Download ENGLISH FOR RELIGIOUS STUDIES

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Fideism wikipedia , lookup

Jewish existentialism wikipedia , lookup

Christian deism wikipedia , lookup

Feminist theology wikipedia , lookup

History of Christian theology wikipedia , lookup

Re-Imagining wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
English for Religious Studies
ENGLISH FOR RELIGIOUS STUDIES
Edmund Ryden SJ
September 2008 – June 2009 Temporary schedule. Dates correct except for 4 May
which is ambiguous in university calendar.
Purpose: To enable students to consult material in English in the field of religious
studies, with a focus on four areas: comparative religion, Buddhism, Christianity and
Daoism. The course will involve reading key texts in English from the religions and
also in reading articles about the said religions. To help learning to read there will also
be demands on writing English, however the course will not teach conversation or
listening.
Assessment: By final exam at the end of each semester. Students will also be expected
to prepare each week’s reading before class and will be examined on their preparation.
Semester 1: Buddhism & Comparative Religion
BUDDHISM
1 15 Sept
An introduction to English grammar and etymology
2
2 22 Sept
Buddhist terminology: Sanskrit and Pali
4
3 29 Sept
A Buddha’s Qualification for Teaching (The Lohicca Sutta) 6
4 06 Oct
The Recorded Conversations of Zen Master Yi Xuan
9
5 13 Oct
Dadosky, Merton and Zen
12
6 20 Oct
Dadosky, Christian-Buddhist Dialogue
15
7 27 Oct
Takemura, Zen Enlightenment 1
18
8 3 Nov
Takemura, Zen Enlightenment 2
21
COMPARATIVE RELIGION
9 10 Nov
Angelo Amato, “Christian Truth spreads by Conviction”
24
10 17 Nov
Pope Benedict XVI, “Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite”
27
11 24 Nov
Hugo Meynell, “A Letter to Professor Dawkins”
30
12 1 Dec
David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order, Ch. 3.1 Experience and language
13 15 Dec
David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order, Ch. 3.2 Two Sources of Theology
14 22 Dec
David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order, Ch. 3.3 Phenomenology
15 29 Dec
David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order, Ch. 3.4 Hermeneutics
16 5 Jan
David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order, Ch. 3.5 Transcendental Method
Exam 12 Jan
1
English for Religious Studies
1 AN INTRODUCTION TO ENGLISH GRAMMAR AND ETYMOLOGY
Grammar
English grammar is best when it is simple. The basic construction is Subject-VerbObject.
Mary loves Peter. (S-V-O)
Only in imperative sentences (orders, eg. Come!, Go!), is the subject omitted.
Every verb must have a subject.
*loves Peter (*=incorrect grammar): Mary loves Peter.
The word which marks the subject of a verb can never be the object of another verb.
*Mary loves Peter loves cats. : Mary loves Peter, who loves cats.
Active, transitive verbs have a direct object.
Mary loves Peter. (S-V-O)
Intransitive verbs have no object.
Mary dreams. (S-V)
The verb ‘to be’ has a complement.
Mary is pretty. (S-V-C)
Sentences may be joined together in various ways giving rise to Main Clauses and
Subordinate Clauses. Each clause has its own subject, verb and (when necessary)
object or complement.
Main clause
S
V
O
Mary loves Peter,
Subordinate Clause
S
V
O
who loves cats.
Main clause
Subordinate Clause1
Clause2
S
V
C
S
V
Life is not only a fight for survival,
where one part only wins
Subordinate
S
V
if the other part
loses.
Main Clause
S
V
C
The encounter of faith with scientific discovery is not a new experience for the church.
A phrase does not have a verb but it can have a noun formed from a verb (often
ending in –ing) and this verbal noun can have an object, eg more and more intelligent
babies is the object of the verbal noun ‘producing’ but altogether the phrase describes
‘price’ and so is part of the subject of the main verb ‘was’:
The price of producing more and more intelligent babies was (and is) the pain of
squeezing their heads through a birth canal that leads, for historical reasons, through
a rigid pelvis.
2
English for Religious Studies
English is a Germanic language that has been heavily influenced by Romance (French
and Latin) languages. There are also traces of Celtic and Nordic languages. English
also borrows many new words from all over the world, including from Taiwanese: tea.
Germanic words express the simple ideas:
The cat came into the house.
Romance (Latin words that come via French) words express more high class ideas:
The student entered the university.
Words borrowed into English directly from Latin and Greek are used only for abstract
ideas eg
The thoughts of the wise gladden the heart. (All Germanic words).
The reflections of the sages are a delight for the spirit. (French words in italics).
The cogitations of the philosophers are ambrosia for the psyche. (Greek and Latin
words.)
These three sentences all mean exactly the same thing. The first is the easiest to
understand; the second is not too difficult, but the third is very difficult. Therefore,
when writing English try always to use Germanic words. Unfortunately, many
religious books like to use Greek and Latin, which makes them much more difficult to
understand.
Here is an example of a theological text and below is a translation into Germanic
English:
The temporary estrangement between the sciences and theology is now over. It
began when the sciences emancipated themselves from cosmology and reduced it to
a personal belief in the divinity as Creator. The two disciplines established their own
identities on either side of accepted demarcation lines and achieved a peaceful
coexistence based on mutual irrelevance.
The brief hostility between the sciences and theology is now over. It began when the
sciences freed themselves from cosmology and reduced it to a personal belief in God
as Creator. The two fields of learning grounded themselves on either side of accepted
borders and stayed peacefully side by side whilst not bothering about each other.
The words in italics are difficult to replace with Germanic words. The Germanic text
is much easier to understand. However, it perhaps goes too far in cutting out all
romance words. English still likes to use some romance words for abstract ideas.
Nordic words are also Germanic but sometimes differ. They also express everyday
ideas often of a violent nature: die, start, stare.
Eg 開始 in English=commencement (French), beginning (German), start (Norse)
Please use a dictionary that indicates the etymology of a word.
Germanic words: Anglo-Saxon (AS), Old English (OE), Middle English (ME)
Germanic words from Old Norse (ON) are found in Middle English or in AngloSaxon
Romance words may come in via Middle English, or later from French or Latin.
3
English for Religious Studies
2 BUDDHIST TERMINOLOGY: SANSKRIT AND PALI
Chinese
Sanskrit
Pali
English
Siddhartha
Name of Gautama Buddha
悉達多
The sage of the Sakya Clan
釋迦牟尼 Sakyamuni
Tathāgata
Thus come OR Thus gone
如來
Buddhism
佛教
Bhiksu
Bhikkhu
Buddhist monk
比丘
Bhiksuni
Bhikkhunī
Buddhist nun
Sramana
Buddhist monk, ascetic
沙門
Buddha, Dharma, Samgha
Three Jewels
三寶
Dukkha
Suffering
Dukkha-dukkha
Physical and mental suffering
Viparināma-dukkha
Suffering produced by change
Samkhāra-dukkha
Suffering
produced
by
contingencies
5 khandas
5 aggregates
Rūpa
Form
Vedanā
Sensations
Sannā
Perceptions
Samkhāra
Mental formations
vinnāna
Consciousness
Anattā / Anātmavāda Non-susbstance / doctrine of no
soul
Anicca
Impermanence
Samudaya
Arising
Pratiya samutpāda Paticcasamuppāda Nexus of conditioned origination
Avidyā
Avijjā
Ignorance
Samkhāra
Volitional activities
Nāma-rūpa
Name and form
Trsnā
Tanhā
Thirst
Upādāna
Clinging
Bhava
Becoming
Jāti
Birth
Jarā-marana
Decay,death, lamentation
Nirodha
Cessation
Ariya-Atthangika Magga
The Noble Eightfold Path
Sammā ditthi
Right understanding
Sammā sankappa Right thought
Sammā vācā
Right speech
Sammā kammanta Right action
Sammā ājīva
Right living
Sammā vāyāma
Right effort
Sammā sati
Right mindfulness
Sammā samādhi
Right concentration / meditation
Pannā
Wisdom
Sīlā
Morality
Stupa
Pagoda (Tibetan: dagoba)
塔
Ānanda
Disciple of Sakyamuni Buddha
阿難陀
Kāsyapa
Kāssapa
Disciple of Sakyamuni Buddha
迦葉波
4
English for Religious Studies
Mahāyāna
大乘
Hinayāna
小乘
Dhyana
禪那
禪宗
Tantrayana
密宗
淨土宗
西方淨土
蓮花宗
法華經,妙法蓮花經 Saddharma-pundarikasutra
阿彌陀佛 Amitabha
菩堤薩埵
Bodhisattva
阿羅漢
觀音菩薩
Arhat
Avalokitesvara
蓮花手
文殊菩薩
維摩詰
普賢菩薩
Padmapani
Manjusri
Vimalakirti
Samantabhadra
地藏菩薩
菩提達摩
涅槃
彌勒佛
手印
施無畏
與願
轉法輪
尋
觸地
Ksitigarbha
Bodhidharma
Nirvana
Maitreya
Mudrā
Abhaya
Vara
Dharmacakrapravatana
Dharmadhatudhyana
Vitarka
Bhumisparsa
合掌
Anjali
菩提樹
本生
曼荼羅
空
Bodhi
Jataka
Mandala
Sunyā
法界定
Great Vehicle OR Greater Vehicle
Little Vehicle OR Lesser Vehicle
Meditation
Zen School (also Chan School)
Esoteric Buddhism
Pure Land Sect
Pure Land of the West
Lotus Sect = Pure Land Sect
Lotus Sutra
Buddha
of
Immeasurable
Splendour
One who vows to save all sentient
beings
Buddhist saint (Hinayana)
The Bodhisattva who hears the
cries
The Jewel in the Lotus = Guanyin
Bodhisattva of Wisdom (on a lion)
Bodhisattva
of
Benevolence
(elephant)
Bodhisattva who frees from hell
First Patriarch of Zen School
Blowing-out
Future Buddha
Position of the hand:
Assurance from fear (hands lifted)
Bestowing (Hand dropped, open)
Turning the wheel of the law
(Hands touching)
Meditation (Hands open on lap)
Nibbana
Inquiry (Thumbs touching)
Touching earth (arm pointing
down)
Adoration (Hands joined in
prayer)
The bodhi tree
Story about earlier Buddhas
Mandala
Empty
NB: Sanskrit and Pali names are not necessarily accurately transcribed.
5
English for Religious Studies
3 A Buddha’s Qualification for Teaching (The Lohicca Sutta)
There are three sorts of teachers in the world, Lohicca, who are worthy of
blame. And whoever blames such teachers would be justified in doing so for his
rebuke would be in accord with the facts and the truth. What are the three?
In the first place, Lohicca, there is the teacher who has not himself attained the
aim of becoming a samanna, in pursuit of which he left home and adopted the
homeless life. Without himself having attained to it he teaches a doctrine to his
hearers, saying, “This is good for you, this will make you happy.” The those hearers
of his do not listen to him, they pay no attention to his words, and they are in no way
changed by what they hear; they go their own way, regardless of his teaching. Such a
teacher is open to the criticism of being like a man who continually makes advances
to a woman who keeps repulsing him, or who embraces a woman who keeps turning
her face away from him. To go on posing as a teacher of men, when no one heeds,
since they do not trust you, that is, in the same way, a matter of greed. For what, then,
can one man do for another?
This, Lohicca, is the first sort of teacher in the world worthy of blame. And
whoever blames such a teacher would be justified in doing so for his rebuke would be
in accord with the facts and the truth.
In the second place, Lohicca, there is a sort of teacher who has not attained his
aim of becoming a samanna, in the pursuit of which he left home and adopted the
homeless life. Without having himself attained to it he teaches a doctrine to his
hearers, saying, “This is good for you, this will make you happy.” His disciples listen
to him; they pay attention to his words; they become strengthened by their
understanding and they never depart from the teaching of the master, or follow their
own way. Such a teacher may be criticized for being like a man who, neglecting his
own field, is concerned to weed his neighbour’s field. To go on teaching others when
you have not taught yourself, that too is a matter of greed. For what, then, can one
man do for another?
This, Lohicca, is the second sort of teacher in the world worthy of blame. And
whoever blames such a teacher would be justified in doing so for his rebuke would be
in accord with the facts and the truth.
And again, Lohicca, in the third place, there is a sort of teacher who has
himself attained the aim of becoming a samanna, in the pursuit of which he left home
6
English for Religious Studies
and adopted the homeless life. Having attained it, he teaches the doctrine to his
hearers, saying, “This is for your good for you, this will make you happy.” But those
hearers of his neither listen to him, nor pay attention to his words, nor are they
strengthened through their understanding of his doctrine; they go their own way, apart
from the teaching of the master. Such a teacher may indeed be criticized for being like
a man who, having broken through an old bond, entangles himself in a new one. To
go on teaching when you have not trained yourself to teach, that is a matter of greed.
For what, then, can one man do for another?
This, Lohicca, is the third sort of teacher in the world worthy of blame. And
whoever blames such a teacher would be justified, in accord with the facts and the
truth. These, Lohicca, are the three sorts of teachers of which I spoke.”
And when he had thus spoken, Lohicca the Brahman said to the Master, “But
is there, Gotama, any sort of teacher not worthy of blame in the world?” “Yes,
Lohicca, there is a teacher not worthy of blame.” “And what sort of a teacher, Gotama,
is that?”
Suppose there appears in the world a Tathāgata, an arahat, a fully awakened
one, complete in wisdom and goodness, happy, one who knows all worlds,
incomparable as a guide to those who are willing to be led, a teacher for gods and
mortals, a revered Master, a Buddha. From his own experience he knows and sees this
universe, including the upper worlds of the gods, the Brahmas and the Maras, and the
lower world with its ascetics and brahmans, its princes and peoples—and having
understood it he makes his knowledge known to others. He teaches the Truth he
knows, beautiful in its origin, beautiful in its progress, beautiful in its fulfilment. He
teaches it both in the spirit and in the letter; he makes known the higher life in all its
fullness and all its purity.
A householder, or one of his children, or someone of lesser status, hearing that
Truth, trusts the Tathāgata, and having such confidence in what he has heard, reasons
within himself as follows: “The life of a householder is full of hindrances; it is a dusty,
defiling path to tread. The homeless wanderer lives an uncluttered life. It is difficult
for the householder to live the higher life in all its fullness, in all its purity, in all its
perfection. So let me shave off my hair and beard, and put on the yellow robes and
leave the household life and become a homeless wanderer. Then, before long,
forsaking his share of wealth, whether great or small, and forsaking his circle of
7
English for Religious Studies
relatives, whether many or few, he cuts off his hair and beard, puts on the yellow
robes and leaves household life for that of the homeless wanderer.
When he has thus become an ascetic he lives by the rule of life proper to an
ascetic. Scrupulous in matters of behaviour and food, realizing the danger which lies
in the avoidance of small faults, he adopts certain principles of good bodily action and
speech. He leads a wholesome life, observing fully the moral precepts; he guards the
door of his senses; he is alert and self-aware, and rich in contentment.
The bhikkhu holds himself aloof from causing injury to seeds, or plants. He
takes but one meal a day, not eating at night, refraining from food after midday. He
refrains from being a spectator at shows at fairs, with nautch dances, singing and
music. He abstains from wearing, adorning or ornamenting himself with garlands,
scents and ungents. He abstains from the use of large and lofty beds. He abstains from
accepting silver or gold. He abstains from accepting uncooked grain. He abstains from
accepting raw meat. He abstains from accepting women or girls. He abstains from
accepting bondmen or bondswomen. He abstains from accepting sheep and goats. He
abstains from accepting fowls or swine. He abstains from accepting elephants, cattle,
horses and mares. He abstains from accepting cultivated fields or waste. He abstains
from acting as a go-between or messenger. He abstains from buying or selling. He
abstains from cheating with scales or coins or measures. He abstains from the crooked
ways of bribery, cheating and fraud. He abstains from maiming, murder, putting in
bonds, highway robbery, dacoity and violence.
When the Master had thus spoken, Lohicca the Brahman said, “Gotama, it is
just as if a man had caught hold another man, falling over the precipitous edge of
purgatory, by the hair of his head, and had lifted him up safe back onto the firm
land—just so have I, on the point of falling into purgatory, been lifted back onto the
land by the venerable Gotama. Most excellent, Gotama, are your words, most
excellent! Just as if a man were to set up what has been thrown away, or were to
reveal what has been hidden away, or were to point out the right road to him who has
gone astray, or were to bring a light into the darkness so that those who had eyes
could see external forms—just even so has the Truth been made known to me, in
many a figure, by the venerable Gotama. And I, even I, betake myself to the venerable
Gotama as my guide, to the Doctrine and to the Community. May the venerable
Gotama accept me as a disciple; as one who, from this day forth as long as life
endures, has taken him as his guide.”
8
English for Religious Studies
4 The Recorded Conversations of Zen Master Yi Xuan
The Prefect, Policy Advisor Wang, and other officials requested the Master to
lecture. The master ascended the hall and said, “Today it is only because I, a humble
monk, reluctantly accommodate human feelings that I sit on this chair. If one is
restricted to one’s heritage in expounding the fundamental understanding [of
salvation], one really cannot say anything and would have nothing to stand on.
However, because of the honourable general advisor’s strong request today, how can
the fundamental doctrines be concealed? Are there any talented men or fighting
generals to hurl their banners and unfold their strategy right now? Show it to the
group!”
A monk asked, “What is the basic idea of the Law preached by the Buddha?”
Thereupon the Master shouted at him. The monk paid reverence. The Master said,
“The Master and the monk can argue all right.”
Question: “Master, whose tune are you singing? Whose tradition are you
perpetuating?”
The Master said, “When I was a disciple of Huang-bo, I asked him three times
and I was beaten three times.” As the monk hesitated about what to say, the Master
shouted at him and then beat him, saying, “Don’t nail a stick into empty space.”
The Master ascended the hall and said, “Over a lump of reddish flesh there sits
a pure man who transcends and is no longer attached to any class of Buddhas or
sentient beings. He comes in and out of your sense organs all the time. If you are not
yet clear about it, look, look!”
At that point a monk came forward and asked, “What is a pure man who does
not belong to any class of Buddhas or sentient beings?” The Master came right down
from his chair and, taking hold of the monk, exclaimed, “Speak! Speak!” As the monk
deliberated what to say, the Master let him go, saying, “What dried human excrementremoving stick is the pure man who does not belong to any class of Buddhas or
sentient beings!” Thereupon he returned to his room.
The Master ascended the hall. A monk asked, “What is the basic idea of the
Law preached by the Buddha?” The Master lifted up his swatter. The monk shouted,
and the Master beat him. The monk asked again, “What is the basic idea of the Law
preached by the Buddha?” The Master again lifted up his swatter. The monk shouted,
9
English for Religious Studies
and the Master shouted also. As the monk hesitated about what to say, the Master beat
him.
Thereupon the Master said, “Listen, men. Those who pursue after the Law will
not escape from death. I was in my late Master Huang-bo’s place for twenty years.
Three times I asked him about the basic idea of the Law preached by the Buddha and
three times he bestowed upon me the staff. I felt I was struck only by a dried stalk.
Now I wish to have a real beating. Who can do it for me?”
One monk came out of the group and said, “I can do it.” The Master picked up
the staff to give him. As he was about to take it over, the master beat him.
The Master ascended the hall and said, “A man stands on top of a cliff, with
no possibility of rising any further. Another man stands at the crossroad, neither
facing nor backing anything. Who is in the front and who is in the back? Don’t be like
Vimalakīrti (who was famous for his purity), and don’t be like Great Gentleman Fu.
[Fu Xuanfeng (b. 28 CE) put the fish he caught in a basket and submerged it under
water so the fish which wished to escape could do so. He and his wife worked in the
farm for others.] Take care of yourselves.”
The Master told the congregation: “Seekers of the Way, in Buddhism no effort
is necessary. All one has to do is to do nothing, except to move his bowels, urinate,
put on his clothing, eat his meals, and lie down if he is tired. The stupid will laugh at
him, but the wise one will understand. An ancient person [Zen Master Ming-zan (fl.
788)] said, ‘One who makes effort is surely a fool’.”
Question: “What is meant by the mind’s not being different at different
times?”
The Master answered, “As you deliberated to ask the question, your mind has
already become different. Therefore, the nature and character of dharmas have
become differentiated. Seekers of the Way, do not make any mistake. All mundane
and supramundane dharmas have no nature of their own. Nor have they the nature to
be produced [by causes]. They have only the name ‘Emptiness’, but even the name is
empty. Why do you take this useless name as real? You are greatly mistaken!...
If you seek after the Buddha, you will be taken over by the devil of the
Buddha, and if you seek after the patriarch, you will be taken over by the devil of the
patriarch. If you seek after anything, you will always suffer. It is better not to do
anything. Some unworthy priests tell their disciples that the Buddha is the ultimate,
and that he went through three infinitely long periods, fulfilled his practice, and then
10
English for Religious Studies
achieved Buddhahood. Seekers of the Way, if you say that the Buddha is the ultimate,
why did he die lying down sideways in the forest in Kuśinagara after having lived for
eighty years? Where is he now?...
Those who truly seek after the Law will have no use for the Buddha. They will
have no use for any excellence in the Three Worlds (of desires, matter, and pure
spirit). They will be distinctly free and not bound by material things. Heaven and
earth may turn upside down but I shall have no more uncertainty. The Buddhas of the
ten cardinal directions may appear before me and I shall not feel happy for a single
moment. Why? Because I know that all dharmas are devoid of characters. They exist
when there is transformation [in the mind] and cease to exist when there is no
transformation. The Three Worlds are but the mind, and all dharmas are
consciousness only. Therefore [they are all] dreams, illusions and flowers in the air.
What is the use of grasping and seizing them?...
Seekers of the Way, if you want to achieve the understanding according to the
Law, don’t be deceived by others and turn to [your thoughts] internally or [objects]
externally. Kill anything that you happen on. Kill the Buddha if you happen to meet
him. Kill a patriarch or an arhat if you happen to meet him. Kill your 0parents or
relatives if you happen to meet them. Only then can you be free, not bound by
material things, and absolutely free and at ease…
I have no trick to give people. I merely cure disease and set people free… My
views are few. I merely put on clothing and eat meals as usual, and pass my time
without doing anything. You people coming from the various directions have all made
up your minds to seek the Buddha, seek the Law, seek emancipation, and seek to
leave the Three Worlds. Crazy people! If you want to leave the Three Worlds, where
can you go? ‘Buddha’ and ‘patriarch’ are terms of praise and also bondage. Do you
want to know where the Three Worlds are? They are right in your mind which is now
listening to the Law.” …
The Master asked a monk: “Sometimes a shout is like the sacred sword of the
Diamond King. Sometimes a shout is like a golden-haired lion squatting on the
ground. Sometimes a shout is like a rod or a piece of grass [used to attract fish]. And
sometimes a shout is like one which does not function as a shout at all. How do you
know which one to use?” As the monk was deliberating what to say, the Master
shouted.
11
English for Religious Studies
5 Dadosky, “Merton and Zen” Fu Jen International Religious Studies 2.1
From 1959 to 1966 Merton carried on a rich and substantial dialogue with a
prominent authority on Japanese Zen, Daisetz Teitaro Suzuki 鈴木大拙. The dialogue
was unique and pioneering because both scholars were purported experts in their own
traditions and each had an intense interest in the other’s tradition.
A formal dialogue between the two took place in print in Merton’s Zen and the
Birds of Appetite. Later, Merton writes an article entitled “A Zen Revival” that
prompted Suzuki to declare after reading it that Merton had the best grasp of any
Westerner he has ever met. Merton also considered Suzuki an authority and refers to
his work as “certainly without question the most complete and most authentic
presentation of an Asian tradition and experience by any one man in terms accessible
to the West”. Granted, this essay is written in the form of a eulogy which Merton
writes in honour of the man he greatly admired. However, Merton’s laudatory
comments are tempered by the words, “in terms accessible to the West.” Suzuki was a
communicator and popularizer of Zen due in part to his exceptional command of
English and his fascination with Western culture. Many scholars now criticize Suzuki
because they disagree with his interpretation of Zen and because his success as a
popularizer has led to misconceptions by Western scholars. These critics not only
believe Suzuki misrepresents Zen, but they believe he ignores the various complex
lineages of various schools and the doctrinal aspects as well.
Keenan’s critique of Merton flows from this context of post-Suzuki criticism.
To summarize: Based as his works are on D.T. Suzuki’s Zen teachings, I think
we must recognize that we cannot look to Merton for any adequate understanding of
Buddhism. Because of the limitation of sources available to him in his time, his
understanding of Zen Buddhism as presented, for example in Zen and the Birds of
Appetite and in Mystics and Zen Masters, was imperfect and incomplete. It is not
enough—as Merton learned to do from Suzuki—to appeal to a simple, nondiscriminative experience of truth and reality as if that were the core experience
behind all our varied and sorry words and doctrines.
There are some points to be made about Keenan’s passage. First, Merton does
recognize that Zen has very complex doctrines, but he admits that having had limited
time with Suzuki, he wanted to use the time more wisely to discuss matters of more
12
English for Religious Studies
immediate interest. Not only is Merton aware that there is a complex system of
doctrines in Zen, he is also aware that his knowledge is incomplete, and perhaps
always will be.
Second, while there may be some truth in Keenan’s critique, I wonder why he
generalizes this to Merton’s understanding of Buddhism, as for example, in the
Tibetan tradition which Merton also delved into. It may seem like I am quibbling here,
but consider that Merton’s contemplative lifestyle may have predisposed him to grasp
certain elements of Buddhism more readily than others, and as such, he may not have
been as reliant on ‘book knowledge’. It is worth considering the comment by the
Tibetan monk Chadral Rinpoche, who after having a stimulating dialogue with
Merton, called him a rangjung, a naturally arisen Buddha. Perhaps Chadral was being
polite, but if there is such a thing as a ‘naturally arisen Buddha’ then it would seem
that there is the possibility of grasping essential aspects of a tradition without a formal
apprehension of them.
Having said all of this, I would concede that Keenan may be correct when he
says that we should not rely on Merton for an adequate understanding of Buddhism,
and if Merton were alive today he would probably agree. So while his knowledge of
Buddhism may have been pioneering for its time, and in some ways it might be now
passé, what is truly going forward in Merton’s engagement with Buddhism is his
success at interreligious dialogue. It is a method that seems to have taken the
magisterium of the Catholic Church 50 years to accept. Despite the achievements of
Vatican II Merton was ahead of his time.
Roger Corless raised the initial questions concerning the genuine integrity of
Suzuki’s grasp of Christianity and Merton’s grasp of Zen. Keenan is in agreement
with Corless and relies heavily on him to support his own argument. In his article “In
Search of a Context for the Merton-Suzuki Dialogue,” Corless criticizes Suzuki’s
understanding of Christianity along with the latter’s preferences and biases pertaining
to Zen as well as his assumptions about what is distinctively ‘Japanese’.
The tone of Corless’ article is iconoclastic and sweeping, so much so that after
reading it one wonders if there is anything worth salvaging in Suzuki’s work.
Nevertheless, Corless’ critique is probably legitimate to some extent, especially with
respect to Suzuki’s knowledge of Christianity. Most significantly, it highlights
Suzuki’s neglect of the importance of the symbol and theology of the Cross within
Christian theology.
13
English for Religious Studies
Second, regarding Suzuki’s knowledge of Zen, Corless concurs with the
growing tendency to blame Suzuki’s version of Zen for perpetuating caricatures and
being too simplistic. Moreover, central to Suzuki’s ideas is the belief that the
fundamental aspect of Zen is the ‘transcendental’ experience and it is Corless’ critique
of this that I will return to in a subsequent section.
Corless focuses his critique of Suzuki on a personal and political context.
From a personal context, he suggests that Suzuki’s emphasis on ‘transcendental’
experience may have come from his mother’s adherence to a marginal sect of Shin
Buddhism which emphasizes a “direct experience of Amida Buddha”. Corless
declares that Suzuki interpreted “the Zen of his father in terms of the experiences of
his mother.”
While this is intriguing, it seems like a stretch, especially if one considers that
other Zen practioners, especially non-Japanese ones, have emphasized the
‘transcendental’ experience of Zen. Moreover, according to Robert Sharf, Nishida
Kitaro, the founder of the Kyoto School of Zen, shared this same interest with Suzuki,
and Corless does not seem to think the sect of Buddhism that Nishida’s mother
followed is relevant, or at least he does not mention it.
There is a Zeitgeist among various scholars in Japan and Europe in the early
twentieth century which gives an ontological priority to a transcultural experience as
the basis of religion, and these scholars included Suzuki and Nishida. Thus, Suzuki
was influenced by certain figures in Western scholarship including Friedrich
Schleiermacher, Rudolf Otto, and William James (one could even add Mircea Eliade),
who distinguish between the fundamental essence of religion as experience on the one
hand, and the subsequent cultural mediation of that experience on the other. Corless
argues that Suzuki borrowed this distinction from the Western scholars, and this
consequently coloured the Zen that he exported to the West. “[I]n fact, a conservative
‘back to bodhi’ reform movement, was ignored in favour of packaging it as a nondoctrinal, pan-human awakening to reality-as-it-really-is.” From this he can speak to
Suzuki’s influence on Merton:
It was perhaps because Merton accepted Suzuki’s transcendental interpretation
of Zen that he felt it might provide the needed stimulus to revive the contemplative
tradition in Christianity. What Merton did not seem to realize is that Zen Buddhism is
Buddhism, and to practice it sincerely entails, as with any other form of Buddhism,
the giving up of belief in the Christian (or any other) God.
14
English for Religious Studies
6 Dadosky, “Christian-Buddhist Dialogue” Fu Jen Internat. Religious Studies 2.1
In the last section of his article Keenan raises an important question about
interreligious dialogue. Merton’s lasting contribution is probably going to be in this
area rather than in his knowledge of Buddhism. Although the need for dialogue with
Buddhism may not seem as urgent as dialogue with some other religions, still
relatively little progress has been made in the dialogue between Buddhism and
Christianity.
The relationship between Christianity and Buddhism has been wrought with
suspicion since the arrival of the first Jesuit missionaries. Even the celebrated success
of Matteo Ricci in 16th century China in establishing relations with important
patriarchs and aristocrats, and in achieving a high social standing in the community,
could not claim the same success with the Buddhists he encountered. In fact, Faure
argues that Ricci viewed Chan as a rival group and so he was antagonistic towards
them. His success lay more with Confucianism.
More recently, Pope Benedict has commented: “I repeat with insistence [that]
research and interreligious and intercultural dialogue are not an option but a vital
necessity for our time.” This indicates that the Catholic Church is still coming to grips
with the implications of the unprecedented positive valuation of non-Christian
religions in the documents of Vatican II (1962-1965). This Council represented a
paradigmatic shift in the Church’s self-understanding and attitude to other religions,
but it left in its wake the need for a method of dialogue which the official Church has
yet to fully realize.
This paradigm shift is represented by a movement from a strictly selfmediating identity that viewed its relationship with the Other in terms of a one-way
relationship to a more two-way direction or mutually self-mediating direction. That is,
the Vatican II documents represent the official recognition that the Church has mutual
relations with the Other. For example, consider the title of the final chapter of
Gaudium et Spes “The Church and the World as Mutually Related.” This refers to the
Church’s self-understanding as mutually self-mediating as opposed to a strictly selfmediating stance that views the ‘world’ antagonistically and with suspicion. Vatican
II is the official recognition that just as the Church has treasures to share with the
Other, likewise it recognizes that the Church is also enriched by the treasures it finds
in the Other.
15
English for Religious Studies
In this way, Keenan is correct that there is a need for a method of
interreligious dialogue because the recognition that the Church has mutual relations
with the Other has put the Catholic Church in a precarious position. The affirmation
of the Other, that is, of other Christian faiths, non-Christian religions, non-European
cultures and secular society, runs counter to an ecclesial self-understanding that
preceded Vatican II where the distortions of the Church’s self-understanding could
lead to triumphalism, clericalism, and juridicism. While a movement beyond these
attitudes is a welcome development, it has put the post-Vatican II Church in a kind of
‘identity crisis’ in the face of a vast pluralism.
One example of this is the struggle that the Church continues to deal with
concerning the question of evangelization/dialogue with respect to other religions.
When does the Church evangelize, when does it dialogue with others and how does
one avoid dialogue becoming simply a veiled form of evangelization, and how does
one remain faithful to the evangelical mission of the Church in the dialogue? Indeed
there is a tension between proclamation and dialogue but they need not be mutually
opposed. Moreover, dialogue is now considered to be a part of the mission of the
Church. How does one keep one’s Christian identity in this dialogue? Consequently,
the question of how to relate to the Other comes to the forefront, and this is a question
of method.
Thomas Merton’s life example gives us a clue as to how dialogue can be
successfully carried out. In this way, Merton was significant for two reasons. He was
a pioneer by successfully carrying on dialogue before it was fashionable. Secondly,
Merton was successful at it, perhaps more successful than any other major Christian
thinker. Merton exemplifies the method of mutual self-mediation. Of course, the latter
is technical language; the more descriptive language of his methodology could be
called friendship.
James L. Fredericks argues that friendship is an “invaluable” approach for
interreligious dialogue. For example, when the Buddhist and the Christian sit down
together for dialogue in a spirit of friendship, this spirit provides the best context for
mutual enrichment, for mutual challenge, and for the ‘surprise’ of something new
emerging through their respectful sharing and camaraderie. The spirit of friendship
provides a context for engaging the different types of differences even contradictory
ones: “…Christians will do well to develop deep and abiding friendships with the
non-Christian neighbours as a useful way to disagree with honesty and depth”.
16
English for Religious Studies
Interreligious friendships enrich the Church’s self-understanding in two ways. On the
one hand, it keeps our self-understanding from falling into complacency: “Making
new friends requires us to step out of our security and enter into a less comfortable
world where the unpredictable replaces the tried and true”. On the other hand, the
encounter is enriching in that it offers “new and welcome ways” of understanding
oneself.
Keenan and Sharf are correct in that we should not ignore or reduce the
differences to ‘sameness’. Dialogue should preserve the difference. However, equally
important is the ability to recognize the different types of differences—
complementary and contradictory. But this does not preclude the possibility of some
underlying unity as echoed by Wilfred Cantwell Smith’s description of dialogue as
when we discover that ‘we are all talking with each other about us.’
Religious traditions develop dialectically throughout history and undoubtedly
this means that our knowledge of Buddhism will continue to develop. Therefore,
Keenan’s claim that we cannot rely on Merton for knowledge of Buddhism is not
really fair. Any serious student of Buddhism, including Merton himself, recognizes
that our knowledge develops and continues to develop so that even the contributions
of Sharf and Faure will be checked by subsequent future studies. It may be that
Suzuki, Nishida and the others may in fact represent a new movement in the
development of Zen although if so history will ultimately determine its significance.
It strikes me that Keenan and others are quite influenced by the critiques of
post-modernity. While they are quick to point out Suzuki’s reliance on
Schleiermacher and James as a liability, they are not as aware of their own
philosophical assumptions which stem from a post-modern suspicion of any universal
claims to knowledge and normative experiences of transcendence. In fact, the
epistemological problems we inherited from modernity are perpetuated rather than
resolved by relying solely on the post-modern approach. One cannot build a
philosophy on the sand of a hermeneutic of suspicion or viva-la-difference alone. The
study of philosophy and religion is not just about criticizing positions or simply the
preservation of ‘difference’; it is also about the advance of our understanding of
human being’s desire for transcendence, where transcendence includes a horizon
beyond that of hopeless suffering. Unfortunately, the post-modern approach too often
focuses on reversing the attempts to advance such understanding without providing
any sufficient alternatives.
17
English for Religious Studies
7 Takemura, Zen Enlightenment 1
When I hear the word ‘mysticism’ I recall the enlightenment of Buddhism.
And when I hear the word ‘enlightenment’ I at once recall the enlightenment of Zen
Buddhism. Zen Buddhists maintain that they have handed down the enlightenment of
Shakyamuni under the Bodhi-tree from person to person, and even today the word
‘enlightenment’ is often used in their ordinary life.
The content of enlightenment experiences has been reported in various ways,
but the most typical instance is that of Kyogen 香厳, who achieved enlightenment
when he heard the sound of bamboo, or Reiun 霊雲, who became enlightened when,
from a mountain road, he looked at peach blossom in a village. In the experiences of
these masters we find a self-awareness by which life itself is lived in a way in which
subject and object are not separated. In many cases, the enlightenment of Zen monks
occurs in the realm of the senses. So what kind of experience was the enlightenment
of the founder of Buddhism, Shakyamuni?
Among Japanese Buddhist scholars it is often said that Shakyamuni became
enlightened about the dependent arising 縁起 or the truth of dependent arising. This is
based on a description of the scene in the Mahavagga 大品 from the Vinaya where
Shakyamuni achieves his enlightenment and clarifies the twelve links of dependent
arising 十 二 縁 起 . However, if we read the description carefully we find that
Shakyamuni observed the structure of the twelve links of dependent arising after he
had spent a week contemplating the state of liberation. In fact, the Mahavagga says
that Shakyamuni first achieved basic enlightenment under the Bodhi tree and then
tasted religious joy for a week. It was only after this that he observed the twelve links
of dependent arising.
In this case, what is basic enlightenment? I think the following sentences in
the Ariyapariyesanasutta 聖求経 may help us to understand: “Even though I, myself,
was subject to birth, I sought what was also subject to birth. But then I chose to pursue
the greatest unborn calmness and nirvana and so I attained the greatest unborn
calmness and nirvana. Even though I myself was subject to aging, sickness, death,
sorrow, and defilement, I sought what was also subject to aging, sickness, death,
sorrow, and defilement. But then I chose to pursue the greatest unaging, unailing,
deathless, sorrowless, and undefiled calmness and nirvana, and so I attained the
greatest unaging, unailing, deathless, sorrowless, and undefiled calmness and nirvana.
18
English for Religious Studies
Then I attained wisdom and insight as follows: my liberation is secured. This life is
the final life. I will not be born anywhere any more.”
This description informs us that Shakyamuni’s enlightenment about the
unborn and undying nirvana was entirely different from his enlightenment about the
twelve links of dependent arising. It is an enlightenment detached from all words or
discriminations. I think this enlightenment is really the basic enlightenment of
Shakyamuni.
I regard these sentences from the Ariyapariyesanasutta as most important,
because the same enlightenment is expressed among the sutras and articles of
Mahayana Buddhism. For instance, in the Saddharmapundarikasutra it is said, that
the Tathāgata had the wisdom of enlightenment about unborn and undying truth: “The
Tathāgata understands this common world as unborn and undying, not going and not
coming, not living and not reaching nirvana, not true and not false, not the same and
not different. So the Tathāgata does not understand this common world as ordinary
people do. The Tathāgata has clear insight, as shown above, and has never made
mistakes.”
Likewise, in the refuge verse 歸敬頌 of Nagarjuna’s Madhyamikakarika 龍樹
中論頌, enlightenment about the Middle Path of Eight Negations (八不中道) is
presented as follows: “I take refuge in the Buddha as the best Buddha of Buddhas who
preaches about the calm and language-vanished truth of a dependent arising that is not
dying, not born, not annihilated, not everlasting, not the same, not different, not
coming, not going.”
This enlightenment is explained by the Yogacara School 瑜伽行派 as the
enlightenment of non-discriminative wisdom (nirvikalpa-jnana 無 分 別 智 ). Nondiscriminative wisdom is described in verse 28 of the Trimsikakarika 唯識三十頌 by
Vasubandhu 世親. The verse says that when a practitioner’s consciousness has no
object the practitioner dwells on the original nature of consciousness-only, because
there there is neither object nor subject. The Jyoyuishikiron 成唯識論 interprets the
verse as follows: “When a bodhisattva has no object in his non-discriminative wisdom
because he does not focus on any false matter, he can indeed dwell solely on the
original nature of the ultimate truth of the world of consciousness-only. There, when
he is absolutely detached from the seeing or seen form, both wisdom and original
nature become equal.”
19
English for Religious Studies
This can be interpreted as meaning that, during the bodhisattva’s practice,
when he reaches a situation in which he has no object, he will attain the wisdom of
enlightenment and in the wisdom both of the subject and the object will become equal.
In the Jyoyuishikiron this non-discriminative wisdom is defined as having only a
subjective part and no objective part. And yet the wisdom is also aware of original
nature (tathata 真如). So it is said that wisdom holds original nature directly and very
tightly. I think this means that wisdom and original nature are united as one.
As mentioned above, the wisdom of enlightenment means directly knowing
one’s original nature. Our original nature is just the world of the Eight Negations, and
non-discriminative wisdom becomes united with it directly.
So should this enlightenment of the Eight Negations be identified with the
enlightenment of Zen monks—that is, the enlightenment of hearing the sound of
bamboo or seeing the colour of peach blossoms? I think both enlightenment about the
Eight Negations and the enlightenment of Zen monks are one and the same. Original
nature—that is, our ultimate nature (paramarthata 勝義実性)—is indeed absolutely
free from the path of language and the activity of the mind. However, if we were to
regard it as nothingness our views would be in error and nothing more than views
based on the discrimination of ordinary people. Actually, it may be realized that a
sound or color enters the sensory world of the practitioner by transcending both
subject and object when the practitioner has no object at all in his mind. Dogen 道元
(1200-1254), the famous Japanese Zen master and the founder of the Soto Zen School
曹洞宗 in Japan, said: “When a practitioner enters into practice in accordance with
the Buddhist teachings, explores his skin, flesh, bone, and marrow, and drops off his
skin, flesh, bones, and marrow, then peach blossoms will emerge suddenly from the
inside of his eyes, or the sound of bamboo will emerge astonishingly from the inside
of his ears.”
When a practitioner drops himself off via Zen practice he never falls into
nothingness. In this situation he sees the colour of peach blossoms or hears the sound
of bamboo, as subject and object are not divided. However, this world cannot be
explained by words. When we want to describe this world we can do so only in terms
of the Eight Negations.
20
English for Religious Studies
8 Takemura, Zen Enlightenment 2
In fact, the world expressed by the term ‘original nature’ should not be
regarded—as we ordinary people suppose—as nothingness. It should be regarded by
us as a world of the senses in which there is oneness of subject and object beyond
objective cognition. Therefore, Shakyamuni’s enlightenment is said in Zen Buddhism
to be to see the morning star.
In Zen Buddhism the word ‘kensho’ (seeing one’s nature 見性) is often used
as one of the enlightenments. Many people understand the meaning of this word as
‘seeing the original nature or Buddha-nature within human beings’. However, in terms
of the wisdom of enlightenment some of this nature may not be objectively visible
from outside the person. Therefore SUZUKI Daisetu 鈴木大拙 (1870-1966) says that
seeing itself is the seeing person’s nature, and the seeing person’s nature is seeing
itself. ‘Seeing itself is the seeing person’s nature, and the seeing person's nature is
seeing itself” means achieving self-realization of the truth of the undivided subject–
object by entirely becoming the truth itself.
In this situation, the seeing (that is, the wisdom) must be established in the
individual being, and yet enlightenment is realized under the condition of
transcending any objective cognition or ego-consciousness. So the world of
enlightenment is the world of the trans-individual. Hence the phrase ‘seeing itself is
the seeing person’s nature, and the seeing person's nature is seeing itself’ expresses a
situation in which the individual is the trans-individual and the trans-individual is the
individual. Dogen’s enlightenment as “Dropping off of body and mind, and body and
mind dropped off” also expresses the situation in which the individual is the transindividual and the trans-individual is the individual, because mind and body
correspond to the individual and the dropping off corresponds to the trans-individual.
Consequently, enlightenment should be understood as realization of the self as the
individual of trans-individual. In the experience of enlightenment the individual never
vanishes. Of course the ordinary ego—that is, the ego grasped objectively in a
situation in which the subject and object are divided—must be transcended, but the
individual is revived. Finally, to express the sense of enlightenment logically we
should say that the individual of the trans-individual is established in enlightenment
but the individual is never dissolved into the trans-individual. If a man or woman
21
English for Religious Studies
prefers to be dissolved into the absolute in mysticism in an effort to seek the ultimate
truth, then this is very different from the enlightenment handed down in the Buddhist
tradition.
The phrase ‘the individual of the trans-individual’ was used by Suzuki. For
example, Suzuki says in the Thoughts of Zen 禅の思想: “The trans-individual will act
only through the individual. This statement does not mean that the trans-individual
must rely upon the individual. When the trans-individual relies upon the individual,
the trans-individual must rest himself under the individual. This means that the transindividual will become one with the individual. The trans-individual must be just the
trans-individual and does not exist outside the individual and also does not exist inside
it …”
The trans-individual is nothing but the individual and the individual is nothing
but the trans-individual. A relationship like this may not be maintained in general
logic, but I think logic must be transformed to adapt to this fact because I myself
cannot think of another state of fact.
Japan’s most famous philosopher, NISHIDA Kitaro 西田幾多郎 (1870-1945),
who was a most intimate friend of Suzuki, also says in his religious philosophical
article “The Logic of Basho (Place) and the Religious World View” that kensho
(seeing one’s nature) is not seeing one’s nature but becoming oneself thoroughly that
is based on the trans-self (場所的論理と宗教的世界観). He says:
Unlike what many people think, Zen Buddhism is not mysticism. A ken-sho
event involves a thorough realization of the root of self. Our self is established
through self-denial 自己否定 of the Absolute 絶対者. Our self is established as one of
many individual beings that are nothing but the self-denial of the Absolute. Therefore,
our self is basically a self-contradictory being. Self-awareness—the concept of self
knowing itself—is a self-contradiction. Therefore, our self retains itself absolutely in
the Trans-self, which transcends the very depth of the self and affirms itself through
self-denial. The process of ken-sho means becoming thoroughly grounded in this selfcontradiction.
Dogen draw this self-contradictory fact clearly with the following interesting
metaphor in Genjo koan 現成公案 in the Shobogenzo.
A fish swims in water that is endless and a bird flies in sky that is limitless.
The fish or the bird has never left the water or the sky. When they wish to go far away
22
English for Religious Studies
they use a large amount of water or sky, and when they wish to go near they use a
little of each. In that way they can go every time and they can go every place.
However, if the bird leaves the sky the bird will immediately die, and if the fish leaves
the water the fish will die at once. It should be known that water is life itself and the
sky is life itself. Or the bird is life and the fish is life. Life must be the bird and the life
must be the fish. You can guess the other dimensions. A living thing is like this.
A fish or a bird may be regarded as the individual and the water or sky may be
regarded as the trans-individual. Life must not be only by the individual and also must
not be only by the trans-individual. We should imagine that our life or self is realized
absolutely in the way of the individual of the trans-individual.
In conclusion, as explained above, we can say that enlightenment in Buddhism
is the realization of the Self as the individual of the trans-individual. I think the
metaphor of the fish and water or the bird and sky is excellent, because the water or
sky helps us to recall the sense of emptiness (sunyata 空性). In Buddhist thought, our
individual self does not live in absolute being but in emptiness. In the Heart-Sutra 般
若心經 it is said that matter is emptiness and emptiness is matter, and the emotions,
cognitions, will, and intelligence are also emptiness and vice versa. The five elements,
matter, emotions, cognitions, will, and intelligence are the actual being of the
individual but are only phenomenal, not substantial. So this phrase shows that the
individual is established in emptiness. Moreover, this emptiness is to be denied by
emptiness itself. In the philosophy of the Huayan School 華嚴宗 it is said that original
nature (tathata 真如) does not sustain itself 不守自性. The metaphor of the water or
sky shows this fact.
Nishida explored exhaustively the logical expression of the absolute. Nishida
thought that the mere absolute, which is separated from the relative, is in fact one with
the relative and is not, therefore, the true absolute: the absolute is to be found in the
relative. How is this possible? In Nishida’s conclusion, the true absolute denies itself
absolutely and transforms itself into many relative individuals. The absolute
establishes every human being by becoming absolute nothingness. This logic
corresponds to the phrase ‘emptiness is matter’ or ‘original nature does not sustain
itself’.
23
English for Religious Studies
9 Angelo Amato, “Christian Truth spreads by Conviction”
An initial epistemological proposal concerning religious dialogue advises that
it be implemented by way of two distinct tracks, since each has a different destination
not necessarily linked to the other. On is the dialogue of charity, which endeavours to
build a reconciled and peaceful human civilisation. The other is the dialogue of truth,
which aims instead to discern the truth in individual religious beliefs.
The dialogue of charity can appear first of all in the dialogue of life, through
respect for the conversation partner as a member of the same humanity and
consequently as entitled to acceptance, esteem and even friendship. Secondly, this
dialogue can be put into practice in the dialogue of action. This implies collaboration
among world religions in order to achieve peace among the nations, to defend nature
and its laws, to protect life, especially that of the weakest, to show solidarity regarding
the goods to this earth, to safeguard the freedom of every human being—especially
religious freedom—to affirm justice, equality and brotherhood, to overcome the
negative aspects of globalisation and to eliminate poverty and hunger in the world.
The dialogue of charity visibly opens a horizon as boundless as that of God’s love
poured into our hearts.
The other aspect of interreligious dialogue is the dialogue of truth, which
entails the freedom to confront one’s own convictions with another’s, respecting both
the validity of that person’s conscience and the sincerity of his/her beliefs. This
dialogue, whose aim is not to achieve a universal religion with a minimum common
denominator, is a difficult one, since it presses conversation partners to explain the
essential characteristics of their religius beliefs. It should be borne in mind that all
great religions, and not only Christianity, put forward their claim to truth and
universality. Thus, the dialogue of truth is indispensable for an objective discernment
of reality.
I shall present several reflections that focus on this dialogue of truth, stating
beforehand that they are perfunctory references, since the Church has a long
experience of this dialogue. I begin with an affirmation from the Declaration Dominus
Jesus which says, “in the practice of dialogue between the Christian faith and other
religious traditions as well as in seeking to understand its theoretical basis more
deeply, new questions arise that need to be addressed through pursuing new paths of
24
English for Religious Studies
research, advancing proposals, and suggesting ways of acting that call for attentive
discernment” (n. 3).
I believe that now is the time to go beyond the theories of exclusivism,
inclusivism and relativism with their further specifications and to focus instead on a
dual direction. First of all, it is necessary to steer clear of generic interreligious
dialogue that does not take into account the specific identity of each conversation
partner. Interreligious dialogue, just as ecumenical dialogue, demands a bilateral
confrontation in which the dialogue partners may be considered in their specific
originality and may thus express their own ‘truths’.
In addition, it is necessary that the interreligious dialogue of truth focus on the
essential content of the different beliefs and hence on their vision of God (should they
mention it), of the human being and of the cosmos. The dialogue of truth must
examine in concrete terms religious, ethical, educational, political and cultural
convictions, in a word, the hard core of the interlocutor’s religious identity. Hence it is
essential to avoid generic comparisons that are based solely upon superficial
phenomenological analyses and to open oneself instead to an open and frank bilateral
exchange regarding the respective religions’ perspectives on the truth about God, man
and the cosmos.
This implies a correct and articulate knowledge of one’s own faith and an
equally complete familiarity with the beliefs of the other. The dialogue of truth, then,
cannot come about without the risk of trivialising and perhaps even betraying one’s
own convictions as well as those of others. Certainly, in a culture such as our postmodern culture in which opinion dominates and the truth seems an evanescent mirage,
the dialogue of truth appears as a challenge to go against the tide of opinion.
This entails a certain change in the dynamics of interreligious dialogue.
Benedict XVI’s lecture in Regensburg can be considered the beginning of a new
approach that breaks away from the rigid patterns of a diplomatic dialogue that
disregards the consequences of a virtual dialogue cut off from reality, in order to enter
into the life of a dialogue of truth and life which brings into play the actual lives of the
conversation partners, in the entirety and complexity of their plans for human and
religious fulfilment. To respond to those who ask us to account for Christian hope, we
must refer to the truth. Indeed St John says, “This is the disciple who is bearing
witness to these things, and who has written these things; and we know that his
testimony is true” (Jn 21:24).
25
English for Religious Studies
Dialogue is a literary genre with a long tradition, present in Greek philosophy
and also in the Gospels. In interreligious exchange, ancient Christianity was obliged
to face certain inter-connected challenges that are still relevant today: the rational
justification of faith, the question of its truth and the possibility of its actuation in the
practical life of Christians….
A ‘Christian’, in Ignatius of Antioch’s opinion, was someone who lived a life
in harmony with his/her faith. Origen maintained that the truth of Christianity was
proven by putting it into practice. Christian life, in fact, is not only interiority but is
expressed in the conduct and language of the faithful... Criticised by Celsus, who
maintained that there was nothing original in Christian morals, Origen refrained from
protesting and explained that the presumed lack of newness in Christian ethics
depended on the fact that God had desired to provide common ethical criteria for all
humanity, to ensure that the verdict of the Last Judgment would be based on criteria
that ere truly the same for all.
The way in which Christianity serves as an essential completion of ancient
thought contains two elements. First of all, the Christian truth is not a truth only for
experts but for everyone. It is not only theoretical but is also a practical truth. It is not
only a truth for academia but also for practical life. This Christian simplicity is far
removed from Gnostic fabrications. Those who helped to spread Christianity were not
only scholars but also simple people. The Fathers often called Christians “the true
philosophers”.
Jerome wondered, “Who reads Aristotle? Who knows Plato or his books or
even his name?... On the other hand everyone is talking of our ordinary people and
our fishermen; talk of them echoes through the world. Therefore it is necessary to
offer them simple words in an equally simple language.”
What is more, Christian simplicity is not simple-mindedness or superficiality
but docta ignorantia, in analogy with Socratic ignorance. It indicates a loftier
knowledge that goes beyond the dialectic of philosophers and rhetoricians and
succeeds in reaching all. Christianity’s claim to truth and universality has therefore
been inherent in its identity from the outset. This is proven not so much by technical
reasoning as by living a visible and exemplary life. And this truth was not spread by
coercion but by conviction. At the very foundations of the Christian proclamation lies
the principle of freedom.
(L’osservatore romano, (weekly edition in English) 30 July 2008, pp 6-7 (extracts)
26
English for Religious Studies
10 Pope Benedict XVI, “Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite”
Today I would like to speak of a rather mysterious figure: a sixth-century
theologian whose name is unknown and who wrote under the pseudonym of
Dionysius the Areopagite. With this pseudonym he was alluding to the event
recounted by St. Luke in chapter 17 of the Acts of the Apostles where he tells how
Paul preached in Athens at the Areopagus to an elite group of the important Greek
intellectual world. In the end, the majority of his listeners proved not to be interested
and went away jeering at him. Yet some approached Paul and opened themselves to
the faith. The Evangelist gives us two names: Dionysius, a member of the Areopagus,
and a woman named Damaris.
If five centuries later the author of these books chose the pseudonym
‘Dionysius the Areopagite’, it means that his intention was to put Greek wisdom at the
service of the Gospel, to foster the encounter of Greek culture and intelligence with
the proclamation of Christ. He wanted to do what this Dionysius had intended, that is,
to make Greek thought converge with St Paul’s proclamation; being a Greek, he
wanted to become a disciple of Paul, hence a disciple of Christ…
[He choose a pseudonym, partly because] he himself desired to make an act of
humility. He did not want to glorify his own name. He did not want to build a
monument to himself with his work but rather truly to serve the Gospel, to create an
ecclesial theology, neither individual nor based on himself. Actually, he succeeded in
elaborating a theology which we can date to the sixth century but cannot attribute to
any of the figures of that period. It is a theology which expresses a common thought
and language. He said, “I do not wish to spark polemics; I simply speak of the truth; I
seek the truth”. And the light of truth by itself causes errors to fall away and makes
what is good shine forth. And with this principle he purified Greek thought and
related it to the Gospel. This principle is also the expression of a true spirit of dialogue:
it is not about seeking the things that separate, but seeking the truth in Truth itself.
This then radiates and cause errors to fade away…
All Creation speaks of God and is praise of God. Since the creature is praise of
God, Pseudo-Dionysius’ theology became a liturgical theology: God is found above
all in praising him, not only in reflection; and the liturgy is not something made by us,
something invented in order to have a religious experience for a certain period of time;
it is singing with the choir of creatures and entering into cosmic reality itself. And in
27
English for Religious Studies
this way the liturgy, apparently only ecclesiastical, becomes expansive and great, it
becomes our union with the language of all creatures. He says: God cannot be spoken
of in an abstract way; speaking of God is always—he says using a Greek word—a
‘(hymnein), singing for God with the great hymn of the creatures which is
reflected and made concrete in liturgical praise.
Yet, although his theology is cosmic, ecclesial and liturgical, it is also
profoundly personal. He created the first great mystical theology. Indeed, with him the
word ‘mystic’ acquires a new meaning. Until then for Christians such a word was
equivalent to the word ‘sacramental’, that is, what pertains to the 
(mysterion), to the sacrament. With him the word ‘mystic’ becomes more personal,
more intimate: it expresses the soul’s journey toward God. And how can God be
found? Here we note once again an important element in his dialogue between Greek
philosophy and Christianity, and, in particular biblical faith.
Apparently what Plato says and what the great philosophy on God says is far
loftier, far truer; the Bible appears somewhat ‘barbaric’, simple or pre-critical one
might say today; but he remarks that precisely this is necessary, so that in this way we
can understand that the loftiest concepts on God never reach his true grandeur: they
always fall short of it.
In fact these images enable us to understand that God is above every concept;
in the simplicity of the images we find more truth than in great concepts. The Face of
God is our inability to express truly what he is. In this way one speaks—and PseudoDionysius himself speaks—of a ‘negative theology’. It is easier for us to say what
God is not rather than to say what he truly is. Only through these images can we intuit
his true Face. Moreover, this Face of God is very concrete: it is Jesus Christ.
And although Dionysius shows us, following Proclus, the harmony of the
heavenly choirs in such a way that it seems they all depend on one antoher, it is true
that on our journey toward God we are still very far from him. Pseudo-Dionysisu
shows that in the end the journey to God is God himself, who makes himself close to
us in Jesus Christ.
Thus, a great and mysterious theology also becomes very concrete, both in the
interpretation of the liturgy and in the discourse on Jesus Christ. With all this,
Dionysius the Areopagite exerted a strong influence on all medieval theology and on
all mystical theology, both in the East and in the West. He was virtually rediscovered
28
English for Religious Studies
in the 13th century, especially by St. Bonaventure, the great Franciscan theologian
who in this mystical theology found the conceptual instrument for reinterpreting the
heritage—so simple and profound—of St Francis.
Together with Dionysius, the Povererello tells us that in the end love sees
more than reason. Where the light of love shines the shadows of reason are dispelled;
love sees, love is an eye and experience gives us more than reflection. Bonaventure
saw in St Francis what this experience is: it is the experience of a very humble, very
realistic journey, day by day. It is walking with Christ, accepting his Cross. In this
poverty and in this humility, in the humility that is also lived in ecclesiality, is an
experience of God which is loftier than that attained by reflection. In it we really
touch God’s Heart.
Today Dionysius the Areopagite has a new relevance: he appears as a great
mediator in the modern dialogue between Christianity and the mystical theologies of
Asia, whose characteristic feature is the conviction that it is impossible to say who
God is, that only indirect things can be said about him; that God can only be spoken
of with the ‘not’, and that it is only possible to reach him by entering into this indirect
experience of’not’. And here a similarity can be seen between the thought of the
Areopagite and that of Asian religions; he can be a mediator today as he was between
the Greek spirit and the Gospel.
In this context it can be seen that dialogue does not accept superficiality. It is
precisely when one enters into the depths of the encounter with Christ that an ample
space for dialogue also opens. When one encounters the light of truth, one realises
that it is a light for everyone. Polemics disappear and it is possible to understand one
another, or at least to speak to one another, to come closer. The path of dialogue
consists precisely in being close to God in Christ, in a deep encounter with him, in the
experience of the truth which opens us to the light and helps us reach out to others—
with the light of truth, the light of love.
And in the end, he tells us: take the path of experience, the humble experience
of faith, every day. Then the heart is enlarged and can see and also illumine reason so
that it perceives God’s beauty. Let us pray to the Lord to help us today too to place the
wisdom of our day at the service of the Gospel, discovering ever anew the beauty of
faith, the encounter with God in Christ.
(L’osservatore romano, (weekly edition in English) 21 May 2008, p 11 (extracts)
29
English for Religious Studies
11 Hugo Meynell, “A Letter to Professor Dawkins” Heythrop Journal 49.4
The main part of my letter has to do with the rationality of belief in the
existence of God. Now there are two types of explanation which we generally take for
granted in our dealing with the world: that which appeals to physical causes, and is
taken to magnificent lengths in your physical sciences; and that which is in terms of
agents acting for reasons. (Gilbert Ryle, the famous philosopher of mind, is said to
have been asked on one occasion what was the ultimate furniture of the universe; and
to have replied, “Things and chaps”.) Now there is something of a puzzle about how
thing-explanation is to be related to chap-explanation. I think you would probably say,
as you confessed yourself a materialist monist, that chap-explanation is merely a very
complicated sort of thing-explanation (I think this is a necessary corollary of
materialism), though chap-explanation would presumably survive as a convenient
shorthand, just as we still say, in spite of Copernicus, that the sun rises. But I think—
and this is a crucial aspect of my case—that this must be a mistake. What is more, the
matter has very important bearings on the very possibility of science, as we shall see.
Now I regard the natural sciences as perhaps the supreme spiritual
achievement of humankind. That statement is obviously a bit of coat-trailing; what on
earth could I mean by it? I would begin with the counter-question: To what are the
great achievements of science due, and why do the rest of us believe scientists, and
rightly believe them, on the topics in which they specialise? Philosophers of science
are as contentious as most sorts of philosophers; but I do not think any of them would
disagree with the following summary account. They are due to people having attended
to the relevant evidence in experience; having envisaged an adequate number of
possibilities or hypotheses to account for that experience; and having preferred in
each case the hypothesis which best fits the experience—as opposed, say, to the one
that suits their inherited prejudices or the wishes of their paymasters. Let us say
summarily that they have been attentive, intelligent and reasonable in relation to the
relevant experience—we may say ‘rational’ for short.
It seems to me a cardinal point in metaphysics, that the universe which we get
to know by being rational in the way I have described, must be intelligible; it amounts
to one consistent set of intelligible possibilities; which set, it is the business of
reasonableness progressively to determine.
30
English for Religious Studies
So far as I can see from my reading, some scientists excel in attentiveness,
some in intelligence and reasonableness. Tycho Brahe had attended to the positions of
the planets as he saw them in the night sky, and recorded them. Both on the Ptolemaic
view and on the crude Copernican one, where the planets were supposed to be
travelling in circular orbits round the sun, this gave rise to some anomalies which set
Kepler wondering about possible explanations. He intelligently (if I remember rightly,
C.S. Peirce said that it was one of the supreme intellectual feats in human history)
hypothesized that the anomalies would disappear if the planets were thought to be
travelling in elliptical orbits within which the sun was one of the foci, and if straight
lines from the sun to the any particular planet always swept out equal areas. And
when he reasonably considered how well his hypothesis stood up to Brahe’s data as
compared with others, this turned out to be correct.
Darwin (whose first cousin, by the way, I can’t work out quite how many
times removed, I am very proud of being) seems to have excelled in all three
capacities. He attended to his Galapagos finches, which raised questions in his mind;
why did otherwise very similar species, in these isolated conditions, have thick bills
on one island where nuts were readily available, and thin bills on another, where a
bird had to prod in crevices for insects? Would this not be very neatly explained by
the finches which had thicker bills tending to survive and breed successfully on nutisland, and those with the thinner bills on insect-island? Could not this account be
readily extended to the whole biomass, with species developing according to random
mutation and natural selection, rather than being brought into existence each by
special creation? (As I remember, at one point late in The Origin of Species, Darwin
actually suggests that the resulting idea of God, as planning and executing creation as
it were in a single sweep, was much nobler than that of God engaging in perpetual
petty interferences as would be involved in multitudes of special creations.)
I have suggested that agent-explanation is irreducible, on the grounds that, if it
were not, science, as involving people believing things because there was really good
reason to do so, would be impossible. Now I take it that the idea of God is basically
that of a being who intelligently conceives all possible worlds, and wills that which
actually exists; in other words, that of an agent. Rather as you can here and now either
apply yourself to your next article on the obscurantism and other evils of religion; or
have a shave; or do nothing; so God in eternity can decide either to create a universe
which has elephants and uranium in it; or to create a universe which doesn’t have
31
English for Religious Studies
elephants and uranium in it; or to not create it at all. But why postulate such an agent?
To account for the fact the universe is intelligible. And it is intelligible because
science is possible. Scientists (here I speak as a fool) are often having reasonably to
abandon a hypothesis in the light of the evidence; but they never doubt—or I hope
they don’t—that some hypothesis will explain the evidence.
God’s intelligence is needed to explain the intelligibility of the world (unless,
as poor old Kant thought, we somehow put the intelligibility there ourselves); God’s
will to explain that it has the particular intelligibility that it is found to have—in terms
of special relativity rather than the luminous aether, in terms of oxygen rather than
phlogiston, in terms of the selfish gene rather than whatever alternative someone
might think up.
“But Mummy, who made God?” Certainly, in invoking God as in some kind
of causal relation to the universe, the would-be rational theist is under some obligation
to show that the same kind of argument is not needed again, and so ad inifinitum. But,
briefly, if God is supposed to be the intelligent will on whose fiat all else depends for
its existence, one cannot properly ask, “on what does that depend?” One might protest,
“Well, by ‘the universe’ one means ‘all that exists’. What could be neither that as a
whole nor a part of it, other than nothing?” The proper question is then, within the
universe in the sense of ‘all that exists’, is there good reason to suppose that there is
something related to the rest of what exists rather as cause to effect, or agent to
product? The odd conspiracy between the structure of our minds and the structure of
the universe suggests that there is something in the depths of the universe analogous
to our minds. Here we are, on a tiny bit of rock orbiting an insignificant sun on the
outskirts of a galaxy of tens of millions of stars, with the galaxy itself one of tens of
millions; yet we can compass the depths of space and time with our thought.
C.S. Lewis, in considering what he called the popular scientific world-view,
said that one central inconsistency ruins it; we are asked to believe at once that nature
at large is at bottom a random and fortuitous material process, and reason a
completely incidental offshoot of this; and yet we rely on reason, and rightly so, to
penetrate the depths of the material universe. What he meant has been developed at
length in the work of the greatest Christian philosopher of the twentieth century: the
late Bernard Lonergan. His theory of knowledge is based basically on the selfdestructiveness of the notion that we do not apprehend the truth about the world and
what is good in action, by being as fully rational as possible.
32
English for Religious Studies
33
English for Religious Studies
12 David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order, Chapter 3
A Revisionist Model for Contemporary Theology
In its briefest expression, the revisionist model holds that a contemporary
fundamental Christian theology can best be described as philosophical reflection upon
the meanings present in common human experience and language, and upon the
meanings present in the Christian fact. To explain and defend this model for the task
of theology, five these will be proposed which are intended to explicate the principal
meanings involved in this model of theology. The structure of the present argument is
best grasped by an understanding of the interrelationships of the theses themselves.
The first thesis defends the proposition that there are two sources for theology,
common human experience and language, and Christian texts. The second thesis
argues for the necessity of correlating the results of the investigations of these two
sources. The third and fourth theses attempt to specify the most helpful methods of
investigation employed for studying these two sources. The fifth and final thesis
further specifies the final mode of critical correlation of these investigations as an
explicitly metaphysical or transcendental one. At the time of the discussion of this
final thesis, one should be able to provide a summary of the meaning and truth-value
of the present model proposed for theology, viz., philosophical reflections upon
common human experience and language, and upon Christian texts.
There are, of course, thorny problems and several alternative views possible
not only for the model as a whole, but for each ‘thesis’ in the model. I hope that the
lengthier discussions of the later chapters may serve to clarify why those alternative
views have not been followed—or perhaps should have been followed.
First Thesis: The Two Principal Sources for Theology are Christian Texts and
Common Human Experience and Language
This thesis seems the least problematic of the five proposed. For it seems
obvious that any enterprise called Christian theology will attempt to show the
appropriateness of its chosen categories to the meanings of the major expressions and
texts of the Christian tradition. This source of the theological task is variously labelled:
the message as with Paul Tillich, the kerygma as with Rudolf Bultmann, the Christian
witness of faith as with Schubert Ogden, the tradition as with most contemporary
Catholic theologians.
34
English for Religious Studies
Whatever title is chosen, the recognition of the need for the Christian
theologian to show just how and why his conclusions are appropriate to the Christian
tradition remains as obvious in its demand as it proves to be difficult in its execution.
A subsidiary but no unimportant corollary of this demand is that the scriptures remain
the fundamental although not exclusive expression of that Christian faith. Hence a
principal task of the theologian will be to find appropriate interpretations of the major
motifs of the scriptures and of the relationship of those interpretations to the
confessional, doctrinal, symbolic, theological and praxis expressions of the various
Christian traditions. Except for those few theologians who would maintain that
theology is without remainder a philosophical reflection upon our contemporary
experience and language, this commitment to determining the ability of contemporary
formulations to state the meanings of Christian texts remains an obvious, albeit
difficult task.
Even from the limited perspective of this understanding of the nature of a
theologian’s responsibility to the tradition, it would also seem that the task of
theology involves an attempt to show the adequacy of the major Christian theological
categories for all human experience. In fact, insofar as the scriptures claim that the
Christian self-understanding does, in fact, express an understanding of authentic
human existence as such, the Christian theologian is impelled to test precisely that
universalist claim. He will ordinarily do so by developing criteria that generically can
be labelled ‘criteria of adequacy’ to common human experience. Whether this source
of theological reflection can be called the ‘situation’ as with Paul Tillich, the
‘contemporary scientific world view’ as with Rudolf Bultmann, the contemporary
phenomenon of a full-fledged ‘historical consciousness’ as with Bernard Lonergan, or
‘common human experience’ as here, again the task seems a fully necessary one.
However, this demand is not forced upon the Christian theologian only by his
commitment to the authentic aspects of modernity, much less by a search for
contemporary relevance. Rather that task is primarily demanded for inner theological
reasons. Rudolf Bultmann, for one, clarifies these reasons by his firm insistence that
demythologizing is demanded not only by the contemporary world-view but also by
the universalist, existential assumptions of the New Testament self-understanding
itself.
This commitment to determine methods and criteria which can show the
adequacy of Christian self-understanding for all human experience is a task demanded
35
English for Religious Studies
by the very logic of the Christian affirmations; more precisely, by the Christian claim
to provide the authentic way to understand our common human existence. This insight
theologically disallows any attempt to force a strictly traditional inner-theological
understanding of the sources of theological reflection. Whether that inner theological
self-understanding be explicated through any of the forms of theological orthodoxy or
through the kind of neo-orthodoxy represented by Karl Barth in the Church
Dogmatics is a relatively minor matter.
The major insight remains the insistence present in theological reflection at
least since Schleirmacher: the task of a Christian theology intrinsically involves a
commitment to investigate critically both the Christian faith in its several expressions
and contemporary experience in its several cultural expressions. In this important
sense one may continue to find Schleiermacher’s slogan for the task of theology still
accurate: “The theses of faith must become the hypotheses of the theologian”.
36
English for Religious Studies
13 David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order, Ch. 3.2 Two Sources of Theology
Second Thesis: The Theological Task will involve a Critical Correlation of the
Results of the Investigations of the Two Sources of Theology
Given the fact of two sources needing investigation, some way of correlating
the results of these investigations must be developed. The full dimensions of this task
of correlation cannot, of course, be developed until the methods of investigation
analysed in the next two theses are clarified. For the moment, however, it is sufficient
to clarify the need for some method of correlation. Perhaps the clearest way to clarify
the meaning of this thesis will be to compare the method of correlation proposed here
with the best known method of correlation in contemporary theology, Paul Tillich’s.
This ‘clarification through contrast’ procedure is here a useful one since so many
contemporary theologians are justly indebted to Tillich for formulating the task of
theology in terms of the general model of a method of correlation.
There are, it is true, some significant differences between the Tillichian
notions of ‘situation’ and ‘message’ and the present articulation of the two sources of
theology as ‘common human experience’ and ‘Christian texts’. Still, the twofold
nature of the theologian’s commitment implied by these expressions, as well as the
recognition that such a commitment logically involves the need for some kind of
correlation, is a shared position.
Moreover, one may continue to find Tillich’s articulation of the ideal for
contemporary theology to be fundamentally sound. As Tillich expresses it in volume I
of the Systematics, the ideal contemporary theological position would provide an
Aufhebung of both liberalism and neo-orthodoxy. As Tillich expresses the same ideal
in his introduction to volume II, the theologian must attempt to move beyond both
classical ‘supernaturalism’ and secular ‘naturalism’ by developing some form of ‘selftranscending naturalism’.
In sum, Paul Tillich’s position continues to seem peculiarly helpful: for his
expression of the proper ideal of contemporary theology; for his insistence that only
an investigation of both ‘situation’ and ‘message’ can hope to fulfil this ideal; and for
his articulation of the need for some general model of correlation as the proper
response to this need.
However, many critics find Tillich’s own formulation of how the method of
correlation actually functions neither intrinsically convincing nor consistent with the
task of theology which he himself articulates. The fact is that Tillich’s method does
37
English for Religious Studies
not call for a critical correlation of the results of one’s investigations of the ‘situation’
and the ‘message’. Rather, his method affirms the need for a correlation of the
‘questions’ expressed in the ‘situation’ with the ‘answers’ provided by the Christian
‘message’. Such a correlation, in fact, is one between ‘questions’ from one source and
‘answers’ from the other.
Even on the limited basis of the position defended in the first thesis, one
cannot but find unacceptable this formulation of the theological task of correlation.
For if the ‘situation’ is to be taken with full seriousness, then its answers to its own
questions must also be investigated critically. Tillich’s method cannot really allow
this. A classic example of this difficulty can be found in Tillich’s famous dictum,
“Existentialism is the good luck of Christian theology”. We are all indebted to
Tillich’s brilliant reinterpretation pointing out the heavy debt which existentialist
analyses of man’s estranged situation owe to classical Christian anthropology. Yet no
one (not even a Christian theologian!) can decide that only the questions articulated
by a particular form of contemporary thought are of real theological interest.
Correlatively, from the viewpoint of the Christian message itself, the very
claim to have an answer applicable to any human situation demands logically that a
critical comparison of the Christian ‘answer’ with all other ‘answeres’ be initiated. To
return to the existentialist example, why do we not find in Tillich a critical
investigation of the claims that either Jean-Paul Sartre’s or Karl Jaspers’ philosophies
of existence provide a better ‘answer’ to the question of human estrangement than the
Christian ‘answer’ does?
In summary, a commitment to two sources for theology does imply the need to
formulate a method capable of correlating the principal questions and answers of each
source. Yet Tillich’s method of correlation is crucially inadequate. Tillich’s implicit
commitment to two sources and his explicit insistence upon a theological ideal which
transcends both naturalism and supernaturalism could be successfully executed only
by a method which develops critical criteria for correlating the questions and the
answers found in both the ‘situation’ and the ‘message’. Any method which attempts
less than that cannot really be called a method of correlation. Tillich’s method does
not actually correlate; it juxtaposes questions from the ‘situation’ with answers from
the ‘message’. Insofar as this critique is true, the contemporary theologian can accept
Tillich’s articulation of the need for a method of correlation, but he cannot accept
Tillich’s own model for theology as one which actually correlates.
38
English for Religious Studies
14 David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order, Ch. 3.3 Phenomenology
Third Thesis: The Principal Method of Investigation of the Source ‘Common Human
Experience and Language’ can be described as a Phenomenology of the ‘Religious
Dimension’ present in everyday and scientific Experience and Language.
The principal intention of this thesis is to clarify the method needed to
investigate the first source of theology. It should be emphasized at once, however, that
the present thesis does not involve a determination of the truth-value of the meanings
uncovered. Rather this thesis merely attempts to analyze what method will best allow
those meanings to be explicated as accurately as possible.
A widely accepted dictum of contemporary theological thought holds that all
theological statements involve an existential dimension, indeed a dimension which
includes a claim to universal existential relevance. On that basis it seems fair to
conclude that the theologian is obliged to explicate how and why the existential
meanings proper to Christian self-understanding are present in common human
experience. As long as one’s understanding of the concept experience is not confined
to Humean sense-data but involves a recognition of the pre-reflective, pre-conceptual,
pre-thematic realm of the everyday, then the task of theology in this moment of its
enterprise seems clear.
That task is the need to explicate a pre-conceptual dimension to our common
shared experience that can legitimately be described as religious. Historically, that
task is best represented by the liberal theological tradition’s search for a method
capable of explicating an ultimate or final horizon of meaning to our common
everyday life and language, and to our scientific and ethical reflection which can
properly be described as both ultimate and religious.
One way of formulating this task is to suggest that contemporary
phenomenological method is the method best suited for it. The reasons for the choice
of the title ‘phenomenology’ at this point are basically twofold. First, several major
figures in the phenomenological tradition from Max Scheler through the recent work
of Langdon Gilkey have demonstrated the effectiveness of phenomenological
reflection in explicating that final or ultimate horizon precisely as a religious one.
Second, the history of phenomenological reflection on the nature of the
method itself has developed ever more sophisticated ways to formulate the full
dimensions of any phenomenological investigation. Indeed, phenomenological
method has undergone several important transformations from the earlier ‘eidetic’
39
English for Religious Studies
formulations of Husserl and the Göttingen circle through the existential
phenomenology of Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Scheler, and the early Heidegger to the
hermeneutic phenomenology of Gadamer, the later Heidegger, and Paul Ricoeur.
Each of these redefinitions of the nature of phenomenology has been impelled by the
inability of an earlier method to explicate the full dimensions of the phenomena
uncovered by earlier reflection.
If the most recent formulations of phenomenology’s task (the hermeneutic) be
sound, then it seems reasonable to suggest that theologians might employ such a
method to analyze those symbols and gestures present to our everyday life and
language that may legitimately manifest a religious dimension to our lives.
To be sure, the present position does not argue that only phenomenological
method can succeed in this analysis. It does argue that a recognition of the real
possibilities of that method promises a new surety to the several attempts to explicate
the religious dimension of our common experience and language.
As one example of phenomenology’s relative adequacy for theology’s task,
consider the crucial question of the linguistic and symbolic character of our
experience. On that question, it seems clear that so-called ‘hermeneutic
phenomenology’ is far better prepared than either the ‘reformed subjectivist principle’
of the Whiteheadians or the earlier ‘critical phenomenology’ of Pual Tillich to
explicate the linguistic (usually symbolic) character of everyday experience; this
holds as well for the properly linguistic and symbolic dimensions of the final and
ultimate horizon of that world as religious. Not a plea for exclusive rights, the
argument for phenomenology takes the form of suggesting its relative adequacy for
uncovering the full dimensions of the common task.
Thus far in this third thesis the emphasis has been upon the kind of method
needed for this common theological task. Hopefully, such an emphasis does not
obscure the nature of the task itself: the continued search in most contemporary
theology for an adequate expression of the religious dimension of our common
experience and language. To repeat, that task seems demanded both by the
universalist claim of Christian self-understanding and by the otherwise inexplicable
character of our shared experience itself.
In fact, so complex does this aspect of theology’s contemporary task become
that only a phenomenology in continued conversation with those human sciences
which investigate the religious dimension in human existence, and in conversation
40
English for Religious Studies
with other philosophical methods can really hope to succeed. As an example of such
collaboration, it may prove helpful to close this thesis with mention of a few
conversation partners available at the moment.
The work of Paul Tillich on this question (viz., his analysis of the religious
‘ultimate concern’ involved in the human ‘situation’) has, in fact, been continued and
refined by the work of such diverse interpreters of Tillich as Langdon Gilkey, Tom
Driver, Nathan Scott and David Kelsey. The work of Bernard Lonergan on the
religious dimension in human cognition and action is presently being advanced both
by Lonergan himself, in his more recent work, and by Lonergan interpreters such as
John Dunne, David Burrell, and Michael Novak. Enterprises like these are, I believe,
central to any serious contemporary attempt at fundamental theology.
41
English for Religious Studies
15 David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order, Ch. 3.4 Hermeneutics
Fourth Thesis: The Principal Method of Investigation of the Source ‘The Christian
Tradition’ can be described as an Historical and Hermeneutical Investigation of
Classical Christian Texts.
This thesis begins with a truism: if the Christian theologian must articulate the
meaning of the phenomenon variously called the ‘Christian fact’, ‘witness’, ‘message’,
or ‘tradition’, then he is obliged to enter into the discussion of the nature of the
disciplines of history and hermeneutics. This thesis does not pretend to resolve the
many problems encompassed by historical and hermeneutical knowledge. Rather, it
attempts only to outline the particular understandings of the historical and
hermeneutical methods that may prove helpful for this aspect of the theological task.
The theological need for history and hermenutics concerns us first. If the
phenomenon labelled the ‘Christian fact’ includes the significant gestures, symbols
and actions of the various Christian traditions, then the theologian must learn those
historical methods capable of determining exactly what facts can be affirmed as
probable. For the present investigation of texts, he must also learn historical methods
in order to allow for the historical reconstruction of the basic texts of Christian selfunderstanding. On that historical basis of reconstruction, the theologian must then find
a hermeneutic method capable of discerning at least the central meanings of the
principal textual expressions of Christianity (viz., the scriptural).
The general need for historical method articulated here is a modest one. It does
not imply that the theologian employ a specific category like ‘salvation-history’ as a
useful theological one. The call for historical method does imply that the theologian
as historian pay heed to those historical reconstructions of Christian events and texts
which modern historical scholarship has made available.
The argument for historical method implied by the first three theses, then, is a
limited but important aspect of the theologian’s larger task. If one were to define
Christian theology as simply a philosophy of religion, then historical method need not
be employed. But if Christian theology is adequately defined only as a philosophical
reflection upon both common human experience and language and upon Christian
texts, then a historical reconstruction of the central texts of that tradition is imperative.
Perhaps the exact nature of the historical task of the theologian might best be
understood by recalling a familiar instance of its exercise. That instance is the
common Christian affirmation “Jesus of Nazareth is the Christ”. That exercise is the
42
English for Religious Studies
attempt to determine what historical and hermeneutical methods can best aid the
contemporary theologian to understand what Christians have actually meant by this
familiar affirmation. Rather than spelling out at length an understanding of historical
and hermeneutic methods, in the remainder of this thesis I shall risk the belief that
these crucial theological tasks are best grasped by examining their emergence in a
specific theological problem. That problem is the primary existential meanings of
Christological texts.
The first questions to be addressed to the affirmation that “Jesus is the Christ”
are ordinarily historical ones. The historian does want to know what conclusions
historical inquiry can reach about the person Jesus of Nazareth and about the belief of
the Christian community that Jesus was the Christ. On these historical questions it
seems fair to state that, short of a position like J.M. Allegro’s at least, the
accumulation of historical evidence on the existence of Jesus of Nazareth seems
secure, even if the range of interpretations of his significance is wide indeed. Yet
whatever interpretation of the ‘historical Jesus’ is accepted as most probable by
various historians through old and new ‘quests’, the principal factor demanding
theological clarification is the religious existential meaning expressed in the New
Testament Christological texts as those texts are reconstructed by contemporary
historical scholarship.
If the historian can reconstruct the texts in question, then the next problem
becomes the need to discover what discipline will allow one to determine the
meanings of those metaphors, symbols, and ‘images’ used in the New Testament texts
to express the religious significance of the proclamation that Jesus of Nazareth is the
Christ. Much of the language of the New Testament is metaphorical, symbolic, and
parabolic as distinct from conceptual; the principal meaning expressed by the texts is
one which manifests or represents what can be properly labelled a religious meaning,
a religious way of being-in-the-world. These two factors can be discerned by various
combinations of historical and linguistic methods. Yet to determine with greater
exactness the full meaning of the ‘images’ demands a more explicit formulation of the
hermeneutic, as distinct from the historical task.
The present discussion of that hermeneutical task does not pretend to provide
an exhaustive analysis. Indeed, the history of reflection on the nature of that
notoriously complex discipline makes one justifiably wary of any exhaustive claims.
For the moment, I will simply advance certain contemporary refinements of the
43
English for Religious Studies
hermeneutic tradition which seem applicable to the problem of discerning the
meanings embedded in any written text—and only such developments in recent
hermeneutic theory which seem particularly apt for illustrating the nature of the
theologian’s hermeneutic commitment.
The first development with which we are concerned is the process of linguistic
‘distanciation’ expressed, for example, in the character of written as distinct from
spoken language. Summarily stated, this recent development in contemporary
linguistic and hermeneutic theory allows the prospective interpreter to understand that
a written text, precisely as written, is distanced both from the original intention of the
author and from its original reception by its first addressees. If this be correct, the
hermeneutic circle as it is ordinarily formulated by theologians needs reformulation.
For the task of interpretation is not best understood in terms of the interpreter’s own
subjectivity attempting to grasp the subjectivity either of the author’s intentions or of
the original addressee’s reception of its meaning. Neither should the interpreter, as his
principal concern, attempt to uncover the subjectivity of the historical person (here,
Jesus of Nazareth) described in certain images and symbols (e.g., ‘Son of Man’, ‘the
Christ’, ‘Prophet’) which seemed especially germane for representing the existential
significance of this person.
If this be the case, it does not seem to be of major theological import to engage
in old and new quests for the historical Jesus as something distinct from finding a
hermeneutic method capable of explicating the meanings of those Christological texts
referring both to Jesus and to a certain Christian mode-of-being-in-the-world.
A second major development in contemporary hermeneutic and linguistic
theory should allow one to approach that latter task with greater surety. That
development is the insistence that the contemporary interpreter must distinguish
clearly between the ‘sense’ and the ‘referents’ of the text and hence between the
methods needed to explicate each. The ‘sense’ of the text means the internal structure
and meaning of the text as that structure can be determined through the ordinary
methods of semantic and literary –critical inquiries. The ‘referents’ of the text do not
pertain to the meaning ‘behind’ the text (e.g., the author’s real intention or the sociocultural situation of the text). Rather, to shift metaphors, ‘referent’ basically manifests
the meaning ‘in front of’ the text, i.e., that way of perceiving reality, that mode of
being-in-the-world which the text opens up for the intelligent reader.
44
English for Religious Studies
Although this understanding of ‘referent’ is not divorced from either prior
historical or semantic investigations, still ‘referent’ here is clearly distinct from those
prior factors. Further, the referents of the text, on this understanding, are the factors
demanding a properly hermeneutical as distinct from wither an historical or a
semantic exercise. To show why this understanding of the hermeneutic task of the
theologian seems sound, once can concretize the discussion by applying it to the task
of understanding the existential referent of the New Testament affirmation that “Jesus
is the Christ”. At least four related methods are needed for this task: the historical
method, semantics, literary-critical methods, and finally, the explicitly hermeneutical.
First, the historian, by a full application of his methods of historical inquiry,
can reconstruct the christological texts, i.e., both those texts of Jesus and about Jesus.
Semantics can then help the interpreter to determine the linguistic structure of
the images and symbols involved in the text.
With literary-critical methods, the interpreter can determine the particular
character of the literary genres by means of which the images, metaphors and symbols
are structured, codified and transformed.
Still the meaning of major import to the theologian remains a concern that can
be formulated by a question like the following: what is the mode-of-being-in-theworld referred to by the text? That question is not really answered until an explicitly
hermeneutic enterprise is advanced. On this understanding, hermeneutics is the
discipline capable of explicating the referent as distinct from either the sense of the
text or the historical reconstruction of the text.
[Cut paragraph on Herbert Braun.]
Such a determination of a religious referent would, in fact, complete the
explicitly hermeneutic task of the theologian. The further question of the truth-status
of the referent explicated by hermeneutics remains. For that question, a distinct mode
of reflection is needed. Even if his hermeneutic enterprise were successful, the
theologian must still face the further task of correlating the results of his hermeneutic
reflections with the results of his reflections upon contemporary experience and
language. To achieve this correlation he must ask what further reflective discipline
will allow him to determine whether his earlier conclusions can legitimately be
described not only as accurate meanings but also as true. It will be the purpose of the
fifth and final thesis to articulate one understanding of what discipline can undertake
this.
45
English for Religious Studies
16 David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order, Ch. 3.5 Transcendental Method
Fifth Thesis: To determine the Truth-Status of the Results of one’s Investigations into
the Meaning of both Common Human Experience and Christian Texts the Theologian
should employ an explicitly Transcendental or Metaphysical Mode of Reflection.
This final thesis on the task of fundamental theology is probably the least
commonly accepted position of those argued for thus far. For that reason, I will
concern myself here with the attempt to show only the need for and the basic nature of
the metaphysical reflection involved in the task of theology.
The word ‘need’ is used advisedly since the proposed argument for
metaphysical inquiry is not posed as one alternative way of doing theology. Rather the
present claim is that, if the argument of the first four theses is sound, then one cannot
but recognize an exigence for metaphysical or transcendental reflection. Indeed, by
recalling the conclusions of these earlier theses we should also be able to show the
need for the metaphysical reflection suggested here.
Summarily stated, the argument has had the following structure: there are two
sources for theology (common human experience and language, and Christian texts);
those two sources are to be investigated by a hermeneutic phenomenology of the
religious dimension in common human experience and language and by historical and
hermeneutic investigations of the meanings referred to by Christian texts; the results
of these investigations should be correlated to determine their significant similarities
and differences and their truth-value. The kind of correlation needed depends, of
course, primarily upon the nature of the phenomena manifested in the prior
investigation of the two sources. Thus far, the argument has been principally for the
formal methods of investigation needed as distinct from the material conclusions
reached by such methods. Yet in order to show the need for metaphysical inquiry it
will be necessary to advance the earlier discussion by suggesting what conclusions
may be reached by contemporary investigations of the type outlined above.
In the case of a phenomenology of ordinary experience and language, several
contemporary thinkers have tried to show how a religious dimension is present to our
cognitive, moral, and everyday experience and language. [Cut]
As a first example, let us recall the existentialist analysis of the manifestation
of No-thing (i.e., no object in the world alongside other objects) in an analysis of the
phenomenon of anxiety as distinct from the phenomenon of fear. That analysis has
provided an occasion not only to show the meaning an possibility of metaphysics (as
46
English for Religious Studies
for Heidegger), but also to show the meaning and possibility of a ‘negative’ entry
point to a final, ultimate, and properly religious horizon to our everyday lives.
As a second example, the process philosopher’s analysis of the phenomenon
of that fundamental confidence or trust in existence continually re-presented in the
self-conscious faith of our everyday, our scientific, and our moral activities has also
provided a way of rendering meaningful the basic ‘faith’ operative in our secular lives.
As a third example, Paul Tillich’s analysis of the inevitable presence of an
ultimate (as distinct from a finite) concern in all human activity (however ‘demonic’
the forms of such ultimacy may become) has rendered intelligible the ontological
status of an authentically religious dimension.
As a final example, Bernard Lonergans’s analysis of the ‘formally
unconditioned’ factor presupposed by scientific and moral inquiry as well as his more
recent analysis of explicitly religious experience as “a being-in-love-withoutqualification” manifests a similar explication of the kinds of meanings present in
either the implicitly religious dimensions of our secular lives or the explicitly
religious language of the Christian tradition.
Moreover, in an intellectual context where a religious dimension to everyday
experience and language has been rendered intelligible, the question of God can be
formulated anew as the question of the necessary referent (or object) of such a
religious or ‘basic faith’ dimension. This theistic question, to be sure, involves further
and extensive reflection insofar as it is the case that even some explicitly religious
persons (e.g., some Buddhist and lately some Christian theologians) are also nontheistic. However, the theistic question itself seems both logically unavoidable and…
capable of receiving a positive answer once an authentically religious dimension is
admitted and explicated.
Correlatively, if one accepts the notion of ‘referent’ articulated in the previous
thesis, then religious and theistic meanings can also emerge from properly
hermeneutic investigations of Christian texts. From the viewpoint of historical
investigation, a secure conclusion would seem to be that whatever else Christianity
has been it has also been (and ordinarily understood itself to be) a theistic religion.
From the viewpoint of the kind of hermeneutic enterprise suggested above, the
referent of the classical texts of the Christian tradition can be described as a religious
way of being-in-the-world which understands itself in explicitly theistic terms. It is
47
English for Religious Studies
true, of course, that the further specifications of that Christian way of being-in-theworld can be and will continue to be variously described. [Cut]
If the interpretation of both contemporary experience and language and of
Christian texts could legitimately reach such similar conclusions, then the first
moment of critical correlation—the comparative moment—would be accomplished.
For the results of one’s investigations into both major sources of theology would
conclude to an identical insight: the fundamentally religious and theistic selfunderstanding presupposed by common way human experience and language and
explicitly referred to in representative Christian texts. But even this moment of
correlation does not complete the theological task. Comparative analysis may allow
one to know the basic religious referents of Christian texts and the fundamental
meaningfulness of religious and theistic categories for common experience and
language. Such analysis does not of and by itself resolve the question of the truthstatus of such meanings.
For that we must ask what reflective discipline can adequately investigate the
truth-claims of the religious and theistic meanings manifested by the prior
investigations. The exact nature of that discipline is admittedly difficult to determine.
However, certain characteristics of the discipline seem clear.
First, the discipline will have to be a reflective one capable of articulating
conceptual and not merely symbolic categories. Otherwise, the theologian can never
be sure that he has avoided either incoherence or vagueness in determining the
cognitive character of religious and theistic claims.
Second, the discipline must be able to explicate its criteria for precisely those
cognitive claims. It seems fair to affirm that such criteria will involve at least such
widely accepted criteria as the following: there must be a necessary and a sufficient
ground in our common human experience for such claims; any such claims must have
a coherence both internally and with other essential categories of our knowledge and
belief.
If such criteria are in fact the criteria widely accepted for any cognitive claims,
it becomes imperative for the theologian to specify how such criteria might function
in theology since theology too makes cognitive claims about the nature of experience.
Yet the dimension of meaning in question for theology (the religious) is not simply a
meaning coordinate with other meanings like the scientific, the aesthetic, or the
ethical. Rather the religious dimension precisely as such can be phenomenologically
48
English for Religious Studies
described as an ultimate or grounding dimension or horizon to all meaningful human
activities.
The reflective discipline needed to decide upon the cognitive claims of
religion and theism will itself have to be able to account not merely for some
particular dimension of experience but for all experience as such. Indeed, precisely
this latter insight is required to show why the theologian cannot resolve the religious
and theistic cognitive claims of theology by any ordinary criteria of verification or
falsification. Rather the very nature of the cognitive claim involve in religious and
theistic statements demands a metaphysical or transcendental mediation.
As Antony Flew quite properly insists, an investigation of the cognitive claims
of religion and theism demands that one seek to answer two fundamental questions: (1)
the ground in our common human experience for having any notions of religion and
God at all; (2) how these notions may be conceptually explicated to avoid both
vagueness and incoherence. But as it has been argued that Antony Flew fails to see,
only a reflective discipline capable of explicating criteria for the ‘conditions of the
possibility’ of all experience could really resolve the question of the meaning and
truth of authentically religious and theistic claims.
One clear way of articulating the nature of the reflective discipline capable of
such inquiry is to describe it as ‘transcendental’ in its modern formulation or
‘metaphysical’ in its more traditional expression. As transcendental, such reflection
attempts the explicit mediation of the basic presuppositions (or ‘beliefs’) that are the
conditions of the possibility of our existing or understanding at all. Metaphysical
reflection means essentially the same thing: the philosophical validation of the
concepts ‘religion’ and ‘God’ as necessarily affirmed or necessarily denied by all our
basic beliefs and understanding. We seem to be unavoidably led to the conclusion that
the task of fundamental theology can only be successfully resolved when the
theologian fully and frankly develops an explicitly metaphysical study of the
cognitive claims of religion and theism as an integral moment in his larger task.
[Cut final two paragraphs]
49