Download Making Race Out Of nOthing: PsychOlOgically cOnstRained sOcial

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Intercultural competence wikipedia , lookup

Enactivism wikipedia , lookup

Sociological theory wikipedia , lookup

History of social work wikipedia , lookup

Philosophy of history wikipedia , lookup

Social theory wikipedia , lookup

Community development wikipedia , lookup

Unilineal evolution wikipedia , lookup

Social Bonding and Nurture Kinship wikipedia , lookup

Discrimination based on skin color wikipedia , lookup

Social psychology wikipedia , lookup

Social group wikipedia , lookup

Social history wikipedia , lookup

Social perception wikipedia , lookup

Race (human categorization) wikipedia , lookup

Caucasian race wikipedia , lookup

Origins of society wikipedia , lookup

Race and health wikipedia , lookup

History of the social sciences wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
chapter 21
Making Race
Out of Nothing:
Psychologically
Constrained
Social Roles
Ron Mallon and Daniel Kelly
21.1. Introduction
Race is one of the most common variables in the social sciences, used to draw correlations between racial groups and numerous other important variables such as education,
health care outcomes, aptitude tests, wealth, employment and so forth. But where concern with race once reflected the view that races were biologically real, many, if not
most, contemporary social scientists have abandoned the idea that racial categories
demarcate substantial, intrinsic biological differences between people. This, in turn,
raises an important question about the significance of race in those social sciences: If
there is no biological basis of race, why are racial categories useful to social scientists?
More specifically, in virtue of what are racial categories a successful basis of informative,
important social scientific generalizations?1 We’ll call this social science’s race puzzle.
A main aim of this chapter is to set out the sort of solution that has typically been
given to this race puzzle, and suggest some ways in which such a solution might be
extended and improved. We begin by developing what we will call the standard
answer: Racial categories are not biological groupings, but are rather social roles of
some sort. These social roles are produced and sustained by cultural understandings,
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
507
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
508
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
social conventions, institutions, and common practices of classification. Those social
roles, in turn, causally influence the individual persons that occupy them. Generalizations involving races are about individuals occupying the same type of (racial)
social role, and the regularities those generalizations capture exist because those
­individuals are subject to the same types of socially mediated causal influences.
While we believe the standard answer explanation of racial difference is basically
correct, we hold that development of the standard answer’s explanation of racial difference is hampered by an anti-psychological bias that manifests itself in the dearth of
discussion of the underlying psychological mechanisms that support and shape racial
social roles. We argue that appreciation of these mechanisms leaves us better equipped
to explain a range of phenomena of importance to social scientists of race including:
1. The particular patterns of racial categorization and inference characteristic
of racial categories.
2. The stability of racial categories over time and the reappearance of similar
categories across cultures and history.
3. The nature and character of racism, and the sources and persistence of
certain racial disparities.
In short, we argue that understanding the way racial social roles are psychologically
constrained allows us to develop a more complete and satisfactory solution to the
social sciences’ race puzzle.
Here, then, is how we do this. In section 21.2, we set out a more detailed account
of the standard answer. Then, in sections 21.3 and 21.4, we go on to illustrate the kind
of recent work in evolutionary, cognitive, and social psychology can be used to
­develop a hybrid social constructionism about race. In section 21.3, we discuss
recent developments in the evolutionary cognitive approach to racial categorization
that suggest certain features of racial classification and generalization emerge from
the nature of the particular cognitive mechanisms subserving those capacities.
Then, in section 21.4, we go on to discuss recent work in the social psychology of
racism suggesting that many racial evaluations emerge as the result of implicit and
automatic evaluation, and that the relevant mechanisms can contribute to different
kinds of racial inequalities. Finally, in section 21.5, we pull strands of these previous
discussions together to formulate the idea of a psychologically constrained social
role. We briefly situate this idea with respect to other work in the social sciences that
explores how what seem to be small factors operating at the level of individuals—
what have been called micro-affirmations and micro-inequalities—can scale up to
influence or create regularities at the level of groups and societies.
21.2. The Standard Answer
The orthodox view of race and racial phenomena is that regularities expressed by
generalizations using racial terminology exist as a consequence of current or past
social conventions, practices of racial classification of persons, and the differential
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
508
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
509
treatment of those persons. We will unpack the two main components of this view:
the denial of the biological reality of race, and an account of racial phenomena
spelled out in terms of social roles, representations and practices of racial classification.
21.2.1. Denying the Biological Reality of Race
Denials of the biological reality of race rest on a combination of conceptual and
empirical arguments. The most widespread conceptual argument involves characterizing “folk racialism,” a term used to capture the classificatory and inferential
principles that implicitly govern folk conceptions of race, as committed to essentialism about racial categories. Essentialism here is the idea that categories like
black or white pick out some inner, defining essence of those people they apply to.
Such essentialism about race, however, is now widely recognized to be implausible
on biological grounds. This is based both on the general considerations that lead
contemporary biological thought to the abandonment of essentialist thinking about
types (Mayr 1976, Sober 1980), and also on the specific consideration that intragroup
variation in biological races is nearly as great as intragroup variation (Lewontin
1995), leaving candidate essences thin or nonexistent.
This consensus has not been complete. Some biologically oriented philosophers
have suggested that the resulting anti-racialist view is both quite weak (Mallon
2007) and one that biologically sophisticated racialists would be unlikely to hold
(Edwards 2003; Kitcher 1999; Mallon 2007; Sesardic 2003; 2010). Moreover, it has
long been known that human populations—even ones that are geographically and
ethnically closely related—are characterized by biological differences, including
­genetic differences, even if these differences are not essences (e.g. Ward and Neel
1970). More recently, the availability of ancestry identifying genetic tests and the
public discussion over race-specific medicine have seemed to lend plausibility to
the idea that racial categories have at least some biological correlates.
On the other hand, a host of additional arguments against the biological reality
of race have also been advanced in recent decades. These include the claims that:
1. Genes are independently assorted, and so unlikely to cluster with racial
membership (Lewontin 1972, 1974; but see Edwards 2003);
2. Human natural history is such that evolution is unlikely to have continued
(Root 2000, but see Cochran et al. 2006; Hawks et al. 2007).
3. Human variability is continuous (e.g. Diamond 1994).
4. The kinds or populations identified by such a view would be unlikely to match up
with folk racial divisions (Appiah 1996, 73; Glasgow 2003, 458ff; Zack 2002, 76).
Some take such arguments to undermine the existence of outright (Appiah 1996;
Blum 2002; Zack 2002) while others argue for skepticism about race on broadly
pragmatic grounds (Kitcher 2007). Still others remain unconvinced that there is no
acceptable biological grounding for race (Edwards 2003; Sesardic 2010).
Our goal here is not to adjudicate this debate, but to explore and develop the
possibilities for the standard answer as an account of racial difference. Despite ongoing debate about the biological or psychological (e.g. Rushton and Jenson 2005)
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
509
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
510
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
reality of race, and some evidence from what may be special cases (e.g. Cochran et
al. 2006), many of the social sciences and humanities proceed on the assumption
that biological races do not, in general, exist. It is this state of affairs that gives rise
to what we’re calling the race puzzle. Denying the biological reality or significance
of race, or denying the explanatory relevance of whatever differences might exist,
creates the need for an alternative, nonbiological account of those racial differences
that do figure so prominently in the investigations and discoveries of contemporary
social sciences.2
21.2.2. In Place of Biology, Step 1: Enlightened
Realism about Social Practices
The standard answer explains many differential features of race by reference to our
historical and contemporary classifications. In this regard, the standard answer is an
instance of a more general strategy, common throughout the social sciences, of
­understanding certain regularities as being themselves produced by other social
practices. Michael Root invokes the strategy clearly for the case of race:
Race is like marital status; no one would be married or single had we not
invented matrimony; however, given that we did, we now divide our-selves along
discernible boundaries, into categories like “husband” and “wife” or “single” and
“divorced” and treat each other differently depending on which of these categories we belong to. So too with race; we assign each other a race and treat each
other differently depending on that race. As a result, epidemiologists can discover
that the rates of mortality or morbidity are different for one race than another
even though race is not biological just as they can discover that health risks vary
with marital status even though marital status is not in our genes. In other words,
race can be a biologically salient category even though there are no biological
races, and race can mark the risk of a biological condition like diabetes or heart
disease even though race is not itself a biological condition but a social status.
(2003, 1175)
This strategy may raise eyebrows of those concerned to defend a realist interpretation of the phenomena studied by social sciences, or of those who think that that
science is or should be in the business of describing what is real. It might seem that,
according to the standard answer, race is real only because we treat it as being real.
Such worries, though understandable, are misplaced here; we need only recall that
our social practices are real things, with real causal effects, and that any social
­science that left out these practices and their effects would surely provide an incomplete picture of the various social phenomena they seek to understand (Taylor 2000;
Sundstrom 2002).
As it happens, racial classifications are used to express and explain numerous
phenomena—for example. differential tuberculosis rates among American blacks
(but not those in the United Kingdom) (Root 2000); differential test performances
resulting from so-called stereotype threats (Steele 2010); different rates of drug use
(Bachmann et al. 1991); or effects of race in jury selection (Haney-Lopez 2000).
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
510
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
511
21.2.3. In Place of Biology, Step 2: Racial Social Roles
From the recognition that social practices—conventions, patterns of classification
and evaluation, and so forth—have real and systematic effects on individuals and
social groups, one can begin to develop the notion of a social role. The fundamental
idea of a social role is that the differential properties of individuals who fall in a
human category are to be explained (at least in part) by the set of (stable) understandings, policies, and practices concerning proper classification and differential
treatment that a community holds about of those persons. We can characterize this
idea more precisely as follows:
i. There is a term, label, or mental representation that picks out a category of
persons P, and a set of beliefs and evaluations—or a conception—of the
persons so picked out.
ii. Many or all of the beliefs and evaluations in the conception of the role are
widely shared by members of a community, as is the knowledge that they
are widely shared, and so forth. That is, the conception of the category is
common knowledge.3
iii. Many of the beliefs and evaluations are action guiding, specifying appropriate behavior by and toward members of P.
Because communities use classifications of persons as a basis for identifications,
predictions, explanations, and coordination, a conventionally secured social role
creates a social context in which individuals in the category develop, live, and act.
To the extent the representations and conventions constituting the role are stable,
the actions and evaluations they motivate will be stable too. This illuminates how
social roles can give rise to stable, socially produced regularities (cf. Mallon 2003).
Note, for now, that this way of unpacking the idea of a social role appeals to a
variety of psychological entities: representations, beliefs, evaluations, knowledge,
and the like. At this level of generality, we do not take ourselves to be saying ­anything
controversial—any plausible spelling out of the idea of a social role must acknowledge that the causal pressures that shape social roles are psychologically mediated.
Below we make our case for a stronger claim, roughly, that the character of the
­mediating psychology helps explain the character of the resultant social roles, and
ultimately the character of the associated regularities and differences.
This is the burden we take up in the next two sections, where we consider two
types of psychological systems that are implicated in racial cognition. First, in
­section 21.3, we explore the possibility that racial conceptions are shaped by innate,
domain-specific, and species typical proclivities of the sort described in recent
­evolutionary and cognitive psychology. If those conceptions are thus influenced,
then their associated social roles are as well, and it follows that understanding the
relevant psychological proclivities can illuminate the explanation of racial difference. In section 21.4, we explore another sort of proclivity: implicit biases. We argue
that specifically racial biases (which may well be learned) offer individual-level
­psychological mechanisms that ought to figure in standard answer explanations of
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
511
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
512
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
racial difference. Finally, in section 21.5 we discuss more generally how appreciation
psychological proclivities can help shed light on the nature of the social roles that
they shape, and hence help explain the types of regularities that many of the social
sciences investigate.
21.3. An evolutionary cognitive approach
to racial representations
21.3.1. Social Construction and The Race Puzzle
“Social constructionists,” as we use the term here, explain things as products of
human culture and human decision. The standard answer is a sort of social constructionism about racial difference (and one we endorse) because it explains racial
difference by appeal to human culture and the beliefs and practices that such culture
structures.
However social constructionism about racial difference is traditionally paired
with another sort of social constructionism: social constructionism about the representations that in part constitute the culture and social roles that figure in the standard
answer. The claim is, in effect, that our individual or collective racial representations
have the content that they do, rather than some other content (or no content at all),
because of the content of transmitted human culture and human decision. Call this
parallel constructionism, for it holds that the social construction of racial representations proceeds in parallel with the construction of racial difference among those
represented.
In contrast, in this section, we pair social constructionism about racial difference with a partially nonconstructionist account of racial representations. We argue
that the available empirical evidence better supports this view, which we call hybrid
constructionism. Recent work in evolutionary and cognitive psychology has suggested that important features of racial representations are explained by appeal to
mental mechanisms that are species-typical, domain-specific, and innate (Astuti et
al. 2004; Hirschfeld 1996; Gil-White 2001a, 2001b; Gelman 2003; Machery and
­Faucher 2005a, 2005b; Jones 2009; cf. Mallon 2010). But we also note that traditional
social constructionist explanations are ill equipped to explain the stability and distinctiveness of racial representations, and this compromises their ability to fully
address social science’s race puzzle. In effect, we are arguing that relaxing one’s commitment to the social construction of racial representations strengthens one’s hand
with respect to the social construction of race.
Social constructionist explanations of racial representations and recent evolutionary cognitive explanations of racial representations are different empirical
hypotheses about why racial representations have the content they do. They also
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
512
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
513
make different predictions: evolutionary cognitive accounts suggest that at least
some significant aspects of our racial representations are constrained by psychological mechanisms that are innate, domain-specific, and species-typical—in effect
that racial representations are stabilized by features of human nature. In contrast, in
insisting that racial representations are supported by human culture and decision
alone, social constructionist explanations in effect suggest that such representations
should vary considerably over historical time and across cultures as the content of
culture itself shifts.
And this is, in fact, what constructionists say. For example, a frequent claim
of humanists and many humanistically oriented social scientists is that the idea or
concept of race was itself invented, perhaps at the end of the eighteenth or the beginning of the nineteenth century, but at least sometime since the Renaissance (e.g.
Fredrickson 2002; Guillaumin 1980; Banton 1978). Racial thinking, according to
this line of thought, is a socio-historically local product of the West, produced in
a crucible of disparate forces that include the declining influence of the Roman
Catholic church and of religion more generally, the rising influence of science, and
the need for Europeans and Americans to justify their colonial adventures and
slaveholding in a political environment in which democratic equality was an
emerging norm (Fredrickson 2002). Not only are racial representations supposed to
be historically local, but they are often said to be unstable, as in this much-quoted
passage from Michael Omi and Howard Winant’s Racial Formation in the United
States, wherein they urge “effort must be made to understand race as an unstable and
‘decentered’ complex of social meanings constantly being transformed by political struggle”
(1986, 68; italics in original). These claims express exactly what we should expect if
social constructionism about racial representations were true, for without a culturally
independent reality to track (for race is not biologically real) and in the absence of
psychological proclivities stabilizing the content of racial representations, racial representations would be relatively unconstrained, exhibiting a lack of stability over time.
21.3.2. Evolutionary Cognitive Accounts of
Racial Essentialism
Recent evolutionary cognitive work suggests the possibility of a more stable core of
racial representations that, despite numerous changes in cultural understanding
over time, is organized by the theoretical assumption of racial essentialism. While
essentialism is a fixture of social theoretical discussions of race and many other
kinds (e.g. Putnam 1975; Appiah 1996; Mallon 2007), recent psychological work
suggests its role in categorization judgments, inductions, and inferences involving
inheritance in the biological and racial domains (Hirschfeld 1996; Astuti et al. 2004;
Kanovsky 2007; Jones 2009; Mallon 2010). In the biological and racial domains,
such essentialism amounts to the assumption that kind-membership is underwritten by an underlying explanatory property that both explains kind-typical
properties and is passed on in biological inheritance. For example, knowing that an
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
513
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
514
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
individual baby animal or plant seed is of a certain kind causes children to judge
that it will develop the typical properties associated with that kind, even when its
developmental environment is characteristic of another kind. And Susan Gelman
and Henry Wellman (1991, experiments 3, 4 and 5)) showed that 4-year-old children
judge that a baby cow, raised by pigs, will nonetheless say “moo” rather than “oink.”
The work suggests such patterns emerge early (Hirschfeld 1996) and cross-culturally
(Astuti et al. 2004; Atran 1990, 1998; Atran and Medin 2008; Gil-White 2001a,
2001b; Kanovsky 2007; Jones 2009; cf. Mallon 2010) in the biological and racial
domains, and because of the parallels, suggests a common psychological mechanism at work in both domains. While the specific content of, for example, American
racial categories is tied to the American racial context, human groupings organized
by similar, essentialist assumptions are relatively easy to find across a range of
­cultures. For instance, while Indian castes have many differences among themselves
and with American racial classifications, they nonetheless exhibit the idea that “to
be of high or low caste is a matter of innate quality or essence” (Bayly 1999, 10).
Many evolutionary cognitive theorists hypothesize that racial cognition shares
a common structure with biological cognition, and some view this structure as an
evolutionary adaptation. However, in part because they do not believe in biological
race, evolutionary cognitive theorists do not believe this mechanism is adapted for
thinking about race. Rather, they believe it is adapted for some other domain—for
example, for thinking about important social kinds (Hirschfeld 1996) or about
human ethnic groups (Gil-White 2001a).
21.3.3. The Explanatory Relevance of Evolutionary
Cognitive Accounts
These features of the mechanism thought to underlie racial categorization, together
with the assumption made by most theorists that the mechanism in question is a
part of an innate, species-typical psychological endowment of humankind, can
explain features of racial representations that are important and relevant to a wide
range of investigations of racial thought and racial difference in the contemporary
humanities and social sciences. Here we focus upon three examples: category
­stability, patterns of cultural commonality and variation, and the distinctiveness of
the causal effects of racial categories.
21.3.3.1. Category Stability
We have already noted social constructionists’ emphasis on the malleability and instability of racial representations. But the suggestion that categories are so unstable
raises the question of how could they be the basis for successful generalizations in
the social sciences—in effect, threatening to undermine the standard answer’s social
role strategy for answering the race puzzle.
Consider Signithia Fordham and John Uzo Ogbu’s controversial and influential
claim that American blacks’ lower performance in schools than white peers was the
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
514
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
515
result of a black culture that devalues excelling at school as “acting white” (Fordham
and Ogbu 1986). This hypothesis suggests that students manage their behavior in
ways that attempt to balance the needs of successful self-presentation to ones peers
against other values, and it fits nicely as an example of social role explanation of
differential behavior. However, subsequent research has cast doubt on the explanation. In 2003, Karolyn Tyson and William Darity Jr. directed a North Carolina study
that found no difference in school attitudes between white and black students.
However, more recent work by Roland Fryer and Paul Torelli (2010) suggest there
may still be something to the idea. Crucially, for our purposes, is the question of if
and how such findings might generalize. If racial representations are so unstable, it
is unclear how claims about, for example, black North Carolinian attitudes toward
education in North Carolina in the twenty-first century could generalize to, or have
any bearing at all on claims about black Californian attitudes toward education in the
late twentieth century. Unless we take the predicate “black” to have a common meaning
purporting to pick out a single sort of person, it is unclear how a social role structured
by such meaning could perform explanatory work stably across time and space.
Elsewhere, one of us has argued that some stability can be achieved in a social
milieu in which conventions of classification are at some sort of equilibrium with
the social regularities they produce (Mallon 2003; also see Hacking 1995, 1999).
­Appeal to equilibria is less and less plausible over further and further stretches of
time and cultural distance. However, once we recognize that folk racial conceptions
are structured by underlying assumptions of racial essentialism, we can see that
variation in beliefs about race over time often overlie (and leave untouched) a essentialist theoretical core that explains the stability of racial classifications over broader
expanses of time and space.
21.3.3.2. Patterns of Cultural Variation
Of course, to say that evolutionary cognitive explanations of racial essentialism
explain some aspects of racial representations is not to say that all aspects of those
representations are fixed by innate, domain-specific, species-typical mechanisms.
This leads to a prediction: There should be less variation across time and cultures in
features of the representation that reflect underlying essentialist assumptions, and
more variation in those beliefs that escape such assumptions.
A case in point is mixed-race categories. If folk racial essentialism is the product
of applying a mechanism to human groups that is adapted to producing judgments
about certain sorts of biological populations, then it makes sense to think that it would
have little to say in cases where human populations are unlike biological species. For
while (many sorts of) biological species exhibit considerable reproductive isolation,
human populations readily interbreed. So the anthropologist Doug Jones (2009) and
one of us (Mallon 2010) have each predicted that principles for the categorization of
mixed race individuals should vary more widely across cultures than principles for
the categorization of individuals with biological or cultural groups, and Jones (2009)
has argued that this is indeed the case.
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
515
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
516
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
If borne out, this prediction looks to have practical consequences. For it suggests that a certain strand of racial skepticism born of attention to the ubiquity of
mixed-race individuals in the modern world (Zack 1992) has a foundation in our
cognitive architecture. When we attend to the complexity of mixed biological
­parenthood, we may dumbfound the essentialist assumptions by which our minds
attempt to organize our social world. Something like this is almost certainly at work
in the widely remarked upon diminished role of race in Latin American life. The
historian George Fredrickson (2002) writes:
[In Latin America] an attempt to order society on the basis of castas defined in
terms of color and ethnicity eventually broke down because the extent and variety
of mestizaje (interracial marriage and concubinage) created such an abundance of
types that the system collapsed into the three basic categories of white, mestizo,
and Indian. Those categories lacked the rigidity of true racial divisions, because
aspirants to higher status who possessed certain cultural and economic qualifications could often transcend them. (39–40)
21.3.3.3. The Causal Effects of Racial Categories
An ongoing feature of theoretical conversation about racial categories is how such
categories related to other categories like class, sex, gender, ethnicity, and so forth.
One distinctive feature of racial classification that looks to be an outgrowth of the
kind of essentialism that orders the biological domain is the inheritance of racial
membership. In this way, racial membership looks unlike other categories that have
been social bases of oppression. This difference also looks to have systematic effects.
Consider, for example, that contemporary blacks typically have a greater percentage
of black ancestors than contemporary whites do (while they don’t differ in the same
way in the percentage of, for example, women ancestors). This, in turn, means that
past oppression of blacks exerts causal effects differentially on current generations
of blacks in a way that past oppression of women does not. Consider that according
to the Federal Reserve, white Americans possessed ten times the wealth of black
Americans in 2007 (Lui 2009). Because wealth is typically passed on by descent in
parallel with race, past racial oppression cascades down to current generations,
­differentially influencing members of different races. If the evolutionary cognitive
program is right, the distinctive way that racial membership is inherited may be in
part a product of the cognitive proclivities underwriting folk racial categories—
mechanisms that tie racial membership with racial inheritance (Mallon 2010).
21.4. Implicit Biases and Race
In this section we shift gears to focus on a different research program, one that
investigates what social psychologists call implicit biases. While the evolutionary
cognitive program discussed in the last section held that specific aspects of racial
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
516
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
517
representations might be the product of innate, domain-specific, and species-typical
proclivities to essentialize human groups, we make no similar nativist claim about
implicit racial biases. Implicit racial biases appear to be members of a family of more
general biases that can be directed at a range of different types of people; research
has revealed implicit race biases, but also implicit gender biases, implicit age biases,
and so forth. Moreover, the ontogenetic origin of such biases remains unclear, and
they may be acquired via individual or social learning. Our main focus here is on
the evaluative component of racial cognition, and its connection to features like the
sources and persistence of racial disparities found at population levels. We begin by
describing a prominent approach to understanding such disparities—one that
emphasizes institutional racism, and we discuss its connection to the race puzzle
and the standard answer. We go on to describe in more detail some psychological
findings about implicit racial biases, and then illustrate their explanatory value for
addressing social science’s race puzzle.
21.4.1. Social Construction, the Institutional
Approach to Racism and the Race Puzzle
Although there is no single canonical statement of institutional—or, alternatively,
structural—approaches to racism, accounts that go under that name have a common
orientation. Here is a typical description:
A “structural racism” approach considers the ways in which the networked
operations between historical legacies, individuals, and institutional arrangements produce unequal and hierarchical racial outcomes. Thus, rather than
understanding racism as an isolated or individual phenomenon, a structural
racism approach understands it as an outcome and suggests that different societal
institutions work together to distribute or limit opportunity along racial lines.4
Several features of this statement deserved to be unpacked. First, this approach
uses a conception of racism that is outcome focused. Intuitively, discrete actions,
attitudes, and individual people can be racist, but this approach focuses primarily
on unequal social level outcomes. In addition to this distinctive way of conceiving
racism itself, institutional approaches typically favor a distinctive, anti-individualist
kind of explanation of those disparate outcomes as well. The sources and persistence of such inequalities are best explained not by appeal to the characteristics of
individual people (including their psychological characteristics), but mainly by
­appeal to the institutions, social structures and policies of the society in which individual people live, and the policies that govern them. For many advocates of the
institutional approach, the details about individuals and their psychological makeup
are of minor explanatory value, if of any at all. Because racism (in the form of unequal
outcomes) can exist and thrive even in the absence of racists (individual people who
evaluatively rank racial groups), institutional approaches to racism countenance the
possibility of racism without racists (for discussion, see Arthur 2007; Berard 2008l
Brown et al. 2003).
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
517
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
518
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
Like our own approach, institutional approaches provide a version of the standard answer to explaining racial difference. They disavow biological explanations,
and instead explain, for example, racial inequality by appeal to features of cultures,
policies, conventions, and institutions—an approach we have unpacked in terms of
social roles (section 21.1). However, institutional approaches also exhibit resistance
to psychological explanation with which we disagree. In this case, the reluctance to
engage with psychological research appears to stem from an anti-individualist
strain. Indeed, some who favor institutional approaches to racism explicitly argue
that understanding racial cognition is irrelevant to a proper understanding of
racism, and to the most promising strategies for dealing with it (Wellman 2007).5
This sort of institutional approach also suggests rather straightforward predictions
about how to correct or ameliorate the forms of outcome-based racism it focuses
on: Rather than directly targeting individual behaviors or attitudes, the institutional
orientation suggests making higher level changes to the structure of the institutions
and the governing policies themselves.
In what follows, we will make our case that standard answer approaches focusing
on institutions need not be hostile to psychological research, and that relaxing one’s
commitment to anti-individualism, and taking account of the types of psychological
proclivities that influence racial evaluations, allows for a more complete and explanatorily powerful application of the standard answer to racial difference.
21.4.2. Brief overview of implicit racial bias
For roughly the last twenty years, social psychologists have been developing more
sophisticated, indirect ways of measuring individuals’ attitudes, biases, and other
mental states (Devine 1989; Greenwald and Banaji, 1995; Fazio et al., 1995.) To say
these methods are indirect is to say that they do not simply use introspection and
self-report, but instead rely on performance on tests or tasks relevant to the types of
mental states under investigation. Many of the most well known and widely used
indirect tests, such as the implicit attitude test, or IAT, are sorting tasks, in which
subjects must classify stimuli like words or faces as quickly as possible, and under a
variety of conditions. Such methods, designed to bypass the difficulties associated
with self-deception, lack of sincerity, or problematic introspective access, are often
used in conjunction with more direct measures, such as surveys in which participants simply answer questions or rate the degree to which they agree or disagree
with a relevant statement.6 These methods have been used to gather an enormous
amount of data, and shed light on the workings of implicit and automatic cognition
in a number of different domains. Of the mental states investigated using such indirect techniques, some of the most well known have come to be called implicit biases.
As noted above, social psychologists have found evidence of a variety of implicit
biases. These include: biases against the elderly (Levy and Banaji, 2002), biases associated with gender (Lemm and Banaji, 1999), biases associated with sexuality (Banse,
Seise, and Zerbes 2001), biases associated with weight (Schwartz et al. 2006), biases
against the disabled, as well as biases against religious groups (see Lane et al. 2007
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
518
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
519
for a review). Some of the earliest discovered, and most well confirmed, are implicit
racial biases.
The literature on implicit biases is large and growing, so instead of attempting
to give a comprehensive review, we will confine our discussion to some the most
relevant and stable lessons that can be drawn from this research project. Perhaps the
most striking thing about implicit biases, including racial biases, is that they can
coexist within a single individual, with explicit attitudes that are prima facie incompatible with them. A single person can explicitly embrace anti-racist doctrines and
can loudly and sincerely profess to hold egalitarian and tolerant racial views, on the
one hand, while still harboring implicit biases against members of certain races, on
the other. Though they are about the same groups of people (in this case races), racial
evaluation appears to involve two distinct types of mental states, each processed by
it own distinct kind of cognitive mechanism.
In addition to being distinct from their explicit counterparts, implicit biases
have a number of surprising features (much of this, and the evidence in support of
it, is reviewed in greater detail in Kelly, Machery, and Mallon 2010b). Implicit biases
appear to be easy to acquire, and are difficult to get rid of once acquired. As revealed
by a number of studies, some utilizing several indirect techniques, these biases are
unconscious and difficult to detect via introspection. Despite this, however, implicit
biases are far from causally inert. Indeed, they have been found to influence evaluations of people who are classified as belonging to a particular race, and, in turn,
have been found to influence interactions with members of that same race. Even for
those who become aware of implicit racial biases, and the fact that they themselves
harbor them, those implicit biases to not appear to be easily or straightforwardly
manageable. Indeed, a wide range of strategies for mitigating the influence of implicit racial biases have and continue to be investigated, and while it is not yet clear
what separates out those that have some degree of success from those that do not—
or those that outright backfire—it appears that consciously attempting to suppress
their influence on thought and behavior provides an incomplete and only sometimes
effective solution (also see Kelly, Faucher, and Machery 2010a for discussion).
21.4.3. Explanatory Benefits
Implicit racial biases can be thought of as features of individual psychologies that, as
such, exert influence on individuals occupying the racial social roles that are in part
constituted by racial representations. We maintain that collectively, the influence of
implicit biases can scale up to shape the types of population regularities that social
sciences attempt to capture with generalizations about race in particular societies,
cultures, and institutions. In what follows we will go over a specific example in some
detail in an attempt to illustrate how this might work.
We may first note that what we will be proposing there is not completely without precedent. For example, Haney-Lopez (2000) advocates a form of institutional
explanation of racism that he calls the “New Institutional” approach. His concern is
with racial outcomes at the level of prosecution and conviction of certain crimes.
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
519
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
520
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
He finds that for the trials he is looking at, the defendants were Mexican Americans,
but the juries contained little or no Mexican Americans. He argues that the outcome
of those trials is in part explained by appeal to the racial composition of the juries.
He further argues that the racial composition of those juries, in turn, is in part
explained by appeal to a form of racism, more specifically racial discrimination on
the part of the judges who selected the relevant juries.
Haney-Lopez’s discussion is particularly useful from our point of view for a pair of
reasons. First, it represents an attempt to expand the institutional approach to racism
so that it can take into account characteristics of individual actors—particularly actors
who occupy important “gatekeeper” roles within the context of their ­institutions, and
who are therefore in position to exert more amplified influence over institutional outcomes. Perhaps more importantly, however, is his sensitivity to the psychological subtleties involved. The judges relevant to his explanation explicitly claim, under oath, to
not harbor any conscious or intentional discriminatory intent. He sees this as compatible with his favored explanation, which appeals to discrimination on the part of the
judges who selected the juries. Indeed, his stated goal is to
elaborate a theory of racism capable of reconciling the statistical evidence of judicial
discrimination with the judges’ insistence that they never intended to discriminate.
More generally, it sets out to build a theory of racism that explains organizational
activity that systematically harms minority groups even though the decision-making
individuals lack any conscious discriminatory intent. (Haney-Lopez 2000, 1717)
We need only to point out that the research on implicit biases provides a wealth of
empirical support for the kind of psychological possibility required by Haney-Lopez’s
explanation—that actors can be explicitly unbiased but implicitly biased. Thus, incorporating the findings of empirical work on racial cognition is not only compatible
with institutional approaches to racism, but can substantially enrich the associated
explanations of racial regularities and outcomes.
Finally, however, it is worth reflecting on how appreciation of the nature of
implicit biases might help understand certain components of racial representations
themselves. More specifically, appeal to implicit biases may help explain some of
the evaluative, rather than purely descriptive, content that racial representations
can take on.7 If this line of thought is on target, then it supplies one more way in
which a parallel constructionist account of race and racism is at best incomplete;
important elements of the evaluative components of racial representations are a
product of psychological proclivities—in this case the implicit biases—of the
classifiers.
Racial disparities in employment provide another area in which social scientific
explanations can be usefully enriched by appeal to implicit racial biases. Consider
the study performed by Bertrand and Mullainathan (2003), who sent out over 5,000
resumes in response to help wanted ads in Boston and Chicago for a range of different types of jobs. Each of the resumes was made up. Some resumes were designed
to be highly qualified for the position they were sent in response to, while others
were not. Finally, each resume was given either a very black sounding name or a
very white sounding name.
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
520
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
521
The results were eye-opening. First, the resumes with white sounding names
got roughly 50 percent more callbacks in general. Second, within the set of resumes
with white sounding names, those that were highly qualified for the respective
­position received 30 percent more callbacks than others, but no similar effect was
found for resumes with black sounding names. Being more qualified did not increase
the chance that a resume with a black sounding name would get an interview. Third,
the relative levels of discrimination were similar across occupations and industries.
Finally, just less than one third of those companies explicitly described themselves
as “Equal Opportunity Employers” in their help wanted ads. Despite this assertion,
these companies showed similar patterns and levels of discrimination against
resumes with black sounding names.
Bertrand and Mullainathan are at pains to show that the discrimination revealed
by this study is a result of race, and not some other factor. They show that the patterns cannot be explained by appeal to the address listed on the resume (whether
the applicant lives in a good or bad neighborhood) or facts about the different types
of job requirements or industries associated with the positions being applied to.
Before discussing this in terms of the social science’s race puzzle, we need to
make the case that these patterns of discrimination are caused, in part, by the implicit racial biases of people making decisions about individual resumes. This, of
course, requires some speculation, but we believe the claim is plausible. Bertrand and
Mullainathan show that the discriminatory patterns are linked to race, as indicated
by the names on the resumes. This leaves two possibilities: Either the people deciding
which resumes deserve callback and which that do not are explicitly racist, or they
harbor implicit racial biases that influence their decisions. We believe the later explanation is more plausible. First, implicit racial biases are relatively widespread, and
research has demonstrated that implicit biases can influence the judgments and
behaviors of individuals in a number of ways, and in a number of conditions (Lane
et al. 2007). So they are able to do the explanatory work being asked for them.
­Second, it seems to us that implicit, rather than explicit biases are more likely to be
the culprits in this case. In general explicit racial biases have been on the decline in
the population for some time (Schuman et al. 1997). Furthermore, Bertrand and
Mullainathan found similar patterns of discrimination in those businesses that
went out of their way to describe themselves as Equal Opportunity Employers. This
means that, collectively, those individuals making decisions about resumes in Equal
Opportunity businesses produced patterns of racial discrimination despite having
instructions and incentives to assess resumes impartially.
Now, let us recall the race puzzle: If biological races offer no explanatory purchase, then what explains the success of racial categories in expressing the types of
true generalizations studied by the social sciences? If there are no biological races of
the sort once thought, then why are there robust population level statistical regularities that are captured using racial terminology? What we called the standard answer
claims that racial categories are social roles that are invented, but then take on a life
of their own once they become involved in the looping effects of human classificatory dynamics. Our discussion here accepts this as far as it goes, but we think that it
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
521
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
522
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
leaves out an important piece of the puzzle: namely, the influence of specific features
of individual psychologies on those classificatory dynamics, and the types of patterns those features can generate and sustain.
We think Bertrand and Mullainathan’s resume study finds a pattern that illustrates just this phenomenon: Resumes with white sounding names are 50 percent
more likely to get interviews that resumes with black sounding names. Explaining
this, we claim, involves not just appeal to explicit beliefs about race, but also appeal
to the fact that, at the individual level, many people have implicit racial biases that
tacitly influence their judgments about those categories and the people that fall under
them. The effects of these biases, in turn, scale up to help produce the types of population level patterns discovered by social scientists, such as the disparity in interviews
offered to resumes bearing black versus white sounding names. In general, such
biases can contribute to the types of disparities in employment documented by social
scientists and others working on race (for instance see Horton 1995; Bendick and
Egan 2009; Bendick, Rodriguez, and Jayaraman 2009).
Race may not be biologically real, but it remains important because people
think it is, and act as if it was, thus keeping racial categories and social roles in high
currency. Racism remains very real, in part because the cognitive machinery that
underpins how people think about and act on racial social roles involves implicit
biases, and the influence of those biases scales up to systematically shape population
levels patterns concerning race and discrimination.
21.5. Psychologically Constrained Social
Roles, and the Power of Small Causes
Social sciences’ race puzzle arises from the assumption that there is no or little
biological basis of race, which leaves it unclear why racial categories can serve as
a successful basis of informative, important social scientific generalizations. As
we have argued, the standard answer to this puzzle is a social constructionist
­explanation of racial difference, invoking something like racial social roles. While
we agree with this answer, we have argued that the exploration and development
of more sophisticated forms of the standard answer have been hindered by antipsychological bias manifested in two related strands of thought, which we have
called parallel constructionist and anti-individualist, respectively. Instead, we have
argued that versions of the standard answer can be supplemented and improved
by taking account of the types of psychological findings we have discussed in the
last two sections.
Let us sum up the argument we have been offering. Standard answer explanations of category difference appeal (tacitly or otherwise) to the way representations
structure our social lives, an idea we have sketched in terms of social roles. Any
plausible account of these representations and the ways they structure our social
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
522
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
523
lives will appeal to psychological entities and processes that can guide practices of
classification, influence social conventions, and shape formal and informal policies
concerning membership in a social role.
Parallel constructionists see these representations as themselves being socially
constructed, and thus exclusively the product of human decision and culture. As such,
parallel constructionists see the social roles they structure as primarily a result of historical circumstances, social conventions and common practices of classification.
Anti-individualists see social regularities and outcomes as best explained by appeal to
features of institutions and social policies, rather than individuals. Both explanations
exhibit anti-psychological bias.
Another way to think of this is that both parallel constructionist and antiindividualist explanations deal in what might be called purely conventional social
roles. Some social roles, such as divorcee or licensed chihuahua owner, may very well
be purely conventional, in this sense. We have offered reason to believe, however,
that others are what we can call psychologically constrained social roles. To say that
a social role is psychologically constrained is to say more than the (fairly trivial
claim that) relevant representations are, at some point, operated on or mediated by
individual human psychologies. It is rather to claim that social roles are strongly
influenced, in some way or another, by the specific character of the psychological
mechanisms in play.
Understood in these terms, the case we have been making in the last couple of
sections is that the behavior of the racial social roles invoked by the standard answer
is best understood as psychologically constrained in a number of ways. To make this
case, we have tried to show that explaining the stability and distinctiveness of racial
social roles, and explaining the evaluations associated with and the causal effects of
those social roles requires a better appreciation of the specific character of the psychological mechanisms that contribute to and constrain them.8,9
One might suspect that the types of psychological influences that we claim can
constrain social roles are too small to actually shape population level regularities.
However, intuition is not always the best guide to understanding how factors that
are slight, even at the level of the individual, will aggregate upward to affect the
character of a population, especially when those factors are widespread. Indeed, the
power of micro-affirmations and micro-inequalities is beginning to be discussed
and better appreciated by those attempting to understand the sources of persistent
population level disparities associated with gender (Rowe 2008; also see Saul manuscript). Theorists of culture, attempting to understand the engines and dynamics
of cultural change and stability more generally, make a similar point: “Small, dull
effects at the individual level are the stuff of powerful forces of evolution at the level
of populations” (Richerson and Boyd 2005, 123). In the types of (psychologicallyconstrained-social-role) cases we’re talking about, some of those small, dull effects
are generated by features of individual psychologies and the psychological mechanisms they contain. That said, we see no reason that their being psychological would
make them an exception to the rule that when such effects are slight but many, they
can aggregate upward to have powerful effects at the level of populations, either as
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
523
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
524
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
forces of change or as forces that help maintain certain aspects of the status quo. The
best explanations of many population level generalities, outcomes, and disparities,
then, may very be found in psychologically constrained social roles.
Acknowledgments
Our thanks go out to Luc Faucher, Jennifer Saul, Emma Gilby, Harold Kincaid, and the participants in the Current Issues in the Philosophy and Methodology of the Social Sciences
conference at the University of Alabama at Birmingham for providing useful feedback on
previous versions of this material.
Notes
1. We are indebted to Root (2000)’s articulation of this problem.
2. In the philosophy of race, widespread endorsement of the failure of biological
race as a referent for racial thought and talk has given rise to a debate over whether we
should retain or eliminate racial categories like “black,” “white,” “Asian,” and “race” itself
from our ordinary, expert, and policy discourse. While much of this discourse has been,
at least on the surface, guided by semantic assumptions—for example, assumptions about
the conditions under which terms like “race” would refer—there are substantial practical
questions about the relative value and costs of racial classification also in play (Mallon
2006, 2007).
3. David Lewis (1969) introduced the idea of common knowledge. Cf. Vanderschraaf
and Sillari (2009) for an extensive discussion of a range of ways of specifying the idea.
4. Available online from The Ohio State University’s Kirwan Institute for the Study
of Race and Ethnicity at www.structuralracism.org/publications/documents/SRC%20
SR%20Bibliography_No%20annotations.pdf.
5. Wellman even goes a step further, arguing that certain psychological explanations
of racism actually inhibit efforts to deal with it. See Machery, Faucher, and Kelly 2010 for
discussion and rebuttal of those arguments.
6. Descriptions of indirect testing methods, and the statistical techniques used to
interpret data gathered using them, can get quite technical (see citations in main text, and
also Lane et al. 2007 and Greenwald et al. 2009). One can get a visceral feel for such tests
by taking an IAT online at https://implicit.harvard.edu/implicit/demo/.
7. One useful way of thinking about this is in terms of the philosopher Bernard
Williams’s (1985) distinction between thick and thin ethical concepts. Thin concepts are purely
evaluative, and often quite abstract; examples include good, justice, wrong, etc. Thick concepts,
on the other hand, are hybrid concepts, in that they contain both descriptive and evaluative
elements; example here include courageous, compassionate, brutal and untrustworthy.
Certainly in some cultures, racial terms seem to operate like “thick” concepts; they not only
purport to pick out a group of people based on some description, but also carry an attendant
evaluation of that group of people as well.
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
524
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
525
8. Compare with the notion of “multidisciplinary explanations” of racism discussed
in Machery, Faucher, and Kelly 2010.
9. Psychologically constrained social roles could be appealing in areas of philosophy
and social science beyond discussions of race though the burden of this chapter has been
to make the case that racial social roles in particular are constrained in a number of
interesting and perhaps unexpected ways.
References
Appiah, K. A. 1995. “The Uncompleted Argument: Du Bois and the Illusion of Race.” In
Overcoming Racism and Sexism, L. A. Bell and D. Blumenfeld, eds., 59–77. Lanham,
MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Appiah, K. A. 1996. “Race, Culture, Identity: Misunderstood Connections.” In Color
Conscious: The Political Morality of Race, K. A. Appiah and A. Guttmann, eds.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Arthur, John. 2007 Race, Equality, and the Burdens of History, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Astuti, R., G.E.A. Solomon, and S. Carey. 2004. “Constraints on Cognitive Development:
A Case Study of the Acquisition of Folkbiological and Folksociological Knowledge in
Madagascar.” Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 69(3): I, v,
vii, viii, 1–161.
Atran, S. 1998. “Folk Biology and the Anthropology of Science: Cognitive Universals and
Cultural Particulars.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21(4): 547–609.
Atran, Scott. 1990. Cognitive Foundations of Natural History. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Atran, Scott and Douglas L. Medin. 2008. The Native Mind and the Cultural Construction
of Nature. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Bachmann, J. G., J. M. Wallace, Jr., P. M. O’Malley, L. D. Johnston, C. L. Kluth, and
H. W. Neighbors. 1991. “Racial/Ethnic Differences in Smoking, Drinking, and Illicit
Drug Use Among American High School Seniors, 1976–89.” American Journal of
Public Health 81(3): 372–77.
Banse, R., Seise, J., and Zerbes, N. 2001. “Implicit Attitudes Toward Homosexuality:
Reliability, Validity, and Controllability of the IAT.” Zeitschrift für Experimentelle
Psychologie 48(2): 145–60.
Banton, M. 1978. The Idea of Race. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Bayly, Susan. 1999. Caste, Society, and Politics in India. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Bendick, M. and Egan, M.L. 2009. Research Perspectives on Race and Employment inthe
Advertising Industry. Washington, D.C.: Bendick and Egan Economic Consultants,
Inc., for the Madison Avenue Project. Available at http://bendickegan.com/pdf/2009/
Bendick%20Egan%20Advertising%20Industry%20Report%20Jan%2009.pdf.
Bendick, M., Rodriguez, R. and Jayaraman, S. 2009. Race-Ethnic Employment Discrimination
in Upscale Restaurants: Evidence from Paired Comparison Testing. Washington, D.C.:
Bendick and Egan Economic Consultants, Inc., for the Madison Avenue Project.
Available at http://bendickegan.com/pdf/2009/Testing_article_%20Feb_2009.pdf.
Berard, Tim J. 2008 “The Neglected Social Psychology of Institutional Racism,” Sociology
Compass 2(2): 734–64.
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
525
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
526
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
Bertrand, M. and Mullainathan, S. 2003. “Are Emily and Greg More Employable Than
Lakisha and Jamal?: A Field Experiment on Labor Market and Discrimination.”
Poverty Action Lab Paper No. 3. Cambridge, MA: Abdul Latif Jameel Poverty Action
Lab. Available at http://povertyactionlab.org/papers/bertrand_mullainathan.pdf
Blum, L. 1999. “Race, Community and Moral Education: Kohlberg and Spielberg as Civic
Educators.” Journal of Moral Education 28(2): 125–43.
Blum, Lawrence. 2002. “I’m not a Racist But . . .” Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Blum, L. 2009. “Prejudice.” In Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Education, H. Siegel, ed.,
451–68. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Brown, Michael, Conroy, Martin, Currie, Elliott, Duster, Troy, Oppenheimer, David B.,
Shultz, Marjorie, and Wellman, David. 2003. Whitewashing Race: The Myth of A
Color-Blind Society. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Cochran, G., J. Hardy, and H. Harpending. 2006. “Natural History of Ashkenazi Intelligence.”
Journal of Biosocial Science 38(5): 659–93.
Devine, P. 1989. “Stereotypes and Prejudice: Their Automatic and Controlled Components.”
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 56(1): 5–18.
Diamond, Jared. 1994. “Race Without Color.” Discover (Nov.): 82–89.
Edwards, A.W.F. 2003. “Human Genetic Diversity: Lewontin’s Fallacy.” BioEssays 25: 298–801.
Fazio, R., Jackson, J., Dunton, B. and Williams, C. 1995. “Variability in Automatic Activation
as an Unobtrusive Measure of Racial Attitudes: A Bona Fide Pipeline?” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 69(6): 1013–27.
Fordham, S. and J. Ogbu. 1986. “Black Students School Success: Coping with the Burden of
Acting White.” Urban Review 18(3): 176–206.
Fredrickson, G.M. 2002. Racism: A Short History. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Fryer, R. and Paul Torelli. 2010. “An Empirical Analysis of Acting White.” Journal of Public
Economics 94(5–6): 380–96.
Gelman, S. A. 2003. The Essential Child: Origins of Essentialism in Everyday Thought. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Gelman, S. A. and H. M. Wellman. 1991. “Insides and Essences: Early Understandings of
the Non-Obvious.” Cognition 38: 213–44.
Gil-White, F. 2001a. “Are Ethnic Groups Biological ‘Species’ to the Human Brain?” Current
Anthropology 42(4): 515–54.
Gil-White, F. 2001b. “Sorting is Not Categorization: A Critique of the Claim that Brazilians
Have Fuzzy Racial Categories.” Cognition and Culture 1(3): 219–49.
Gil-White, F. 2006. “The Study of Ethnicity and Nationalism Needs Better Categories:
Clearing Up the Confusions That Result from Blurring Analytic and Lay Concepts.”
Journal of bioeconomics 7(3): 239–70.
Glasgow, Joshua. 2003. “On the New Biology of Race.” The Journal of Philosophy (September):
456–74.
Greenwald, A. and Banaji, M. 1995. “Implicit Social Cognition: Attitudes, Self-Esteem, and
Stereotypes.” Psychological Review 102(1): 4–27.
Greenwald, A., McGhee, D. and Schwartz, J. 1998. “Measuring Individual Differences in
Implicit Cognition: The Implicit Association Test.” Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology 74(6): 1464–80.
Greenwald, A.G., Poehlman, T.A., Uhlmann, E., and Banaji, M.R. 2009. “Understanding
and Using the Implicit Association Test: III. Meta-Analysis of Predictive Validity.”
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 97(1): 17–41.
Guillaumin, Colette. 1980. The Idea of Race and Its Elevation to Autonomous Scientific and
Legal Status. Sociological Theories: Race and Colonialism. United Nations Educational,
Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO). Paris: UNESCO.
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
526
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
527
Hacking, I. 1995. “The Looping Effects of Human Kinds.” In Causal Cognition, D. Sperber
et al., eds., 351–94. New York: Clarendon Press.
Hacking, I. 1999. The Social Construction of What? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Haney-Lopez, I. 2000. “Institutional Racism: Judicial Conduct and a New Theory of Racial
Discrimination.” The Yale Law Journal 109(8): 1717–885.
Hawks, J., E. T. Wang, G. M. Cochran, Henry C. Harpending, and R. K. Moyziz. 2007.
“Recent Acceleration of Human Adaptive Evolution.” Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences 104(52): 20753–58.
Hirschfeld, L. W. 1996. Race in Making: Cognition, Culture, and the Child’s Construction of
Human Kinds. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Horton, Hayward Derrick. 1995. “The Impact of Population and Structural Change on
Racial Inequality in the United States: An Examination of Employment Toward the
21st Century.” In Race and Ethnicity in America: Meeting the Challenge in the 21st
Century, G. E. Thomas, ed., 227–37. Washington, D.C.: Taylor and Francis.
Jones, Doug. 2009. “Looks and Living Kinds: Varieties of Racial Cognition in Bahia,
Brazil.” Journal of Cognition and Culture 9(3): 247–69.
Kanovsky, Martin. 2007. “Essentialism and Folksociology: Ethnicity Again.” Journal of
Cognition and Culture 7(3–4): 241–81.
Kelly, D., Faucher, L. and Machery, E. 2010a. “Getting Rid of Racism: Assessing Three
Proposals in Light of Psychological Evidence.” Journal of Social Philosophy 41(3): 293–322.
Kelly, D., Machery, E. and Mallon, R. 2010b. “Race and Racial Cognition.” In The Oxford
Handbook of Moral Psychology, J. Doris et al., eds., 433–72. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Kirwan Institute for the Study of Race and Ethnicity, “Bibliographical Guide to Structural
Racism.” Available at www.structuralracism.org/publications/documents/SRC%20
SR%20Bibliography_No%20annotations.pdf.
Kitcher, Philip. 1999. “Race, Ethnicity, Biology, Culture.” In Racism, L. Harris, ed., 87–120.
New York, Humanity Books.
Kitcher, Philip. 2007. “Does ‘Race’ Have Future?” Philosophy and Public Affairs 35(4): 293–317.
Kurzban, R., J. Tooby and L. Cosmides. 2001. “Can Race Be Erased? Coalitional Computation
and Social Categorization.” Proceeding of the National Academy of Science 98(26):
15387–92.
Lane, K. A., Banaji, M. R., Nosek, B. A., and Greenwald, A. G. 2007. “Understanding and
Using the Implicit Association Test: IV: Procedures and Validity.” In Implicit Measures
of Attitudes: Procedures and Controversie, B. Wittenbrink and N. Schwarz, eds., 59–102.
New York: Guilford Press.
Lemm, K., and Banaji, M. R. 1999. “Unconscious Attitudes and Beliefs About Women and
Men.” In Wahrnehmung und Herstellung von Geschlecht (Perceiving and performing
gender), U. Pasero and F. Braun, eds., 215–33. Opladen: Westdutscher Verlag.
Levy, B., and Banaji, M. R. 2002. “Implicit Ageism.” In Ageism: Stereotyping and Prejudice
Against Older Persons, T. Nelson, ed., 49–75. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Lewis, D. 1969. Convention: A Philosophical Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Lewontin, R. 1972. “The Apportionment of Human Diversity.” Evolutionary Biology, T.
Dobzhansky, M. Hecht, and W. Steer, eds., 381–98. New York: Appleton Century Crofts.
Lewontin, R. 1974. The Genetic Basis of Evolutionary Change. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Lewontin. R. C. 1995. Human Diversity. New York: Scientific American Library.
Lui, Meizhu. 2009. “The Wealth Gap Gets Wider.” Washington Post. March 23. A15.
Machery, E. and Faucher, L. 2005a. “Why Do We Think Racially?” In Handbook of Categorization in Cognitive Science, H. Cohen and C. Lefebvre, eds., 1009–33. Orlando, FL: Elsevier.
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
527
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
528
Norms, Culture, and the Social-Psychological
Machery, E. and Faucher, L. 2005b. “Social Construction and the Concept of Race.”
Philosophy of Science 72(5): 1208–19.
Machery, E., Faucher, L. and Kelly, D. 2010. “On The Alleged Inadequacies of Psychological
Explanations of Racism.” The Monist 93(2): 228–55.
Mallon, Ron. 2003. “Social Construction, Social Roles and Stability.” In Socializing Metaphysics.
F. Schmitt, ed., 327–53. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Mallon, Ron. 2006. “‘Race’: Normative, Not Metaphysical or Semantic.” Ethics 116(3): 525–51.
Mallon, Ron. 2007. “Human Categories Beyond Non-Essentialism.” Journal of Political
Philosophy 15(2): 146–68.
Mallon, Ron. 2010. “Sources of Racialism.” Journal of Social Philosophy 41(3): 272–92.
Mayr, E. 1976. “Typological versus Population Thinking.” Evolution and the Diversity of Life,
26–29. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Omi, Michael and Howard Winant. 1986. Racial Formation in the United States: From the
1960s to the 1980s. New York: Routledge.
Putnam, Hilary. 1975. “The Meaning of ‘Meaning.’” Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical
Papers, Vol. 2., 215–71. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Richerson, P. and Boyd, R. 2005. Not By Genes Alone. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Root, M. 2000. “How We Divide the World.” Philosophy of Science 67 (Proceedings): 628–39.
Root, Michael. 2003. “The Use of Race in Medicine as a Proxy for Genetic Differences.”
Philosophy of Science 70(5): 1173–83.
Root, M. 2005. “The Number of Black Widows in the National Academy of Sciences.”
Philosophy of Science 72(5): 1197–207.
Rowe, M. 2008. “Micro-Affirmations and Micro-Inequities.” Journal of the International
Ombudsman Association 1: 1.
Rushton, J. Philippe and Arthur R. Jensen. 2005. “Thirty Years of Research on Race
Differences in Cognitive Ability.” Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 11(2): 235–94.
Saul, J. Forthcoming. “Implicit Bias, Stereotype Threat and Women in Philosophy.” In
Women in Philosophy: What Needs to Change?, F. Jenkins and K. Hutchinson, eds.
Schwartz, M.B., Vartanian, L.R., Nosek, B.A., and Brownell, K.D. 2006. “The Influence of
One’s Own Body Weight on Implicit and Explicit Anti-Fat Bias.” Obesity 14(3): 440–47.
Sesardic, Neven. 2003. “Book Review of N. Zack, Philosophy of Science and Race.”
Philosophy of Science 70(2): 447–49.
Sesardic, N. 2010. “A Social Destruction of a Biological Concept.” Biology and Philosophy,
25(2): 143–62.
Schuman, H., Steeh, C., Bobo, L., and Kryson, M. 1997. Racial Attitudes in America: Trends
and Interpretations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Sober, E. 1980. “Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism.” Journal of Philosophy
47: 350–83.
Steele, C. 2010. Whistling Vivaldi: And Other Clues to How Stereotypes Affect Us. New York:
Norton.
Sundstrom, R. 2002. “Racial Nominalism.” Journal of Social Philosophy 33(2): 193–210.
Taylor, P. 2000. “Appiah’s Uncompleted Argument: Du Bois and the Reality of Race.” Social
Theory and Practice 26(1): 103–28.
Tyson, Karolyn, William Darity Jr., and Domini Castellino. 2004. “Breeding Animosity:
The ‘Burden of Acting White’ and Other Problems of Status Group Hierarchies in
Schools.” Working Paper. Chapel Hill: Department of Sociology, University of North
Carolina Chapel Hill.
Vanderschraaf, Peter and Giacomo Sillari. 2009, Spring 2009. “Common Knolwedge.” The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/
spr2009/entries/common-knowledge/, accessed December 2009, 2009.
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
528
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF
Making Race Out of Nothing
529
Ward, R.H. and J.V. Neel. 1970. “Gene Frequencies and Microdifferentiation Among the
Makiritare Indians IV. A Comparison of a Genetic Network with Ethnohistory and
Migration Matrices: A New Index of Genitic Isolation.” American Journal of Human
Genetics 22(5): 538–61.
Wellman, David 2007 “Unconscious Racism, Social Cognition Theory, and the Legal Intent
Doctrine: The Neuron Fires Next Time.” In Handbook of Racial and Ethnic Relations,
H. Vera and J. Feagin, eds., 39–65. New York: Springer.
Williams, B. 1985. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London: Fontana.
Zack, N. 1993. Race and Mixed Race. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Zack, N. 1998. Thinking about Race. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Zack, N. 1999. “Philosophy and Racial Paradigms.” Journal of Value Inquiry 33(3): 299–317.
Zack, N. 2001. “Race and Philosophical Meaning.” In Race and Racism, B. Boxill, ed., 43–57.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Zack, N. 2002. Philosophy of Science and Race. New York: Routledge.
Zack, N. 2003a. “Race and Racial Discrimination.” In The Oxford Handbook of Practical
Ethic, H. Lafollette, ed., 245–71. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zack, N. 2003b. “Reparations and Rectification of Race.” The Journal of Ethics 7(1): 139–51.
Zack, N. 2004. “American Mixed Race.” In Mixing It Up: Multiracial Subjects, S. Kwan and
K. Speirs, eds., 13–30. Austin: University of Texas Press.
KINCAID-Chapter 21-PageProof
529
March 10, 2012 2:49 PM