* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Kanniainen 01 ee08 6538261 en
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
Firms’ Ethics, Consumer Boycotts, and Signalling Amihai Glazer, Vesa Kanniainen & Panu Poutvaara Firms’ Ethics, Consumer Boycotts, and Signalling ¤ Amihai Glazery Vesa Kanniainenz Panu Poutvaarax February 4, 2008 Abstract This paper develops a theory of consumer boycotts. Consumers care both about the products they buy and about the images of the …rms producing those goods. To a¤ect a …rm’s ethical behavior, moral consumers may refuse to buy from an unethical …rm. Consumers who do not care about ethical behavior may join the boycott to (falsely) signal that they do care. In the choice between an ethical or unethical behavior, it is optimal to play a mixed strategy when the cost of it is not small or substantial. For low and high cost of ethical investment, a pure strategy is optimal. In particular, when the cost is low, the ethical behavior arises from prisoners’ dilemma. Key words: …rm’s ethical code, consumer morality, boycotts JEL classi…cation: M14, D43 1 Introduction A …rm deviating from an accepted social norm like environmental protection, sound personnel policy, or avoidance of child labor, may risk punishment by consumers. Examples of such punishments are many. Shell Oil su¤ered damage to its image from the military action of the Nigerian government against domestic protests aimed at protecting the delta of its river. Nestle su¤ered from lost reputation after selling inappropriate milk to pregnant mothers in developing countries. The accounting …rm Arthur Andersen never recovered from ¤ Prepared for the CESifo Ethics and Economics conference, February 7-9, 2008. The initial draft of this was presented at the NORIO VI Conference in Stockholm, June 1-2, 2007 and in the EBEN Conference on Business Ethics, Leuven September 19-20, 2007. y Department of Economics, University of California– Irvine, Irvine, California 92697, USA. E-mail: [email protected] z Department of Economics, Arkadiankatu 7 (P.O. Box 17), 00014 University of Helsinki, Finland. E-mail: [email protected].…. x Department of Economics, Arkadiankatu 7 (P.O. Box 17), 00014 University of Helsinki, Finland. E-mail: panu.poutvaara@helsinki.…. 1 its involvement with Enron. When Turku Mustard was bought by a Swedish …rm which moved production to Sweden, Finnish consumers boycotted their favorite mustard, causing its share price to fall by about ten percent. In 2005, an Estonian ship, owned by Tallink, was caught releasing waste into the Baltic Sea. Two days after passengers organized a boycott against the …rm, the …rm announced a change in its policy, pledging to safely release waste into containers in Helsinki. The plan of the …rm producing the British condiment HP sauce to move production to the Netherlands caused a consumer boycott. A person who joins a consumer boycott is typically willing to pay a higher price for a good produced by a …rm not boycotted. Moreover, those organizing the boycott often want to see other consumers join.1 The internet and other modern means of communication provide consumers with new instruments to in‡uence the ethical behavior of other producers (Andersen, 1999).2 The consumers’ concerns can induce a …rm to devote attention to its image. Indeed, the internet home pages of many …rms describe their work in helping development projects and controlling environmental damage.3 4 Our paper asks how many and under what conditions consumers join a boycott. We also ask how …rms behave under the threat of a boycott. We analyze a model in which competing …rms produce identical products but can choose their corporate ethics, di¤erentiating their image among consumers. Consumers observe the behavior of …rms and may avoid buying from a …rm which violated some ethical position. Some consumers join a boycott because of their moral outrage. Other, amoral, consumers may join a boycott because of the private bene…t of appearing to have moral considerations. We also ask how …rms behave under the threat of a boycott.5 We examine in particular whether a boycott can e¤ectively direct corporate ethics and how competition determines the market outcome. The existing literature is meager. A few papers study corporate ethics but none studies consumers’ actions. In our paper the e¢ciency of a boycott is determined by the moral reaction of consumers and the cost imposed on consumers who do not 1 The Danish …rm Arla is an interesting special case in that its boycott in the Islamic world led to a counter boycott among the western consumers regarding the initial boycott unfair. 2 Consumers’ in‡uence can be thought to be the greatest in industries where products are not too di¤erentiated and where competition is strong. Those features can be expected to be measured by price elasticities. Elastic demand points to high substitutability and a low switching cost. Research supports the proposition that consumers can in‡uence …rms, see Morales (2005). Cronberg (1986) analyzes consumers’ in‡uence on new technology. Reasons for why boycotts arise are studied by Klein, Mith, and John (2004). Information on how consumers react to other aspects than the price—a …rm’s image—can apparently be based on case studies only. Stock prices and consumer prices can there be helpful indicators. 3 Klein, John and Smith (2001 and 2004) explore the motivations for consumer boycotts. The deviating …rms may su¤er from a boycott by its competitor, cf. Brennan (1992). 4 Yet, there may be switching costs, especially if transaction costs make consumers commit to some products. Switching costs are analyzed by Klemperer (1995). See also Antheon, Camarero and Carrero (2007). 5 A …rm can respond to a boycott by playing tough or weak, depending on how much it values a good image. The reaction of a …rm may result in a particular reputation and may in‡uence the success or failure of a future boycott. We ignore such reputation building in the current paper. 2 join the boycott. By joining the boycott, an individual can signal - falsely - his type in his reference network. Consumer opportunism and the option of free riding, however, reduce the success of a boycott. For concreteness, we shall say that a …rm behaves ethically if and only if it invests in pollution abatement. We shall …rst consider the investment decision as …xed for the …rm, not subject to its choice. Such an approach is useful in considering the e¤ects of di¤erent regulations in di¤erent jurisdictions. Thus, we can consider competition between a …rm in a country which imposes strict environmental regulations and a …rm in a country with lax regulations. In the absence of consumer reactions, the …rm subject to lax requirements will earn higher pro…ts. But if some consumers prefer to buy from a non-polluting …rm, then the opposite may hold. Indeed, consumer behavior may lead countries to engage in a “race to the top," with one country not wanting to appear to have laxer requirements than another. What makes the problem non-trivial is the joint consideration of consumer and …rm behavior. The price a …rm charges will depend on how much consumers are willing to buy from a non-polluting …rm. And consumers in turn will decide what to buy on the basis of both pollution activity and the prices the …rms charge. Later in the paper we will consider behavior of a …rm when it is not subject to regulation, but can instead choose whether to invest in pollution abatement. Of interest is whether it would do so. 2 2.1 Assumptions Consumers and ethical preferences We cast the analysis in terms of a duopoly market where two …rms compete for customers. The products (or services) are physically identical but the production processes can di¤er. There is, say, a polluting one and a non-polluting one. People di¤er with respect to their morality in respect of pollution and some may …nd it valuable to misrepresent their hidden preferences. There are two types of consumers. An -type has moral preferences; a -type does not.6 The mass of -type consumers is , while the mass of -type consumers is scaled to 1.7 Each consumer buys at most one unit of the good. In both groups, consumers are indexed in decreasing order by [0 ] or [0 1] with respect to their basic willingness to pay for the product. Consumer = 0 has the highest basic willingness to pay for the product, say in both groups; consumers = and = 1 have zero willingness to pay for it in the two groups. The willingness to pay 6 The origin of ethical preference lies beyond the scope of the current paper. A natural source is that the preferences are created by evolutionary mechanisms within human beings as part of a social contract, cf. Binmore (1998). It is appropriate to think that the ability to commit to a social norm, the option to participate in a boycott, develops like a meme. The idea of a social gene, “meme" in contrast to the biological gene, was introduced by Dawkins (1976). 7 The society hence consists of individuals of homo moralis and homo oeconomicus. 3 by the remaining consumers is uniformly distributed on (0 ) in both groups. To illustrate, and ignoring moral and reputational e¤ects for the moment, the utility from consumption by consumer (in any group) is given by an indirect utility function = (1 ¡ ) ¡ where is the market price. In the absence of ethical issues, the goods produced by di¤erent …rms are identical. In our model, the products are not identical if one …rm pollutes while the other does not. In the social context, a reputation for moral concerns has bene…ts for individuals. Absence of such reputation may lead to exclusion from particular groups, loss of friendship, and even barriers in the marriage market. We simplify matters by assuming that a consumer who participates in a boycott gets a bene…t of 0 compared to a consumer who does not. This assumption can approximate the situation when the bene…ts of having a reputation for ethical concerns is non-linear, with the bene…t increasing rapidly as the probability that a person has moral concerns rises above zero. In our model, however, we make the simpli…cation that only the less moral consumers enjoy this bene…t; the moral ones are committed to boycott anyway. We introduce a further e¤ect. We let 0 denote the cost imposed on a consumer who does not join the boycott. This can be thought of as a social pressure, commonly observed. 2.2 Firms There are two periods. In period 1, each …rm decides on its code of ethical conduct; it invests or not say, in pollution abatement. The cost of abatement can di¤er across …rms. We consider the cases where mixed strategies or alternatively pure strategies are optimal. In period 2, each …rm’s ethical conduct becomes common knowledge, and each consumer decides at which …rm to buy. 3 Equilibria when the Ethical Codes Di¤er We shall consider three di¤erent sets of investment: no …rm invests, both …rms invest, or only one does. As we eventually have to …nd out the outcome of the investment game under various strategies, it is most illuminating to start with the case of two pure strategies. In this section therefore, we consider the case where one of the …rms invests, thereby incurring a …xed cost 0, while the other does not invest. In the market, the products of the …rms, though perfect substitutes in consumption, are now di¤erent with di¤erent images of their producers. Some consumers will then switch from buying the product of the …rm with no ethical code, say , to buying from the …rm with the ethical code, say . More speci…cally, the boycotting high-moral consumers abstain from buying at …rm and buy only at …rm . Since in equilibrium not all may buy, we denote the active high-moral buyers by . The number of low-moral consumers who stay at …rm is denoted by Some of the low types, however, switch to the …rm in order to (falsely) signal high morality. Their number is denoted by . 4 Equilibrium We denote the resulting price at the ethical …rm by and the price at the non-ethical …rm by . The resulting market equilibrium has the following structure. From the de…nition of the marginal moral consumer , we know that the equilibrium price at …rm satis…es (1 ¡ 8 )= (1) We can of course have a market equilibrium where no low-moral consumer switches to …rm . However, to make the analysis interesting, we assume that the bene…t from signalling is su¢cient so that some, i.e. do. The marginal low-moral consumer must be indi¤erent between the two markets. Thus, prices must satisfy (1 ¡ )+ ¡ = (1 ¡ )¡ ¡ (2) where, to recall is the signalling bene…t when the consumer buys at …rm and is the social pressure when he does not. Therefore, Lemma 1. The price di¤erence arises from the signalling bene…t and from the cost of social pressure, ¡ 9 = + (3) The marginal low-moral consumer (with an index + ) is indi¤erent between buying at …rm or buying nothing. Thus, his net utility is (1 ¡ ¡ (4) )¡ = In the Cournot model, …rms decide on their outputs allowing the prices to adjust. We denote the outputs by and Then, = + (5) = Thus, ¡ = To solve for the prices, we …rst …nd the number of signalling consumers. Using ¡ = + (1 ¡ ) ¡ (1 ¡ + This gives = ¡ 1+ ¡ + 8 It )+ = + (1 + ) (6) will thus not be the case that all moral consumers buy. They buy only if = making = 0 Otherwise, 9 We notice that actually all low-moral types are indi¤erent between the two markets as the signalling bene…t and the social cost of pressure just match the price di¤erence. The …rms plan their output knowing the consumers’ behavior. 5 Then the pro…ts of the …rms are = ¡ = ( ¡ + 1+ · + 1+ = = ¡ + ¡ = ¡ 1+ ¡ 1+ ¡ 1+ From the …rst-order conditions, µ ¶ = 1¡ + 1+ 1+ (7) )¡ 1+ ¡2 1+ ¡ ¡2 1+ ¸ (8) Solving for the Nash-Cournot equilibrium, the …rst FOC gives: 2 1+ = = µ 1¡ 1+ 2 1+ ¡ 2 ¶ + + 1+ 2 We obtain: = = Proposition 1. shares (1 + ) (1 + 2 ) + 2(1 + ) ¡ 3 3 (1 + ) (2 + ) + (1 + ) + 3 3 (9) (10) The Cournot-Nash equilibrium is given by the market = = (1 + ) (1 + 2 ) + 2(1 + ) ¡ 3 3 (1 + ) (2 + ) + (1 + ) + 3 3 The ethical …rm bene…ts from the incentive of the less moral consumers who mimic the moral ones. Similarly, social pressure on the amoral consumers bene…ts this …rm; the unethical …rm su¤ers from a loss of customers. Noticing that the signalling bene…t or the social pressure may di¤er between products, we state 6 Corollary 1. The economic e¤ect of a boycott is smaller when the boycott is of products which are less useful for signalling reasons, or where the social punishment is low. Solving next for the number of mimicking customers, = = ¡ + 1+ (1 + ) 1¡ (2 + 5 + 2 2 ) (1 + 2 ) + + 3 3 (1 + ) 3 (11) Lemma 2 The number of mimicking customers is determined by the signalling bene…t and the cost of social pressure relative to the basic willingness to pay by the consumers. Thus, a consumer boycott by moral (non-opportunistic) people induces some opportunistic amoral people to take advantage of the signalling bene…t, making the consumer market in the aggregate behave more morally. The smaller is the signalling bene…t relative to the basic willingness to pay, the less e¤ective is the boycott. We solve the prices starting from non-moral consumers. It holds that = = (1 ¡ ¡ )¡ (1 + 2 ) 2 ¡ ¡ 3 3(1 + ) 3 and = = + + ( + )(1 + ) + (2 + ) 3(1 + ) (12) and rewriting = ( ¡ 2 )(1 + ) ¡ (1 + 2 ) 3(1 + ) The equilibrium studied above is characterized by pro…ts we calculate next = = ¡ (( + )(1 + ) + (2 + ) )2 ¡ 9(1 + ) (13) ¡ ¢ which (14) = = (( ¡ 2 )(1 + ) ¡ (2 + ) )2 9(1 + ) 7 (15) 4 Firm’s Ethical Decisions: To Be or Not To Be? 4.1 Mixed strategy equilibria To examine the conditions for the mixed strategy, call the …rms and Assume that the investment is not observable when undertaken but that in the production stage, consumers observe whether a …rm invested in the ethical action. Now, the …rms can for competitive reasons randomize their investments and we start by studying the mixed strategy equilibrium. We also work out whether and when a pure strategy can be optimal. We let denote the probabilities of undertaking the investment. The expected pro…ts then are £ ¤ £ ¤ [ ]= + (1 ¡ ) + (1 ¡ ) + (1 ¡ ) (16) [ ]= £ + (1 ¡ ¤ ) + (1 ¡ ) £ + (1 ¡ ) ¤ (17) We notice that the expected pro…ts are linear in the probabilities. A (mixed) Nash equilibrium in terms of the optimal probabilities satis…es [ ] [ =0 The …rst-order conditions are = = ¡ 1¡ = = ¡ 1¡ ¡ ¡ 1 ( ( ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ 1 ( ( ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ] ¡ ¢ ¡ ¡ =0 ¢ ¡ ) ) ¡ ¢ ¡ ¡ ) ) ¢ ¡ ¢ (18) ¢ (19) These conditions represent a Nash equilibrium without a dominating strategy. An interior solution, 0 1 0 1 it is required that ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ ¢ ¢ 0 0 ¡ ¡ Therefore, before addressing these conditions, we need to study the pure strategies to …nd out the pro…t levels. 8 4.2 Pure Strategies In this section, we allow for the costs of investment, 4.2.1 to di¤er. Neither Firm Acts Ethically It is also possible that one of strategies is a dominating one for both …rms. When it is optimal to choose = = 0 no investing represents the dominant strategy. Now one group of customers - boycotters - leaves the market, i.e. the market size is squeezed to 1, there is one price and the …rms share the customers on an equal basis. The pro…ts are then = = 10 Necessary conditions for no investing representing a dominant strategy are To solve, the marginal customer has zero utility (1 ¡ ¡ )¡ ¡ =0 Pro…ts are = [ (1 ¡ = [ (1 ¡ ¡ ¡ )¡ ] )¡ ] Solving for the Nash-Cournot equilibrium, = 1 ¡ ( ) 3 1 ¡ = ( ) 3 (20) The price can be solved as 1 = ( ¡ ) 3 Pro…ts in the no investment equilibrium are = = 1 ( ¡ )2 9 (21) 1 0 These conditions are not, however, su¢cient, as a prisoners’ dilemma to be studied below arises under these same conditions (strengthened by some others) with = = 1 representing the dominating strategy. 9 4.2.2 Both Firms Invest When it is optimal to choose strategy. Pro…ts are then = 1 ethical behavior is a dominant = ¡ = ¡ = The outcome is a symmetric Cournot equilibrium. This equilibrium can appear if the cost saving is small.11 Necessary conditions for investment representing a dominant strategy are To solve for the market shares, we notice …rst that the total mass of potential customers in the market now is 1 + and the two …rms share them. The …rms now face a less steep market demand as the mass of potential customers is increased. Denoting the total amount of buying customer which also is the index of the last buyer, it must hold that he is indi¤erent between buying and not buying. As his willingness to pay has to match with the market price, it must hold, (1 ¡ )= (22) 1+ As the market is shared, we have that = + The pro…ts are = (1 ¡ = (1 ¡ + 1+ + 1+ ) ¡ ) ¡ The …rst-order conditions are = (1 ¡ = + 1+ )¡ 1+ 3 = 1 1+ =0 (23) The pro…ts are = (1 ¡ = (1 + ) 9 + 1+ ¡ ) µ 1+ 3 ¶ ¡ (24) 1 1 We show below that this is not the only case where investing is the optimal strategy. It can arise as a prisoners’ dilemma. 10 5 When is the mixed strategy optimal? We …rst collect the above …ndings under pure strategies = (( + )(1 + ) + (2 + ) )2 ¡ 9(1 + ) = (( ¡ 2 )(1 + ) ¡ (2 + ) )2 9(1 + ) = (1 + ) ¡ 9 = 1 ( ¡ )2 9 Repeating, to have the mixed strategy appear optimal, we must have [ ] [ =0 1, we must have that12 ¡ ¡ ¡ ¡ Now, for ¢ ¢ ] =0 0 This condition holds in two exclusive cases. (i) Case 1 0 & ¡ Evaluating the …rst condition, ¡ = (1 + ) ¡ 9 (1 + )2 2 ¡ ¡ 0 (( ¡ 2 )(1 + ) ¡ (2 + ) )2 9(1 + ) 0 ¡ (( ¡ 2 )(1 + ) ¡ (2 + ) )2 9(1 + ) Evaluating the second condition, ¡ 1 2 We = (( + )(1 + ) + (2 + ) )2 1 ( ¡ )2 ¡ ¡ 9(1 + ) 9 2 2 (( + )(1 + ) + (2 + ) ) 1( ¡ ) ¡ 9(1 + ) 9 = notice that when thse conditions are satis…ed, it also always holds 11 0 Combining, (( + )(1 + ) + (2 + ) )2 1 ( ¡ )2 ¡ 9(1 + ) 9 (1 + )2 2 ¡ (( ¡ 2 )(1 + ) ¡ (2 + ) )2 9(1 + ) This can never hold because the value of the left-hand side exceeds the value of the right-hand side.13 (ii) Case 2 0 & ¡ ¡ 0 These conditions amount to stating (1 + )2 2 ¡ (( ¡ 2 )(1 + ) ¡ (2 + ) )2 9(1 + ) (( + )(1 + ) + (2 + ) )2 1 ( ¡ )2 ¡ 9(1 + ) 9 We have proved: Proposition 2. The necessary and su¢cient condition for the existence of a mixed strategy as an optimal choice for a …rm is that the cost of investment of its rival ( ) satis…es the above conditions. Corollary 2: Pure strategies can be played only if 2 (1+ )2 2 ¡(( ¡2 )(1+ )¡(2+ ) )2 (( + )(1+ )+(2+ ) )2 or if ¡ 19 ( ¡ ) 9(1+ ) 9(1+ ) As the mixed strategies are not always optimal, it does make sense to study also the pure strategies i.e. when does not satisfy any of the above two conditions. Pure strategies in the limit Consider the optimal strategies when ap2 2 ¡2 )(1+ )¡(2+ ) )2 proaches its limits. In the limiting cases, when ! (1+ ) ¡(( 9(1+ ) ¡ ¢ )+(2+ ) )2 we have ¡ = 0 Similarly, when !¡ (( + )(1+ ¡ 9(1+ ) ¡ ¢ 2 ( ¡ ) 1 = 0 Linking with the expression for we we have ¡ 9 have lim ! = 1 lim ! (25) =0 Similarly for We conclude that the …rms do not always choose to play a mixed strategy. For a mixed strategy for being optimal it is necessary that the conditions (24) 1 3 Strictly speaking, this conclusion is based on the case with 12 = 1. are satis…ed. These conditions link the value of consumer signalling with the …rms’ cost of being ethical. Proposition 3. Ethical behavior can arise an optimal strategy but only in conditions where the cost of investment is not high. 6 Ethical behavior arising as the prisoners’ dilemma: low pro…t equilibrium. An argument put forward by Shleifer (2001) is that competition is detrimental to high corporate ethics. Our analysis challenges his view. We have arrived at this view by examining the case whether there exists a combination of pure strategies which satis…es the conditions for the prisoners’ dilemma. This amounts to asking whether, in the absence of commitment, a low-pro…t equilibrium with both …rms investing replaces a joint pro…t maximization where neither invests. It amounts thus to asking whether both …rms would generate more pro…ts by not investing but in the face of a rival’s move of investment, it is optimal to follow the lead. In the current model, such a harsh requirement appears reasonable as otherwise the …rms lose all the boycotting customers which leave the market. Intuitively, the equilibrium depicting a prisoners’ dilemma can be characterized by the conditions (26) The condition indicates that if invests it can increase its pro…t subject to the condition that does not invest. The condition indicates that in such a case can lose a lot. To state in terms of the optimal strategies, the strategy pair arising as prisoners’ dilemma requires that = = 1 I.e. it should be optimal to have the -equilibrium when the …rms optimize individually, [ Evaluating, say ¡ ¡ [ ] + ] [ 0 ] (27) 0 0 gives + ¡ ¡ ¢¢ ¡ Given that the incentive to deviate from the ¡outcome exists for both …rms, the right-hand side is positive. It is then su¢cient for this inequality to hold that ¡ + 0 which amounts to having representing one of the characterizations of the prisoners’ dilemma. We now examine what conditions are required for the equilibrium to be characterized as prisoners’ dilemma given the structure of our model. 13 First, when a …rm, say switches individually from the strategy pair , the other playing the pro…t of …rm increases, (( + )(1 + ) + (2 + ) )2 ¡ 9(1 + ) Second, the pro…t of the …rm, say to 1 ( ¡ )2 9 is reduced if it does not follow, i.e. (( ¡ 2 )(1 + ) ¡ (2 + ) )2 9(1 + ) 1 ( ¡ )2 9 Third, the pro…ts are lower under the strategy pair than under the strategy pair (1 + ) 1 ( ¡ )2 ¡ 9 9 Fourth, the pro…ts cannot be negative when the strategy pair is chosen, (1 + ) 9 Multiplying the second condition by (1 + ) (( ¡ 2 )(1 + ) ¡ (2 + ) )2 ( ¡ )2 (1 + ) one can judge that this (quite surely) is satis…ed. Consider the rest of the conditions to be combined as min µ (1 + ) 9 ¡ 1 ( ¡ )2 9 (( + )(1 + ) + (2 + ) )2 1 ( ¡ )2 (1 + ) ¡ 9(1 + ) 9 9 ¶ It remains to produce a numerical example as to when these conditions can hold. Take = 1 Moreover, it makes sense to examine the limiting case ! 0. The lower limit for then becomes 1 (2 ¡ ) 9 For example, having then = 0 25 one obtains 0 0486 Now the upper limit. µ (1 + + 2 )2 1 1 min ¡ (1 ¡ )2 9 9 9 With = 0 25 = 0 25 one has min(2 50 0 11) = 0 11 14 ¶ Thus, when the investment satis…es 0 0486 0 11 we can have that the strategies arises from the prisoners’ dilemma - provided that it is not optimal to play a mixed strategy studied earlier. From there we know that a mixed strategy cannot be optimal if (1 + )2 2 ¡ (( ¡ 2 )(1 + ) ¡ (2 + ) )2 9(1 + ) With the numerical values above, 1 ¡ ((1 ¡ 0 5) ¡ 2 )2 1 = 9 9 = 0 11 Indeed, when 0 0486 0 11 the equilibrium arises from a prisoners’ dilemma. This conclusion was strictly obtained by having the number of moral consumers in the market = 0 By continuity, it must hold also when is positive but su¢ciently small. Would it hold that 0 0486 the equilibrium would arise as a dominating pure strategy. We can state the conclusion as a proposition: Proposition 4: When the number of moral consumers is small and when the investment cost is small but strictly positive, …rms may end up undertaking the ethical investment even if their pro…ts are reduced. The equilibrium then arises from a prisoners’ dilemma. For completeness, it is worth stating that when the investment cost is high, the becomes the dominating strategy. 7 Final Remarks Modern communication media, including the internet, enhance the opportunities for consumers to in‡uence the ethical behavior of producers. This increased in‡uence has induced …rms to devote substantial e¤ort on their image among consumers. Firms often highlight their contributions to economic development or to environmental quality. Consumer power apparently has been increasing and will continue to increase though we only have indirect evidence on that. Consequently, with increasing concern about environmental issues like the greenhouse e¤ect, one can expect that we will see an increased incentive for individuals to organize boycotts in the future. In the end, there may be fewer, however, if such a threat leads …rms to behave better. Are there two few boycotts from the social point of view? Do markets produce the right amount of boycotts? This is a challenging welfare issue. In an individualistic society with utilitarian preferences, the well-being of (all) citizens are often taken as the starting point for the evaluation of the social welfare. Boycotts enhance the market position of well-behaving …rms and the consumer 15 surplus of their customers. There are, however, quite a few welfare aspects. The negative externalities, say pollution, is reduced - we have not modelled such an externality explicitly. The moral individuals who abstain from buying from the unethical …rm do bene…t, though we abstracted from introducing this mechanism in our formal model if only to simplify wherever possible. By implication, the immoral consumers who for the reasons of opportunism switch the …rm tend to cause a positive externality on the moral ones. Such a positive externality tends, however, to be diluted if the private return on signalling a moral characteristic su¤ers from the number of boycotters. Organizing a boycott, however, can be socially costly as it represents a reduction in use of resources in a productive activity. People who bear these costs may not be the same people who bene…t from boycotts as some are free-riders and can take opportunistically the advantage of lower prices of the products boycotted. Those less moral individuals who buy from the unethical …rm su¤er a cost as they de…nitively are now separated from the moral ones. References [1] Andersen, T., (1999) "Consumer Power via the Internet". [2] Antheon, C., Camarero, C. and Carrero, M., (2007), "Analyzing …rms’ failures as determinants of consumer switching intentions: The e¤ect of moderating factors", European Journal of Marketing, 41, 135-158. [3] Baron, D.P., (2002) “Private Politics and Private Policy: A Theory of Boycotts." Stanford Graduate School of Business. [4] Binmore, K., (1998), Game Theory and the Social Contract II. Just playing, MIT Press. [5] Brennan, T.J., (1992) "Refusing to Cooperate with Competitors: A Theory of Boycotts", Journal of Law and Economics, 35, 247-264. [6] Cronberg, T., (1986) "Consumer in‡uence on new technology - Real potential or false hopes?", Journal of Consumer Policy, 9, 335-343. [7] Dawkins, R., (1976) The Sel…sh Gene. [8] Diamond, J., (2005), Collapse. How Societies Choose to Fail or Survive, Penguin Books. [9] Florida, Richard (1996) “Lean and green: The move to environmentally conscious manufacturing." California Management Review, 39: 80-105. [10] Folkes, V.S., (1999) "E¤ects of Information About Firm’s Ethical and Unethical Actions on Consumers’ Attitudes", Journal of Consumer Psychology, 8, 243-259. 16 [11] Innes, R., A. “A Theory of Consumer Boycotts under Symmetric Information and Imperfect Competition." University of Arizona. [12] Kanniainen, V., and Pietarila, E., (2006) “Corporate Social Responsibility: Can Markets Control?" Homo Oeconomicus, 23: 153-179. [13] Klein, J.K., Smith, N.C., and John, A., (2001) "Exploring Motivations for Participation in a Consumer Boycott", London Business School, Centre for Marketing Working Paper No. 01-701. [14] Klein, J.K., Smith, N.C., and John, A., (2004) "Why We Boycott: Consumer Motivations for Boycott Participation", Journal of Marketing, 68, 92-109. [15] Klemperer, P., (1995), "Competition when Consumers have Switching Costs: An Overview with Applications to Industrial Organization, Macroeconomics, and International Trade." Review of Economic Studies 62, 515539. [16] Morales, A.C., (2005), "Giving Firms and "E" for E¤ort: Consumer Responses to High-E¤ort Firms." Journal of Consumer Research, 312: 806812. [17] Shleifer, Andrei, (2001), "Does Competition Destroy Ethical behavior?", NBER Working Paper No: 10269. 17