* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Griesemer, James 2006, "Theoretical Integration, Cooperation, and
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
Theoretical Integration, Cooperation, and Theories as Tracking Devices James Griesemer Departments of Philosophy and Center for Population Biology University of California, Davis, CA, USA [email protected] The theoretical problem of integrating evolution, heredity, development, and cognition has a long pedigree with a complicated history. Many of these fields were considered the subjects of one science in the 19th century (Maienschein 1987). Leading theoretical biologists of the age wrote large, expansive treatises that biologists now can read only with equal measures of wonder and incredulity: wonder at their wide and deep learning and incredulity at their peculiar visions of biological integration. Think of Herbert Spencer (1900, pt 2: 367): “Evolution is an integration of matter and concomitant dissipation of motion; during which the matter passes from a relatively indefinite, incoherent homogeneity to a relatively definite, coherent heterogeneity and during which the retained motion undergoes a parallel transformation.” Or consider Ernst Haeckel (Gastraea theory), Hans Driesch (entelechies), August Weismann (biophors, ids, idants), and even Charles Darwin (use inheritance, pangenesis). None of these ideas were especially crazy in their time, but they drove integration projects that are quite different from ours. Historically, each of these special subjects has been a contender for the role of primary theory from which an understanding of all biological phenomena would flow. To take but a few examples, Dobzhansky (1973: 125) gave us “Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution” on behalf of Darwin’s theory. De Vries gave us his Mutationstheorie and Johannsen his pure line theory as alternative explanations of the root cause of hereditary change. Both were intended originally to replace natural selection as theoretically primary. Driesch gave us entelechies of individual development as a fundamental philosophical principle for the biological sciences. James Mark Baldwin, Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, Francisco Varela, Rupert Riedl, and Donald Campbell, in very different 4 ways, put cognition in the center of theoretical concern for general biological science, evolution in particular. Thinking about integration from the point of view of any of these specialties has traditionally depended on a notion of unification by explanatory theory reduction: explanations flow from a fundamental primary theory to phenomena that are organized at the surfaces, so to speak, of those phenomena considered central for the primary theory—for example, trait heredity and organism development in the light of evolution in Darwin’s day, or population change and the development of hybrids in the light of Mendelian heredity circa 1905, recapitulation and phylogeny in the light of ontogeny in Haeckel’s, de Beer’s, and Gould’s days (Haeckel 1866; de Beer 1930; Gould 1977), learning as coequal to inheritance and selection as a force in evolution. In the 20th century, phenomena have tended to be organized hierarchically, in terms of the composition of matter from the smallest to the largest units, so that there is a general expectation and drift of reductionism toward lower levels of compositional organization—to the behavior of smaller and smaller bits of matter—as the primary concern of fundamental theory. In biology, this reductionist drift led theorists from organisms to organs and tissues, to cells, and on to molecules as the foci of theoretical interest. Genes, the “molecules of life,” have been the focus of biological reductionism for nearly all of that century. A different model of integration centers on cooperation and communication among theoretical and phenomenal equals, rather than on imperialism and competition for primacy and fundamentality, which reduces or replaces one theory by another or trivializes one explanandum as epiphenomenal to another. An explanatory domain can become integrated when its bumps, twists, and turns are smoothly traversable, but we need not achieve integration by leveling the domain and making it conceptually homogeneous, just as nation-states can be unified by the smooth flow of goods, services, people, and ideas across their borders rather than by the obliteration of local and regional differences making flow irrelevant. September 27, 2005; accepted October 1, 2005 c 2006 Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research Biological Theory 1(1) 2006, 4–7. James Griesemer Increasingly in science, as in other endeavors, “Cooperative work now routinely spans organizational, geographical and other boundaries” (Gerson in press). Likewise, explanatory reductionism can be practiced as a multidisciplinary, cooperative heuristic that serves as a means of triangulation to truer theories (Wimsatt 1987, 2002). A cooperative approach to theory making facilitates explanatory traversals in all directions between models, levels, and perspectives, not just from higher levels to lower ones. There is no reason we cannot and should not turn reductionism on its head and use genetic theories as tools to build developmental ones as well as seek reduction of developmental phenomena to gene activity (Griesemer 2000, 2002, 2005a). What is left of primacy or foundations is simply the idea that we start from what we know and move out from there, guided by our theoretical commitments. And when we meet others guided by different commitments, we try to reconcile our differences. Genetics is not more fundamental than development, it is just that its theoretical apparatus was rationalized first (see Gerson in press on the process of rationalization). That is, its conceptual parts were made to fit and work smoothly and economically together, in no small measure by the experimental and mathematical insights of Mendel and the cytologists who studied chromosome behavior in meiosis. Hence genetics tends to be, but need not be, one’s first stop in crafting a strategy for integration of biological theory. Why should we think that the first formal, articulated theory we come to in a domain will turn out to be more fundamental than those arrived at later, even if it is true that, by getting there first, a theory tends to become entrenched in our ways of looking for (and at) subsequent theory (see Wimsatt 1986 on entrenchment)? If anything, early theories get articulated first because they are easier to work with, or by accident, or through a lucky break, or because of a social or political or economic consequence that motivated early workers to start there. What does any of that have to do with being “fundamental” or “foundational” in the logical sense reductionists expect? Mendel’s theory was easily articulated in an algebraic form because his materials and experiments were arranged to do just that. It is not just that Mendel’s mind was prepared to make his famous discovery; his discovery was prepared to make his theory. The developmentally invariant property Mendel called a factor or “Merkmal” is just the sort of property that can be easily expressed mathematically (see Griesemer in press). Conceptual boundaries, e.g., between genetical, developmental, and evolutionary problems, can be traversed by theoretical, experimental, or observational means. If mathematical results can flow seamlessly between representations of networks of interacting genes and the statistics of populations undergoing natural selection in changing environments, or niche constructing activities of species can be represented in a model alongside the contributions of Mendelizing alleles, then the Biological Theory 1(1) 2006 theoretical domain of evolution can be traversed in integrated and unified ways across the disciplinary boundaries separating heredity, development, and evolution. If manipulation of the development of hybrid offspring in breeding experiments can be traced to consequences for quantitative trait loci or nucleotide sequences located in particular chromosomal regions and nucleotide changes can be tracked through molecular interactions to phenotypes, then experimental domains can be traversed across the heredity-development border in an integrated and unified way. If microscopists can track luminescent molecules across stages of embryonic development from fertilization through differentiation of new germ cells, then observation can traverse the border between development and heredity. If such traversals are the occasion for integration by cooperation, e.g., when scientists approach a phenomenon from different paths, what can we expect the theoretical products to look like? What, for example, would a theory of EvoDevo look like, as opposed to the motley collection of applications of existing theory we have now: of phylogenetic inference to and from developmental characters (Gould 1977), of population genetics models to systems of developmental genes (Nijhout and Paulsen 1997), of molecular developmental models of cis-acting regulatory regions to evolution and phylogeny (Davidson 2001)? A merger of classical theories does not seem like the right answer for a new science of EvoDevo, nor for any of the other integration projects one can imagine for evolution, heredity, development, and cognition. Why not? One reason is that these theories were formulated under the assumption that the processes they describe, while sharing fundamental units, are separable. This is a generalization of the doctrine of Weismannism (Griesemer and Wimsatt 1989). Weismannism pictures the relation of heredity and development as separate processes flowing from a common cause: the gene, or, in Weismann’s day, the germ plasm (see Weismann 1893). Evolution, under Weismannism and later Mendelism, becomes alteration of the flow and distribution of germ plasm or genes within and among generations because that process was separated by a theoretical abstraction from development. By abstraction from inheritance, development becomes the elaboration of germ plasm (gene expression) into the soma (body), whose interactions with external environments subject germ plasm to forces of evolution. (On abstraction as a means of theory generalization, see Griesemer 2005b.) With the perspective of Weismannism in hand, theoretical integration looks like a problem concerning the duality of the gene’s autocatalytic and heterocatalytic roles and their consequences. Weismannism, however, faces a severe problem as a fundamental doctrine for biology despite the successes of this rationalization strategy in the 20th century. First, as Buss (1983, 1987) pointed out, the distribution of the Weismannian 5 Theoretical Integration, Cooperation, and Theories as Tracking Devices “preformistic” mode of development is spotty and rather rare among living phyla, so it ill-serves the general theoretical project. Second, the autocatalytic and heterocatalytic properties of the gene are not intrinsic to nucleic acid polymers but are “in” the systems in which they are embedded and these systems engage the “separate” processes of inheritance, development, and evolution simultaneously and integratedly. Replication is a cellular process. Genetic encoding and decoding are cellular processes. They are not properties of genes. Consider, for example, where the genetic code lies. The triplet code is best described as residing in the aminoacyltRNA synthetase enzymes that can simultaneously recognize particular amino acid species and particular tRNA species. The set of relations between these two recognition functions constitutes the genetic code and is embodied in the collection of enzymes that cells have at any particular living moment. Not only does this entail that a genetic code can exist without any genes (a test tube of enzymes will do), but it also implies that any failure to transmit one or more of the 20 classes of these enzymes from parent cell to offspring cell constitutes a change in a genetic code. To an evolved, complex cell, such failures are always lethal “mutations.” Mutation is in quotation marks because, of course, the transmission of enzymes from parent to offspring is not usually implied by the term. Indeed, since enzymes are part of the soma and their function is translation, not replication, their role in the autocatalytic function of genes is obscured. And yet, if not for their direct hereditary transmission, these enzymes could not play any role in gene heterocatalysis. It does no good to pretend, by invoking Weismannism, that enzyme properties can be explained by gene expression one generation back, reducing the problem to one of heterocatalysis in a previous generation, because something must explain the inheritance of the enzymes in the previous generation in order to account for the heterocatalytic function of genes there. This molecular chicken-egg problem is, in fact, the problem of Weismannism restated in molecular terms. It cannot be invoked to explain the causal roles of genes without begging the question of the origin of the functional relation already established between the enzymes and the genes. The temptation is to address this kind of theoretical problem by assuming a weak “contextualism,” seeking to integrate evolution and development by sorting out the “right” contexts in which to invoke developmental principles and those in which to invoke genetic/hereditary ones. That would be another form of theoretical segregation like the nature/nurture dichotomy, one which Susan Oyama (2000) was right to criticize. Integrating theory cannot simply be a matter of identifying the “right” context for different sorts of principles; moreover, because the contexts themselves have histories—they are no more fixed than genes are. More importantly, biological contexts, like biological processes, are entwined. The context of gene expres6 sion is also the context of gene heredity in the sense that the forces influencing the distribution and probability of transmission occur in the context of gene expression. And the context of gene heredity is also the context of gene expression, since the configurations governing gene expression depend on “maternal” inheritance and the conditions transmitted from parent to offspring. An adequately integrated biological theory will be one which respects the entwinement of biological processes, even while it abstracts them for reasons of mathematical tractability, experimental control, and observational tracking. In fact, it might be best to drop old assumptions about what theories are like for the sake of making progress toward integration. One common thread through my remarks has been that, with whatever mix of theoretical, experimental, and observational techniques biologists proceed, their activity always involves tracking: following genes, cells, organisms, mathematical quantities, light spots on film, phenotypes in genetic hybrids, and so on. Perhaps it is time to get away from a physicscentred view of theories and theory making and adopt one more appropriate to biology. As far as EvoDevo goes, we might begin with the recognition that development is both cause and consequence of genetic continuity, so the project of tracking development through inheritance and inheritance through development will require new ways of thinking about theories and theoretical integration. An exciting prospect for this new journal, Biological Theory: Integrating Development, Evolution, and Cognition, is that each of its subdomains developed using tracking methods suited to its particular phenomena and model systems. As contributions to the journal traverse the boundaries, new opportunities and new ways of theory making will arise, provided investigators remain open to the project of theoretical integration by cooperation and collaboration. References Buss LW (1983) Evolution, development, and the units of selection. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 80: 1387– 1391. Buss LW (1987) The Evolution of Individuality. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Davidson EH (2001) Genomic Regulatory Systems: Development and Evolution. San Diego, CA: Academic Press. de Beer G (1930) Embryology and Evolution. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Dobzhansky T (1973) Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. American Biology Teacher 35: 125–129. Gerson E (in press) Reach, bracket, and the limits of rationalized coordination: Some challenges for CSCW. In: Resources, Co-evolution, and Artifacts: Theory in CSCW (Ackerman MS, Halverson C, Erickson T, Kellogg WA, eds). New York: Springer. Gould SJ (1977) Ontogeny and Phylogeny. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Griesemer J (2000) Reproduction and the reduction of genetics. In: The Concept of the Gene in Development and Evolution: Historical and EpistemoBiological Theory 1(1) 2006 James Griesemer logical Perspectives (Beurton P, Falk R, Rheinberger H-J, eds), 240–285. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Griesemer J (2002) Limits of reproduction: A reductionistic research strategy in evolutionary biology. In: Promises and Limits of Reductionism in the Biomedical Sciences (Van Regenmortel MHV, Hull DL, eds), 211–231. Chichester, UK: Wiley. Griesemer J (2005a) Genetics from an evolutionary process perspective. In: Genes in Development (Neumann-Held EM, Rehmann-Sutter C, eds), 343–375. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Griesemer J (2005b) The informational gene and the substantial body: On the generalization of evolutionary theory by abstraction. In: Idealization XII: Correcting the Model, Idealization and Abstraction in the Sciences (Jones MR, Cartwright N, eds), 59–115. Amsterdam: Rodopi. Griesemer J (in press) Tracking organic processes: Representations and research styles in classical embryology and genetics. In: From Embryology to Evo-Devo (Maienschein J, Laubichler MD, eds). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Griesemer J, Wimsatt WC (1989) Picturing Weismannism: A case study of conceptual evolution. In: What the Philosophy of Biology Is: Essays for David Hull (Ruse M, ed), 75–137. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Biological Theory 1(1) 2006 Haeckel E (1866) Generelle Morphologie der Organismen. Berlin: Reimer. Maienschein J (1987) Heredity/development in the United States, circa 1900. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 9: 79–93. Nijhout HF, Paulsen SM (1997) Developmental models and polygenic characters. American Naturalist 149(2): 394–405. Oyama S (2000) The Ontogeny of Information: Developmental Systems and Evolution. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Spencer H (1900) First Principles, 6th ed. London: Williams and Norgate. Weismann A (1893) The Germ-Plasm, A Theory of Heredity. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. Wimsatt WC (1986) Developmental constraints, generative entrenchment, and the innate-acquired distinction. In: Integrating Scientific Disciplines (Bechtel W, ed), 185–208. Dordrecht: Nijhoff. Wimsatt WC (1987) False models as means to truer theories. In: Neutral Models in Biology (Nitecki M, Hoffman A, eds), 23–55. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wimsatt WC (2002) Using false models to elaborate constraints on processes: Blending inheritance in organic and cultural evolution. Philosophy of Science 69: S12–S24. 7