Download the natural vs . the human sciences myth, methodology and ontology

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Marx's theory of human nature wikipedia , lookup

Philosophy of human rights wikipedia , lookup

Transactionalism wikipedia , lookup

Neohumanism wikipedia , lookup

Natural philosophy wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
The natural vs. The human sciences:
myth, methodology and ontology
Lo natural vs. las ciencias humanas: mito, metodología y ontología
Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson
Lund University, Sweden. [email protected]
Recibido el 25 de abril de 2013 y aprobado el 17 de mayo de 2013
Resumen
Sostengo que las ciencias humanas (i.e. las
humanidades, las ciencias sociales y las
de la conducta) no deben tratar de imitar
la metodología de las ciencias naturales.
Las ciencias humanas estudian fenómenos
significativos cuya naturaleza es
decididamente diferente de los fenómenos
meramente físicos que estudian las
ciencias naturales, y cuyo estudio, por
tanto, requiere métodos diferentes; los
fenómenos significativos obviamente no
obedecen a leyes naturales, mientras que
lo meramente físico necesariamente lo
hace. Esto no quiere decir que las ciencias
humanas no estudian una realidad
objetiva sobre la que no podemos tener
un conocimiento genuino. Se discute
la noción de realidad objetiva, y se
sugiere que las construcciones sociales se
pueden entender como entidades reales
objetivamente.
Palabras clave
ciencias humanas, metodología, ciencias
naturales, filosofía de la ciencia, objetivo,
realidad objetiva, construcciones sociales.
Abstract
I argue that the human sciences (i.e.
humanities, social ─ and behavioural
sciences) should not try to imitate the
methodology of the natural sciences.
The human sciences study meaningful
phenomena whose nature is decisively
different from the merely physical
phenomena studied by the natural
sciences, and whose study therefore
require different methods; meaningful
phenomena do not obviously obey natural
laws while the merely physical necessarily
does. This is not to say that the human
sciences do not study an objective reality
about which we cannot have genuine
knowledge. The notion of objective reality
is discussed, and it is suggested that
social constructions can be understood as
objectively real entities.
Key words
human science, methodology, natural
science, philosophy of science, objective,
objective reality, social constructions.
Discusiones Filosóficas. Año 14 Nº 22, enero – junio, 2013. pp. 25 - 41
Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson
Introduction
A myth that now and again rises to the surface is that the humanities
and the social and behavioural sciences (henceforth human sciences)
are methodologically and hence scientifically retarded in comparison
to the natural sciences, i.e. to the ‘exact sciences’, or Science with a
capital S. The essence of this myth is reflected in Braithwaite’s claim
that the methodology of the human sciences, in so far as they profess
to be applying an autonomous humanistic methodology focused on
understanding rather than explaining, is a “policy of deep breathing
followed by free association” (Haack 36). The underlying idea is that
the human sciences should regard the natural sciences as a role model
and try to assimilate their exact methodology. In this paper I will present
what I take to be the defining feature of the human sciences, and to
argue that on the basis of that hypothesis it is a mistake to treat natural
science as the ideal for all research.
It is important to note that I am not suggesting that the human sciences
apply, or should apply, a methodology wholly autonomous from the
methodology of the natural sciences, or that they produce some altogether
different kind of knowledge. I am suggesting that on the basis of the
very same kind of rational thinking that is applied in science in general,
a different methodology is motivated by a difference in the nature of
the phenomena that the human vs. natural sciences are studying. It is
universally acknowledged that different phenomena must be studied by
different methods, its just that the difference between the kind of objects
that the human vs. natural sciences study is slightly greater than, say,
the difference between electromagnetism and combustion.
The human sciences
The human sciences contain a multitude of disciplines that do not selfevidently offer a common denominator. Research in social work focuses
on the interaction between individual and public authorities, often using
qualitative research methods. They may want to find out how different
outreach programmes should be organised to achieve the best effect, e.g.
in reducing anti-social behaviour. Economy studies economical systems,
often using mathematical models. The goal might be to find out how 1%
price increase in raw cotton from India could affect British households.
Archaeology studies the past with the guidance of artefacts found in
the ground, sometimes using carbon dating. Literature studies various
26
Discusiones Filosóficas. Año 14 Nº 22, enero – junio, 2013. pp. 25 - 41
The natural vs. the human sciences: myth, methodology and ontology
aspects of the meaning mediated through literature and how it affects us,
usually using some form of linguistic or narrative analysis. One might
want to find out about the impact of 1984 on contemporary ideas about
government control. Philosophy studies, for instance, what cannot be
studied empirically but which the empirical sciences take for granted,
e.g. objectivity, rationality, and meaning. There is no tracking device for
the reliable identification of rationality or ways to chemically analyse
it. Conceptual analysis is the appropriate method, simply because
rationality is not a chemical compound. As everyone knows, the validity
of methods is relative to the subject matter. Given this short but extremely
varied list of disciplines one might wonder what on Earth could unite
the human sciences and set them apart from the natural sciences. They
deploy a range of methods—interviews, mathematical modelling, carbon
dating, questionnaires, narrative analysis, and conceptual analysis—
some of which require/allow statistical analysis of the data.
The subject matter of different disciplines within the human sciences
seems equally disparate: social interactions, exchanges of goods/
money, the past, texts, and concepts/ideas. My suggestion is despite
the disparate character of the objects being studied, the human sciences
actually study a particular type of entities that are decisively different
from the type of entities studied by the natural sciences. While natural
science studies inanimate matters of all kinds, the human sciences study
what I call ‘meaningful phenomena’ (see section 4 below). To my mind,
the methodological difference we observe is a consequence of differences
in the nature of the entities being studied. Science, in the most general
sense, designs and uses methods in accordance to what suits the study
of the objects they are interested in. This is the rational thing to do.
The natural sciences
Natural science, I suggest, is the study of what I will call the merely
physical; unconscious physical matter in all its forms. Of course, some
scientific disciplines traditionally classified as natural sciences, e.g.
medicine and biology, do study conscious beings, like humans. But, ex
hypothesi, in so far as this study is correctly labelled ‘natural science’
it only studies the physiology of humans. It is possible to study most
of the functions of the body quite independently of what goes on in
the consciousness of the person inhabiting that body. However, when
medicine diverts its attention to the investigation of a patient’s wishes,
wants and preferences (e.g. psychosomatic disorders)—things that
27
Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson
we are at present unable to understand in physical terms—it is no
longer involved in pure natural science. And, typically, the study of
psychosomatic disorders suffers from the same criticism as the human
sciences; lack of decisive evidence and strict laws that can give accurate
predictions and/or treatments. It is important to discern here between
approaches that assume that fixing the mind is to fix the body, e.g. with
the use of chemicals, which is a natural science approach, and those
who assume that to fix the mind might at least require a combination
of chemicals and some form of cognitive approach. This apparently
interdisciplinary approach, it seems to me, consists in the simultaneous
application of two distinct types of treatment that we hope will interact
in ways we do not yet fully understand. Who knows what the future
will reveal about the connection.
The most important aspects of the study of the merely physical, from
the perspective of this paper, is that everything in the physical domain,
we assume, is (i) completely governed by natural laws, and (ii) mindindependent; it has a certain nature independently of what we happen
to believe about its nature. Salt is, has been and always will be, watersoluble. It was water-soluble before anyone came to form any ideas
about either salt or water. Natural science aims to discover the nature
of unconscious physical matter in all its forms.
The merely physical vs. meaningful phenomena
The human sciences, on the other hand, study humans, but not primarily
as physical bodies. They study meaningful phenomena: social interactions,
experiences, thoughts, intentional actions, attitudes, humour, phobias,
etc; everything that involves human beings qua self-conscious beings.
That is why I choose to call them the human sciences. Others have
called them the ‘intentional sciences’, e.g. the philosopher Susan Haack.
According to her
the more important line of demarcation runs, not exactly
between the natural and the social sciences, but between
those areas of scientific inquiry which take human beings’
beliefs, intentions, and motives as part of their subject
matter, and those which do not. (Haack 36)
It must be added that the human sciences also study those meaningful
structures that humans create, e.g. societies, research communities, legal
28
Discusiones Filosóficas. Año 14 Nº 22, enero – junio, 2013. pp. 25 - 41
The natural vs. the human sciences: myth, methodology and ontology
systems, education systems, the world economy, businesses, languages,
literature, music and art, etc. Arguably, all these things exist only in
virtue of the intentional acts and thoughts of human beings. These things
are, in a particular sense, social constructions. The legal system would
cease to exist the moment the community of humans either ceases to
exist or ceases to have the intention of enforcing the law whenever they
judge that this is needed. We take the law so for granted. We think of
it as something as inevitable and natural as the weather. But in fact it
came into being by a long and gradual social process and continues to
exist and develop only as long as there is a body of humans that want
to uphold a social structure and order; as long as there are humans
that want to live in a society in which as many as possible can thrive
and be happy (well, humanists think that this ought to be the motive of
constructing a legal system).
The value of the human sciences
This is a place to mention briefly the question of the utility of the human
sciences, which is now and again called into doubt. Natural science, it
is said, has given us cures for all kinds of diseases, TV’s, computers,
and has brought us (some of us anyway) to the Moon and back again.
What have the human sciences ever done for us? Well, in so far as
there has been a progress in the structure and content of the law, in
educational systems, social structures, organisation of businesses and
world market, not to speak about literature and arts, this has been in
accordance to developments in the human sciences. It may perhaps be
difficult to calculate the value of such development in terms of cash
flow to the state budget, but it has made the world a better place to
live in. Is it a coincidence that the Bill of Human Rights echoes the
results of philosophical, sociological and psychological thinking about
the nature of humanity and the necessary conditions for us to achieve
the ‘good life’? It is absurd that we still have to defend the value of the
human sciences, and have to motivate why they should get their fair
share of government spending on research. Televisions, telephones, and
computers are all well and good, but I didn’t buy any of these things
only to marvel at the technological advances, but because these devices
enable me to see, hear and to read/write something interesting. It is the
meaningful content conveyed by these devices that is valuable to me.
29
Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson
Further details about meaningful phenomena
The human sciences also study artefacts, i.e. material objects intentionally
created by humans. But, and this is a decisive difference, a hammer
studied from the perspective of the natural sciences might turn out to be
a lump of chrome molybdenum iron, while from the perspective of the
human sciences it is a tool with a particular function and meaning in the
everyday life of human beings, irrespective of its chemical constitution;
it is useful, expensive, a symbol of status (or maybe of masculinity or
DIY-nerdity). Archaeologists date and chemically analyse their findings,
that is true, but they are aiming for more than just finding out their age
and chemical constitution. This data only helps to place the artefacts
in a certain historical context in order to aide our understanding of the
humans that made and used them, what they knew, what they did, what
kind of constructions were they capable of, what did they value, how
was their society organised. Archaeology is not a science of dating, but
of the history of human development. If we want to understand our
future, we’d better know about our past.
The human sciences ultimately study what could be called meaningful
phenomena, e.g. world economy, parenthood, music, art; everything
related to the general meaning and value of human existence. Again it
is important to realise that the human sciences cross the boundaries of
faculties, e.g. in the study of whether GP’s treat women differently than
men because of gender bias (i.e. because of their pragmatic construction
of gender) or of how user friendly a new lawn mower is. The definition
does not respect the boundaries of departments either. In one and the
same department we can find someone investigating the physical
mechanisms behind gluten intolerance and another investigating why
teenagers with gluten intolerance find it difficult to stick to a gluten free
diet. One investigator is looking at enzymes and the cellular composition
of the intestines (things wholly unaffected by our consciousness), and the
other is looking at the preferences, attitudes, psychological character and
cultural environment of gluten intolerant human beings. In the latter case
we are studying phenomena whose determinate nature is determined
by the intentional states of human beings and we look (or should look)
to the human sciences for theoretical guidance. Getting to know about
the social factors that make life difficult for the gluten intolerant may at
first be a cost to society, but if it results in changes that make life easier
for them and consequently reduces the cost of treatment for those who
fail to stick to their diet, the world will have become a better place.
30
Discusiones Filosóficas. Año 14 Nº 22, enero – junio, 2013. pp. 25 - 41
The natural vs. the human sciences: myth, methodology and ontology
Meaningful phenomena are dependent for their properties on human
thoughts, emotions, and actions, because our thoughts, emotions
and actions are constitutive parts of these phenomena. There are no
meaningful phenomena that do not involve conscious beings that
perceive the phenomena as meaningful in some particular way. The
world economy is what it is because there are 6 billion people that many
times a day make conscious decisions to buy/sell (or not to buy/sell)
some commodity. The economy changes when the actions of these people
change, e.g. because their attitudes towards the commodities in question
change. Say, if suddenly they start to believe that organic or fair-trade
origin of a commodity is more important than its glamour factor, or
even more important than the price (within limits of reason of course).
The world economy is an object of investigation whose properties is
constantly changing (perhaps not in every respect) due to changes in the
dynamics between the actors involved, and these dynamics can change
as a result of changes in the attitudes of the actors. No one will deny
that economics has found very strong relationships between various
factors, e.g. between price, demand and supply, but no one will claim that
economics has provided us with an equation that allows us to determine
how these factors interact with the same exactness as Boyle’s gas law can
predict the interactions between temperature, pressure and volume in
a gas. Are we to suppose that the lack of predictive reliability is merely
due to the incompetence of economists to ultimately discover the details
of the law of supply and demand, or could it be the case that this is a
different kind of law/regularity? Could it be the case that laws evade
the human sciences because there are none in the reality they investigate,
or that the regularities that do exist just aren’t as deterministic as those
that hold for inanimate matter?
Meaningful vs. lawful phenomena
The nature of the phenomena studied by the human sciences are special
because the properties relevant for their study are at least partly decided
by the meaning ascribed to these phenomena by autonomous human
beings, and by the actions they spontaneously initiate on the grounds of
some or other idea about these phenomena. As opposed to the behaviour
of salt, it is not assumed that the behaviour of human beings is causally
necessitated (i.e. lawful), which is why we can still insist we have a
free will. Of course we are at any given time influenced by a number of
external factors, and often, if not always, they do push us in a certain
direction, and yet we firmly believe it possible for a person to choose to
31
Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson
endure torture and death rather than betray a good cause. The free will
and every action initiated by a free will, is at least not easily described
or explained in terms of universally valid natural laws.
The phenomena studied by the human sciences are also in a certain sense
particularly difficult to study because they appear to lack a determinate
physical shape. Where is ‘rationality’ as an object of inquiry? Can we find
it in the library, bring it into the laboratory and submit it to controlled
randomised studies to ascertain its nature? And yet, there is no criterion
of greater importance than rationality when evaluating the conclusions
of natural science. Where do we find the ‘greater good’ or determine the
‘public benefit’ in whose service the natural sciences claim to deserve
the main part of public spending on research? I wish anyone good luck
who aims to discover what they are by an investigation of the merely
physical, i.e. without asking people about what they think is good and
useful, and why. It is ironic that the public benefit of the results of natural
science—by whose authority natural science claims its priority over the
human sciences—is a matter for the human sciences to discover.
The natural sciences have completely different prospects of finding
regularities of the sort we can generalise to laws, and that we can use
to make uncannily exact predictions about future behaviour of various
phenomena. The simple reason being that physical nature is lawful and
predictable; it offers laws on a silver plate. If we throw salt in unsalted
water at room temperature, the salt will dissolve. The result will
invariably be the same in those conditions and is therefore generalizable
to all salt everywhere at all times. This does not hold for humans. If you
throw a human in the water then the first reaction might be cheerfulness.
When repeated, the reaction may become ever so slightly less cheerful
until it ends in violent retaliation; unless the series of reactions develop
in the opposite direction, or differently today than it did yesterday. A
subject may laugh heartily but swear inside.
The indeterminateness found on the quantum level is in a completely
different ballpark. As far as we know, we find only probabilities on the
quantum level, but it is a predictable probability that can be universally
generalised, and be used to predict the behaviour of physical systems to
a degree of exactness never before seen. There is no more exact science
than the ‘indeterminate’ quantum physics.
Salt is not in any case unreliable and varied in the way a human is. It
doesn’t behave in accordance to its own ideas about how it ought to
32
Discusiones Filosóficas. Año 14 Nº 22, enero – junio, 2013. pp. 25 - 41
The natural vs. the human sciences: myth, methodology and ontology
behave (sometimes in conflict with how it wants to behave). It does not
lie or cheat, is not affected by the ideas and intentions of the researchers
about what is to count as a “right”, “wrong” or “wanted” reaction. That
kind of influence can have dramatic consequences in the human sciences,
and even for silly things like market research. A respondent might be
smitten by the enthusiasm of the questioner, suspect that they would be
very pleased with positive reactions to Magda’s Margerine and don’t
want to make anyone disappointed. Too many ‘helpful’ responses of
that kind might warrant a large-scale venture and end in tears. There are
no reliable tools to find out what a person really is thinking, as opposed
to what she says or writes. Not that it always matters that the subject
is honest in her replies, because humans don’t always know what they
think and feel, or why they did something or other. Someone might
honestly think that they vote for the Liberal democrats because of their
policy in foreign affairs, while really they were given a positive attitude
to the party through years of upbringing and have a tendency to think
that any policy of the Liberal democrats in foreign affairs is by default a
good policy. We don’t like the idea that we are influenced by such social
factors. We like to think that every morning we choose the clothes we
wear on the basis of individual choice, and yet miraculously manage
to dress perfectly in tune with the demands of fashion. Coincidence? I
don’t think so. However, even though we are to a high degree creatures
of habit and prone to comply to the demands of our social environment,
even unconsciously, then it appears to be within our power to break
the habit and chock the environment in a way no electron is able to do.
Can a natural scientist really imagine what it would be like to conduct
research on that kind of material? Imagine that every grain of salt was
in some significant sense unique and every now and then completely
changed its modus of being and of reacting to stimuli due to their ever
changing ideas about what they should do in light of their most recent
reflections on what it is that defines their very being as grains of salt?
You ever seen a Goth grain of salt, or a Punk electron? What if it reacted
in accordance to the expectations of the experimenter, or defied her
expectations every other time, because it regretted the way they reacted
last week? What if the only way to find out about the nature of salt
was to ask it, knowing that there is great risk that it didn’t really know
anything about its nature, or that it would lay if it did know? Would
the natural sciences then be the ‘exact’ sciences? My guess is that a
science can only be as exact as its subject matter allows it to be. I think
we have good reasons to believe that research in the human sciences is
33
Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson
decisively different because the phenomena they study are decisively
different from unconscious physical matter.
Objective reality vs. Objective knowledge
I have so far argued that the human sciences study meaningful
phenomena, which are decisively different from the merely physical
phenomena studied by the natural sciences. This claim can very easily
be conflated with the view that natural sciences study objective reality
while the human sciences do not; that there is after all a distinction to be
made between proper objective science and a science of “deep breathing
followed by free association”. This is not my view, nor is it entailed by
anything I have said so far. I think that the meaningful phenomena
studied by the human sciences are objectively real even though they are
mind dependent. Since I am sure many readers are used to thinking of
‘objective reality’ in terms of ‘that which exists independently of minds’,
there is some risk of misunderstanding here and I need to explain why
I think that this understanding of ‘objective reality’ is mistaken.
To repeat, the basis for the peculiar nature of the human sciences, to my
mind, is that they study a special type of objectively real phenomena,
phenomena that depend for their characteristics and existence on the
existence of intentional thoughts in sentient beings. An example of such
phenomena would be scientific research, which, I assume, is objectively
real, but only exists in so far as there exist researchers who study various
things in the intention of finding out what they are like. As such, scientific
research is a social enterprise and its character depends on a range of
ideas in the heads of researchers, say, about correct interpretation of data,
about good and bad research practice, and what counts as important
scientific problems. In other words, scientific research is a phenomenon
that is partly constituted by the contents of the minds that partake
in it, but it is nonetheless objectively real. However, to understand
scientific research in this way as objectively real, clashes with the idea
that ‘objective’ is equivalent to ‘independent of thoughts’ or ‘mindindependent’. Surely, this does not mean that scientific research is not
objectively real but instead that something must be wrong about this
idea of what it is to be ‘objectively real’.
The term ‘objective reality’ refers to the world as it is in itself
independently of our ideas about what it is like and of our attempts
to measure what it is like. The contents of minds can, accordingly, be
34
Discusiones Filosóficas. Año 14 Nº 22, enero – junio, 2013. pp. 25 - 41
The natural vs. the human sciences: myth, methodology and ontology
objectively real because this content can be what it is independently of
our ideas about what that content is. Someone may want to object: can
the contents of our minds really be a certain way independently of what
we think that content is; can we be wrong about our own thoughts?
Admittedly we are usually aware of the mental contents of our minds,
even when we are not reflecting upon it (i.e. when we are not thinking
about what we are thinking), but we can be uncertain about what it is
exactly we are thinking and feeling even when we are reflecting upon
it. And we can have incoherent thoughts apparently without realising it
ourselves. It appears to be possible for someone to form the idea ‘I am
incredibly humble’ without realising that they thereby no longer are all
that humble. We often misunderstand social contexts (this is one of our
greatest fears) and also fail to grasp how that misunderstanding comes
to be a constituent part of that particular social event and determines
the outcome of the situation. Imagine hearing a female acquaintance
say to her friend that she is pregnant, but you don’t realise that this
is a joke about her having gained weight. Then you are not going to
understand the evil eye you get if you blurt out ‘I thought you looked
a bit rounder than last I saw you’. Similarly, if you use the thumb signal
when hitchhiking in Italy—oblivious of the fact that in Italy the thumb
is used to signal ‘up yours’—then the angry faces and failure to get a
ride will surprise you. There are, then, plenty of aspects of meaningful
phenomena that could be clarified by the human sciences.
Too often ‘objective’ is defined in terms of ‘what exists independently of
our minds’ in the belief that this is equivalent with ‘the world as it is in
itself independently of our ideas about it and our attempts to measure
what it is like’. That is why the contents of our minds is not always
included as a part of what makes up objective reality, or at least not as
something that could have certain properties independently of what we
happen to believe about its properties. In the natural sciences no one
encounters any problems with this view because they only investigate
non-conscious objects and states of affairs. It just so happens that the
particular part of objective reality that the natural sciences study is mindindependent. Not so for the human sciences, which seek knowledge
about other subjects, the contents of their minds and how it affects their
behaviour. In that perspective, it is natural that the question should
arise whether some of the things the human sciences study really are
‘for real’ because clearly they are not independent of thoughts. To my
mind, it would be absurd to deny that the contents of thoughts are ‘for
real’, even if it doesn’t exist independently of thoughts?
35
Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson
It is not reasonable to deny the reality of mental content, because such
a denial is equivalent to denying that our actions have any meaning.
Researchers discuss and investigate which of their ideas best explains
what the world is like, because they have different ideas about it and
also believe that two incompatible ideas cannot be simultaneously
true. Their thoughts are constitutive elements of what we call scientific
research, and which makes it meaningful. Does this mean that scientific
research, because mind-dependent, isn’t ‘for real’?
To study research is not simply a matter of describing the movements
of researchers in time and space, and their empirically measurable
properties, but also the content of their ideas and how they motivate their
reasoning and actions. This is an essential part of validating scientific
results. However, according to the idea that ‘objective’ is equivalent to
‘independent of minds’ then the contents of the minds of researchers is
not a part of objective reality and therefore not ‘for real’. I don’t take this
to show that the human sciences do not study objective reality. I take it
to show that something is wrong with this idea about objective reality.
It is also worth noting that sometimes ‘objective’ is used in the meaning
‘measurable/observable’, under the assumption that if something is
objectively real then it can in principle be observed/measured by anyone
with the appropriate equipment. I don’t think it is quite that simple. It
isn’t self-evident that it will ever be possible to observe the contents of
minds by anyone other than the person having that content. The contents
of minds isn’t publicly available in the same way as physical objects
and their properties, which is why self-reported data on the contents
of a mind cannot be confirmed by a third party. Most importantly:
‘measurable/observable’ simply isn’t equivalent to ‘the world as it is in
itself independently of our ideas about it and our attempts to measure
what it is like.’
What I am trying to say is that one should distinguish very clearly
between (i) the idea that there is a world that exists independently of
minds, a world that has whatever properties it happens to have (the
world as it is in itself), and (ii) the idea that the we can obtain knowledge
that accurately represents what that world is like (representations of the
world as it is in itself). Typically the two have been bundled together
to make up the definition of what it is to be an objectivist, i.e. someone
who believes in an objective reality and that we can know what such
a reality is like. The two ideas come apart quite easily when we admit
36
Discusiones Filosóficas. Año 14 Nº 22, enero – junio, 2013. pp. 25 - 41
The natural vs. the human sciences: myth, methodology and ontology
that we may coherently admit that there might be an objective reality
about which we cannot perhaps have absolutely objective knowledge.
Perhaps the source to this confusion is that the terms ‘objective’ and
‘subjective’ are often used to denote two different perspectives, notably
the unbiased and the biased perspective. But, this use of the terms can
really only apply to subjects, i.e. the subject that can see the world
without being affected by subjective bias and the subject that is affected
by subjective bias. However, the idea of the world as it is in itself has
nothing to do with any perspective of any kind; it is not the idea of a
world that has an unbiased perspective of itself.
Social constructions are objectively real
From my point of view the study of ‘meaningful phenomena’, e.g.
linguistic categories or hierarchies of power— often called ‘social
constructions’—are just as properly objects of scientific research because
I consider them to be a part of objective reality. But it may be worth while
to give a more nuanced picture of social constructions than is usually the
case, because, arguably, there are various types of such constructions,
and, arguably, their nature is not a matter of mere taste or personal
opinion; they are not ‘mere fictions’.
Roughly following Haslanger (1995), I will mention three types of
social constructions and how they are very reasonably considered to
be objectively real phenomena: generic, discursive and pragmatic. A
generic construction is something that is created by a social activity
(genesis ≈ creation). The English legal system is a concretely existing
social phenomenon, which has been created by humans through direct
and indirect agreements about following certain rules in accordance
to various ideas about what is right and wrong (really about how we
want the society to be, ideally). It is based on ideas and agreements
(conventions) that reflect our intentional striving towards an ideal
society, but is nonetheless a real phenomenon that can be scrutinised
scientifically, even if it only exists insofar as there exists a body of human
beings that intentionally uphold the law. But it is not obvious that it is a
phenomenon that works in accordance to universally valid natural laws,
hence it should not by default be explained in terms of such laws, nor
is it obvious that we should be looking for such laws in the first place
when trying to understand or explain it.
37
Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson
A discursive construction is an object that has at least partially been
shaped by a social activity. A human being is a biological creature from
birth but is from then on shaped as a person through social influences
(upbringing/socialisation) and is in that sense a social construction.
Such entities are called ‘discursive constructions’ because the persons
we eventually become are very much influenced by the way others
talk about us. We are constantly told (or overhear) that we are ‘girls/
boys’ and must do this and that because we are ‘girls/boys’. We come
to find it unavoidable/natural to behave like the ‘girls/boys’ that our
environment clearly perceives and expects us to be, and unnatural to
defy that norm. We might even come to regard ourselves as being freaks
of nature merely for entertaining the thought of defying the norm. To
the extent that we are shaped as persons by such influences then we
are discursive social constructions; that doesn’t render us any less real
even though we might not be entities that fully obey natural laws; at
least not if we actually do have a free will.
Pragmatic constructions are really just concepts or ideas, often called
conceptual categories because it is in virtue of them that we identify
things as belonging to a certain category of objects. They are what usually
associated with the term ‘social construction’. As a general rule there
are as many conceptual categories in a language as there is a practical
use for (therefore the term ‘pragmatic construction’). In the research
community we use concepts like ‘transcendent’ and ‘operationalize’
which no one uses in colloquial language because there simply is no
use for them in that context.
Concepts are conceptual structures, whose content, for the lack of a better
characterisation, describe various aspects of reality (truly or falsely). The
problem is that we tend to think of every concept as denoting naturally
occurring phenomena, even when they denote generic and discursive
constructions, or even mere fictions. This is because our ideas tend
to become a part of our perception of the very things they are about.
For instance, we tend to think of ‘nations’ as denoting some kind of
naturally given kinds, just like lions, elephants and giraffes. And we
tend to see the ‘Britishness’ in every Briton, whether or not it is really
there to be seen. But nations are generic constructions; they are created
and destroyed by social activities, sometimes by a handshake. We can
change nationalities by agreement. In comparison, lions and elephants
couldn’t change species no matter what agreements they made because
they really are a natural kind.
38
Discusiones Filosóficas. Año 14 Nº 22, enero – junio, 2013. pp. 25 - 41
The natural vs. the human sciences: myth, methodology and ontology
Even though concepts are pragmatic constructions, i.e. they are the best
idea we have so far come up with about something, it does not follow
that the objects they denote must also be constructions (some are), and
it is a mistake to think that nations are not ‘for real’ just because they are
social constructions. Nations are real even though they are not obviously
objects that exist independently of the mental contents of the humans
that constitute the nation, and even though nations are objects whose
character depends on the individuals’ ideas about what it is to be of
that nationality. Brits genuinely tend to be ‘British’ because they regard
themselves to belong to that particular creed of people, but this is not
a matter of natural law. If minds do not obey universally valid natural
laws, then the nations they constitute don’t either, but that does not in
any way dilute their reality.
Yet further complications
Studies of the past offer yet another complication. The historian is
studying what no longer exists, the past, with the help of presently
existing clues, e.g. archived documents. It is difficult to know the
attitudes of the authors to what they wrote; whether they exaggerated
(negatively or positively) in light of some unstated political agenda, or
not. The object of study is no more, and something equivalent cannot
be recreated in the laboratory. To simplify, history studies unique events
while natural science studies repeatable events. Also, an historian is
not interested in tracking the footsteps of Shackleton’s journey merely
in order to know his coordinates in time and space, how much weight
he lost and how many fingers and toes, but to know and understand
what it was like to be on that journey in order to be able to appreciate
the accomplishments of those who endured the struggle. What was
Shackleton thinking while he was leading his men across the Antarctic
on a voyage that must at times (or throughout) have seemed doomed to
failure to everyone? Can anyone even hint at an ‘exact’ way of objectively
assessing/measuring what that was like? And, in the absence of such
‘exact’ ways, is anyone going to suggest that we shouldn’t even try or
that any such assessment is as good as worthless? It seems to me that
a refusal to engage in that kind of speculation or to even consider its
results, due to some misconceived ideas about the merits of stringent
‘scientific’ reasoning, will inevitably lead to an intellectual poverty that
I do not covet.
A further difficulty is the fact that the purpose of the human sciences is
not always descriptive but often normative. It often aims at finding out
39
Rögnvaldur D. Ingthorsson
what something ought to be like, instead of what it is like: what ought
the law to be like, how should we conduct scientific research? The latter
question is interesting, because natural scientists have of course a lot
to contribute with, regarding the nature of science, but any attempt
on their behalf to say what science ought to be like will fail to live up
to their standards of ‘science proper’. Indeed, natural scientists gladly
enter into debates about the nature of science oblivious to the fact that
thereby they have become part of the human sciences. I welcome them.
Anyhow, the social ideals we are striving towards do not already
exist somewhere to be empirically studied and then copied. It is more
likely that they are constantly being construed, and maybe perfection
is unattainable because the preconditions change with the birth of
new generations that turn out to be ever so slightly different from the
previous. There are no natural scientists, as far as I know, that study
how salt should behave as opposed to how it actually behaves. In my
opinion, the natural sciences have been allotted the easier task, and they
can afford to laugh good-heartedly at such a statement.
In conclusion
I think the claim that the human sciences are methodologically retarded
and should adopt the exact method of natural science is unfounded.
The human sciences have their own problems, determined by the
nature of their subject matter, and must resolve them in their own
way. I’m not claiming that the human sciences are at the peak of their
accomplishments. I don’t deny that they are in many ways in their
infancy and could learn a lot from natural science (and vice versa). I only
claim that those who have looked upon the human sciences as the less
talented sibling to the natural sciences have not adequately appreciated
the difference between the two kinds of phenomena that they are
studying and the methodological consequences of that difference. In fact
the stubborn insistence that there is only one way to do science, notably
the ‘exact’ way, may have delayed the methodological development of
the human sciences.
That the contents of minds are constituent parts of social phenomena
is the reason why the human sciences face different methodological
challenges than the natural sciences. Partly because this content is not
publicly available (cannot be independently verified by third party), and
partly because the mind doesn’t obviously obey universal natural laws.
40
Discusiones Filosóficas. Año 14 Nº 22, enero – junio, 2013. pp. 25 - 41
The natural vs. the human sciences: myth, methodology and ontology
So if my reasoning is to be criticised it should be criticised for assuming
that the thinking and actions of autonomous human beings isn’t causally
determined and that therefore their behaviour can’t be fully explained
in terms of natural laws. However, if this assumption is accepted, the
methodological consequences that follow from it should be accepted to.
To my mind, the acceptance of the reasoning developed here entails that
knowledge about human behaviour should not take the form of natural
laws that enables us to predict with unerring precision how humans
will behave, nor should hypotheses about human nature and behaviour
be tested in the same way that we test hypothesis about natural laws. It
is no favour to the human sciences to insist they copy from the natural
sciences methods that were designed for the study of a completely
different kind of subject matter.
I have here simplified and exaggerated the differences between the
human and natural sciences. Overall the similarities are greater than
the differences, especially in so far as they both deploy the same kind
of rational scrutiny of the validity and reliability of its methods with
respect to their subject matter, of the manner of reasoning about the data,
and of the conclusions drawn on the basis of that reasoning. They
judge the validity of conclusions in terms of relevance, reliability and
generalizability, except that the criterions for each of these, and the
degree to which they can be established, depend on the nature of the
subject matter. The human sciences are, in Susan Haack’s words, “the
same, only different”. One definite difference in my view is that they
are studying different types of phenomena, of which one type is lawful,
while the other isn’t obviously so.
References bibliographical
Haack, Susan. ‘The same, only different’. Journal of Aesthetic Education.
Aug. 2002: 34-9.
Haslanger, Sally. ‘Ontology and Social Construction’. Philosophical Topics.
1995: 95-125.
41