Download a PDF version

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Philosophy of science wikipedia , lookup

Philosophy in Canada wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Prediction and Accommodation in Evolutionary Psychology
Malcolm Forster
Department of Philosophy
University of Wisconsin – Madison
Lawrence Shapiro
Department of Philosophy
University of Wisconsin – Madison
Ketelaar and Ellis have provided a remarkably clear and succinct statement of Lakatosian
philosophy of science and have also argued compellingly that the neo-Darwinian theory of evolution fills the Lakatosian criteria of progressivity. We find ourselves in agreement with much
of what Ketelaar and Ellis say about Lakatosian philosophy of science, but have some questions
about (1) the place of evolutionary psychology in a Lakatosian framework, and (2) the extent to
which evolutionary psychology truly predicts new findings.
Lakatos, as Ketelaar and Ellis observe, conceives of research programs as having two levels: a hard core consisting of fundamental meta-theoretical assumptions and a protective belt
containing auxiliary assumptions. Together, the hard core and the protective belt produce hypotheses and predictions that, ultimately, can confirm or disconfirm the assumptions in the hard
core. Typically, however, failed predictions do not call into question the meta-theoretical assumptions of the hard core. This is so, for hypotheses and predictions derive from the hard core
and the auxiliary assumptions of the protective belt. Consequently, given recalcitrant data, one
can always place the blame on the assumptions in the protective belt, leaving untarnished the
meta-theoretical assumptions of the hard core. It is only when the protective belt begins to function simply as a device for explaining away anomalies and does little by way of generating new
predictions that the time comes to suspect the assumptions of the hard core.
Lakatos' main concern is with the evaluation of the assumptions in the hard core. Toward
this end, Lakatos distinguishes between progressive and degenerative research programs. A progressive research program – one that absorbs anomalies and generates new predictions – confirms the assumptions of the hard core. In contrast, when a research program is degenerative –
when it dedicates its auxiliary assumptions to explaining away anomalies that otherwise would
endanger the meta-theoretical assumptions and fails to yield new predictions – the assumptions
of the hard core become disconfirmed.
So far, we have said nothing that disagrees with Ketelaar and Ellis' description of Lakatos.
But, we now come to our first question. How does Lakatos' understanding of the structure of
science apply to evolutionary psychology? Ketelaar and Ellis often claim that it is evolutionary
theory that is a progressive research program. Few would question this. In Lakatosian terms, the
hard core of evolutionary theory would presumably include assumptions like the following: organisms evolve by natural selection, heritable traits are transmitted from parent to offspring via
genes, etc. Evolutionary psychology is not part of the hard core of this research program.
Rather, it lies in the protective belt. As Ketelaar and Ellis seem to recognize, evolutionary psychology is an application of the principles in the hard core of the Neo-Darwinian research program to questions about psychological processes.
Yet, if this is correct, Ketelaar and Ellis' use of Lakatos to assuage doubts about the legitimacy of evolutionary psychology is confused. If, as we suggested above, evolutionary psychology does not belong in the hard core of the Darwinian research program, then Lakatos' distinc-
tion between progressive and degenerative research programs does not help in the evaluation of
evolutionary psychology. Whether a research program is progressive or degenerative matters to
the confirmation of the assumptions in the hard core, but, we are assuming, evolutionary psychology is not part of the hard core of the Neo-Darwinian research program.
In short, Ketelaar and Ellis are unclear about whether their interest in Lakatos is for the purpose of lending credence to the Neo-Darwinian research program or to evolutionary psychology.
If the former, one wonders why they feel the need. If the latter, they have misapplied Lakatosian
philosophy of science.
We turn now to a second complementary issue. If evolutionary psychology is not to be
evaluated as a part of a scientific hard core, then how should it be evaluated? Even more fundamentally: What is evolutionary psychology? In considering these questions, it pays to shift one’s
focus from Lakatosian philosophy of science to Kuhnian philosophy of science. Kuhn offers us
the concept of normal science. Normal science is not concerned with testing the assumptions of
the hard core. Rather, normal science proceeds on the assumption that the hard core is wellconfirmed and consists in the investigation of puzzles and questions that have aroused scientists’
curiosity. It is entirely rare for a scientist to engage in research that tests the assumptions of the
hard core. Far more likely, the scientist will seek answers to puzzles that have little bearing on
meta-theoretical assumptions: Why do oil tankers sink? What makes a tornado? What effect
will genetically altered corn have on monarch butterfly populations? While Kuhn’s normative
view of science is unacceptable ("As in political revolutions, so in paradigm choice – there is no
standard higher than the assent of the relevant community" (1970, p.94)), philosophers of science
need to recognize that normal science is a knowledge-generating process in its own right. The
merits of normal science rest not in its ability to confirm the hard core, but in its facility to solve
puzzles. The remaining question is: How should puzzle solutions be evaluated?
An analogy will help to illustrate the standard that evolutionary psychology must meet.
Newtonian physics left unexplained a small amount of rotation of the ellipse of Mercury's orbit,
referred to as the precession of the perihelion. Naturally, a desperate Newtonian could have revised various parameters in his theory, or introduced new ones, in an effort to account for the
unexpected precession. However, to do so would have been ad hoc – it would have been an exercise in accommodation rather than explanation. It is precisely because Einstein's theories of
special and general relativity predict just such a motion in Mercury's orbit – given the same values for the various parameters that the Newtonians recognized – that Einstein's explanation is
superior. Einstein could account for mercury's precession without having to modify wellconfirmed values of parameters or to introduce new parameters whose sole purpose would have
been to accommodate the effect.
The difference between how Einstein did explain the precession in Mercury's orbit and how
a Newtonian might have explained it corresponds with Lakatos' distinction between a progressive problemshift and a degenerative one. Progressive problemshifts are those that lead to
genuine predictions; degenerative ones are those that lead to false predictions or offer mere accommodation. Thus, the basic ingredients for the evaluation of normal science are present in
Lakatos’s methodology, even if they are not used for that purpose.
But, is evolutionary psychology progressive or degenerative? First of all, it would be wrong
to suppose that this is a simple either/or affair. Different applications of evolutionary psychol2
ogy may be evaluated independently of one another. We also believe that it is too soon to judge
the merit of some of these applications. In this regard, our discussion of the dispute between
Newtonians and Einstein suggests some points that evolutionary psychologists do well to heed.
First, in favor of Einsteinian normal science is the fact that it offers predictions that Newtonian
physics does not. However, it is no easy matter to limn the predictive power of a theory. If we
are to accept the explanations of evolutionary psychology as superior alternatives to nonevolutionary psychology, we must be clear about what sorts of phenomena non-evolutionary
psychology is capable of predicting and, on the other hand, what sorts of phenomena nonevolutionary psychology cannot predict.
Similarly, like any successful normal science, the predictions of evolutionary psychology
must go beyond mere accommodation. We do not wish to claim that any and all accommodation
is degenerative. Indeed, accommodation plays a crucial role in theory development – the constants in a theory are, after all, initially the product of accommodating theory to data. Nonetheless, a progressive research program is one that goes beyond accommodation – that uses past accommodation to predict new and perhaps otherwise unexpected phenomena. Can evolutionary
psychology do this? Perhaps, but it seems to us that the burden falls on evolutionary psychologists to show that it can. So, for instance, in their discussion of male parental investment
Ketelaar and Ellis say that "selection should concomitantly favor the evolution of male strategies
designed to reduce the chance of diverting parental effort toward unrelated young" (p. 17). They
then cite Daly et al.'s claim that these strategies include "the use or threat of violence to achieve
sexual exclusivity and control" (Daly et al. 1982, p. 11). But, is the use of violence to achieve
sexual exclusivity a prediction of evolutionary psychology? It is difficult to see why. Surely
there are many ways that a male parent might insure that the offspring in which he invests are his
own. He might, as Daly et al. suggest, use violence to prevent his sexual partner from philandering. Alternatively, he might make his investments conditional on the fidelity of his partner, or
he might sequester his partner for the duration of their courtship, or he might enlist the help of
relatives to serve as a chaperon for his partner, etc.
The problem is that the hypothesis Ketelaar and Ellis invite us to consider – that selection
should favor the evolution of male strategies that reduce the chance of investment in unrelated
young – does not by itself entail anything about the use of violence to achieve sexual exclusivity.
It does predict that males who invest in young will take measures to insure that these young are
relatives, but it doesn't predict how they will do so. To discover which strategies males actually
adopt, one must collect data. One might, as Daly et al. surmise, find that investing males use
violence to enforce fidelity. But, we wonder, is this surmise a prediction, or is it accommodation
to what has already been observed? Until these questions are sorted out, and this is by no means
a trivial task, the value of evolutionary psychology remains uncertain.
Ketelaar, Timothy, and Ellis, Bruce J. (forthcoming): “Are Evolutionary Explanations Unfalsifiable?: Evolutionary Psychology and the Lakatosian Philosophy of Science.” Evolutionary Psychology.
Kuhn, Thomas (1970): The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Second Edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
3