* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Divine Injunction
Problem of religious language wikipedia , lookup
Meaning of life wikipedia , lookup
Existence of God wikipedia , lookup
Divine command theory wikipedia , lookup
Euthyphro dilemma wikipedia , lookup
Perennial philosophy wikipedia , lookup
Jewish existentialism wikipedia , lookup
DIVINE INJUNCTION This section deals with the existence of God and the usefulness of religious rules (in general) as moral guidelines. Material specific to the Judeo-Christian tradition and religious organizations as social institutions will be found in the chapter called The Church. Theism and atheism are the only two functional beliefs Peter A. Facione (prof. of philosophy, Calif. State Univ. at Fullerton), The Student’s Guide to Philosophy 1988, p. 133 “Try as you might, you cannot avoid the issue. For practical purposes, there are only two views: theism (I believe God exists) or atheism (I believe God does not exist). Agnosticism (I’m not sure whether God exists) comes to the same thing in terms of practical day-to-day living as either theism or atheism, in most cases atheism.” Humans do not have souls Daniel C. Dennett (Austin B. Fletcher Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Cognitive Studies at Tufts University), “How to Protect Human Dignity from Science,” in Human Dignity and Bioethics: Essays Commissioned by the President’s Council on Bioethics, 2008, p. 44 “People have immortal souls, according to tradition, and that is what makes them so special. Let me put the problem unequivocally: the traditional concept of the soul as an immaterial thinking thing, Descartes’s res cogitans, the internal locus in each human body of all suffering, and meaning, and decisions, both moral and immoral, has been utterly discredited. Science has banished the soul as firmly as it has banished mermaids, unicorns, and perpetual motion machines. There are no such things. There is no more scientific justification for believing in an immaterial immortal soul than there is for believing that each of your kidneys has a tap-dancing poltergeist living in it.” God exists UNIVERSAL BELIEF Religious faith is a constant in every human culture Anthony Layng (emeritus prof. of anthropology, Elmira College; adjunct professor of anthropology at Wake Forest University), “Religious Beliefs and their Consequences: A Comparative Perspective,” Skeptical Inquirer, March/April 2004, p. 47 “When defined as something that entails or presumes supernatural power, religion can be recognized in all cultures, past and present, indicating that such beliefs have played a role in the lives of people for a very long time. Identifying the supernatural dimensions of religious beliefs in tribal and industrial societies avoids any ethnocentric distinction between “true” religion (that which we believe) and superstition (that which we do not believe).” FIRST CAUSE The first cause argument demonstrates that God exists Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 239 The first cause argument for God’s existence: “The argument is briefly to the effect that we require a reason to account for the world, and the ultimate reason must be of such a kind as itself not to require a further reason to account for it. It is then argued that God is the only kind of being who could be conceived as self-sufficient and so as not requiring a cause beyond himself but being his own reason. The argument has Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager an appeal because we are inclined to demand a reason for things, and the notion of a first cause is the only alternative to the notion of an infinite regress, which is very difficult and seems even self-contradictory. Further, if any being is to be conceived as necessarily existing and so not needing a cause outside itself, it is most plausible to conceive God as occupying this position.” DESIGN The argument from design shows that God exists Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 242 Argument from design: “Suppose we saw pebbles on the shore arranged in such a way as to make an elaborate machine. It is theoretically possible that they might have come to occupy such positions by mere chance, but it fantastically unlikely, and we should feel no hesitation in jumping to the conclusion that they had been thus deposited not by the tide but by some intelligent agent. Yet the body of the simplest living creature is a more complex machine than the most complex ever devised by a human engineer.” God’s handiwork can be seen from the fact that the universe so well suits human existence Kenneth R. Miller (cell biologist, Brown Univ.), as quoted in “Seeing and Believing” by Jerry A. Coyne, The New Republic, February 4, 2009, p. 37 “The scientific insight that our very existence, through evolution, requires a universe of the very size, scale, and age that we see around us implies that the universe, in a certain sense, had us in mind from the very beginning ... If this universe was indeed primed for human life, then it is only fair to say, from a theist’s point of view, that each of us is the result of a thought of God, despite the existence of natural processes that gave rise to us.” [ellipsis in original text] ONTOLOGICAL PROOF The ontological argument is described John Allen Paulos (prof. of mathematics, Temple Univ.), Irrelegion: A Mathematician Explains Why the Arguments for God Just Don’t Add Up, 2008, p. 38 “Finally on to the more serious ontological argument for the existence of God, which is generally attributed to Anselm, Archbishop of Canterbury in the eleventh century. A very rough version of this argument defines God to be the greatest and most perfect possible being. It continues by assuming that this most perfect being must possess all the attributes of perfection. Since it’s better to exist than not to exist, existence is a characteristic of perfection. Hence and presto, God exists by definition.” Descartes bases his variation of the ontological argument on the concept of perfection John Allen Paulos (prof. of mathematics, Temple Univ.), Irrelegion: A Mathematician Explains Why the Arguments for God Just Don’t Add Up, 2008, p. 39-40 “Even the French philosopher Descartes subscribes to a version of the ontological argument. It derives from his conviction that he has an idea of God as a perfect being. This idea must have as a cause something external to him since he is not perfect. Therefore, Descartes concludes, the only possible cause for his having this idea is an external perfect being, God.” St. Anselm’s ontological proof demonstrates God’s existence Robert C. Solomon and Kathleen M. Higgins (both professors of philosophy, Univ. of Texas at Austin), A Short History of Philosophy, 1996, p. 143 “In his ontological proof, Anselm argues that the very definition of God implies His existence. God, according to Anselm, is ‘that than which none greater can be conceived.’ Even those who do not believe in God understand that this is what is meant by ‘God.’ God is by definition the most perfect conceivable being. What follow from this is that God, so understood, must exist. If God were a mere possibility, a glorious idea without a referent, God would not be the most perfect being that could be conceived. One could conceive of a still more perfect being, namely, one that shared all the perfections of the idea, but also existed. Once one Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager accepts the conception of God as the most perfect conceivable being, one is logically committed to the existence of God as well.” St. Anselm’s ontological proof was never meant to convince doubters Paul Vincent Spade (prof. of philosophy, Indiana Univ.), “Medieval Philosophy” in The Oxford History of Western Philosophy, ed. by Anthony Kenny, 1994, p. 77-78 “But two things should be noted about Anselm’s use of reasoning. First, he was not trying to prove the truths of theology as though they were otherwise subject to doubt. His purpose was not to shore up a faith that might otherwise falter, but rather simply to explore what he already firmly believed. His attitude is summed up near the beginning of the Proslogion in a famous statement: ‘I believe in order to understand (Credo ut intelligam). Second, Anselm did not think his appeal to reason excluded the realm of mystery in religion. In the Monologion, for example, he thinks he can prove that God is a Trinity of persons, but he does not think he can explain just how this works.” Refutations of the ontological proof don’t stand up under scrutiny Paul Vincent Spade (prof. of philosophy, Indiana Univ.), “Medieval Philosophy” in The Oxford History of Western Philosophy, ed. by Anthony Kenny, 1994, p. 79-80 “Finally, Anselm’s argument has frequently been rejected on the grounds that it illicitly moves from the realm of pure concepts (the ‘relations of ideas,’ as Hume called it) to the realm of actual existence (‘matters of fact’). And that, it is said, simply cannot be done; otherwise, one could infer the existences of all sorts of spurious things from the mere fact that one can conceive them. But this refutation is frivolous. It in no way follows from Anselm’s argument that one can infer the existence of just anything whatever from its mere concept. It only follows that one can do this in a certain special case, for the reasons given in the argument itself. Furthermore, it is not as if we can tell nothing at all about actual existence by examining concepts. One can correctly infer from the concept of a square circle, for example, that such a thing does not exist. Why should it be possible to infer the non-existence of things from their concepts, but not their existence? That would seem oddly asymmetric. In a word, this type of ‘refutation’ of the ontological argument seems nothing but a dogma that would try to refute the argument without actually taking the trouble to look at it.” The philosophical community has never refuted the ontological argument Anthony Kenny (Master, Balliol College, Oxford) in The Great Philosophers, edited by Bryan Magee, 1987, p. 70 “But the most interesting thing is that while a great many philosophers through history have thought there was something wrong with the ontological argument, they all give different reasons for saying that it goes wrong. Today there is no consensus about what is wrong with it; indeed, there isn’t any consensus that there is something wrong at all.” EXPERIENCE and INTUITION Religious experience demonstrates the existence of God Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 255 “The mere existence of religious emotion could hardly of itself constitute a valid ground for asserting the existence of God, but what is meant by the appeal to religious experience is usually the claim in states where this religious emotion is present to have a direct apprehension, not based on inference, of the existence and to some extent the nature of God.” Religious intuition is quite common Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 256 “This is a very common situation, I think, of as regards religious intuition. We must not suppose this intuition to be limited to a few great mystics: it is in some (though a much lesser) degree possessed by the plain man who says ‘I cannot prove, but I feel there is a God,’ when in saying this he is really sincere.” Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager Religious intuition has been quite common in human history Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 256 “Intuitive religious conviction has been so widespread and such a dominating factor in the thought of many, we might indeed say ‘most,’ who were in other respects obviously among the greatest and best of mankind, and so much the basis throughout history of a whole extraordinarily persistent, fertile, and fundamental side of life and thought as to constitute a strong prima facie case for the view that there is at least a great deal to it.” Religious intuition is just as viable as other strongly-held but unprovable beliefs Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 257 “Religious beliefs are after all only in the same position as other fundamental beliefs in not being strictly provable. By ‘fundamental beliefs’ I mean a belief presupposed by a whole important department of human thought. When we consider belief in memory, in an external world, in minds other than one’s own, in induction, in ethics, we are driven back to something which we either cannot prove at all or at least cannot prove in a way which wins general agreement among philosophers, yet we continue unflinchingly to hold the beliefs.” Religious intuition is as valid as other intuitions Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 258 “The main positive objections to the claims of religious intuition are made by dogmatic empiricists who assert that knowledge is limited to sense-experience, but as we have seen this dogma cannot be proved. There must be some intuition if there is to be inference at all, and there is no way of determining by a priori argument in what fields intuition is or is not possible.” Religious intuition is more than wishful thinking Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 260 “We may add that it is by no means such a simple task as might be thought to explain religion by a reference to wish-fulfillment. Religious beliefs are by no means always pleasant to the person who hold them or is on the verge of doing so. The acceptance of religious beliefs has often exposed those who adopted them to terrible persecutions, it has often intensified their sense of sin till this became agonizing, it has inspired the dread of hell. I do not wish for a moment to countenance the morbid exaggerated sense of sin or the belief in eternal hell which have been far too often prevalent in religious circles, but am merely citing these to show that we cannot explain religious conviction simply by the desire to believe what is pleasant, because the beliefs have often been acutely painful.” OTHER PROOFS Thomas Aquinas’s cosmological proofs demonstrates God’s existence Robert C. Solomon and Kathleen M. Higgins (both professors of philosophy, Univ. of Texas at Austin), A Short History of Philosophy, 1996, p. 146 “Thomas [Aquinas] famously provided his own proofs for the existence of God based on reason’s analysis of contingent beings (beings, in other words, that depend on something other than themselves to exist or behave as they do). In general, his arguments take the form of a cosmological proof, an inference from factual existence to ultimate explanation. For example, the motion of contingent things is causally dependent on other things that moved them. Believing, with Aristotle, that an infinite regress is unintelligible, Thomas was convinced that this realization would lead the mind to seek a first mover. This Prime Mover that the mind concludes must exist is God, according to Thomas. In each of his five proofs of God’s existence (also called his ‘five ways’), Thomas makes a similar move, concluding that the contingent being of things in the natural world depends on something that transcends them, namely, God.” Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager The existence of moral rules implies the existence of God Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 253 “Kant himself in a later work, and many other thinkers, have argued from the existence of the moral law to a lawgiver, God. This argument has also been used: The moral law is objective. In what, then, does it reside? Certainly not in the physical world. Nor only in the minds of men. An ethical proposition such that it is better to forgive one’s enemies than to hate them might be true even at a time when no human realized its truth at all. Yet it is impossible to see what else the moral law could reside in but a mind. Therefore we must postulate a super-human mind. Such arguments have the advantage, if valid, or directly establishing not only the existence but the perfect goodness of the supreme mind. A being in which the whole moral law resided could hardly fail to be perfectly good.” Descartes derives God’s existence as an implication of his own self-awareness Bryan Magee (UK television documentarian, former Member of Parliament, and former philosophy lecturer or visiting fellow at Yale, Harvard, Oxford, and Cambridge), Confessions of a Philosopher: A Journey through Western Philosophy, 1997, p. 92-93 “Descartes believed that from the contents of his own consciousness alone he could prove that there must be an infinite, omnipotent, and perfect being. He believed this because he thought that the greater could not be conceived by the less. Therefore I, a finite, weak, and imperfect being, would not be able by myself to form the clear concept of an infinite, omnipotent, and perfect God. The fact that I have this concept means that something corresponding to it must exist and must have given me an apprehension of itself.” [Reference is to René Descartes (1596-1650), French philosopher, scientist, and mathematician] Natural beauty demonstrates God’s existence Karl W. Giberson (prof. of physics, Eastern Nazarene College), as quoted in “Seeing and Believing” by Jerry A. Coyne, The New Republic, February 4, 2009, p. 40 “Why is [bird] song so pleasant to hear? Why, for example, does almost every scene of undeveloped nature seem so beautiful, from mountain lakes to rolling prairies? If the evolution of our species was driven entirely by survival considerations, then where did we get our rich sense of natural aesthetics?... There is an artistic character to nature that has always struck me as redundant from a purely scientific point of view.... I am attracted to the idea that God’s signature is not on the engineering marvels of the natural world, but rather on its marvelous creativity and aesthetic depth. Scientists are not supposed to talk about God this way, for it raises questions that can’t be answered.” [Brackets and ellipses in original text] God does not exist GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS The question of God’s existence may not be a question at all, just a misapplication of language Thomas Cathcart (social services worker and former philosophy teacher at Westbrook Junior College), and Daniel Klein (former philosophy student, Harvard; professional joke writer), Plato and a Platypus Walk Into a Bar: Understanding Philosophy Through Jokes, 2007, p. 130-131 “The ordinary language philosophers thought that the centuries-old philosophical struggle over belief in God grew out of trying to frame the question as one of fact. They said religious language is a different language altogether. Some said it is an evaluative language like the kind film critics Ebert and Roeper use: ‘I believe in God’ really only means ‘I believe certain values get two thumbs way up.’ Others said religious language expresses emotions: ‘I believe in God’ means, ‘When I ponder the universe, I get goosebumps!’ Neither of these alternative languages results in the philosophical muddles you get by saying ‘I believe in God.’ Poof! Puzzle resolved! And 2,500 years of the philosophy of religion down the tubes.” Belief in God may come from many motives, but truth is not one of them Bryan Magee (UK television documentarian, former Member of Parliament, and former philosophy lecturer or visiting fellow at Yale, Harvard, Oxford, and Cambridge), Confessions of a Philosopher: A Journey through Western Philosophy, 1997, p. 348 Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager “People hold religious beliefs for umpteen different kinds of reason: because they deep conviction of its truth, or because it provides a welcome explanation of their experience, or makes them feel better, of comforts them, or makes them members of a sympathetic social group, or because they imbibed it at a critical age — or for goodness knows how many other reasons; but from none of these does it follow that the belief is true. And although I have pressed the question often enough I have never received an answer that really is an answer. In the end it usually comes down to one thing: people want to believe. But this has nothing to do with truth. Something I have had occasion to say many times is that ignorance is not a license to believe what we like: it is ignorance, and renders believing what we like unjustified.” Scriptures cannot validate their own legitimacy John Allen Paulos (prof. of mathematics, Temple Univ.), Irrelegion: A Mathematician Explains Why the Arguments for God Just Don’t Add Up, 2008, p. 64 “Because proponents of the huff-and-puff argument repeat it incessantly, I’ll repeat that claiming that a holy book’s claims are undeniable because the book itself claims them to be convincing only to the convinced.” If God does not exist, then moral action becomes even more important for man Simone de Beauvoir (1908-1986; French existentialist philosopher, novelist, and dramatist); The Ethics of Ambiguity, 1964, p. 15-16 “Dostoievsky asserted, ‘If God does not exist, everything is permitted.’ Today’s believers use this formula for their own advantage. To re-establish man at the heart of his destiny is, they claim, to repudiate all ethics. However, far from God’s absence authorizing all license, the contrary is the case, because man is abandoned on the earth, because his acts are definitive, absolute engagements. He bears the responsibility for a world which is not the work of a strange power, but of himself, where his defeats are inscribed, but his victories as well. But if God does not exist, man’s faults are inexpiable.” FIRST CAUSE The first cause argument is flawed Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 239 The first cause argument for God’s existence: “Further, it may be doubted that whether we can apply to the world as a whole the causal principle which is valid within the world; and if we say that the causal principle thus applied is only analogous to the latter, the argument is weakened. Finally, and this I think the most telling point, it is exceedingly difficult to see how anything could be its own reason.” The First Cause argument cannot explain why God must be the first cause John Allen Paulos (prof. of mathematics, Temple Univ.), Irrelegion: A Mathematician Explains Why the Arguments for God Just Don’t Add Up, 2008, p. 4-5 First Cause argument: “The gaping hole in it is Assumption 1, which might be better formulated as: Either everything has a cause or there’s something that doesn’t .The first-cause argument collapses into this hole whichever tack we take. If everything has a cause, then God does, too, and there is no first cause. And if something doesn’t have a cause, it may as well be the physical world as God or a tortoise. Of someone who asserts that God is the uncaused first cause (and then preens that he’s really explained something), we should thus inquire, ‘Why cannot the physical world itself be taken to be the uncaused first cause?’ After all, the venerable principle of Occam’s razor advises us to ‘shave off’ unnecessary assumptions, and taking the world itself as the uncaused first cause has the great virtue of not introducing the unnecessary hypothesis of God.” God cannot be outside the world of phenomena John Allen Paulos (prof. of mathematics, Temple Univ.), Irrelegion: A Mathematician Explains Why the Arguments for God Just Don’t Add Up, 2008, p. 5-6 Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager “Furthermore, efforts by some to put God, the putative first cause, completely outside time and space give up entirely on the notion of cause, which is defined in terms of time. After all, A causes B only if A comes before B, and the first cause comes — surprise — first, before its consequences. (Placing God outside time and space would also preclude any sort of later divine intervention in worldly affairs). In fact, ordinary language breaks down when we contemplate these matters. The phrase ‘beginning of time,’ for example, can’t rely on the same presuppositions that ‘beginning of the movie’ can. Before a movie there’s popcorn-buying and coming attractions; there isn’t any popcorn-buying, coming attractions, or anything else before the universe.” DESIGN The argument from design relies on a slippery use of analogy Thomas Cathcart (social services worker and former philosophy teacher at Westbrook Junior College), and Daniel Klein (former philosophy student, Harvard; professional joke writer), Plato and a Platypus Walk Into a Bar: Understanding Philosophy Through Jokes, 2007, p. 36 “One use of the argument from analogy is found in response to the question of what or who created the universe. Some have argued that because the universe is like a clock, there must be a Clockmaker. As the eighteenth-century British empiricist David Hume pointed out, this is a slippery argument, because there is nothing that is really perfectly analogous to the universe as a whole, unless it’s another universe, so we shouldn’t really try to pass off anything that is just a part of this universe. Why a clock anyhow? Hume asks. Why not say the universe is analogous to a kangaroo. After all, both are organically interconnected systems. But the kangaroo analogy would lead to a very different conclusion about the universe: namely, that it was born of another universe after that universe had sex with a third universe. A fundamental problem with arguments from analogy is the assumption that, because some aspects of A are similar to B, other aspects of A are similar to B. It ain’t necessarily so.” The creator’s own complexity undermines the argument from design John Allen Paulos (prof. of mathematics, Temple Univ.), Irrelegion: A Mathematician Explains Why the Arguments for God Just Don’t Add Up, 2008, p. 12-13 “Creationists explain what they regard as the absurdly unlikely complexity of life-forms by postulating a creator. That this creator would have to be of vastly greater complexity and vastly more unlikely than the life-forms it created does not seem to bother them. Nonetheless, it’s only natural to ask the same question of the creator as one does of the alleged creations. Laying down a recursive card similar to that played with the first-cause argument, we ask about the origin of the creator’s complexity. How did it come about? Is there a whole hierarchy of creators, each created by higher-order creators and all except for the lowest, ours, creating lower-order ones?” ONTOLOGICAL PROOF The ontological argument implies the existence of all manner of perfect things John Allen Paulos (prof. of mathematics, Temple Univ.), Irrelegion: A Mathematician Explains Why the Arguments for God Just Don’t Add Up, 2008, p. 39 “As with some other alleged proofs for the existence of God, this one ‘proves’ too much. Even Gaunilo, one of Anselm’s contemporaries, notes this. Gaunilo asks us to imagine the most perfect island conceivable, the island than which no greater island can be conceived. The same argument as above now demonstrates that this most perfect island must exist.” EXPERIENCE and INTUITION Contradictions between believers make religious inspiration unreliable John Allen Paulos (prof. of mathematics, Temple Univ.), Irrelegion: A Mathematician Explains Why the Arguments for God Just Don’t Add Up, 2008, p. 77-78 Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager “A sighted person’s directions, for example, to take eleven steps and then to turn left for eight more steps to reach the door of the building can be checked by a blind person. How can an agnostic or atheist learn anything from someone who simply claims to know there is a God? Unlike the situation with sighted people, whose visions and directions are more or less the same, the ‘knowledge’ that different religious people and groups claim to possess is quite contradictory. Blind people might wonder about the worth of being sighted were different sighted people to give inconsistent directions to get to the door. Instead of the directions just mentioned, say a different sighted person directed someone to take four steps, turn left for seventeen more steps, and then right for six more steps to get to the door.” Religious epiphanies are insufficient to demonstrate the existence of God Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 255-256 Religious emotion: “It has, however, been objected that the assertion of an intuitive conviction can be of no help in a discussion on the ground that, if I have the conviction already, I do not need to be convinced of it, while if I do not have it, the mere statement of the fact that somebody else has it will be no ground for my accepting it apart from any argument he may give.” Religious intuition is inadequate as a proof of God’s existence Charles Larmore (W. Duncan MacMillan Family Professor in the Humanities, Brown University), “How Much Can We Stand?” The New Republic, April 8, 2008, p. 43 “We may hope that there is something more to things than is contained in the disenchanted picture of modern science. There may even be moments in our experience when we feel moved by what may be some deeper spiritual reality. (Weber himself might have acknowledged such a feeling if he had reflected on his own passionate devotion to truth.) But intimations are not an adequate basis for jumping to metaphysical or religious conclusions. They should be seen for what they are: inklings, no more. In such situations, leaping is precisely what we ought not to do.” SCIENCE Scientific advances make God an increasingly remote hypothesis Bart Kosko (philosopher; prof., Univ. of Southern Calif.), Fuzzy Thinking: The New Science of Fuzzy Logic, 1993, p. 277 “And where is God in all this? We see deeper and deeper into nature and we find no sign of him. NO EVIDENCE. No God in math. No God in fact. We have not seen or measured Him with microscope or telescope. He does not seem to be in the observable universe. And He seems to have left no footprints. We find only the smooth flow of events according to physical law.” Science and religion seem fundamentally incompatible Jerry A. Coyne (professor in Dept. of Ecology and Evolution, Univ. of Chicago), “Seeing and Believing,” The New Republic, February 4, 2009, p. 33 “True, there are religious scientists and Darwinian churchgoers. But this does not mean that faith and science are compatible, except in the trivial sense that both attitudes can be simultaneously embraced by a single human mind. (It is like saying that marriage and adultery are compatible because some married people are adulterers.) It is also true that some of the tensions disappear when the literal reading of the Bible is renounced, as it is by all but the most primitive of Judeo-Christian sensibilities. But tension remains. The real question is whether there is a philosophical incompatibility between religion and science. Does the empirical nature of science contradict the revelatory nature of faith? Are the gaps between them so great that the two institutions must be considered essentially antagonistic? The incessant stream of books dealing with this question suggests that the answer is not straightforward.” Science resolves questions, but religious questions are immune to the scientific method Jerry A. Coyne (professor in the Department of Ecology and Evolution at the University of Chicago), “Creationism for Liberals,” The New Republic, August 12, 2009, p. 42 Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager “On one hand we have Islam, Christianity, Judaism, Hinduism, and the whole panoply of faiths with their irresolvably conflicting claims, and on the other hand we have science, and only one brand of science. Independent scientific observers can decide whether electrons are real, but there is no way to decide whether Jesus was the Son of God or Muhammad was the Prophet.” God’s existence is immune to the key test of science, falsifiability Jerry A. Coyne (professor in Dept. of Ecology and Evolution, Univ. of Chicago), “Seeing and Believing,” The New Republic, February 4, 2009, p. 39 “Most scientists can tell you what observations would convince them of God’s existence, but I have never met a religious person who could tell me what would disprove it. And what could possibly convince people to abandon their belief that the deity is, as Giberson asserts, good, loving, and just? If the Holocaust cannot do it, then nothing will.” Strategies to reconcile science and religion only undermine religion Jerry A. Coyne (professor in Dept. of Ecology and Evolution, Univ. of Chicago), “Seeing and Believing,” The New Republic, February 4, 2009, p. 33 “Theologians sometimes suggest a reconciliation by means of naturalistic deism, the idea that the creation of the universe — and perhaps the laws of physics — was the direct handiwork of a deity who then left things alone as they unfolded, never interfering in nature or history again. For the faithful, this has been even more problematic than pantheism: it not only denies miracles, virgin births, answered prayers, and the entire cosmological apparatus of Christianity, Judaism, Islam, Hinduism, and much of Buddhism, but also raises the question of where God came from in the first place.” Presuming the existence of God has no positive effect on science Jerry A. Coyne (professor in Dept. of Ecology and Evolution, Univ. of Chicago), “Seeing and Believing,” The New Republic, February 4, 2009, p. 38 “There was a time when God was a part of science. Newton thought that his research on physics helped clarify God’s celestial plan. So did Linnaeus, the Swedish botanist who devised our current scheme for organizing species. But over centuries of research we have learned that the idea ‘God did it’ has never advanced our understanding of nature an iota, and that is why we abandoned it. In the early 1800s, the French mathematician Laplace presented Napoleon with a copy of his great five-volume work on the solar system, the Mechanique Celeste. Aware that the books contained no mention of God, Napoleon taunted him, ‘Monsieur Laplace, they tell me you have written this large book on the system of the universe, and have never even mentioned its Creator.’ Laplace answered, famously and brusquely: ‘Je n’avais pas besoin de cette hypothese-la,’ ‘I have had no need of that hypothesis.’ And scientists have not needed it since.” Scientific tests of religious claims have always failed to find evidence of God Jerry A. Coyne (professor in Dept. of Ecology and Evolution, Univ. of Chicago), “Seeing and Believing,” The New Republic, February 4, 2009, p. 39 “Many religious beliefs can be scientifically tested, at least in principle. Faith-based healing is particularly suited to these tests. Yet time after time it has failed them. After seeing the objects cast off by visitors to Lourdes, Anatole France is said to have remarked, ‘All those canes, braces and crutches, and not a single glass eye, wooden leg, or toupee!’ If God can cure cancer, why is He impotent before missing eyes and limbs? Recent scientific studies of intercessory prayer — when the sick do not know whether they are being prayed for — have not shown the slightest evidence that it works. Nor do we have scientifically rigorous demonstrations of miracles, despite the Vatican’s requirement that two miracles be proven for canonizing every saint. Holy relics, such as the Shroud of Turin, have turned out to be clever fakes. There is no corroborated evidence that anyone has spoken from beyond the grave.” Religion is in conflict with rationality, not merely with science Jerry A. Coyne (professor in Dept. of Ecology and Evolution, Univ. of Chicago), “Seeing and Believing,” The New Republic, February 4, 2009, p. 40-41 “With his usual flair, the physicist Richard Feynman characterized this difference: ‘Science is a way of trying not to fool yourself. The first principle is that you must not fool yourself, and you are the easiest person to fool.’ With religion, there is just no way to know if you are fooling yourself. So the most Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager important conflict — the one ignored by Giberson and Miller— is not between religion and science. It is between religion and secular reason. Secular reason includes science, but also embraces moral and political philosophy, mathematics, logic, history, journalism, and social science — every area that requires us to have good reasons for what we believe. Now I am not claiming that all faith is incompatible with science and secular reason — only those faiths whose claims about the nature of the universe flatly contradict scientific observations. Pantheism and some forms of Buddhism seem to pass the test. But the vast majority of the faithful — those 90 percent of Americans who believe in a personal God, most Muslims, Jews, and Hindus, and adherents to hundreds of other faiths — fall into the ‘incompatible’ category.” VARIOUS DISPROOFS The fact that there are no public miracles is indicative of God’s nonexistence Jerry A. Coyne (professor in Dept. of Ecology and Evolution, Univ. of Chicago), “Seeing and Believing,” The New Republic, February 4, 2009, p. 38 “There are so many phenomena that would raise the specter of God or other supernatural forces: faith healers could restore lost vision, the cancers of only good people could go into remission, the dead could return to life, we could find meaningful DNA sequences that could have been placed in our genome only by an intelligent agent, angels could appear in the sky. The fact that no such things have ever been scientifically documented gives us added confidence that we are right to stick with natural explanations for nature. And it explains why so many scientists, who have learned to disregard God as an explanation, have also discarded him as a possibility.” The existence of free will demonstrates that God does not exist Peter A. Facione (prof. of philosophy, Calif. State Univ. at Fullerton), The Student’s Guide to Philosophy 1988, p. 138 “God is all-knowing. As all-knowing, God knows the truth or falsehood of all statements. Statements about the future as well as the past or present. So God knows the future even before it happens. This implies that God knows what I will choose even before I choose it. Therefore, I am not free; I must choose what God knows I will choose. Given the fact that I am free, there can be no all-knowing God.” The misery of human life proves that the world was not created by a benevolent god Arthur Schopenhauer, German philosopher (1788-1860)], as quoted in The Consolations of Philosophy, by Alain de Botton, 2000, p. 172 “In my seventeeth year, without any learned school education, I was gripped by the misery of life as Buddha was in his youth when he saw sickness, old age, pain and death. The truth... was that this world could not have been the work of an all-loving Being, but rather that of a devil, who had brought creatures into existence in order to delight in the sight of their sufferings; to this the data pointed, and the belief that it is so won the upper hand.” [Ellipsis in original text] We cannot know whether God exists God cannot be disproved John Allen Paulos (prof. of mathematics, Temple Univ.), Irrelegion: A Mathematician Explains Why the Arguments for God Just Don’t Add Up, 2008, p. 41-42 “The above argument notwithstanding, there is no way to conclusively disprove the existence of God. The reason is a consequence of basic logic, but is not one from which theists can take much heart. In fact, existential statements, those asserting that there is a nonmathematical entity having a certain property (or a set of noncontradictory properties) can never be conclusively disproved. No matter how absurd the existence claims (there exists a dog who speaks perfect English out of its rear end), we can’t look everywhere and check everything in order to assert with absolute confidence that there’s no entity having the property.” Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager Religious rules are the foundation for moral rules God is the inspiration for the human moral sense Lewis B. Smedes (instructor in theology and ethics, Fuller Theological Seminary), Choices: Making Right Decisions in a Complex World 1986, p. 20 “We intuit the moral dimension in human life because we still have the sense for genuine humanity that God created us with.” Moral rules, having come from God, are meant for everyone Lewis B. Smedes (instructor in theology and ethics, Fuller Theological Seminary), Choices: Making Right Decisions in a Complex World 1986, p. 51 “Since moral rules come from the Creator of the human family, they are meant for everyone who belongs to that great family. They are not exclusive rules for special people. God’s moral rules are mirrors of how all his human creatures are meant to live. The point is of the essence. The Creator of humanity is not a tribal God and his rules are not tribal laws.” God is the foundation of love as morality Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 254 “If anything is evident in ethics, it is that love and benevolence are better than hate and indifference, and therefore we may be quite confident that a good God will love and concern Himself closely with the welfare of the beings dependent on him. The argument is: God is good, goodness entails love, therefore God loves.” Belief in God is the closest man has come to making the world understandable Alfred C. Ewing (Lecturer in Moral Science and Reader in Philosophy, Cambridge Univ.), The Fundamental Questions of Philosophy, 1962, p. 241 “Now theism cannot indeed completely rationalize the universe till it can show how God can be his own cause, or how it is that he cannot need a cause, and till it can also overcome the problem of evil completely, but it does come closer to rationalizing it than any other view. The usual modern philosophical views opposed to theism do not try to give any rational explanation of the world at all, but just take it as a brute fact not to be explained, and it must certainly be admitted that we come at least nearer to a rational explanation if we regard the course of the world as determined by purpose and value than if we do not.” God is not merely “good,” he is beyond goodness Paul Vincent Spade (prof. of philosophy, Indiana Univ.), “Medieval Philosophy” in The Oxford History of Western Philosophy, ed. by Anthony Kenny, 1994, p. 75 “For the Latin West, Pseudo-Dionysius is the proximate source of the familiar doctrine that there are three ways of speaking about God: (1) the via affirmativa, in which predicates are affirmed of God; (2) the via negativa, in which predicates are denied of him; and (3) the via eminentiae, which reconciles the first two ways and in which predicates are affirmed of God only with an indication of some kind of super-eminence. Thus (1) we may call God ‘good’ in so far as he is the source of all the goodness we find in creatures; but (2), if we wish to speak about God as he is in himself, not as he is related to creatures, we must deny all predicates of God, since he is not like any of the familiar things languages is used to describe. In that sense, then, God is not good, and in fact does not even exist! But the via negativa does not amount to outright atheism, as (3) shows. God in himself is not good and does not exist. But that does not mean that he is less than good or less than existing; rather, he is ‘super-good’ or ‘hyperexisting’ — more than good, more than a being.” Augustine places God at the peak of the moral hierarchy Paul Vincent Spade (prof. of philosophy, Indiana Univ.), “Medieval Philosophy” in The Oxford History of Western Philosophy, ed. by Anthony Kenny, 1994, p. 59 “In the best Platonic manner, Augustine views the world as hierarchically arranged. The principle of ordering is one of intrinsic value. Thus the better or more worthy something is, the higher it stands in the Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager hierarchy of things. God is at the top (like Plato’s form of the good), physical objects occupy a very low position, and human souls are somewhere in between, the souls of good people higher than those of wicked ones.” Christian ethics are consistent with other moral systems John Macquarrie (prof. of philosophy, Oxford Univ.), Three Issues in Ethics, 1970, p. 88 “Christianity, I wish to assert, is not a separate moral system, and its goals and values are not fundamentally different from those that all moral striving has in view.” God is a necessary check on the human impulse toward evil Charles Colson (former special counsel to President Nixon; founder and chairman, Prison Fellowship), “Can We Be Good Without God?” Imprimis, April 1993, p. 2 “In his classic novel, The Brothers Karamatzov, the 19th century Russian novelist Dostoyevsky asked essentially, ‘Can man be good without God?’ In every age, the answer has been no. Without a restraining influence on their nature, men will destroy themselves. That restraining influence might take many abstract forms, as it did for the Greeks and Romans, or it might be the God of the Old and New Testaments. But it has always served the same purpose.” Religion can be a profound socializing agent Phil Zuckerman (associate professor of sociology at Pitzer College), “The Virtues of Godlessness,” The Chronicle of Higher Education, Jan 30, 2009. “Here in the United States, for example, religious ideals often serve as a beneficial counterbalance against the cutthroat brand of individualism that can be so rampant and dominating. Religious congregations in America serve as community centers, counseling providers, and day-care sites. And a significant amount of research has shown that moderately religious Americans report greater subjective well-being and life satisfaction, greater marital satisfaction, better family cohesion, and fewer symptoms of depression than the nonreligious. Historically, a proliferation of religious devotion, faith in God, and reliance on the Bible has sometimes been a determining factor in establishing schools for children, creating universities, building hospitals for the sick and homes for the homeless, taking care of orphans and the elderly, resisting oppression, establishing law and order, and developing democracy.” Historically, philosophy has been bound closely with religious teachings Robert C. Solomon and Kathleen M. Higgins (both professors of philosophy, Univ. of Texas at Austin), A Short History of Philosophy, 1996, p. 15 “Similarly, one should carefully consider the relationship between religion and philosophy. Some of the ancient Greeks cautiously separated the two, but for most of the past two thousand years Western philosophy has been inseparable with the Judeo-Christian tradition, even in the case of those philosophers who spend their lives attacking that tradition. It is only in the past two hundred years that many American and some European philosophers have presupposed a separation, and in many other cultures, the identity of religion and philosophy remains entirely intact. In many societies, including most tribal cultures, the religion defines the philosophy.” Philosophy does not necessarily conflict with religion Robert C. Solomon and Kathleen M. Higgins (both professors of philosophy, Univ. of Texas at Austin), A Short History of Philosophy, 1996, p. 79 “The close identification of philosophy with science during certain periods has encouraged the sharp opposition of philosophy and religion, but it is worth remembering that many of the greatest scientists and mathematicians, Pythagoras and Isaac Newton, for example, refused to accept that opposition.” Religious rules do not serve well as moral rules Religious decrees are not subject to logical analysis Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager Pascal Boyer (Henry Luce Professor at Washington University), “Why Is Religion Natural?” Skeptical Inquirer, March/April 2004, p. 26 “Religious concepts are irrefutable. Most incorrect or incoherent claims are easily refuted by experience or logic, but religious concepts are different. They invariably describe processes and agents whose existence could never be verified and are subsequently not refuted. As there is no evidence against most religious claims, people have no obvious reason to stop believing them.” Claiming to know God’s will on an issue is no guarantee you’ll get it right Patricia S. Churchland (University of California President’s Professor and Chair of the Department of Philosophy at the University of California at San Diego), “Human Dignity from a Neurophilosophical Perspective,” in Human Dignity and Bioethics: Essays Commissioned by the President’s Council on Bioethics, 2008, p. 112 “There are plenty of other examples of religious condemnations of scientific technologies that have greatly benefited mankind, including contraceptive techniques, in vitro fertilization (which allegedly violates human dignity, division (dissection) of the dead body (Boniface VIII in 1300) and organ donation by living donors (Pope Pius XII, 1956), as well as religious blessings of such practices as female subjugation, slavery, forced conversions, and genital mutilation of females. Part of the point of these historical interludes is that claims to know what God wants are no guarantee against moral failure. Humility, whatever one’s religious inclinations or moral convictions, is surely appropriate.” Secular rules must govern, because religious questions can never be resolved Jonathan Chait (senior staff editor), “Pray Tell,” The New Republic, November 19, 2007, p. 5 “The depth of American religiosity is precisely why secularism is so important. Since religion is premised on faith, theological disputes cannot be settled through public reason. Even the most vicious public policy disputes get settled over time. (Americans now agree on slavery and greenback currency.) But we’re no closer to consensus on the divinity of Jesus than we were 200 years ago.” We accept the moral laws of religion only because they agree with our moral instincts Paul Kurtz (prof. of philosophy, State Univ. of New York), “Humanist Ethics: Eating the Forbidden Fruit,” Free Inquiry, Spring 1989, p. 26 “In the Old Testament, Abraham’s faith is tested when God commands him to sacrifice his only son, Isaac, whom he dearly loves. Abraham is fully prepared to obey, but at the last moment God stays his hand. Is it wrong for a father to kill his son? A developed moral conscience understands that it is. But is it wrong simply because Jehovah declares it to be wrong? No. I submit that there is an autonomous moral conscience that develops in human experience, grows out of our nature as social beings, and comprehends that murder is wrong, whether or not God declares it to be wrong. We should be highly suspicious of the moral development of one who believes that murder is wrong only because God says so. Indeed, I believe that we attributed this moral decree to God simply because we apprehended it to be wrong.” God cannot be our sole standard for measuring goodness Jerry A. Coyne (professor in the Department of Ecology and Evolution at the University of Chicago), “Creationism for Liberals,” The New Republic, August 12, 2009, p. 41 “But since the fourth century B.C.E., philosophers have shown convincingly that our considerations of what is moral or immoral cannot be derived from religion. In Plato’s Euthyphro, Socrates argues that the statement ‘God is good’ has meaning only if we have a standard of good that is independent of God. If it were otherwise, anything that God sanctioned would be good by definition. This would include, in the case of Abraham, the readiness to murder, and in the case of Jephthah the actual murder of, one’s children.” Acting morally without God is superior to those who act morally out of religious belief John Allen Paulos (prof. of mathematics, Temple Univ.), Irrelegion: A Mathematician Explains Why the Arguments for God Just Don’t Add Up, 2008, p. 140 “An atheist or agnostic who acts morally simply because it is the right thing to do is, in a sense, more moral than someone who is trying to avoid everlasting torment or, as is the case with martyrs, to achieve eternal bliss. He or she is making the moral choice without benefit of Pascal’s divine bribe. This choice is all the more impressive when an atheist or agnostic sacrifices his or her life, for example, to rescue a drowning Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager child, aware that there’ll be no heavenly reward for this lifesaving valor. The contrast with acts motivated by calculated expected value or uncalculated unexpected fear (or worse, fearlessness) is stark.” Natural moral intuitions supersede religious moral rules Pascal Boyer (Henry Luce Professor at Washington University), “Why Is Religion Natural?” Skeptical Inquirer, March/April 2004, p. 29 “Indeed, it is difficult to find evidence that religious teachings have any effect on people’s moral intuitions. Religious concepts do not change people’s moral intuitions but frame these intuitions in terms that make them easier to think about. For instance, in most human groups supernatural agents are thought to be interested parties in people’s interactions. Given this assumption, having the intuition that an action is wrong becomes having the expectation that a personalized agent disapproves of it. The social consequences of the latter way of representing the situation are much clearer to the agent, as they are handled by specialized mental systems for social interaction. This notion of gods and spirits as interested parties is far more salient in people’s moral inferences than the notion of these agents as moral legislators or moral exemplars. In the same way, the use of supernatural or religious explanations for misfortune may be a byproduct of a far more general tendency to see all salient occurrences in terms of social interaction. The ancestors can make you sick or ruin your plantations; God sends people various plagues.” Religious belief limits the human mind James Madison (fourth U.S. president, architect of the Constitution), letter to William Bradford, April 1, 1774; from The Madisons by Virginia Moore, 1979, p. 43 “Religious bondage shackles and debilitates the mind, and unfits it for every noble purpose.” The worshiper sets the limits of the religion Ralph Waldo Emerson (American transcendentalist philosopher, essayist, and poet, 1803-1882), “Worship” in Essays: The Conduct of Life, 1860, reprinted in The Works of Ralph Waldo Emerson, Black’s Readers Service: 1928, p. 379 “But the religion cannot rise above the state of the votary. Heaven always bears some proportion to earth. The god of the cannibals will be a cannibal, of the crusaders a crusader, and of the merchants a merchant.” Making God’s will the standard of ethics is too arbitrary Peter Singer (prof. of philosophy, Monash Univ., Australia), The Expanding Circle: Ethics and Sociobiology, 1981, p. x “If all values result from God’s will, what reason could God have for willing as he does? If killing is wrong only because God said: ‘Thou shalt not kill,’ God might just as easily have said: ‘Thou shalt kill.’ Would killing then have been right? To agree that it would have been right makes morality too arbitrary; but to deny that it would have been right is to assume that there are standards of right and wrong independent of God’s will. Nor can the dilemma be avoided by claiming that God is good, and so could not have willed us to kill unjustly — for to say that God is good already implies a standard of goodness that is independent of God’s decision. For this reason many religious thinkers now agree with the non-religious that the basis of ethics must be sought outside religion and independently of belief in God.” Religion makes truth a matter of geography Richard Dawkins (Professor of the Public Understanding of Science at the University of Oxford), “The Religion of Science,” from The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Delivered at Harvard University, November 19 and 20, 2003, p. 70; Online: www.tannerlectures.utah.edu/lectures/documents/volume25/dawkins_2005.pdf, accessed May 1, 2008 “One of the most striking features of religion is that it runs in families. This country, like my own, has many Christians and Jews. If we lived in Pakistan or India we’d be worshipping Allah or the Hindu pantheon of hundreds of gods. If we’d been brought up in ancient Greece, we’d be worshipping Zeus and Apollo. If Vikings, Wotan and Thor. Out of hundreds of possible religions, the vast majority of people just happen to end up in the same religion as their parents. And isn’t it a remarkable coincidence: whichever religion you are brought up in, it always turns out to be the right religion. We are all familiar with those maps of the world, colour-shaded to denote predominant language. Atlases use the same kind of colour-coding to designate predominant religion. Since religions hold contradictory beliefs about important truths, it is as if Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager those truths depended upon the geographical location of the believer. We have become so accustomed to this that it doesn’t seem strange.” Different religions promote very different ethical rules Joshua Halberstam (prof. of philosophy, New York Univ.), Everyday Ethics, 1993, p. 174 “Traditional Buddhism is atheistic, Hinduism has thousands of gods, and Manichaean religions see the world as a constant struggle between the force of good and the force of evil, with no supreme God to decide the battle. Animists and pantheists don’t view the gods or God as the creator of the universe but synonymous with it. These theological differences spill over into ethical ones. You can’t tell people to sacrifice their lives in the service of a god if they don’t believe in one. Buddhists do not postulate a god, but they certainly preach an ethics based on their understanding of the human condition. It isn’t the same ethics as Calvinism, of that you can be sure.” Even the three major Western religions are incompatible Joshua Halberstam (prof. of philosophy, New York Univ.), Everyday Ethics, 1993, p. 174-175 “The three major Western religions, in chronological order, are Judaism, Christianity, and Islam. These theistic religions not only believe that God exists and that He wants us to live our lives a certain way, but also that he’s already told us how to live our lives. When did God reveal His will? That depends on your religious persuasion. For Jews, God revealed His will when he gave the Torah to Moses at Mount Sinai; for Christians, God’s will is manifested in the life of Jesus; for Muslims, God’s will is found in the Koran as dictated to Muhammed in the cave. All three major Western religions share many values and oppose much of the teaching of Eastern religions — the fatalism and the caste system of Hinduism, for example. But you’ll also find significant differences between the Western religions themselves when you get down to specifics — and that’s where the action is, after all. The Catholic prohibition against divorce strikes Jews and Muslims as harsh, Islamic restrictions on women are abhorrent to non-Muslims, and many Christians and Muslims are offended by the tribal underpinnings of Jewish ethics.” It’s not clear religion is good at either explanation or moral guidance Richard Dawkins (Professor of the Public Understanding of Science at the University of Oxford), “The Religion of Science,” from The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Delivered at Harvard University, November 19 and 20, 2003, p. 64; Online: www.tannerlectures.utah.edu/lectures/documents/volume25/dawkins_2005.pdf, accessed May 1, 2008 “Theistic religions have traditionally offered answers to questions that today we hand over to science: questions of cosmology and biology, which are nowadays answered by, for example, the Big Bang theory and the theory of evolution. What has happened today is that sophisticated theologians wisely abandon explanation — which religion does badly — to science, which does it well. Instead, theology concentrates on topics like morality and guidance for life. Science doesn’t pretend to do morality, and it doesn’t do it well. It is by no means clear that religion does it well either. Indeed, I think a powerful case for the opposite can be made, but that is not my topic here.” Even religious leaders recognized that religious truths and moral rules are not the same Jerry A. Coyne (professor in the Department of Ecology and Evolution at the University of Chicago), “Creationism for Liberals,” The New Republic, August 12, 2009, p. 41 “The distinction between religion and morality was recognized by rational theologians in all the monotheistic faiths, even if their views did not always carry the day. Aquinas wrote that ‘right is not right because God wills it, but God wills it because it is right.’ If this is true, then we need to look elsewhere to determine what is right — and religion may be viewed not as the origin of morality, but a vehicle for conveying moral values or feelings that arise elsewhere.” Unlike other human endeavors, religion has failed the test of providing new answers Milton Rothman (prof. emeritus of physics, Trenton State College), “Realism and Religion,” Skeptic, Vol. 2 Number 2 (1993), p. 73 “In conclusion, the ironic fact is that religion has no ability to explain anything. While scientific discovery has increased exponentially during the past century, religious discovery has remained a flat zero. There have been important historical discoveries, but no improvements in explaining where the gods reside, how Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager they interact with man, where the gods lived before the universe was formed, and how they learned to create the universe. (I use the plural gods, because each religion has its own variety of god). Recent attempts to claim that a god caused the Big Bang really do not explain anything. They just push the unanswered questions back into the past.” There is a distinct division between religion and ethics Ralph Waldo Emerson (American transcendentalist philosopher, essayist, and poet, 1803-1882), Essay on Nature, 1836, reprinted in The Works of Ralph Waldo Emerson, Black’s Readers Service: 1928, p. 547 “Ethics and religion differ herein; that the one is the system of human duties commencing from man; the other, from God. Religion includes the personality of God; Ethics does not.” The history of religion shows lessening tolerance and flimsier ethics Jerry A. Coyne (professor in the Department of Ecology and Evolution at the University of Chicago), “Creationism for Liberals,” The New Republic, August 12, 2009, p. 40 “One can in fact make a good case that, contrary to Wright’s claim, ethics went downhill as religion evolved — specifically, that it declined in the transition from polytheism to monotheism. Hume insisted upon this, expounding admiringly on ‘the tolerating spirit of idolaters.’ He maintained that a plurality of gods led to social and intellectual pluralism, whereas the belief in a single god led to exclusiveness and intolerance. ‘The intolerance of almost all religions, which have maintained the unity of God, is as remarkable as the contrary principle of polytheism,’ he wrote in The Natural History of Religion. And he added pungently that ‘if, among Christians, the English and Dutch have embraced the principles of toleration, this singularity has proceeded from the steady resolution of the civil magistrate, in opposition to the continued efforts of priests and bigots.’ This is sound intellectual and religious history, belying Wright’s view of theology’s linear march toward goodness and light.” Religious scriptures promote actions we would consider deeply immoral John Hartung (social science and medical writer; assoc. prof. of anesthesiology, State Univ. of New York), “Love Thy Neighbor: The Evolution of In-Group Morality,” Skeptic, vol. 3, no. 4, 1995, p. 96 “There is a stark contradiction between abhorring genocide and paying homage to a god who commanded his followers to commit genocide. There is a deep structural discrepancy between outrage over persecution of people because of their religious beliefs and simultaneous reverence for scriptures that condemn non-coreligionists to death and damn them to hell.” Moral progress occurs despite religion, rather than because of religion Jerry A. Coyne (professor in the Department of Ecology and Evolution at the University of Chicago), “Creationism for Liberals,” The New Republic, August 12, 2009, p. 41 “Finally, consider what most of us agree are real improvements in ethics over the last several centuries: the idea of democracy; the elimination of more horrible punishments; the adoption of equal rights for racial and ethnic minorities, homosexuals, and women; the disappearance of slavery; the improved treatment of animals; and the increasing view that adult sexuality is a private matter. In each case, the impetus for change came overwhelmingly from secular views. Religion either played no role, or it played a small role, or it opposed the moral innovations, or it came aboard only when change was underway. (It is true that the American civil rights movement was supported by many churches, but we should also recall that in earlier times the faithful cited the Bible as support for slavery.) If a part of the world has improved morally, this change may have occurred not because of religion, but in spite of it.” Religion is not a prerequisite for morality John Macquarrie (prof. of philosophy, Oxford Univ.), Three Issues in Ethics, 1970, p. 97 “I believe that there is a connection between religion and morality, and that this connection is intrinsic and important. However, we must look for a way of interpreting it which will not do violence to the integrity of either religion or morality, and will not impugn the undoubtable achievements of secular morality. It can never be a question of subordinating religion to morality, or the other way around: nor can there be any question of claiming that morality is dependent on religious faith, in view of the plain fact that many nonreligious people are highly moral.” Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager Atheists are just as moral as believers Jerry A. Coyne (professor in the Department of Ecology and Evolution at the University of Chicago), “Creationism for Liberals,” The New Republic, August 12, 2009, p. 41 “If religion promotes morality, moreover, we can confidently predict that atheists will be less moral than believers. But the prediction fails. Consider a statistic: atheists constitute roughly 10 percent of the American population, but only 0.2 percent of our prison population. Now there are confounding factors, such as socio-economic status, at work here, but these data are clearly in the wrong direction. And consider that atheistic Europe, rather than being a hotbed of barbarism and immorality, is at least as moral as America. In his book Society Without God, the sociologist Phillip Zuckerman shows that Sweden and Denmark, two of the most atheistic countries in the world, are also two of the most moral, at least in terms of their lack of crime, high levels of government aid for the disadvantaged, and large amounts of per capita aid to other countries. There is certainly no evidence that many atheists have a qualitatively different type of morality than many believers. A survey by the biologist Marc Hauser and the philosopher Peter Singer showed that believers of many faiths did not differ from one another, or from atheists, in how they resolved hypothetical moral dilemmas.” Nations with high numbers of atheists seem to be just as moral as ‘godly’ nations Phil Zuckerman (associate professor of sociology at Pitzer College), “The Virtues of Godlessness,” The Chronicle of Higher Education, Jan 30, 2009. “Many people assume that religion is what keeps people moral, that a society without God would be hell on earth: rampant with immorality, full of evil, and teeming with depravity. But that doesn’t seem to be the case for Scandinavians in those two countries [Denmark and Sweden]. Although they may have relatively high rates of petty crime and burglary, and although these crime rates have been on the rise in recent decades, their overall rates of violent crime — including murder, aggravated assault, and rape — are among the lowest on earth. Yet the majority of Danes and Swedes do not believe that God is ‘up there,’ keeping diligent tabs on their behavior, slating the good for heaven and the wicked for hell. Most Danes and Swedes don’t believe that sin permeates the world, and that only Jesus, the Son of God, who died for their sins, can serve as a remedy. In fact, most Danes and Swedes don’t even believe in the notion of ‘sin.’ So the typical Dane or Swede doesn’t believe all that much in God. And simultaneously, they don’t commit much murder. But aren’t they a dour, depressed lot, all the same? Not according to Ruut Veenhoven, professor emeritus of social conditions for human happiness at Erasmus University Rotterdam. Veenhoven is a leading authority on worldwide levels of happiness from country to country. He recently ranked 91 nations on an international happiness scale, basing his research on cumulative scores from numerous worldwide surveys. According to his calculations, the country that leads the globe — ranking No. 1 in terms of its residents’ overall level of happiness — is little, peaceful, and relatively godless Denmark.” Justice does not depend on the will of God John Macquarrie (prof. of philosophy, Oxford Univ.), Three Issues in Ethics, 1970, p. 100 “Men have sometimes complained that God is unjust to them. Their complaints may have been unfounded, but it is interesting that such complaints can even be made, for it implies that those who make them do not identify justice with what God wills. Justice is such an ultimate notion that it cannot depend even on the will of God. That does not mean that it is more ultimate than God, but rather that it is not external or subsequent to God, for it belongs to his very being or nature.” It’s a cheap tactic to presume to dictate behavior according to ‘God’s will’ John Macquarrie (prof. of philosophy, Oxford Univ.), Three Issues in Ethics, 1970, p. 101 “In any case, it would be hard to imagine a more abused phrase than ‘the will of God.’ People have committed all kinds of wickedness and folly in the belief that they were carrying out the will of God. In milder but no less objectionable ways, they still pressure other people into adopting their policies by representing their own idiosyncrasies as God’s will which it would be wrong to disobey — a favorite tactic in ecclesiastical debates.” The reward-and-punishment framework of religion makes it a poor grounding for morality Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager Daniel C. Dennett (Director, Tufts Univ. Center for Cognitive Studies), “Consciousness Revisited,” Free Inquiry, Fall 1995, p. 20 “Nietzsche was wonderfully scornful of the vision of Christianity that made morality depend upon pie in the sky: that is, be a good boy or girl now and in heaven you’ll get your reward. On the face of it, this is an ignoble foundation for morality. It concedes the selfishness of the agent. It abandons the hope of an agent’s conceiving of his or her own acts as worthy in their own right, independent of any reward. The idea that a reward in heaven or a punishment in hell is a necessary foundation for morality is a deeply pessimistic, almost nihilistic idea. And yet, of course, there it is, enshrined in many aspects of the Judeo-Christian and Islamic traditions.” Belief in God opens up the option to sin deliberately Simone de Beauvoir (1908-1986; French existentialist philosopher, novelist, and dramatist); The Ethics of Ambiguity, 1964, p. 16 “The believer is also free to sin. The divine law is imposed upon him only from the moment he decides to save his soul. In the Christian religion, though one speaks very little about them today, there are also the damned.” Religion can be toxic to society Phil Zuckerman (associate professor of sociology at Pitzer College), “The Virtues of Godlessness,” The Chronicle of Higher Education, Jan 30, 2009. “In other instances, however, religion may not have such positive societal effects. It can often be one of the main sources of tension, violence, poverty, oppression, inequality, and disorder in a given society. A quick perusal of the state of the world will reveal that widespread faith in God or strong religious sentiment in a given country does not necessarily ensure societal health. After all, many of the most religious and faithful nations on earth are simultaneously among the most dangerous and destitute. Conversely, a widespread lack of faith in God or very low levels of religiosity in a given country does not necessarily spell societal ruin. The fact is, the majority of the most irreligious democracies are among the most prosperous and successful nations on earth.” Prager’s LD Vault: Divine Injunction · Revised July 2010 · © 2010 John R. Prager