Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
1 Alexandra Hill 5 November 2015 Help Received: Works Cited Word Count: 1262 What Is Happiness? In this paper I will argue that happiness derives from eudaimonia and the attainment of all virtue. I will draw off of the philosophical theories of Aristotle and Seneca. I will not only explain the definition of pure happiness, but how to achieve it according to the philosophers listed above. I will argue against John Mill who states that happiness stems from pleasure. For true happiness to exist, man must seek happiness not because he desires a satisfaction that feels good, but because in seeking virtue he is fulfilled and aware in the sense that he knows he is doing and searching for the right soul strengthening aspects of life. Provided for the context of the argument, there are several words that I will not only provide a definition for, but will as well give a standard insight so that the measure of the particular word can be understood fully. Beginning with the most important definition of this paper, is the term eudaimonia. Eudaimonia, according to Aristotle can be used frequently and interchangeably with the word happiness. Aristotle states that happiness essentially means, “the highest human good” while eudaimonia is recognized as “flourishing” or “the state of having a good indwelling spirit, a good genius”. (EncyclopediaBritannica) Though eudaimonia is loosely defined among Aristotle and various philosophers, it is accepted that the term has a subjective definition because there is no axiom, which states “What are the best activities of which man is capable?” Other definitions, which must be clarified, are those aspects of which Aristotle states happiness comes from, the first one being the 2 vegetable soul. The vegetable soul refers to one’s nutrition and our capability to feed our bodies the proper nutrients to survive in all aspects of life. The second point, the animal, refers to impulsive behavior within human beings, which helps us act and react, especially in times of adversity. The third, and last point speaks of the rational, which gives human beings their ability to justify. (Nicomachean Ethics, 7) Stoic philosopher Seneca speaks of the guidance of Nature in “On the Happy Life”. The phrase refers to a doctrine, “which all Stoics are agreed. Not to stray from Nature and to mold ourselves according to her law and pattern- this is true wisdom.” (Seneca, Para. 6) Philosopher John Mill, known for his theories on Utilitarianism, provides a strong counter to this argument. Aristotle and Seneca believe that happiness is eudiamonia, much less of something that is achievable Mill states the definition of happiness as modeled by utilitarianism as pleasure and the absence of pain. “The doctrine that the basis of morals is utility, or the greatest happiness principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong in proportion as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness” (Mill, 5). For happiness to be justified Mill says that the things that make you happy must be “desirable as an end” (Mill, 5). He goes on to state that the thesis of these practices in Utilitarianism and explains the theory that everything in this world that is desirable is either “for the pleasure inherent in it or as a means to the promotion of pleasure and the prevention of pain (Mill, 6) so there for pleasure and the prevention of pain are the ways that happiness can be achieved. Throughout his adult years, Mill was said by scholars to have suffered from severe depression and mental breakdowns 3 causing him to question his life’s work and it’s quality (“John Stuart Mill”, Bio.com). Aristotle, on the other hand was held in high esteem by King Philip II of Macedonia and despite several family deaths his work was always sound and confident (“Aristotle”, History.com). However, Mill says, “If ‘happiness’ is taken to mean a continuous state of highly pleasurable excitement, it is obvious enough that this is impossible.” (Mill, 9) Mill says this because he describes pleasure as a feeling, and not an action. The stability of one’s feelings and emotions are ever changing and that is why we as human beings are able to experience a variety of feelings throughout our lifetime. None are permanent because they depend on the workings of the world, one’s factors surrounding their lives and their lives in accordance with other human being’s lives. Therefore, pleasure cannot be a desirable end. This of course, does not mean that we shouldn’t desire pleasure at all. It can still be seen as causation to happiness, it’s just not the highest, or even most important desirable means to an end. If we are able to understand and accept that eudaimonia is the essence of happiness and flourishment through virtuous acts, one must begin to question what these virtuous acts are, and if some hold a higher power than others. According to the teachings of Aristotle, there are two kinds of virtue, which are found in being helpful to attaining eudaimonia- intellectual and moral. Intellectual happiness stems from the capacity to open your mind and explore the possibilities of the world without being closed off, and to engage in enlightening conversation, whether it is with an idea or another human being in uncovering the mysteries of truth within the 4 world. The moral virtue that Aristotle writes of speaks about habit and practice in accordance with virtuous deeds. Human virtue is spoken of as “a disposition to behave in the right manner and as a mean between extremes of deficiency and excess,” (Nichomanchean Ethics, 8) this meaning that every good thing done to achieve a virtuous life. While there are defined virtues that Aristotle speaks of, like justice, wisdom, and courage, humans are imperfect so true virtue is being the best person one can be while using the virtues as a goal, or guideline. Like Aristotle, Seneca has an extremely similar theory on happiness. He states at the beginning of his essay that, “to live happily, is the desire of all men, but their minds are blinded to a clear vision of just what it is that makes life happy. (Seneca, Para. 1) He then goes into detail on what “the happy life” actually entails. The happy life is one where “life is in harmony with its own nature” This “nature” is referring not to an environmental aspect, but the ability of molding oneself according to law and pattern as stated before- the human race and all of its complexities is included in this. This goes back to being virtuous, contributing to human nature and all aspects of life, and being the best one can be. Like Aristotle’s three points of eudaimonia, Seneca follows a look-a-like pattern stating, “First of all, we must have a sound mind and one that is in constant possession of its sanity; second, it must be courageous and energetic, and too, capable of the noblest fortitude, ready for every emergency, careful of the body and of all that concerns it, but without anxiety; lastly, must be attentive to all the advantages that adorn life.” (Seneca Para. 7) Seneca’s words are almost identical to what Aristotle says, just broken down into more relatable terms. 5 In summary, though Mill’s argument has substantial points, in the end it appears to be contradictory. The idea that happiness stems from pleasure is not possible if pleasure is perceived as an emotion or feeling. If all happiness derives from things that are desirable as an end this makes sense because feelings come and go. Seneca and Aristotle provide a much more concrete idea of happiness which draws off of human virtue as the base of happiness. Virtue, which is in fact desirable as a means to an end. 6 Works Cited: "The Internet Classics Archive | Nicomachean Ethics by Aristotle." The Internet Classics Archive | Nicomachean Ethics by Aristotle. N.p., n.d. Web. 05 Nov. 2015. <http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/nicomachaen.1.i.html>. Copy & paste citation Seneca. "On the Happy Life." Seneca,. N.p., n.d. Web. 05 Nov. 2015. <http://thriceholy.net/Texts/Happy.html>. "Eudaemonism | Ethics." Encyclopedia Britannica Online. Encyclopedia Britannica, n.d. Web. 05 Nov. 2015. <http://www.britannica.com/topic/eudaemonism#ref273308>. Copy & paste citation Mill, John. "Utilitarianism." (1996): n. pag. Utilitarianism. Apr. 2008. Web. 5 Nov. 2015. "John Stuart Mill." Bio.com. A&E Networks Television, n.d. Web. 09 Dec. 2015. <http://www.biography.com/people/john-stuart-mill-9408210>. "Aristotle." History.com. A&E Television Networks, n.d. Web. 09 Dec. 2015. <http://www.history.com/topics/ancient-history/aristotle>.