Download International Sociological Association Mid

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Unilineal evolution wikipedia , lookup

History of the social sciences wikipedia , lookup

Community development wikipedia , lookup

Rebellion wikipedia , lookup

Frankfurt School wikipedia , lookup

Security, Territory, Population wikipedia , lookup

Cultural psychology wikipedia , lookup

Philosophy of history wikipedia , lookup

Foucault's lectures at the Collège de France wikipedia , lookup

Intercultural competence wikipedia , lookup

World Values Survey wikipedia , lookup

Popular culture studies wikipedia , lookup

Anthropology of development wikipedia , lookup

Moral disengagement wikipedia , lookup

Origins of society wikipedia , lookup

Postdevelopment theory wikipedia , lookup

Global justice wikipedia , lookup

Universal pragmatics wikipedia , lookup

Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Author: Anttonen, Saila Maarit
Title: The learning processes of morality, the social justice and the recognition (Die moralische
Lernprozesse, die soziale Gerechtigkeit und die Anerkennung)
Abstract: This article discusses the ambivalent encounters between cultures as a post modern
situation. The purpose of this article is to analyse contemporary social and cultural trends on the
basis of ambivalent theses on the multicultural society and education. The values and ethics must
be examined as part of the social and cultural context which is shaped for instance by the socioeconomic status, the gender and the ethnic identity. The formation of values and ethics is not just
a moral question, as it is to a very large extent also a social and economic problem. Also, this is a
question of the social justice and the recognition of values and morality of different groups.
The problem will be analysed by examining the moral theories which use both the universal and
the relativistic approaches. A third road is sought to surpass these antitheses by analysing the
discourse ethics introduced by Jürgen Habermas and Michel Foucault's ethics of transgression,
"the ethics of crossing the boundaries", too. Finally, the effects of the education and the ethical
education on society and culture are analysed. The alternatives for the social processes of moral
learning will be outlined.
Document type and origin: An English version of conference paper (in German) will presented in
EERA-conference. Network 24 “Open network”. Hamburg 18th September 2003.
Suggested key terms: morality, learning, social justice, recognition, postmodernity, multicultural
education and society, Foucault, Habermas, feminism
Version Number: English version of German paper, which is not direct translation
1
The learning processes of morality, the social justice and the recognition (Die moralische
Lernprozesse, die soziale Gerechtigkeit und die Anerkennung)
Saila Anttonen
University of Lapland
Finland
1. Introduction: a void of values or a flood of values in multicultural society?
Thesis 1.
We are living simultaneously in an increasingly monistic and pluralistic postmodern culture. The
monistic tendency of values is caused by the fact that the diminished significance of the fixed
collective values of the rural society is making room for the large-scale appearance of
commercial values. At the same time, the loosening of collective norms makes a more pluralistic
culture possible. The ambivalent tendencies of the postmodern society produce the impression of
a void of values. The impression of the void is just a fancy which emerges from the erosion of
traditional values produced by the process of modernization. In the minds of people it generates
the impression that values which are different from the traditional values are not values at all, as
we live in a void of values. The impression is particularly strong at times when very rapid
changes are taking place.
The increasingly pluralistic culture is a clearer fact in the ambivalent swells of the l990s caused
by the quickly changed economic and political situation. In the cultural turmoil the remains of
the integrated culture typical of the rural society can still be seen, but their significance is
decreasing. Similar erosion has also affected the working-class culture and labour movement
which aim at active change and social action. Marx’s “Capital” and “the Bible” have been losing
their significance as the basis for people’s sets of values (see e.g. Lyotard, 1985). The changes
from the working-class culture and partly also from the middle-class way of living towards an
unemployment culture can be seen in an increasingly drastic way in the Finnish society.
The problem in the emergence of this postmodern dispersion of values and the superficial yuppie
culture is above all the fact that collectiveness and collective consciousness directed to active
action have lost part of their significance. From the viewpoint of collective consciousness and
action, the idea of a “void of values” is quite justifiable. Subcultures aiming at active influence
and action still exist as cultural relics, with the obvious aim of presenting their dissenting opinion
2
when late capitalism is dashing into the life-world of different social groupings, causing a
turmoil of values there (see and cf. e.g. Venkula & Raustevaara, 1993.) Examples of such social
movements include the feminist movement and the environmental activists.
In the broader context this is not about an absolute void of values, as the things which were
previously valued are replaced in the life-world of human beings by new objects of valuation.
But it is difficult any more to speak about values in their connection, if we assume that there are
certain intrinsic values, which are characterized by stability and reasonable permanence. They
have been replaced by a postmodern superficiality, in which transient valuation has replaced
permanent values.
The valuations in the postmodern or late capitalist society are shaped increasingly by the
thoroughly commercialised way of living and consumption (see Jameson, 1989). This trend tends
to standardize valuations. It forces its way to the consciousness and way of living of all social
and cultural groups. It is obvious that all groups do not meet with this commercialism and
orientation towards consumption in the same way. This is a consequence of the fact that the late
capitalist society has drawn the circles of inequality with increased sharpness, and they
determine as such how different social groups can take part in this feast of abundant
consumption. Meanwhile this causes a different kind of development. The various cultural
groupings and sets of values are differentiated further from each other, because there is more
inequality. At the same time, a situation is generated which aggravates the relations of different
groups.
I will next examine two alternative approaches by means of which it is possible to study the
problem of the debate on values and ethical education in the multicultural postmodern society.
The approaches built on the theories of morality and ethics presented by Jürgen Habermas and
Michel Foucault are debating at the same time along the dimension between moral universalism
and moral relativism. In their own ways, they are both searching for a third way in which this
dichotomy could be surpassed. Finally, I will examine the potential trends of moral learning
which are opened up by multiculturalization.
3
2. Universal or relativistic morality in multicultural society: from Lawrence Kohlberg to Jürgen
Habermas
Thesis 2.
The examination of questions related to values and ethics in terms of an individual’s free choices
or as ethical principles formed in a group is not an adequate starting-point for an analysis of the
problem. The values and ethics must be examined as part of the social and cultural context
which is shaped for instance by the socio-economic status, gender and ethnic identity. The
shaping of values and ethics is not just a moral question, as it is to a very large extent also a
social and economic matter. The values and changes in them are not determined directly by
economic factors, though, but the economic context is manifesting itself in the sets of values and
consciousness of different cultural groups.
2.1. Kohlberg’s monologic universalism and its limits
Lawrence Kohlberg and Robert A. Ryncarz (1 990a) reject cultural relativism, according to
which every culture has different moral conceptions and basic values. According to the relativist
view, values, norms and morality are accepted in certain subcultures, cultures or societies only.
They make a distinction between culturally bound rules and the universal principles which are to
be found in all cultures and represent universal moral values. Universal principles like these
which are to be found in all cultures include those of the respect of human dignity, equality and
justice.
In criticism of the universality emphasized by Kohlberg et al. we can say that there is not a single
culture in which these principles have not been violated, so the violation of these principles can
be thought of as a universal phenomenon. On the other hand, they have been required in most
cultures, not always universally but within one’s own group. As a concrete example of such a
procedure we can mention the National Socialist doctrine and its requirement of the purity of the
Aryan race. This was possible because they were not given human dignity, whereby this
principle did not apply to them. The conflict between reality and ideals is shown in a very
pointed way in Kohlberg’s theory of morality, as the theory does not necessary require the
construction of communication between different cultural groups. Only the construction of such
a relationship could bring out the problems and limits of universal moral principles.
4
The problem has a marginal position in the theory of Kohlberg & Ryncarz (1990a), because they
think that the development of the individuals’ morality follows the same general regularities
irrespective of the cultural environment. In terms of her/his moral views, the human being
develops in all societies in such a way that s/he moves from preconventional, selfish and
egocentric ways of thinking through conventional ways of thinking which respect collective lines
of action to judgements and principles which emphasize universality. Acting in accordance with
the conventional level means that the contracts and conventions prevailing in society are
renewed, which does not, at least in the situation of the modern society, promote the realization
of the principle of universal equality. On the postconventional levels, the judgements which
emphasize universality begin to act as a yardstick also when the moral views of one’s own
community and society are assessed. The criteria for the assessment are human dignity
and universal justice. If the laws or the rules of the community conflict with the principles of
justice, equality, reciprocity and human rights, the human being who has reached this kind of
moral consciousness will act against them.
In their theory Kohlberg & Ryncarz (1990a) also develop a cosmic level of moral development
on which the individual speculates on the essence of morality. The individual speculates why on
the whole it is worth the while to be moral. Why should one act in a moral way? Why should one
act in a just way in an unjust world? The human being feels that s/he is part of the great universe
and understands that the idea of right and wrong is based on the basic logic of this whole and its
preservation. The basis of moral rules is not in the principles which have emerged from social
contracts, but in the universal principles which manifest the order of nature. The cosmic law also
determines the limits of social life. Ethical action means that we act in such a way that the
development of humanity can continue. This requires a universal perspective on moral questions
which surpasses the basic sets of values of different cultural groups and the conflicts between
them.
The monologic nature of Kohlberg’s theory of moral development, which leans ultimately on the
individual’s development, is seen very clearly when it is compared to the discourse ethics of
Habermas which emphasizes intersubjectivity and collectiveness. It does not take into account
the intersubjective, discursive context and society in which the moral development of individuals
takes place. There are no grounds for arguing that individuals develop on a large scale to
postconventional levels in their moral views in Western societies, whose principles of action for
the most part and increasingly follow preconventional moral principles. It is not possible to
surpass these social contexts, if moral questions are examined only as questions related to the
development of individuals.
5
Must note, however, that a strong collective aspect is to be found in the theory of Kohlberg &
Ryncarz (1 990a). It is a problem, however, how such a perspective can be constructed. Critical
observations could also be presented against the emphasis of morality on developmental theory.
Morality does not develop according to some built-in logic of an individual’s development, as it
is learned in social interaction. It is always learned in a certain society and culture, whereby the
existing unjust context of society and cultural hegemony shapes what is actually learned as
morality and as being a moral thing. Sometimes a critical viewpoint can also be learned, through
which it is observed that there is a glaring conflict between moral universalism and the real
social situation.
Gilligan, Murphy & Tappan (1990) criticize Kohlberg’s ethics of universal principles,
maintaining that there is no single correct ethical way to act and think, as the ways of action
which are ethically right are very much bound to the situation. Gilligan et al. (1990) criticize
Kohlberg’s ethics of principles because there is not always any sense in acting on individual
inflexible moral principles, as there can often be several correct moral principles in the moral
problem situations arising from everyday conflicts. According to them, the emphasis on
universality can even serve injustice and inequality on the level of everyday life, which is also
proved by the example which I presented above about the teacher who is unconsciously
marketing middle-class values as if they were universal values.
Gilligan et al. represent a more relativistic view. According to them, no absolutely reliable,
universally valid truths or values exist for solving the moral problems which emerge in human
interaction. Does Gilligan’s criticism based on the relativism of two moralities warrant rejection
of universal moral principles or their reformulation? The basis for the criticism is provided by
the idea that the moral orientation which leans on justice is a masculine one, while women’s
moral orientation is characterized by caring to others and orientation based on situational moral
problems. (also see Nunner-Winkler, 1990; Peltonen 1993). These critical observations do not
unambiguously give occasion to the rejection of universal principles, even though the warning
based on the cultural bounds about their misuse must be taken seriously. Rather it gives cause to
search for a third path in between the dichotomies of moral relativism and universalism. The
perspectives are not mutually exclusive but mutually necessary, which I will try to prove next by
examining Jürgen Habermas discourse ethics first and in the next chapter Michel Foucault’s
“ethics of breaking the bounds”, the ethics of transgression.
2.2. Habermas’ discourse ethics — universal ethical argumentation
6
I will next describe shortly the criticism which Habermas (1990) presents against the theory of
moral development by Kohlberg et al. (1990b) and how he develops Kohlberg’s approach into
discourse ethics. Discourse ethics holds to the principles of universal justice and equality, but it
also takes into account the cultural and value-related variety in the modern society. Its goal is to
overcome the rigid controversy between universalism and relativism.
Habermas (1990) criticizes the theory of Kohlberg et al. (1 990b) for remaining an activity which
is monologic, private and realized in isolation despite its emphasis on taking a universal (or
everyone else’s) perspective. Habermas’ own goal is to make this principle into a public event
which is put into effect by all people together. The goal of this kind of universal, intersubjective
discourse is to overcome the local priorities of things and traditional (conventional)
arrangements. Rational and common formation of will and decision-making can only be realized
in discursive communication which is characterized by taking into account all the other
viewpoints and the ability to criticize the moral views which have been subjected to discussion.
However, carrying out such discourses requires that they are reflective argumentation or
argumentative debate, in which different arguments and interests are subjected to discussion. A
prerequisite is that the argumentation changes previous attitudes, local contracts and views which
are bound to one’s own interests. This enables argumentation in which it is possible to go beyond
prevailing circumstances and to construct a morality which is universally valid. This is necessary
if we adhere to the idea of universal justice and equality in an unjust and unequal world. The idea
of such argumentation in which the viewpoints of all people are represented universally entails
the idea of the universal and equal possibility of everyone to take part in the formulation of
ethical and moral principles. The principles can claim the position of a universal morality only if
they are accepted jointly, i.e. by the imaginary community of the world. (for further details, see
Habermas, 1983; Habermas, 1990; Anttonen, l993a.)
Analysing the boundaries of his discourse ethics, Habermas (1989, 1990) says that the principle
of discourse ethics, according to which all the interested parties must accept a norm before
universal validity can be claimed for it, is in principle a purely regulating one in the context of
discourses which are being realized. Its realization is unlikely and historically more distant.
However, the idea can be used as a tool for criticism and to prove how difficult (if not
impossible) it is to build a universal perspective like this in the present world, which Habermas
actually considers to be modern on the grounds that it has not fully given up the search for a
more equal and rightful world. (also see Anttonen, l993b; Anttonen, 1992.)
7
However, we could criticize that Habermas somehow forgets the prevailing injustice when he
develops his discourse ethics. He forgets the inequality which is prevailing there and the
unevenly distributed resources, which predetermine the context in which this kind of discourse is
carried on. If the cards have already been dealt in such a way that someone has all the aces and
another one has all the deuces, it is not enough just to say that money and power, among others,
distort communication in reality (see Habermas, l987a). Discourse ethics is functional in the
coolly rational academic reasoning, but how durable is it in reality as a tool for solving the value
conflicts which break through the postmodern culture and the increasingly ambivalent cultural
context in which we are proceeding deeper and deeper in the direction of inequality and, at the
same time, injustice, and this situation and trend is even thought to be justifiable. (for more
details, see Anttonen, l993b; Anttonen, 1993c; Anttonen, 1994)
Habermas (1990) is therefore forced to restrict the use of his discourse ethics to the evaluation of
collective action and to questions of justification, leaving questions of application outside his
analysis to avoid these problems. According to him, going beyond the state of the conflicts of
interests requires, however, also solidarity, in which case the principles of solicitude and justice,
which Gilligan considered opposite, are actually matched together. Solidarity with the other
members of a community cannot, however, be built according to traditionalist solidarity in such a
way that it develops into a solidarity in which the individual is ready to sacrifice herself/himself
on behalf of the collective system. Habermas mentions the principles of action of Nazi Germany
as an example of this kind of non-discursively formed, compelling solidarity. One must be
capable of building such a discursiveness in which the arguments go beyond the limits of
particular life-worlds (one’s own group, class, community, race, nationality, gender), so that
justice and solidarity can become universal. So, these different life-worlds should be brought into
a mutual discourse oriented towards mutual understanding to make it possible to make progress
on the way to constructing the universal morality.
3. Michel Foucault: the radical politics of dissimilarity and multiculturalism
Thesis 3.
Moral theories which lean on uncompromising universalism do not seem plausible in the context
of postmodern multiculturalism and dissimilarity. This does not mean, however, that we should
abandon the requirements for universal justice and equality. A third way must be found, one
which goes beyond the dichotomy of staff universalism and relativism.
Could Michel Foucault’s relativistically inclined “ethics of breaking the boundaries” contribute
8
something to the analysis of practical questions of application? At least it does function as a
critical voice in relation to the very strong demands for universality. As far as I can see, their
applicability in the culture of the postmodern radical dissimilarity in particular should be
reassessed. In addition, it brings up more importantly than the approaches analysed previously
also the viewpoint of those social groups which have not yet in the present had a share in this
universal justice (Foucault, 1976; Foucault, 1977; Anttonen, l993b). This point of view is
congruent with the views of expert women involved in ethical discussion. They criticize
Habermas’ discourse ethics, among other things, because it represents the moral views of the
middle-class European man even in its formulations of the principle of discursiveness despite all
its emphasis on discursiveness. (see Benhabib, 1988; Gilligan & al. 1990; Nunner-Winkler,
1990; Richters, 1988.)
Foucault’s “ethics of breaking the boundaries” and politics of radical dissimilarity starts from
this very strong viewpoint of difference. It is built on the idea that a tremendous amount of
disciplining and normalizing power has been used in the history of the project of modernity
through ethical and moral universalism, making us both subjects and subordinated people at the
same time. This is why Foucault thinks that the construction of ‘ethics of dissimilarity” is an
urgent challenge of our times. The basic problem is how to build ethical bases which do not, in
accordance with the moral principles of modernity, any longer carry out any disciplining and
punishing function. (Foucault, 1980.) According to him, religion, law or scientific knowledge as
such cannot any longer function as the unquestioned basis for new kinds of ethics, for the simple
reason that they have lost some of their significance in shaping people’s value sets in the
postmodern, multicultural society. (Richters, 1988; also see Anttonen, 1993a; Foucault, 1976;
Foucault, 1977.)
For this reason the grounds for new kinds of ethics also become problematic. The old grounds
are not good enough for Foucaults (1976; 1977) purposes, because they have, according to him,
advanced disciplining and normalizing processes of power throughout the history of modern
society. The purpose of these processes has been to produce compliance, obedience and
uniformity adhering to strict norms among people, suppressing cultural diversity and radical
dissimilarity. In this respect Foucault’s philosophical system is quite similar to Habermas’
(1981) thesis of the colonization of the life-world. The colonization of the life-world means the
destruction of cultural diversity by colonizing the different cultural forms in accordance with the
ideas of the mainstream. In the late capitalist society, this is effected increasingly by the
supranational market and bureaucratic administrative system. In this context we can see more
clearly the problem which is included in all non-discursive moral starting-points which demand
9
universality. By means of the demands for universality, it is possible to justify the moral views of
a given individual cultural group by claiming that they are universal.
Foucault’s ethics of change or breaking the boundaries has the- same intentions as Habermas’
(1991) discourse ethics. Foucault thinks, above all, that his ethical explication is a chance to go
beyond the limits which have been implanted in us: By taking this view Foucault steps into the
shoes of the victims of normalizing moralism and assumes their perspective more clearly than
Habermas does. The grounds for Foucault’s ethics, however, remain on a much more relativistic
soil than Habermas discourse ethics. Yet his starting-point which puts an emphasis on radical
dissimilarity and diversity of ethics seems to be a more plausible analysis of the truth in the
present cultural diversity. At the same time the relativistic nature of his ethical grounds and the
penetrativeness of his power analysis in particular also call into question the universalism which
Habermas links to the principles of justice, solidarity and equality.
This basic difference gives rise to the criticism which Habermas (1987b) and those who are close
to his thought have presented against Foucault, even accusing him of moral nihilism and of
complete rejection of the moral-political theory. It is actually true that Foucault did not give any
public attention to ethical questions nor did he attempt to formulate his own ethical ideas until
the early 1980s, a little before he died. Yet we must observe that even Foucault’s pure analysis of
power contained certain ethical viewpoints, when he, for instance, outlined the perspective of the
subordinated ones and victims. Additionally, his own radical activities in favour of the victims of
the social control machinery does not support the assumption that he thought in the Nietzschean
way that he was fully beyond morality. (see e.g. Habermas, l987b; Anttonen, 1994; D’Amigo,
1990—91; Dews, 1986; Haaparanta, 1985; Nikolinakos, 1990; Michael, 1990; Foucault, 1978;
Richters, 1988; Soper, 1990.) Richters (1988) argues that the Foucauldian approach does not lead
to moral nihilism, but only to scepticism in relation to the great objectives and universal goals of
modernity.
The fundamental challenge of combining the views of Habermas and Foucault, is provided by
how to do justice both to radical dissimilarity and to commensurability or to the Habermasian
principle of orientation towards consensus and understanding each other. Foucault’s ethics of
transgression is a significant supplement to Habermas discourse ethics. At the same time their
combination reaches beyond the artificial — yet absolutistically presented — boundary in the
dichotomy between relativism and universalism. Is there any obstacle to representing universal
dissimilarity or universalism which takes into account plurality? Foucault’s ethics of
dissimilarity concentrates its attention especially on the change of attitudes, views and starting-
10
points which Habermasian argumentation hopes for. The basic goal of Foucault’s ethics of
breaking the boundaries is to make possible revolting against the ways in which we have been
defined, classified and categorized in advance. This viewpoint does not lead into Nietzschean
nihilism but to a pessimistic activism, in which the starting-point is provided by seeing the
radical dissimilarity of the backyards. Seeing it was also realized in Foucault’s own activities —
in concrete action for the groups which were subdued. (see Richters 1988; Eribon, 1993.)
4. Tendencies of moral learning in multicultural society
Thesis 4.
The crosscurrents caused by the dissimilarity of the life-worlds of different cultural groups are
manifested as attempts winged by many kinds of interests to solve the problem of the dispersion
of collective identity. The attempts to solve it can also be considered as alternative courses of
development for the processes of moral learning. In postmodern culture, crosscurrents are
caused by the attempt to restore premodern moralism, modern normalization, modern
discursiveness, postmodern plurality and postmodern nihilism.
I will finally summarize the various elements of my paper and I will also outline possible
tendencies of moral learning from the viewpoint of the problem of recognition. At the same time
it faces questions related to values, ethics, morality, justice and equality. The problem of
recognition is an ethical problem, because at the same time as we are taking a stand on whether
we are to approach these questions from the viewpoint of ethical universalism or relativism,
among others, we are also promoting different processes of moral learning. The learning
processes are spread through education, shaping the limits within which individuals are
developing into subjects and members of society who realize certain ethical principles. At the
same time, processes of social learning are realized which are in accordance with the acquired
ethical ideas, and these processes can naturally be directed in highly different ways according to
the ideas and principles which have been adopted as the basis for the construction of a subject's
own action and of common action in particular.
On the basis of my previous examinations I will outline a few trends for the processes of moral
learning which also direct the development of Western societies for their part — a development
which has also been called the project of modernity. Or would it perhaps be more up-to-date to
speak about the project of postmodernity? (also see Anttonen, 1992; Anttonen, 1993a.)
11
1. Premodern moralism
Premodern moralism represents an attempt at normalizing cultural dissimilarity to restore
traditionalist values to power. It is characteristic of premodern moralism that it directs its
disapproving attention to everyday action, forgetting at the same time the basic questions of
social morality, such as the question of justice. The tendency is functional for the late capitalist
social development which is based on the advancement of economic growth, as it also promotes
puritanical ethics of obligation and conventions in emphasizing traditional values (also see
Weber, 1980). At the same time, these principles support unintentionally such a set of values of
postmodern nihilism that make possible the rise of attitudes and values which discriminate other
cultural groups. From a setup of an unquestioned set of values it is not possible to build tolerance
of other cultural groups and their values. Premodern moralism can be thought of as an attempt to
resist the dispersion of common moral consciousness. A return to discipline and order is needed.
These attempts at restoration pave the way for the disciplining project of modernity, working for
a return to the values of the past, to a solid community and mythical cosmology. It is a project of
inequality which also feeds various extremist phenomena, such as racism or sexual
discrimination, as it reinforces the boundary of one’s own community and gives its views and
actions priority over other groups and cultures.
2. Modern normalization
According to Richters (1988), the moral views which have been demanding universality, such as
the Western project of modernity which demanded enlightenment of people, have not really
represented universality but have rather wished they were universal. The
European project of the Enlightenment, for instance, has succumbed to moral imperialism, when
it has ignored heterogeneity, otherness and dissimilarity while appealing to universal humanity
and human character. To guarantee the credibility of cultural power system, there is an
increasingly sore need for a disciplining education in values and standards, a normalization
which can in principle accept safe multiculturalism — a multiculturalism which is distant enough
from everyday life or whose deviations from “normality” are small enough or the business of
sufficiently small groups. It is actually not dangerous to the mainstream culture or to the middleclass machinery of normalization.
It is also characteristic of the ethics which produces normalization, as well as of premodern
12
moralism, that an attempt is made to formulate the ethical principles in dichotomies between the
ethical and unethical and the more moral and less moral. The application of this starting-point to
concrete value problems usually effects only the middle-class orientation of values, which claims
or thinks it represents ethical universalism. By means of their seeming universalism, its
representatives justify the normalization processes. The capitalist, supranational economic
system and the value systems built by it will make sure even in the future that the “void of
values” which may develop in transition periods is filled up.
3. Modern discourse ethics and postmodern plurality
Habermas’ attempt to build an approach based on discourse ethics and at the same time to reform
the basis of moral theories oriented towards universality is significant. It is a proposed solution to
resist the dispersed collective consciousness and increased monism in the capitalist society. Its
goal is to assemble collective action from the fragments of pluralistic consciousness by looking
for new ways to communicate. The problem is that it is difficult to start building communication,
if the economic and socio-political context is not taken more clearly into account. Despite all the
emphasis on equality, there is the danger of representing the universalism of white, middle-class
men. Habermas really represents academically cool discourse ethics, the realization of which is
quite unlikely in the multiculturality of the backyards of streets and schools.
The postmodern radical dissimilarity reminds us of the difficulties involved in the realization of
discourse ethics which assumes equal conditions for discussion. Lyotard’s (1985) description of
postmodernity, for instance, is thought provoking. Increased lack of confidence is directed to the
great stories, which results in their fragmentation into local stories and cultural language games,
which of course makes the construction of communication more difficult. Postmodernity swears
by dissimilarity and disagreement. This kind of trend would actually mean that cultures and
different subcultures gradually start to disappear as solid entities, changing into more superficial
formations, in which the important thing is to play with, for instance, styles, roles and
consumption habits. The basic problem in this superficial and seemingly diverse culture is that
the social subject and the actor oriented towards active change is fragmented in postmodernity. A
good point in it is that in principle the cultural freedom of people to choose their own identity
and form of life grows. An interesting question is if this state of cultural dispersion will realize a
fragmentation into partial cultures and subcultures, in which the rights of the minorities are
violated even more, or if the diversity will give rise to communication and processes of learning
which aim at an equal society and in which dissimilarity is not only tolerated but also
encouraged?
13
4. Postmodern nihilism
Foucault’s ethics of transgression could also be important in the realization of the project
described above, especially as the postmodern culture is in danger of turning to moral
nihilism, which reveals best that the plurality of postmodernity is apparent. The late capitalist
economic system has already drawn the boundaries of pluralism, which only seem to be more
flexible than before. At the same time the increasingly strained meritocracy also producers losers
with their own subcultures and sets of values.
The danger of the relativism of values and moral views is in a collective and social slip from
scepticism to moral nihilism. In fact it is already manifesting itself in the form of walking
nihilism, which has slipped into a state of valuelessness and indifference after the dispersion of
the earlier collectiveness and the solid system of values (McLaren, 1993). The trend of thorough
capitalization in our culture supports this situation by building the conditions for inequality
which close the trap. Meanwhile moral nihilism prevents those who would have the greatest
reasons to demand equality from orienting towards active social action. They flee or are edged
outside of it.
The possibilities are still open for all of these trends, because tendencies which are parallel to
them are still living in contemporary dialectically constructed culture which is becoming both
more monistic and pluralistic simultaneously. The encrisement of the monistic system is
gnawing at its own foundations and causing a resistance which rises from the life-world of
people, which in turn rises from the effects of the encrisement of the system and problems with
credibility, forcing different cultural groups to look for a way to communicate (also see
Habermas, 1973; Anttonen, l993c). But is finding a way to communicate a real alternative, as no
support can be found any longer in any single and uniform collective consciousness?
Foucault’s ethics of change and breaking the boundaries could be useful in this context as well,
because its specific goal is to add to the capacity to tolerate dissimilarity, which is needed to
construct communication between quite different systems of values. Even the Habermasian
project of communication could have a place in its realization as a force which provides for
communication and mutual solidarity.
Could the search for a way to communicate between different groups also act as the key to
solving the problem that such a starting-point for universal communication cannot any longer
14
enter the service of disciplining and normalizing power? It opens up perspectives for efforts to
construct an even greater equality — an equality which does not, however, suppress the value
systems of different cultures but gives them the chance to act from each and everyone’s own
starting-points. It is only then that true moral universalism is realized. The combination of
Habermas’ discourse ethics and Foucault’s ethics of breaking the boundaries open up new
horizons and potentials.
Finally, we can note in the spirit of the critical theory of Max Horkheimer (1977) that, even
though we were pessimists in our theoretical analyses, we are not left with any other possibilities
than to be practical optimists, if we wish to act in favour of a better future and in particular if we
wish to take seriously the challenge issued to educators by Theodor W. Adorno (1966): to act as
educators for an ethical education which guarantees that Auschwitz never happens again. This is
indeed the problem of recognition and education for tolerance.
"So erhält der Kampf um Anerkennung ein gleichsam historisches Potential, das über
jeweils etablierte Formen von Anerkennungsverhältnissen hinaustreibt." (Honneth 1990,
153).
15
References
Adorno, T. W. 1966. Erziehung nach Auschwitz. In T.W. Adorno. 1981. Erziehung zur
Mündigkeit. Vortrage und Gespräche mit Helmut Becker 1959-1969. Hrsg von B. Kadelbach,
Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Taschenbuch Verlag.
Anttonen, S. 1992. Vapaa ja mielekäs moderni - kriittisen teorian historiallisen perustelun ehtoja.
Suomen kasvatustieteellinen aikakauskirja, Kasvatus 23 (4), 317-326.
Anttonen, S. 1993a. Modernisaatio ja kasvatuksen suuntautumisen kriisi. Suomen
kasvatustieteellinen aikakauskirja, Kasvatus 24 (2), 115-125.
Anttonen, S. 1993b. Tieteenteoreettiset perusteet yhteiskunnallisissa murroksissa: Tieteen ja
vallan kahdet kasvot. In S. Anttonen & R. Raivola (toim.) 1993. Kasvatus ja koulutus
muuttuvassa yhteiskunnassa. XIV kasvatustieteen päivät Oulussa 26.-28.11.1992.
Kasvatustieteiden tiedekunnan opetusmonisteita j a selosteita 53, 57-83.
Anttonen, S. 1993c Järjen kriisi - korkeakoulutuksen uhka vai mahdollisuus. In H. Jalkanen & L.
Lestinen (toim.) 1993. Korkeakoulutuksen kriisi? Artikkelikokoelma Jyväskylässä 19.-20.8.
1993 järjestetystä Korkeakoulutuksen tutkimuksen V symposiumista. Kasvatustieteiden
tutkimuslaitos, Jyvaskylä: Yliopistopaino, 1-13.
Anttonen, S. 1994. Modernisaation ristivedoissa. Kriittinen matka ajanvirrassa. Acta
Universitatis Ouluensis E 18, 1994. (Abstract in English.)
Benhabib, S. 1988. The Generalized and the Concrete Other: The Kohlberg-Gilligan Controversy
and Feminist Theory. In S. Benhabib & D. Cornell (eds.) 1988. Feminism as Critique. On the
Politics of Gender. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 77-95.
D’Amigo, R. 1990-91. Karl Popper and the Frankfurt school. Telos. A quarterly Journal of
Critical Thought, 86, Winter 1990-91, 33-48.
Dews, P. 1986. Adorno, Poststructuralism and the Critique of Identity. New left review, 157/
1986, May/June, 28-44.
16
Eribon, D. 1993. Michel Foucault. Tampere: Vastapaino.
Foucault, M. 1976. Two Lectures. In M. Foucault. 1980. Power/knowledge. Selected Interviews
and other writings 1972-1977 by Michel Foucault, 78-108. C. Gordon (ed.) Brighton: Harvester
Press.
Foucault, M. 1977. Truth and power. In M. Foucault. 1980. Power/knowledge. Selected
Interviews and other writings 1972-1977 by Michel Foucault, 109-133. C. Gordon (ed.)
Brighton: Harvester Press.
Foucault, M. 1978. Nietzsche, die Genealogie, die Historie. In M. Foucault. Von der Subversion
des Wissens. W. Seitter (Ubers. und Hrsg.) Berlin: Ulstein. Urspr. Foucault, M. 1971. Nietzsche,
la généalogie, l’histoire; aus: Hommage a Jean Hyppolite, Paris, P.U.F.
Foucault, M. 1980. Tarkkailla ja rangaista. Helsinki: Otava.
Gilligan, C., Murphy, J. M. & Tappan, M. B. 1990. Moral Development Beyond Adolescence. In
C. N. Alexander (ed.) 1990. Higher Stages of human development: perspectives on adult growth.
New York: Oxford University Press, 208-225.
Haaparanta, L. 1985. Voiko Nietzschen yli-ihminen olla nainen? In L. Alanen, L. Haaparanta &
T. Lumme (toim.) 1985. Nainen, järki ja ihmisarvo. Esseitä filosofian klassikoiden
naiskäsityksistä.
Juva: WSOY, 271-292.
Habermas, J. 1973. Legitimation Crisis. T. McCarthy (transl.)Boston: Beacon.
Habermas, J. 1981. Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns. Band 2. Zur Kritik der
funktionalistischen Vernunft. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Habermas, J. 1983. Moralbewusstsein und kommunikatives Handeln. Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp.
Habermas, J. 1987a. Järki ja kommunikaatio. Tekstejä 198 1-1985. J. Kotkavirta (toim.)
Helsinki: Gaudeamus.
17
Habermas, J. 1987b. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: twelve lectures. F. Lawrence
(transl.) Cambridge: Polity Press.
Habermas, J. 1989. Yksilöllinen tahdonmuodostus: Mikä on tarkoituksenmukaista, mikä hyvää ja
mikä oikeudenmukaista? Tiede & edistys. Tutkijaliiton aikakauslehti 2/89, 86-95.
Habermas, J. 1990. Justice and Solidarity: On the Discussion Concerning Stage 6. In T. Wred
(ed.). 1990. The Moral Domain. Essays in the Ongoing Discussion between Philosophy and the
Social Sciences. Cambridge: The MIT Press, 224-254.
Habermas, J. 1991. Erlauterungen zur Diskursethik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp taschenbuch
wissenschaft.
Habermas, J. 1993. Anerkennungskämpfe im demokratischen Rechtsstaat. In C. Taylor.
Multikulturalismus und die Politik der Anerkennung. Mit Kommentaren von Amy Gutmann
(Hg.) Steven C. Rockefeller. Michael Walzer. Susan Wolf. Mit einem Beitrag von Jürgen
Habermas. Frankfurt am Main: S. Fischer.
Honneth, A. 1990. Die zerrissene Welt des Sozialen. Sozialphilosophische Aufsätze. Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp.
Horkheimer, M. 1977. Kritische Theorie. Eine Dokumentation. A. Schmidt (Hrsg.) Band 1 und
2. Frankfurt am Main: S. Fischer Verlag GmbH.
Jameson, F. 1989. Marxism and Postmodernism. New left review, 176/1989, August, 3 1-46.
Kohlberg, L. & Ryncarz, R. A. 1990a. Beyond Justice Reasoning: Moral Development and
Consideration of a Seventh Stage. In C. N. Alexander (ed.) 1990. Higher Stages of human
development: perspectives on adult growth. New York: Oxford University Press, 191-207.
Kohlberg, L., Boyd, D. R. & Levine, C. 199Gb. The Return of Stage 6: Its Principle and Moral
Point of View. In T. Wred (ed.). 1990. The Moral Domain. Essays in the Ongoing Discussion
between Philosophy and the Social Sciences. Cambridge: The MIT Press, 15 1-181.
Lyotard, J-F. 1985. Tieto postmodernissa yhteiskunnassa. Tampere: Vastapaino.
18
McLaren, P. 1993. Critical Pedagogy, Multiculturalism and the Politics of Liberation.
Presentation at the Twelfth International Human Science Research Conference at the University
of Groningen, Groningen, the Netherlands. August 10-14, 1993. Abstract of presentation in G.
Biesta, B. Boog, S. Miedema, A. Smalling, W. Wardekker & B. Levering (eds.) 1993. Human
Sciences at the Intersection of Politics, Social Change and Development, and Political Decision
Making. Montfoort: Uriah Heep.
Michael, J. 1990. Vanguard and Critique. Telos. A quarterly Journal of Critical Thought, 83,
Spring 1990, 189-204.
Nikolinakos, D. D. 1990. Foucaults Ethical Quandary. Telos. A quarterly Journal of Critical
Thought, 83, Spring 1990, 123-140.
Nunner-Winkler, G. 1990. Moral Relativism and Strict Universalism. In T. Wred (ed.). 1990.
The Moral Domain. Essays in the Ongoing Discussion between Philosophy and the Social
Sciences. Cambridge: The MIT Press, 109-128.
Peltonen, J. 1993. Moraalikasvatus ja sukupuoli. In S. Anttonen & R. Raivola (toim.) 1993.
Kasvatus ja koulutus muuttuvassa yhteiskunnassa. XIV kasvatustieteen päivat Oulussa 26.28.11.1992. Oulun yliopiston kasvatustieteiden tiedekunnan opetusmonisteita ja selosteita 51.
Richters, A. 1988. Modernity-Postmodernity Controversies: Habermas and Foucault. Theory,
Culture and Society 4, Vol. 5 (1988), 611-643.
Soper, K. 1991. Postmodernism, Subjectivity and a Question of Value. New left review,
186/1991, April, 120-128.
Venkula, J. & Rautevaara, A. 1993. Arvot ja nuorten arvopohdinta. Helsinki: Yliopistopaino.
Weber, M. 1980. Protestanttinen etiikka ja kapitalismin henki. T. Kyntäjä (suom.) Juva: WSOY.
19