* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download “Are There Some Human Beings Who Are Not Persons? A... Medical Ethics” Discussion Offered by John Kavanaugh S.J.,...
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
“Are There Some Human Beings Who Are Not Persons? A Looming Controversy in Medical Ethics” Discussion Offered by John Kavanaugh S.J., Saint Louis University for Philosophers in Jesuit Education, October 28th, 4:30-6:30 PM, Chase Park Plaza Hotel, Westminster Room. Discussion-opener text Note: The following is an updated revision of an Ethics Column I wrote for America Magazine. Since it elicited a number of responses from thoughtful readers, including men and women in the legal and health care professions, I thought it might be valuable to share with professional philosophers to invite supporting or alternative resolutions to the problem, even though it is rather informal in places. Persons and Functioning Brains I received a thoughtful e-mail recently from a late 1980s graduate of a Jesuit University. He is “strongly pro-life,” armed with 27 hours of philosophy and theology requirements to boot, but he’s at loggerheads with some “pro-choice” friends who hold the position that there is “a distinction between a human life and a human person.” He faces a challenge mounted by a growing movement -- philosophical, ethical and rhetorical -- that has as its theme: not all living humans are persons. A decade before my friendly correspondent was taking his philosophy classes, the philosopher Mary Ann Warren wrote in The Monist: “Some human beings are not people… A man or woman whose consciousness has been permanently obliterated but who remains alive is a human being which is no longer a person.” The same applied to profoundly mentally deficient humans and fetuses who are human beings but “not yet” persons. In fact, Warren claimed that a fully developed human fetus was “considerably less personlike” than the average fish. The fish at least exhibited activities like the consciousness of external and internal events, as well as primitive reasoning, both associated with the concept of personhood. Although there have been many historical approximations of this position, the last few decades have been marked by a more explicit application to biomedical issues. While Elelyn Pluhar uses the “marginal human” problem to establish an argument for animal rights in Beyond Prejudice, writers such as Jeff McMahan, in The Ethics of Killing, and Walter Glannon in Biomedical Ethics hold that we persons are not organisms. For them, the beginning of a human organism is not the beginning of a person and the death of a human being may well occur long after the death of that person. My position, with its own many ancient to contemporary advocates, is one that seems particularly strategic in the present debate. It also impinges on our very understanding of and acceptance of what we are. A person is not a set of performances or activities, but a kind of being. As the definition offered by Boethius and affirmed by Thomas Aquinas has it: a person is an individual substance of a rational nature. While each of the four components of this definition are contested in philosophical circles, it is not unreasonable to hold that my nature is “what” I am, not what I do. The things I do as a human person are possible only because I am the kind of being with the inherent powers or endowments of intellect and will (a rational nature) making possible intelligent and free actions. This is not “speciesism.” There might be many other kinds of persons that are not human persons. Whoever has the personal endowments of rationality, or intellect and will, is a personal kind of being. Thus, God, angels, or other extra-terrestrials would be non-human persons. (Think: if you have to have a brain to be a person, where does that leave God?) What’s special about human persons is that we are animal-persons, embodied persons. Part of the reality of being an animal-person is that we have an organic life that develops, thrives and diminishes over time. Our participation in personhood begins when we as individual substances begin. If the act of performing certain activities is what makes us persons, then indeed chimps and dogs are more “person-like” than human fetuses or even newborns. You can say the same thing of spiders and computers, the first, being far more clever at providing for themselves and spinning webs than any stupid human baby; the latter triumphantly superior to any dumb fetus in activities of calculation and translation. But this confuses the logic of empirical discovery with the logic of reality. If, however, being a person means that when I started to exist as a living being, I had endowments of intellect and will, even though they might never be expressed or discovered because of my body’s lack of development, or trauma to it, or diminishment, then a new-born is a fragile, dependent, not very competent, little person and a profoundly brain-damaged friend is not a vegetable, but a wounded friend. The formation and health of a brain is, of course, required for the embodied expression of our personal endowments. But you and I are not our brains. Brains are part of us, part of our personal animality. Our human personhood is not something that erupted from our brains the first time we started acting rationally. Nor is it something that was somehow stuck on to these bodies we are attached to. It is the gift of being the kind of beings we are, endowed not only with brains like other animals, but with powers of intellect, open to all the truth there is to be known, and of will, open to all the good there is to be loved. Some Topics to Discuss: 1. Clinical Issues, especially mis-diagnoses. I would like to offer specific cases concerning a handicapped infant patient and a mature patient declared “brain-dead.” 2. Exclusion of marginal persons from the community of human persons. Perhaps the most pressing problem for me arises from the growing emphasis upon brain functioning as the necessary and sufficient condition for human personhood. Does this subtly appeal to the human tendency to reject the vulnerability of our bodies and creatureliness? 3. Philosophical Barriers and Philosophical Kin. I’ve often wondered whether the technical aspects of philosophical discourse diminish our contributions to families (or health-care providers) in crises concerning handicapped neonates or relatives with profound brain damage. At the same time, I am struck by the philosophical contributions found in the clinical writing of medical professionals like Oliver Sacks. What, then, are the best contributions we philosophers can make to medical ethics?