* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download The Bundesverfassungsgericht sentence
Prague Declaration on European Conscience and Communism wikipedia , lookup
European Day of Remembrance for Victims of Stalinism and Nazism wikipedia , lookup
World government wikipedia , lookup
European integration wikipedia , lookup
High Representative of the Union for Foreign Affairs and Security Policy wikipedia , lookup
United States of Europe wikipedia , lookup
North American Union wikipedia , lookup
The Bundesverfassungsgericht sentence and the future of the European Union After the French “no” to the project of a European Constitution the German answer could not be missing. France availed itself of its veto right. Now, the insurmountable limits of the building of Europe fixed in the German Constitution have been made explicit by Germany. It is a preventive veto right. After the Bundesverfassungsgericht sentence of June 30th, the former constitutional judge Paul Kirchof, declared: “There cannot be a European state while the German constitution continues to exist”. It is a serious statement, which denies the foundations of the European construction. Taken literally, it implies the intention of Germany to do without a European foreign and security policy, the only “sovereign power” still on the brink between the Union and the member states. Is Germany maybe thinking of a new Sonderweg in world politics? In order to discuss these complex issues, first of all we will examine the ideological nucleus on which the German judges have built their reasoning. Then, we will criticise the concept of national sovereignty and, finally, we will take into account the political consequences of the ideological nucleus of the Bundesverfassungsgericht. The sentence of the German constitutional judges is founded on a precise and well reasoned ideological nucleus. Substantially it is the umpteenth reformulation of the doctrine of national sovereignty, which in the contemporary world must be founded explicitly on popular will and democracy. The fundamental element of the democratic state, according to the German Constitutional Court, consists in the recognition of the right of citizens to determine, with a free and equal vote, the formation of public powers, in other words their government. It must be based on a proportional majority of the population, whereas the task of the minority is to represent the political alternative (§ 211, 212, 213, 214, 215). The German Constitution, thanks to representative institutions, guarantees this result by means of laws that must be considered “inviolable”. According to the judges, the Germans’ constitutional power, which gave life to the Constitution, established that these fundamental laws – German “inalienable constitutional identity” – cannot be modified in any way in the future. It is an “eternity guarantee”. The German Constitutional Court has taken on the role of loyal guardian of German constitutional identity (§ 216, 217, 218, 219). From these premises, at first sight irreproachable, the German judges severely criticise the institutions of the European Union, which is designated as a Staatenverbund, that is an association of states which remain sovereign. The judges realise that the Basic Law foresees the integration of Germany into European and world institutions, in order to guarantee a future of peace and prosperity for its citizens. Nonetheless, “neither the integration pari passu into the European Union nor the integration into peacekeeping systems such as the United Nations is tantamount to submission to alien powers” (§ 220). In particular, as far as Europe is concerned, they acknowledge that the Basic Law recognises the chance of a “far-reaching transfer of sovereign power to the European Union” (§ 226), but this transfer of powers must come to a halt before a well defined limit, because “the Basic Law does not grant the bodies acting on behalf of German powers to abandon the right to self-determination of the German people in the form of Germany’s sovereignty under International law by joining a federal state. Due to the irrevocable transfer of sovereignty to a new subject of legitimisation that goes with it, this step is reserved to the directly declared will of the German people alone” (§ 228). Moreover, the Constitutional Court makes it clear that, as the guardian of German constitutional identity, it would object to this step, because it would mean going from a European Union conceived of as a Staatenverbund, in which national governments continue to be the Masters of the Treaties, to a federal state entity, by means of an irreversible transfer of sovereignty. In this case, the exit of Germany from the Staatenverbund would be inevitable (§ 230, 231, 232, 233, 234, 235 e 264). 1 This theoretical construction is open to easy criticism. Among its organs, the European Union envisages a European Parliament elected directly by the citizens; therefore the existence of a sovereign European people should be acknowledged alongside the national people. The German constitutional judges have, however, their own peculiar concept of the functioning of the Union: “the Council is not a second chamber as it would be in a federal state but the representative body of the Masters of the Treaties”; the Commission “need not extensively fulfil the conditions of a government that is fully accountable either to Parliament or the majority decision of the electorate” and the European Parliament is only “an additional independent source of democratic legitimisation” (§ 271). Substantially, the European Parliament does not express full democratic legitimacy at the same level of national parliaments. “The Treaty of Lisbon has also decided against the concept of a European federal Constitution in which a European Parliament as the body of representation of a new federal people that would be constituted by this Constitution would be the focus” (§ 277). Therefore the European Union continues to remain “the creation of sovereign democratic states” (§ 278) and cannot in any way be considered a federal state because within it “the will of the European majority [that] brings about the formation of the government” in such a way that they will accomplish “genuine competition between government and opposition clearly visible to the citizens” cannot be expressed (§ 280). This dialectics between the majority and the opposition could not however appear in the present European Parliament because the European Members of Parliament are elected according to a digressive criterion, on the basis of which the citizens of the smaller countries are more represented compared to the bigger ones. “The result of this is that the weight of the vote of a citizen from a Member State with a low number of inhabitants may be about twelve times the weight of vote of a citizen from a Member State with a high number of inhabitants (§ 285). A majority of Members of Parliament in the European Parliament does not necessarily correspond to a majority of European voters. To sum up, “it is not the European people that is represented according to the meaning of Article 10.1 TEU Lisbon but the peoples of Europe organised in their states” (§ 286); the Treaty of Lisbon “does not lead to a new level of development of democracy” (§ 295), the principles of which are well rooted in the national sovereign States. Let us now consider the limits of this definition of national sovereignty. National sovereignty is not only a legal concept, but also a political myth which served and serves to justify national power, its existence and its expansion, up to the manifestation of a will for power which generated the greatest tragedies of history: the two world wars in the twentieth century. The reformulation of the doctrine of national sovereignty by the German judges is apparently cautious and founded on solid democratic roots of popular will. Nevertheless, it suggests the creation of a myth that could become a political monster. The myth is generated by a vision of history that omits some fundamental features of reality, to exalt others, which are imaginary, with the aim of making an obscure situation comprehensible or of justifying a power; in this case national power. The post-war German State, rebuilt on the ashes of the defeated Hitlerian State, did not arise due to the self-determination of the German people, but thanks to the victorious great powers, first of all the USA and the USSR, who lay the ideological and institutional foundations of the new post-war international relations, divided Europe into two separate domains and split the old Reich into two states. In 1958 the historian Golo Mann wrote, without being contradicted, that “the two principles, democracy and federalism, were imposed on the Germans by the winners, as the winners imposed the monarchy on France after the fall of Napoleon”. To put it less bluntly, the constitutionalist Carl Friedrich (in 1950) gave a convincing explanation for the substantial uniformity of all the European constitutions after the war as far as their internal democratic structure is concerned and their opening to peace-making and to the devolution of national sovereignty to supranational institutions. According to Friedrich, the constitutions are the result of revolutions, as European and American history of the Enlightenment period shows. In post-war Europe the will for renewal was manifested, however, by means of a set of “negative revolutions motivated not so much by any positive enthusiasm for a presumably splendid future as by a negative distaste for a sordid past”. The concept of “negative revolutions” not only explains the democratic contents of the German and Italian Constitutions, the two defeated 2 countries, but also those of France and of other European countries. Therefore, one must acknowledge that the post war international order was built thanks to the will of the winning powers, on the basis of the principle of national sovereignty, mitigated by the spirit of pacific cooperation represented by the United Nations. Even Germany, like all the other European States, could consider itself a sovereign state. But it was a purely formal sovereignty, without substance. One must not forget that Germany in the immediate post war period did not have a currency, nor an army, nor the control of Ruhr. In 1951, it was only thanks to the European Payments Union that Germany managed to overcome a serious economic crisis and it was only thanks to the creation of the European Community that the so called Wirtschaftswunder happened; an economic miracle which should be considered European and not national. Nonetheless, despite the legal terminology of the nineteenth century with which we continue to judge the political situation, Germany (like all the other European states) cannot consider itself a sovereign state, if by sovereign we mean a state that has the necessary and sufficient powers to guarantee full independence to its citizens. The German mark was considered a strong currency, but it was so only because Germany could enjoy the advantages of European integration. Furthermore, Germany never had an independent defence, but only troupes within a military alliance, NATO, governed by the United States. When the German judges set themselves as champions of German sovereignty – the constitutional identity – what do they intend to defend? Free from the ideological prejudice of national sovereignty, the German constitutional judges could have appreciated the innovative features of European democracy in construction. The pure proportional representation, with which they expect to judge the democratic legitimacy of the political institutions, is only a technique used in some democratic states to achieve the objective of a representative government. Other systems consider stability just as important. For this reason the electoral systems of the USA and Great Britain use the electoral technique of “first-past-the-post”. It is well-known that, in these cases, a parliamentary majority which does not correspond to the majority of the voters may occur, and it has actually occurred. But since, by means of this electoral system, stable majorities of government can be guaranteed, English and American citizens are prepared to accept deviations from the principle of pure proportionality. In any case, it is true that in the case of the representation of “national” people there is a tendency to prefer the application of the proportional principle. Nevertheless, the European problem is different. In the European Union the problem consists in the construction of a “supranational democracy”, in which national people can participate in the formation of laws on an equal basis not only of citizens, but of national peoples. In federal systems this issue can be solved through bicameralism, with a chamber in which national peoples are represented and a chamber in which the citizens of the Union are represented, as a people of the European nations. The European Union is facing this challenge – which has never been dealt with by the existing federations, since they are all the expression of national people – by means of innovative solutions, which reconcile representative democracy with the defence of national identity. From this perspective, the European Parliament has accepted to mitigate pure proportionality, through the principle of digressive representation, in which the more populated national states accept the fact that even the smaller states can have a proportionally bigger number of members of Parliament, so that even the small countries can send representatives of all the internal political families to the European Parliament. On the other hand, even the Council of Ministers, in which the national states are represented, have mitigated the internationalist principle “one state, one vote”, accepting a “democratic” proportional amendment, with the criterion of decisions founded on the dual majority of the states and people. The Council of Ministers, contrary to what the German judges claim, has now become a second chamber of the Union at least as far as the approval of European legislation is concerned which takes place on the basis of “co-decision” between the Parliament and the Council. It can therefore be stated that the European Union is actually implementing a new type of democracy, a “supranational democracy” – this is as a matter of fact how the European Parliament has defined it – or, better, a federal democracy, thanks to 3 which all citizens and all national people of the Union can contribute, freely and equally, to the formation of a European political will. We must now consider the second issue, that of the possible political consequences of the doctrine devised in the ideological nucleus previously illustrated. It is a doctrine that signals a turning point in the history of European integration. The first European Community, the ECSC, was built as a first step towards a European Federation, as is stated in the Schuman Declaration. Nonetheless, the final objective of a Federation has been pursued using the method of economic integration which, in time, has made it inconceivable, and therefore impossible, for a new war among the countries of the European Union. Today, we can therefore state that the European Union is a “de facto federation”, if the essence of a federation consists in the member states renouncing war as a means for the solution of their controversies. However, from the Schuman Declaration until the present, a lot of water has flowed beneath the bridge: the Berlin Wall fell, the Cold War is over and the European Union has been enlarged to 27 countries. Moreover, no politician at the top of national politics, today, has directly experienced the tragedy of the Second World War. For the new generations, the problem of the pacification of Europe no longer represents the primary moral motivation for European construction. The European Union has to face new problems, such as economic globalisation, the international financial crisis, the threat of a planetary ecological crisis and international security, in an increasingly multipolar situation, with a declining role of the United States as a hegemonic power. After the failure of the project for a European Constitution, it is therefore understandable how in the Lisbon Treaty rules and principles have appeared allowing the German judges – and before them a great number of “realistic” academics, like Milward and Moravsic – to devise and make credible, for the European Union, the ambiguous concept of Staatenverbund, in other words a Union of national sovereign states. It is such a vague notion that it can be used to evaluate situations which are very different from the European Union, such as for example the League of Nations. It can, for instance, be claimed that the United States of America are a Union of sovereign States – the fifty member states which maintain all the “sovereign” powers that have not been given to the federal government – plus a federal government. It can just as well be said that the European Union is a Union of sovereign States plus a system of confused and not very democratic governance. Nonetheless, the substantial issue is not terminological. We must ask ourselves: what manoeuvring margins do European politicians want to exploit with this ambiguous notion? Is it really possible that Germany (or another important country like France) could leave the European Union? And with what consequences? In order to answer these questions, we can recall an important historical precedent: the doctrine of the “states’ rights” devised by John Calhoun, in the first half of the Nineteenth Century, in an American Federation still uncertain between union and division. The debate originally arose concerning the imposition of the protective duties to favour industrial development. These duties were favoured by the North, but opposed by the South. Calhoun asserted that the federal constitutional pact consisted in the voluntary giving up of powers of the member states – which remained sovereign – to the federal government. The federal government could not exert powers of the citizens of the Union that were not expressly provided for in the original pact. Each state could therefore, on the basis of its constitutional and political system, decide unilaterally to nullify federal legislation if the subject in question was controversial, something the South Carolina Convention actually did in 1832. In response, the federal government threatened the use of military force to make South Carolina reason. Finally, in 1833, President Jackson suggested a compromise and the dispute was solved peacefully. However, when in the following years the controversial problem concerned the abolition of slavery, a compromise between the North and South was not possible and the United States faced a bloody civil war. Calhoun’s doctrine of the states’ rights and of the power of nullification of federal laws became the ideological justification of the disintegration of the American Union. 4 The American case is significant even for contemporary Europe. Calhoun’s doctrine and the tragedy of the American civil war are discussed by Carl Schmitt in Verfassunglehre (1927). Schmitt rightly observes that in a federation “juridical and political antinomies” may appear and can lead to its break-up. “It is inadmissible – claims Schmitt – for the global existence of a federation to eliminate the particular existence of its member states or for the existence of the member states to eliminate that of the federation”. A conflict concerning sovereignty cannot be solved with a legal decision. It is an existential issue that first of all must be cut off politically. In essence, juridical and political antinomy can be overcome only if the member states and the federation agree on shared rules, which should implement “political homogeneity”, by means of a pact of permanent renouncement of the use of force and of secession. At this point only it makes sense to assign the task of solving the controversies between the member states and the federal government to a juridical organ, the supreme federal court. Schmitt’s comment is useful to understand the present difficulties of the European Union and the ways to overcome them. Unlike the United States of America in the first half of the nineteenth century, today the European Union does not have to face existential issues that could cause a conflict among the member states or between them and the federal government (which does not yet exist). It is difficult, if not impossible, for national government to convince European citizens that a war (for example between France and Germany) is a possible and sensible prospect. The true existential conflict Schmitt talks about is purely within the European political class and within its member states, in particular France and Germany. It is these two states which still have to decide how many powers should be assigned to the European Union to allow it to act, with a democratic and efficient government, in the world arena. This does not mean that the danger of the disintegration of the Union can manifest itself in different forms from a war. A Staatenverbund is an instable political construction. Germany, supported by France, is strongly tempted by the request of a national participation in the UN Security Council, as an alternative to European Union participation. France and Germany would like to create a directory (directoire) of strong countries, to become the spearhead of European foreign policy. It is an illusion. The entrance of Germany in the Security Council would be an explicit refusal of a common European foreign policy and, probably, the first step for German nuclear armament. This perspective would generate grudges and jealousy among the other Union countries. On the contrary, the experience of the single currency has shown that the German mark could be considered a strong currency in Europe, but that it has never been so strong as to become a world currency. Today, the euro is a world currency, an alternative to the dollar. Those who want an independent German foreign policy foster the illusion of a possible world German policy (a Weltpolitik). But Germany cannot become a global power. Only the European Union can today have the strength, if united, to speak on the same level with the great continental powers such as China, India, Brazil, besides the USA and Russia. To conclude, it is necessary to be grateful to the German judges for having raised with clarity a crucial problem for the future of the European Union. Their analysis allows the claim that a dual democratic deficit of the Union exists: a deficit of government responsibility (accountability) and a deficit of efficacy, when a decision is blocked by veto. The first deficit depends on the fact that the present powers of the European Union, which are considerable after the creation of the monetary Union and the approval of the Lisbon Treaty, are not managed by organs that are fully responsible before the citizens. The German judges’ statement of the lack of a clear relationship between voters, the European Parliament and a European government is fully justified and shared by the federalists. The second feature of the democratic deficit concerns, instead, the need to abolish the right of veto in the Council of Ministers, even as far as foreign policy and security are concerned as well as taxes which, though modestly (compared to national taxes), must be assigned to the Union to allow it to face the global economic challenges effectively. It is not true, and the German judges are not right on this point, that the abolition of the right of veto would jeopardise the identity of European nations. The German judges cannot accuse the European Union of not being democratic enough 5 and, contemporarily, stand up for the veto right in the Council. The political and cultural identity of European nations in the world of global interdependence will be more guaranteed if European countries will be able to act united in world politics. After the second world war began the process, which Friedrich describes as a negative revolution, by means of which the European national people have conquered new freedoms and new powers through progressive political unification which in daily routines has created a federal unity in many sectors of public life. Now the time has come to decide whether this “de facto federal unity” should also become a legal and political unity. The European Union needs a federal government and a Constitution. The political class and, in particular, the European citizens should make this decision. The judges, however, can contribute, with their opinions, to impeding or supporting this choice. Guido Montani Vice-President of the UEF August, 2009 6