), Naturalism and the First-Person Perspective, Oxford University
Press, Oxford;
Baker, L.R. (2014), Cartesianism and the First-Person Perspective, this issue, pp.
20-29;
Dalgleish, T. (2004), “The Emotional Brain”, Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 5(7),
pp. 583-589;
Ford, N. (1991), When Did I Begin? Conception of the Human Individual in History,
Philosophy and Science, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge;
Greene, J.D., Sommerville, R.B., Nystrom, L.E., Darley, J.M., & Cohen,
J.D. (2001), “An fMRI Investigation of Emotional Engagement in Moral
Judgment”, Science, 293(2105), pp. 2105-2108;
Greene, J.D. (2008), “The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul”, in W. Sinnott-Armstrong
(ed.), Moral Psychology. Volume 3: Emotion, Brain Disorders, and Development, The
MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., pp. 35-79;
Greene, J.D. (2009), “The Cognitive Neuroscience of Moral Judgment”, in M.S.
Gazzaniga (ed.), The Cognitive Neurosciences IV, The MIT Press, Cambridge,
Mass., pp. 987-999;
Haidt, J. (2001), “The Emotional Dog and its Emotional Tail: A Social
Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment”, Psychological Review, 108(4), pp.
814-834;
Haidt, J. (2007), “The New Synthesis in Moral Psychology”, Science, 316(5827),
pp. 998-1002;
Lagercrantz, H. (2014), “The Emergence of Consciousness: Science and
Ethics”, Seminars in Fetal & Neonatal Medicine, 19(5), pp. 300-305;
Layton, D. & Rochat, P. (2007), “Contribution of Motion Information to
Maternal Face Discrimination in Infancy”, Infancy 12(3), pp. 1-15;
Moll, J., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Zahn, R. & Grafman, J. (2008), “The Cognitive
Neuroscience of Moral Emotions”, in W. Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Moral
Psychology. Volume 3: Emotion, Brain Disorders, and Development, The MIT Press,
Cambridge, Mass., pp. 1-18;
Nagel, T. (1986), The View From Nowhere, Oxford University Press, Oxford;
Nichols, S. (2004), Sentimental Rules. On the Natural Foundations of Moral
Judgment, Oxford University Press, Oxford;
Nietzsche, F. (1996), Human, All Too Human: A Book for Free Spirits, R. J.
Hollingdale & R. Schacht (eds.), Cambridge University Press, Cambridge;
Prinz, J.J. (2007), The Emotional Construction of Morals, Oxford University Press,
Oxford;
146
First-Person Morality and the Role of Conscience
Massimo Reichlin Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele
Reichlin, M. (2014), “Neuroethics and the Rationalism/Sentimentalism
Divide”, in C. Lumer (ed.), Morality in Times of Naturalising the Mind, de Gruyter,
Berlin, pp. 127-143;
Rochat, P. (2001), The Infant’s World, Harvard University Press, Cambridge,
Mass.;
Rochat, P. (2012), “Self-Consciousness and ‘Conscientiousness’ in
Development”, Infancia y Aprendizaje, 35(4), pp. 387-404;
Rochat, P. & Hespos, S.J. (1997), “Differential Rooting Response by Neonates:
Evidence for and Early Sense of Self”, Early Development and Parenting, 6(150),
pp. 1-8;
Rochat, P. & Striano, T. (2000), “Perceived Self in Infancy”, Infant Behavior and
Development, 23(3-4), pp. 513-530;
Tomasello, M. (1995), “Joint Attention As Social Cognition”, in C. J. Moore &
P. Dunham (eds.), Joint Attention: Its Origins and Role in Development, Lawrence
Erlbaum Publishers, Hillsdale, NJ, pp. 103-130;
Tomasello, M. (2009), Origins of Human Communication, Bradford Books/The
MIT Press, Cambridge.
147