* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download paper - CEEL
Schools of economic thought wikipedia , lookup
Economic calculation problem wikipedia , lookup
Economics of digitization wikipedia , lookup
Royal Economic Society wikipedia , lookup
American School (economics) wikipedia , lookup
Behavioral economics wikipedia , lookup
Rational choice theory wikipedia , lookup
History of economic thought wikipedia , lookup
Economic model wikipedia , lookup
Microeconomics wikipedia , lookup
History of macroeconomic thought wikipedia , lookup
The pretence of knowledge. An ever-lasting lesson Roberto Tamborini University of Trento, Department of Economics, Via Inama 5, 38100 Trento, Italy, [email protected] In the May 2008 issue of AER (Papers and Proceedings of the American Economic Association), David Colander, Peter Howitt, Alan Kirman, Axel Leijonhufvud, and Perry Mehrling expound the view that macroeconomics should be recast in a conception of the market economy as a complex adaptive system (CAS). The reason being that what makes macroeconomics a separate field of study is the complex properties of aggregate behavior that emerge from the interaction among agents. Since in a complex system aggregate behavior cannot be deduced from an analysis of individuals alone, representative agent models fail to address the most basic questions of macroeconomics (p. 236) The paper by Colander et al. is representative, and provides the relevant references, of "a strong undercurrent of opposition to modern macroeconomic models" − as they say − that is gaining momentum in the widespread methodological debate prompted by the current world crisis. Quite correctly, Colander et al. understand that this challenge should eventually be faced on the grounds of economic policy. Can the science of economic systems provide better services to society (in the form of public policy) if it is projected into the orbit of the "Complexity Vision" (Colander ed., 2000)? An illustrious predecessor The failure of the economists to guide policy more successfully is closely connected with their propensity to imitate as closely as possible the procedures of the brilliantly successful physical sciences. This is not, as it might appear, the complaint of a heterodox economist about the evils of "the mainstream" in the aftermath of the 2008 crisis. It is the opening sentence of the Nobel Prize Memorial Lecture that Friedrich A. von Hayek gave in 1974 (reprinted in the American Economic Review, 1989, 79, pp. 3-7). It was entitled "The Pretence of Knowledge". 2 At that time, economics and the economic profession were living through another period of crisis generated by a sense of confusion and impotence in the face of "stagflation", that combination of recession, unemployment and high inflation which plagued the world economy in the early '70s. The mainstream was then the US brand of Keynesian macrotheory with the new tools of large macro-econometric models used in support of policy-making according to what would become to be known as "optimal stochastic control" (OSC). This approach was growing on the presumption, and conveying the idea, that the system's behaviour can be fully known and controlled up to "user-friendly" ("white noise") random shocks. Here the analogy is with a control system that assists a missile launch unit, the pilot of the Shuttle, or the driver of a Formula 1 car (which, alas, sometimes go out of control anyway). Hayek had been a fierce opponent of Keynes's theory ever since its appearance. However, most of his speech was not aimed against this theory per se, but rather against the advent of that particular approach to macropolicy, and the way in which it was inducing economists erroneously to apply economic theories of any sort to the real world. This is what renders Hayek's lecture a milestone worth recalling today. Hayek was one of the path-breaking thinkers in the theory of CAS, first in his neuro-physiology studies and then in economics. His epistemology was based on the irreducible difference between the physical world and the social world, the former being amenable to reduction to, and quantification of, relatively few laws based on systematic or frequentist observations, the latter not being amenable to such treatment owing to its "self-organized complexity"1. Organized complexity here means that the character of the structures showing it depends not only on the properties of the individual elements of which they are composed, and the relative frequency with which they occur, but on the manner in which the individual elements are connected with each other. In the explanation of the working of such structures [… we] require full information about each element 1 It should noted that, though there is a variety of nuances of it, the complexity view is now common to different fields of modern natural sciences, from physics to biology to chemistry. Hayek himself had contributed to this paradigmatic shift in the view of the physical world too (see e.g. 1952). Hence his contrast between the methods of the natural sciences and of the social sciences is limited to the natural sciences that do not deal with complex phenomena, or, more probably, refers to the naïve view of the natural sciences that so much attraction has always exerted on economists. 3 if from our theory we are to derive specific predictions about individual events (p. 4, emphasis added). The core of Hayek's thought about the free-market organization of society then comes into play: no one in society can ever have access to the entirety of the dispersed and localized information regarding each single individual element. ‘No one’ means economists as well. A theory of essentially complex phenomena must refer to a large number of particular facts; and to derive a prediction from it, or to test it, we have to ascertain all these particular facts […] The real difficulty, to the solution of which science has little to contribute […] consists in the ascertainment of the particular facts (pp. 6, 7). The "difficulty" here is epistemological in nature; that is to say, it cannot be overcome by merely developing new statistical techniques. For it is an illusion "that we can use technique for the determination and prediction of the numerical values of those magnitudes [… and] the vain search for quantitative or numerical constants" (p. 5). Note that in these passages Hayek was referring to the intrinsic limits imposed on economic theory in general – including general equilibrium theory and not Keynesian theory alone – by the very nature of its object. He was wont to quote Pareto's dictum that we cannot predict from general equilibrium theory the price of bread tomorrow. Hayek did not imply that no theory of general and abstract patterns and properties of these structures is possible. He indeed regarded competitive general equilibrium theory as a legitimate and consistent proof that a self-organized order is possible in such a complex structure as a free-market economic system. What Hayek emphatically rejected was the claim that this theory can be brought directly to real world data and aimed at detailed prediction and control in the "scientistic fashion" criticized above. Unlike the position that exists in the physical sciences, in economics and other disciplines that deal with essentially complex phenomena, the aspects of the events to be accounted for about which we can get quantitative data are necessarily limited and may not include the important ones […] In the study of such complex phenomena as the market, which depends on the actions of many individuals, all the circumstances which will determine the outcome of a process […] will hardly ever be fully known or measurable [...] Without such specific information about the individual elements we shall be confined to […] pattern predictions: predictions of some of the general attributes of the structures, but not containing specific statements about the individual elements of which the structures will be made up" (pp. 3, 4; italics added) 4 "Modern economics" In the hands of the then upcoming new generation of Chicago freemarket theorists, those who laid the bases for today's mainstream, Hayek's epistemology was first misinterpreted and then entirely betrayed2. They argued that the origin of the failure and crisis of economics was simply that Keynesian theory offered poor guidance to macro-policy because "it lacked rigorous microfoundations". They then replaced Keynesian theory with general equilibrium theory, while also giving tremendous impetus to the OSC approach to macro-policy. The search for stable and predictable numerical relationships among aggregate variables that had misled the Keynesian macro-econometric models was replaced by the search for stable and predictable "deep parameters" (preferences, etc.) ruling individual optimizing behaviour − the prescriptive side of the so-called Lucas Critique. The "representative agent" short-cut may be seen as an attempt to circumvent Hayek's objection that all the relevant information is simply not attainable. This methodological apparatus has eventually been endorsed also by the "New Keyensian" macroeconomic school that was born to contrast the "no-policy" implications of the new Chicago school and reinstate the role of stabilization policies. The result is a common methodological framework (Blanchard (2008)), the so-called dynamic stochastic general equilibrium (DSGE) models that can be regulated by means of OSC instruments, promising to transform policy-making from art into science (e.g. Clarida et al. (1999)). This methodology is orthogonal to the CAS view. It is telling that this complete misconception of Hayek's epistemology occurred most blatantly at its very core: the (un)predictability and (un)controllability of the system at the level of individual behaviours. In fact, the usual argument in favour of rooting macro-theory in the neoclassical micro-theory of fully rational and optimizing individuals is that this makes the macro-level fully predictable (up to external random shocks). Yet, as a few important papers have shown (e.g. Kirman (1992)), the representative agent is a deceptive short-cut leading nowhere. Underground (in both senses of the word) theoretical and empirical research, and to some extent reality, have vindicated Hayek's view and have, in parallel, shaken the foundations 2 An early warning came from Frydman and Phelps’s (1983) book on the rational expectations hypothesis. 5 of the reductionist programme. Indeed, the opposite idea has emerged, namely that the deeper we penetrate into the micro-structure, the more we find the shifting sands of heterogeneity, bounded rationality, and all sorts of behavioural vagaries. Delving into individual behaviour and microfoundations has turned out to be very much like a one-way journey with no return ticket towards the meso- or macro-surface. Thus, the "rigorous" microfoundations claimed by the reductionists now appear not to be "serious" scientifically, whereas the "serious" microfoundations discovered by scientific investigation of human behaviour are hardly susceptible to "rigorous" aggregative procedures. Defenders of the DSGE-OSC apparatus entertain an intermittent attitude towards the issue of prediction and control. On the one hand, most practictioners subscribe to the popular version of Friedman's instrumentalism (whatever model is good insofar as it gives good predictions of the data, net of normally distributed errors, of course). Nowadays, as a response to the allegation of not being able to predict the crisis, it is often heard the argument that these models never promised accurate predictions of booms and busts. In fact, these are the "exogenous shocks" part of the story, and as such they are removed out of the reach of scientific economics. Yet this delimitation of the pretence of scientific economics is far away from Hayek's, who instead draws it at the very core of what the standard macroeconomist calls the "structural part" of the model. Another oft-heard argument is that seismologists cannot predict the occurrence of earthquakes with precision, but this does not make seismology a useless science. The same applies to meteorologists and long-term weather forecasts. But the unpredictable residuals buffeting DSGE economies attended by OSC tools are totally different from the unpredictable phenomena ("emergent properties") arising from system-wide interactions among heterogeneous particles that characterize CAS. For instance, seismologists, meteorologists, etc., do have a "mainstream" theory of earthquakes and hurricanes (which by the way are complex system theories) and they do know why we cannot predict and control these phenomena accurately (because we cannot know and control all the conditions of the relevant complex dynamic processes). Mainstream economists do not have such a theory of economic disasters: these are simply non-existent in their 6 theory.3 There must be something special that mainstream economists fear when thinking about economic disasters but which mainstream seismologists or meteorologists instead find so attractive in natural disasters. Where can we go from here? If − simply not to trespass the limits of this short note − we ignore the controversial co-existence in Hayek's thought of his complexity view with his confidence in the possibility that "pattern predictions" of economic CAS may include the standard general-equilibrium theorems, many modern followers of the complexity view are probably ready to subscribe to the substance of the statements quoted above. On this background, in their plea for economics as a science of CAS, Colander et al. (2008) recognize that At present, [these models] are still far too simple to bring directly to policy; they are, at best, suggestive […] How should one undertake macro policy today? Our answer is that policy economists need to go back to the engineering approach that economists used up until the 1940s and 1950s. That engineering approach does not search for scientific understanding: it searches for models that shed light on the problems at hand […] One can, and should, search for relationships among macroeconomic variables without worrying about the behavioral foundations of those relations (p. 239). Though sympathetic with the complexity view, I think that the approach to economic policy proposed above is not fully consistent with the epistemology of CAS, and it raises more problems than it offers solutions. First, it is questionable that it is difficult to bring CAS models to policy only because they are still "too simple". Spectacular technical progress in computer-based simulations of artificial CAS has strongly improved the scientific status of this methodology, and the ability of researches to understand how controlled changes in the structure or the inputs of the system produce new configurations and outcomes (Epstein, 1999). However, the hallmark of the complexity view is that complexity is a characterization of how a (possibly "simple") system works by way of "adaptive, self-organizing, out-of-equilibrium processes" (Foley, 2003, p. 2), not a characterization of the way in which the system is designed. Consequently, as was argued by Hayek, the difficulty with policy in the real 3 Lucas (2004) recognized this point with clarity. 7 world − of which we are not the designer nor do we know the exact encoded programme − is not merely technical: it is more radical, and epistemological in nature. Increasing the "complication" of models of complexity will not necessarily improve policy for CAS. Second, any complexity scientist would certainly be upset at hearing that he or she is not searching for scientific understanding. The immediate questions that come to mind are: scientific understanding of what, and of what kind? 4 One may say that the rules, practices, and self-understanding of scientific method pursued by complexity scientists may be different in nature from other methods that are pursued in the study of non-complex entities − and certainly in the no-complexity vision of economic systems. In particular, in a genuine CAS perspective, the search for scientific understanding of human behaviour should certainly not be abandoned by economists. Indeed, it should be fostered on an entirely renewed, nonautistic, relationship with the true sciences of human behaviour5. Third, a more data-driven, empirically-oriented relationship going from organized statistical evidence to theory, and not only the other way round, is certainly welcome (e.g. Hoover et al., 2008)6. Yet, if economic systems are CAS, policy analysis, or policy action, based on black-box econometrics may turn out be no less a dangerous illusion than that based on would-be microfounded econometrics. To mention just one problem, a typical implication of the complexity view is that it is generally unsafe to project past empirical regularities into the future7. Finally, but most importantly, "policy engineering", if it is not just an infelicitous wording, indicates a concept that cannot be the right solution since it is precisely the same operative arm of optimally controllable systems (Mankiw, 2006) that was originally criticized by Hayek8. He instead established the so-called "Ignorance Principle" as one of the key 4 Thorough reflections on these questions can be found in Epstein (1999). 5 As a matter of fact, this necessity is recognized by Colander et al. (2008) elsewhere in the paper and in many other writings in the CAS literature. See for instance Colander (ed., 2000), Epstein (1999). 6 Delli Gatti et al. (2008) exemplify how a CAS can produce a whole set of empirical regularities observed in the actual system, and vice versa, how the same empirical regularities can be used as a means to discipline the design of the artificial model. 7 Also, it is doubtful whether data generated by CAS are subject to classical probability laws as it is assumed by any econometric theory . 8 For a detailed and formalized analysis of this issue see Velupillai (2007) 8 ingredients of economic policy in the complexity view (Brock and Colander (2000, pp. 82 ff.)). The policy makers are part of the system, and no part of the system can track with certainty (or in terms of well-defined probability distributions) the consequences of its own actions on the whole. If man is not to do more harm than good in his efforts to improve the social order, he will have to learn that in this, as in all other fields were essential complexity of an organized kind prevails, he cannot acquire the full knowledge which would make mastery of the events possible (Hayek, 1974, p. 7). These considerations imply neither that there cannot be scientific method in the policy analysis of CAS nor that the only consistent policy implication of the complexity view is the faith in self-regulating markets9. Keynesian "policy engineering", after a couple of decades of apparent successes, suddenly failed to master stagflation, but Hayek had succumbed to Keynes in the debate over the causes and remedies of the Great Depression not for merely theoretical reasons. And he probably would succumb today, given the almost ubiquitous quest and support for Keynesian measures to curb the crisis10. Hayek was probably over-confident in the ability of market systems to always find their way out of instability or disasters without a sufficiently robust visible hand, or he was overpessimistic about the ability of the visible hand to never find a way to keep the system from going astray. After all, chemistry, biology or physics of complex phenomena are not merely contemplative activities. These phenomena do present some empirical regularities at the observable macrolevel, and, for most of them, scientists have been able to achieve sufficiently robust knowledge to the benefit of human beings. However, I think that economists of all persuasions should come to terms with the Ignorance Principle challenge to "policy engineering" in CAS. Will economists be ready to retreat from the unprecedented pretence of knowledge inbuilt in, and conveyed by, policy analysis in the optimal- 9 On these points see e.g. Brock and Colander (2000), Velupillai (2007). 10 It is telling that Lucas (2009), in his defense of mainstream macroeconomics, has argued that its good health is proven by its ability to indicate the right policies to policy makers, so that "the recession is now under control and no responsible forecasters see anything remotely like the 1929-33 contraction in America on the horizon". Notably, Lucas here makes explicit reference to distinguished economists in the policy-making arena, such as Ben Bernanke, who are academically associated with the so-called "New Keynesian" brand of DSGE models, which is not his most preferred brand. 9 control-DSGE fashion? Will they be ready to accompany their theories, predictions and prescriptions with a clear statement of their limits and potential damage if mistaken, as one can find in medicine dosage instructions? Is this deontology consistent with the self-constructed image of the modern economist as social engineer (Mankiw, 2006)? And, on the other hand, will institutional and political authorities be willing to pay pecuniary and non-pecuniary rewards to technicians falling short of the technical certainties of an engineer? References Blanchard, O. J. (2008), "The State of Macro", NBER Working Paper, n. 14259. Brock W. A., Colander D. (2000), "Complexity and Policy", in Colander D. (ed.), The Complexity Vision and the Teaching of Economics, Aldershot, Elgar. Clarida R., Galì J., Gertler M. (1999), "The Science of Monetary Policy: A New Keynesian Perspective", Journal of Economic Literature, 37, pp.1661-1707. Colander D. (ed., 2000), The Complexity Vision and the Teaching of Economics, Aldershot, Elgar. Colander D., Howitt P., Kirman A., Leijonhufvud A. Meherling P. (2008), "Beyond DSGE Models: Toward an Emprically Based Macroeconomics", Papers and Proceedings of the American Economic Association, American Economic Review, 98, 236-240. Delli Gatti D., Gaffeo E., Gallegati M., Giulioni F., Palestrini M. (2008), Emergent Macroeconomics, Wien, Springer. Epstein J. H. (1999), "Agent-based Computational Models and Generative Social Sciences", Complexity, 4, pp. 41-60. Foley D. (2003), Unholy Trinity. Labor, Capital, and Land in the New Economy, London, Routledge. Frydman R., Phelps E. (1983, eds.) Individual Forecasting and Aggregate Outcomes. Rational Expectations Examined, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Hoover K.D., Johansen S., Juselius K. (2008), "Allowing the Data to Speak Freely: The Macroeconometrics of the Cointegrated Vector Autoregression", Papers and Proceedings of the American Economic Association, American Economic Review, 98, pp. 251-255. Kirman A. (1992), "Whom or What Does the Representative Individual Represent?", Journal of Economic Perspectives, vol.6, pp.117-136. Lucas R.E. (2004), "Keynote Address to the 2003 HOPE Conference: My Keynesian Education", in de Vroey M., Hoover K. (eds.), The IS-LM Model: Its Rise, Fall and Strange Persistence", Durham, Duke University Press. 10 Lucas R.E. (2009), "In Defence of the Dismal Science", The Economist, August 8, www.economist.com Mankiw N. G. (2006), "The Macroeconomist as Scientist and Engineer", Journal of Economic Perpsectives, 20, pp. 29-46. Velupillai K. (2007), "The Impossibility of an Effective Theory of Policy in a Complex Economy". In: Complexity Hints for Policy . Colander D., Salzano M. (a cura di), Berlin, New York, N.Y.: Springer von Hayek F. A. (1942), "Scientism and The Study of Society", Economica, vol.IX, Aug. von Hayek F.A. (1952), The Sensory Order, London, Routledge and Keegan Paul. von Hayek F.A. (1974), "The Pretence of Knowledge", Nobel Memorial Prize Lecture, reprinted in American Ecconomic Review, 1989, 79, pp. 3-7.