* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Lecture 04: Risk Preferences and Risk Preferences and Expected
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
Fin 501: Asset Pricing Lecture 04: Risk Preferences and Expected Utility Theory • Prof. Markus K. Brunnermeier Slide 04 04--1 Fin 501: Asset Pricing O Overview: i Ri k Preferences Risk P f 1. State State--byby-state dominance 2. Stochastic dominance 3. vNM expected utility theory a) Intuition b) Axiomatic A i ti foundations f d ti [DD4] [L4] [DD3] 4. Risk aversion coefficients and portfolio choice [DD5,L4] 5 Prudence coefficient and precautionary savings [DD5] 5. 6. Mean Mean--variance preferences [L4.6] Slide 04 04--2 Fin 501: Asset Pricing St t -by StateState b -state byt t Dominance D i - State-by-state y dominance Ä incomplete p rankingg - « riskier » Table 2.1 Asset Payoffs ($) t=0 Cost at t=0 investment 1 i investment t t2 investment 3 - 1000 - 1000 - 1000 t=1 Value at t=1 π1 = π2 = ½ s=1 s=2 1050 1200 500 1600 1600 1050 - investment 3 state by state dominates 1. Slide 04 04--3 Fin 501: Asset Pricing St t -by StateState b -state byt t Dominance D i ((ctd.) td ) Table 2.2 State Contingent ROR (r ) Investment 1 Investment 2 Investment 3 State St t C Contingent ti t ROR (r ( ) s=1 s=2 Er σ 5% 20% 12.5% 7.5% -50% 60% 5% 55% 5% 60% 32.5% 27.5% - Investment 1 mean-variance dominates 2 - BUT investment 3 does not m-v dominate 1! Slide 04 04--4 Fin 501: Asset Pricing St t -by StateState b -state byt t Dominance D i ((ctd.) td ) Table 2.3 State Contingent Rates of Return investment 4 investment 5 State Contingent Rates of Return s=1 s=2 3% 5% 3% 8% π1 = π2 = ½ E[r4] = 4%; σ4 = 1% E[r5] = 5.5%; 5 5%; σ5 = 2.5% 2 5% - What is the trade-off between risk and expected return? - Investment I 4 hhas a hi higher h Sharpe Sh ratio i (E[r]-r (E[ ] f)/σ )/ than h iinvestment 5 for rf = 0. Slide 04 04--5 Fin 501: Asset Pricing O Overview: i Ri k Preferences Risk P f 1. State State--byby-state dominance 2. Stochastic dominance 3. vNM expected utility theory a) Intuition b) Axiomatic A i ti foundations f d ti c) Risk aversion coefficients [DD4] [L4] [DD3] [DD4,L4] 4 Risk aversion coefficients and portfolio choice [DD5,L4] 4. [DD5 L4] 5. Prudence coefficient and precautionary savings [DD5] 6. Mean Mean--variance preferences [L4.6] Slide 04 04--6 Fin 501: Asset Pricing St h ti Dominance Stochastic D i Still incomplete p ordering g “More complete” than state-by-state ordering State-by-state dominance ⇒ stochastic dominance Risk preference not needed for ranking! independently of the specific trade-offs (between return, risk and other characteristics of probability distributions) represented by an agent agent'ss utility function. (“risk-preference-free”) Next Section: Complete preference ordering and utility representations H Homework: k Provide P id an example l which hi h can be b ranked k d according to FSD , but not according to state dominance. Slide 04 04--7 Table 3-1 Sample Investment Alternatives States of nature Payoffs Proba Z 1 Proba Z 2 1 2 10 100 .4 .6 .4 .4 EZ 1 = 64, σ z 1 = 44 Fin 501: Asset Pricing 3 2000 0 .2 EZ 2 = 444, σ z 2 = 779 Pr obability F1 10 1.0 0.9 F2 0.8 07 0.7 0.6 0.5 F 1 and F 2 0.4 0.3 0.2 01 0.1 Payoff 0 10 100 2000 Slide 04 04--8 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Fi t Order First O d Stochastic St h ti Dominance D i Definition 33.1 1 : Let FA(x) and FB(x) , respectively, respectively represent the cumulative distribution functions of two random variables ((cash payoffs) p y ff ) that,, without loss off generality assume values in the interval [a,b]. We say that FA(x) first order stochastically dominates (FSD) FB(x) if and only if for all x ∈ [a,b] FA(x) ≤ FB(x) H Homework: k Provide P id an example l which hi h can be b ranked k d according to FSD , but not according to state dominance. Slide 04 04--9 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Fi t Order First O d Stochastic St h ti Dominance D i 1 0.9 0.8 FB 0.7 FA 0.6 0.5 0.4 0.3 0.2 0.1 0 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 X Slide 04 04--10 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Table 3-2 Two Independent Investments Investment 3 Payoff 4 5 12 Investment 4 Prob. 0 25 0.25 0.50 0.25 Payoff 1 6 8 Prob. 0 33 0.33 0.33 0.33 1 0.9 0.8 0.7 0.6 investment 4 0.5 0.4 0.3 0.2 investment 3 0.1 0 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 Figure 3-6 Second Order Stochastic Dominance Illustrated Slide 04 04--11 Fin 501: Asset Pricing S Second dO Order d St Stochastic h ti Dominance D i Definition 3.2: 3 2: Let FA ( ~x ) , FB ( ~x ) , be two cumulative probability distribution for random payoffs in [a, b]. We say that FA ( ~x ) second order stochastically dominates (SSD) FB ( ~x ) if and only if for any x : x ∫ -∞ [ FB (t) - FA (t) ] dt ≥ 0 (with strict inequality for some meaningful interval of values of t). Slide 04 04--12 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Mean Preserving Spread xB = xA + z ((3.8)) where z is independent of xA and has zero mean for normal distributions fA (x) f B (x) μ = ∫ x fA (x)dx d = ∫ x f B (x)dx d ~ x , Payoff Figure 3-7 Mean Preserving Spread Slide 04 04--13 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Mean Preserving Spread & SSD Theorem 3.4 : Let FA(•) and FB(•) be two distribution functions defined on the same state space with identical means. Then the follow statements are equivalent : x ) SSD FB ( ~ x) FA ( ~ x ) is a mean p preserving ese ving spread sp ead of FA ( ~x ) FB ( ~ in the sense of Equation (3.8) above. Slide 04 04--14 Fin 501: Asset Pricing O Overview: i Ri k Preferences Risk P f 1. State State--byby-state dominance 2. Stochastic dominance 3. vNM expected utility theory a) Intuition b) Axiomatic A i ti foundations f d ti [DD4] [L4] [DD3] 4. Risk aversion coefficients and portfolio choice [DD4,5,L4] 5 Prudence coefficient and precautionary savings [DD5] 5. 6. Mean Mean--variance preferences [L4.6] Slide 04 04--15 Fin 501: Asset Pricing AH Hypothetical th ti l Gamble G bl Suppose someone offers you this gamble: "I have a fair coin here. I'll flip it, and if it's tail I pay you $1 and the gamble is over. If it's head, I'll flip again. If it's tail then, I pay you $2, if not I'll flip again. With every round, I double the amount I will pay to you if it's it s tail tail." Sounds like a good deal. After all, you can't loose. So here here'ss the question: How much are you willing to pay to take this gamble? g Slide 04 04--16 Fin 501: Asset Pricing P Proposal l 1: 1 Expected E t d Value V l With probability 1/2 you get $1. With probability 1/4 you get $2. $2 With probability 1/8 you get $4. etc. Ê (12 )1 times (12 )2 times (12 )3 times 20 21 22 The expected payoff is the sum of these payoffs weighted with their probabilities, payoffs, probabilities ∞ t so ∞ 1 ⎛1⎞ ∑ t =1 t −1 = ⎜ ⎟ ⋅ 2 2⎠ ⎝{ 123 probability ∑2 t =1 1 =∞ payoff Slide 04 04--17 Fin 501: Asset Pricing An Infinitely Valuable Gamble? You should pay everything you own and more to purchase the right to take this gamble! Yet, in practice, no one is prepared to pay such a high price. Why? E Even though th h the th expected t d payoff is infinite, the distribution of payoffs is not attractive… probability 0.5 0.4 0.3 0.2 0.1 0 0 20 40 60 $ With 93% probability we get $8 or less, with 99% probability b bili we get $64 or less. Slide 04 04--18 Fin 501: Asset Pricing What Sho Should ld We Do? How can we decide in a rational fashion about such gambles (or investments)? Proposal 2: Bernoulli suggests that large gains should be weighted less. He suggests to use the natural logarithm. [Cremer - another great mathematician of the time - suggests the square root root.]] ∞ ∑ t =1 t expected utility ⎛1⎞ t −1 <∞ ⎜ ⎟ ⋅ ln(2 ) = ln(2) = of gamble 2⎠ ⎝{ 14243 probability Ê utility of payoff Bernoulli would have paid at most eln(2) = $2 to participate in this gamble. Slide 04 04--19 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Ri Risk Riskk-Aversion A i andd C Concavity it u(x) ( ) The shape of the von Neumann Morgenstern (NM) utility function contains a lot of information. Consider a fifty-fifty lottery with final wealth of x0 or x1 u(x1) E{u(x)} u(x0) x0 E[x] x1 x Slide 04 04--20 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Ri Risk Riskk-aversion i andd concavity it u(x) ( ) Risk-aversion means that the certainty equivalent is smaller than the expected prize. prize Ê We conclude that a risk-averse vNM utility function must be concave. u(x1) u(E[x]) E[u(x)] u(x0) x0 u-1(E[u(x)]) E[x] x1 x Slide 04 04--21 Fin 501: Asset Pricing J Jensen’s ’ IInequality lit Theorem 3.1 3 1 (Jensen (Jensen’ss Inequality): Let g( ) be a concave function on the interval [[a,b], ] and be a random variable such that Prob (x ∈[a,b]) =1 Suppose the expectations E(x) and E[g(x)] exist; then E [g ( ~ x )] ≤ g [E ( ~ x )] Furthermore, if g(•) is strictly concave, then the inequality is strict. Slide 04 04--22 Fin 501: Asset Pricing R Representation t ti off Preferences P f A preference ordering is (i) complete, (ii) transitive, (iii) continuous and [(iv) relatively stable] can be represented by a utility function, i.e. (c0,cc1,…,ccS)  (c (c’0,cc’1,…,cc’S) ⇔ U(c0,c1,…,cS) > U(c’0,c’1,…,c’S) (preference ordering over lotteries – (S+1)-dimensional (S ) space) p ) Slide 04 04--23 Fin 501: Asset Pricing P f Preferences over P Prob. b Di Distributions t ib ti Consider c0 fixed, c1 is a random variable Preference ordering over probability distributions Let P bbe a sett off probability b bilit distributions di t ib ti with ith a finite fi it support over a set X,  a (strict) preference ordering over P P, and Define % by p % q if q ¨ p Slide 04 04--24 Fin 501: Asset Pricing S states of the world Set of all possible lotteries Space with S dimensions C Can we simplify i lif the th utility tilit representation t ti off preferences over lotteries? Space S with ith one dimension di i – income i We need to assume further axioms Slide 04 04--25 Fin 501: Asset Pricing E Expected t d Utility Utilit Th Theory A binary relation that satisfies the following three axioms if and only y if there exists a function u(•) such that p  q ⇔ ∑ u(c) p(c) > ∑ u(c) q(c) i.e. preferences correspond to expected utility. Slide 04 04--26 Fin 501: Asset Pricing vNM NM Expected E t d Utility Utilit Theory Th Axiom 1 ((Completeness p and Transitivity): y) Agents have preference relation over P (repeated) Axiom 2 (Substitution/Independence) For all lotteries p,q,r ∈ P and α ∈ (0,1], p < q iff α p + ((1-α)) r < α q + ((1-α)) r ((see next slide)) Axiom 3 (Archimedian/Continuity) For all lotteries p,q,r p q r ∈ P, P if p  q  r, r then there exists a α , β ∈ (0,1) such that α p + (1( α) r  q  β p + ((1 - β) r.. Problem: p you get $100 for sure, q you get $ 10 for sure, r you are killed Slide 04 04--27 Fin 501: Asset Pricing I d Independence d Axiom A i Independence of irrelevant alternatives: π p<q p π q < ⇔ r r Slide 04 04--28 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Allais Paradox – Violation of Independence Axiom 10% 10’ ≺ 0 9% 15’ 0 Slide 04 04--29 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Allais Paradox – Violation of Independence Axiom 10% 10’ ≺ 9% 0 100% 15’ 0 10’ 90% 15’  0 0 Slide 04 04--30 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Allais Paradox – Violation of Independence Axiom 10% 10’ 9% ≺ 0 100% 0 10’ 90%  10% 15’ 15’ 10% 0 0 0 0 Slide 04 04--31 Fin 501: Asset Pricing vNM NM EU Th Theorem A binary relation that satisfies the axioms 1-3 if and only y if there exists a function u(•) ( ) such that p  q ⇔ ∑ u(c) ( ) p( p(c)) > ∑ u(c) ( ) q( q(c)) i.e. p preferences correspond p to expected p utility. y Slide 04 04--32 Fin 501: Asset Pricing E Expected t d Utility Utilit Th Theory U(Y) U( Y0 + Z 2 ) ~ U( Y0 + E( Z)) ~ EU( Y0 + Z) U( Y0 + Z1 ) ~ CE( Z) Y0 Y0 + Z1 Π ~ ~ CE ( Y0 + Z) Y0 + E(Z) Y0 + Z 2 Y Slide 04 04--33 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Expected Utility & Stochastic Dominance Theorem 3. 2 : Let FA ( ~x ) , FB ( ~x ) , be two cumulative x ∈ [a , b]. probability b bilit distribution di t ib ti for f random d payoffs ff ~ Then FA ( ~x ) FSD FB ( ~x ) if and only if for all non decreasing utility functions U( U(•)). E A U(~ x) ≥ E B U(~ x) Slide 04 04--34 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Expected Utility & Stochastic Dominance Theorem 3. 3 : Let FA ( ~x ) , FB ( ~x ) , be two cumulative probabilityy distribution p x defined on [a , b] . for random payoffs ~ Then, FA ( ~x ) SSD FB ( ~x ) if and only if E A U(~x) ≥ E B U(~x) f all for ll non decreasing d andd concave U. Slide 04 04--35 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Digression: S bj ti EU Theory Subjective Th Derive perceived probability from preferences! Set S of prizes/consequences Set Z of states Set of functions f(s) ∈ Z Z, called acts (consumption plans) Seven SAVAGE Axioms Goes G bbeyond d scope off thi this course. Slide 04 04--36 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Digression: Ell b Ellsberg Paradox P d 10 balls in an urn Lottery 1: win $100 if you draw a red ball L tt Lottery 2: 2 win i $100 if you ddraw a bl blue bball ll Uncertainty: Probability distribution is not known Risk: Probability distribution is known (5 balls are red, 5 balls are blue) Individuals are “uncertainty/ambiguity averse” (non-additive probability approach) Slide 04 04--37 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Digression: Prospect P t Th Theory Value function ((over ggains and losses)) Overweight low probability events Experimental evidence Slide 04 04--38 Fin 501: Asset Pricing I diff Indifference curves x2 Any point in this plane is a particular lottery. Where is the set of riskffree lotteries? 45° x1 If x1=x x2, then the lottery contains no risk.Slide 04 04--39 Fin 501: Asset Pricing I diff Indifference curves x2 π z 45° z x1 Where is the set of lotteries with expected prize E[L]=z? It's a straight line, and the slope is given by the relative probabilities of the two states. Slide 04 04--40 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Suppose the agent is risk averse. Where is the set of lotteries which are indifferent to (z,z)? That's not right! Note th t there that th are risky lotteries with smaller expected x1 prize and which are Slide 04 04--41 preferred. I diff Indifference curves ??? x2 π z 45° z Fin 501: Asset Pricing I diff Indifference curves x2 π z So the indifference curve must be tangent to the iso-expectedprize line. This is a direct p of implication risk-aversion alone. 45° z x1 Slide 04 04--42 Fin 501: Asset Pricing I diff Indifference curves x2 π But riskrisk aversion does not imply convexity. This indifference d ff curve is also compatible p with riskaversion. z 45° z x1 Slide 04 04--43 Fin 501: Asset Pricing I diff Indifference curves x2 ∇ V(z,z) π z The tangency implies that the gradient of V at the point (z,z) is collinear to π. Formally, ∇ V(z,z) = λπ, for some λ>0. 45° z x1 Slide 04 04--44 Fin 501: Asset Pricing C i Certainty Equivalent E i l andd Risk Ri k Premium P i (3.6) (3.7) ~ ~ EU(Y + Z ) = U(Y + CE(Y, Z )) ~ ~ = U(Y +E Z - Π(Y, Z )) Slide 04 04--45 Fin 501: Asset Pricing C i Certainty Equivalent E i l andd Risk Ri k Premium P i U(Y) U( Y0 + Z 2 ) ~ U( Y0 + E( Z)) ~ EU( Y0 + Z) U( Y0 + Z1 ) ~ CE( Z) Y0 Y0 + Z1 Π ~ ~ CE ( Y0 + Z) Y0 + E(Z) Y0 + Z 2 Y Figure g 3-3 Certainty y Equivalent q and Risk Premium: An Illustration Slide 04 04--46 Fin 501: Asset Pricing O Overview: i Ri k Preferences Risk P f 1. State State--byby-state dominance 2. Stochastic dominance 3. vNM expected utility theory a) Intuition b) Axiomatic A i ti foundations f d ti [DD4] [L4] [DD3] 4. Risk aversion coefficients and portfolio choice [DD4,5,L4] 5 Prudence coefficient and precautionary savings [DD5] 5. 6. Mean Mean--variance preferences [L4.6] Slide 04 04--47 Fin 501: Asset Pricing M Measuring i Ri Riskk aversion i U(W) tangent lines li U(Y+h) U[0.5(Y+h)+0.5(Y-h)] 0.5U(Y+h)+0.5U(Y-h) U(Y-h) Y-h Y Y+h W Figure 3-1 A Strictly Concave Utility Function Slide 04 04--48 Fin 501: Asset Pricing A ArrowArrow -Pratt P tt measures off risk i k aversion i and their interpretations absolute risk aversion = - U" ((Y)) ≡ R A (Y) U' (Y) relative risk aversion Y U" (Y) =≡ R R (Y) U' ((Y)) risk tolerance = Slide 04 04--49 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Ab l t risk Absolute i k aversion i coefficient ffi i t π Y+h 1−π Y-h Y Slide 04 04--50 Fin 501: Asset Pricing R l ti risk Relative i k aversion i coefficient ffi i t π Y(1+θ) 1−π Y(1-θ) Y Homework: Derive this result. Slide 04 04--51 Fin 501: Asset Pricing CARA and d CRRA CRRA--utility tilit functions f ti Constant Absolute RA utility function Constant C R Relative l i RA utility ili function f i Slide 04 04--52 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Investor ’s ’ Levell off Relative l i Risk i k Aversion A i 1− γ ( Y + CE) 1- γ Y=0 Y=100,000 ( Y + 50,000 )1 − γ 12 ( Y + 100,000 )1 − γ = + 1- γ 1- γ 1 2 γ=0 γ=1 γ=2 γ=5 γ = 10 γ = 20 γ = 30 CE = 75,000 (risk neutrality) CE = 70,711 CE = 66,246 66 246 CE = 58,566 CE = 53,991 CE = 51,858 CE = 51,209 γ=5 CE = 66,530 Slide 04 04--53 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Ri k aversion Risk i andd Portfolio P tf li Allocation All ti No N savings i ddecision i i (consumption ( i occurs only l at t=1) 1) Asset structure One risk free bond with net return rf One risky asset with random net return r (a =quantity of risky assets) Slide 04 04--54 Fin 501: Asset Pricing • Theorem 4.1: Assume U'( ) > 0,, and U"( ) < 0 and let â denote the solution to above problem. Then â > 0 if and only if E~r > rf â = 0 if and only if E~r = r f â < 0 if and only if E~r < rf . • Define W(a ) = E{U (Y0 (1 + rf ) + a (~r − rf ))}. The FOC can then be written W′(a ) = E[U′(Y0 (1 + rf ) + a (~r − rf ))(~r − rf )] = 0 . By risk aversion (U''<0) (U''<0), W′′(a ) = E[U′′(Y0 (1 + rf ) + a (~r − rf ))(~r − rf )2 ] < 0, that is, W'(a) is everywhere decreasing. It follows that â will be positive if and only if W′(0) = U′(Y0 (1 + rf ))E(~r − rf ) > 0 (since then a will have to be increased from its value of 0 to achieve equality in the FOC). Since U' is always strictly positive this implies aâ > 0 if and only if E(~r − rf ) > 0 . positive, W’(a) W (a) The other assertion follows similarly. a 0 Slide 04 04--55 Fin 501: Asset Pricing P tf li as wealth Portfolio lth changes h • Theorem 4.4 (Arrow, 1971): Let solution to max-problem above; then: be the (i) (ii) (iii) . Slide 04 04--56 Fin 501: Asset Pricing P tf li as wealth Portfolio lth changes h • Theorem 4.5 (Arrow 1971): If, for all wealth levels Y, (i) (ii) ( ) (iii) where η= da/a (elasticity) dY /Y Slide 04 04--57 Fin 501: Asset Pricing L utility Log tilit & Portfolio P tf li All Allocation ti U(Y) = ln Y. 2 states states, where r2 > rf > r1 Constant fraction of wealth is invested in risky asset! Slide 04 04--58 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Portfolio of risky assets as wealth changes Now -- many risky assets Theorem 4.6 (Cass and Stiglitz,1970). Let the vector ⎡ â1 ( Y0 ) ⎤ p y invested in the J risky y assets if ⎢ . ⎥ denote the amount optimally ⎢ ⎥ ⎢ . ⎥ ⎡ â1 ( Y0 ) ⎤ ⎡ a1 ⎤ ⎢ ⎥ â ( Y ) ⎣ J 0 ⎦ ⎢ . ⎥ ⎢.⎥ ⎥ = ⎢ ⎥f ( Y0 ) the wealth level is Y0.. Then ⎢ ⎢ . ⎥ ⎢.⎥ ⎢ ⎥ ⎢ ⎥ â ( Y ) J 0 ⎣ ⎦ ⎣a J ⎦ if andd only l if either ith Δ (i) U ' ( Y0 ) = ( θY0 + κ ) (ii) U ' ( Y ) = ξe − νY0 . or 0 In words, it is sufficient to offer a mutual fund. Slide 04 04--59 Fin 501: Asset Pricing LRT/HARA--utility LRT/HARA tilit functions f ti Linear Risk Tolerance/hyperbolic absolute risk aversion Special Cases B=0, A>0 CARA B ≠ 0, ≠1 Generalized Power B=1 Log utility u(c) =ln (A+Bc) B=-1 Quadratic Utility u(c)=-(A-c)2 B ≠ 1 A=0 A 0 CRRA Utilit Utility function f ti Slide 04 04--60 Fin 501: Asset Pricing O Overview: i Ri k Preferences Risk P f 1. State State--byby-state dominance 2. Stochastic dominance 3. vNM expected utility theory a) Intuition b) Axiomatic A i ti foundations f d ti [DD4] [L4] [DD3] 4. Risk aversion coefficients and portfolio choice [DD4,5,L4] 5 Prudence coefficient and precautionary savings [DD5] 5. 6. Mean Mean--variance preferences [L4.6] Slide 04 04--61 Fin 501: Asset Pricing I t d i Savings Introducing S i • Introduce savings decision: Consumption at tt=00 and tt=11 • Asset structure 1: – risk free bond Rf – NO risky asset with random return – Increase Rf: – Substitution effect: shift consumption from t=0 to t=1 ⇒ save more – Income I effect: ff t agentt is i “effectively “ ff ti l richer” i h ” andd wants t to t consume some of the additional richness at t=0 ⇒ save less – For log-utility (γ=1) both effects cancel each other Slide 04 04--62 Fin 501: Asset Pricing P d Prudence and dP Pre-cautionary Preti Savings S i • IIntroduce t d savings i decision d ii Consumption at t=0 and t=1 • Asset structure 2: – NO risk free bond – One risky asset with random gross return R Slide 04 04--63 Fin 501: Asset Pricing P d Prudence and dS Savings i B Behavior h i Risk aversion is about the willingness to insure … … but not about its comparative statics. How H ddoes th the behavior b h i off an agentt change h when h we marginally increase his exposure to risk? An old hypothesis (going back at least to J.M.Keynes) is that people should save more now when they face greater uncertainty in the future. The idea is called precautionary saving and has intuitive appeal. Slide 04 04--64 Fin 501: Asset Pricing P d Prudence and dP Pre-cautionary Prei Savings S i Does not directlyy follow from risk aversion alone. Involves the third derivative of the utility function. ba ((1990) 990) de defines es abso absolute ute p prudence ude ce as Kimball P(w) := –u'''(w)/u''(w). p Precautionaryy savingg if anyy onlyy if theyy are prudent. This finding is important when one does comparative statics of interest rates. Prudence seems uncontroversial, because it is weaker than DARA. Slide 04 04--65 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Pre--cautionary Saving (extra material) Pre (+) ((-)) in s Is saving s increasing/decreasing in risk of R? Is RHS increasing/decreasing is riskiness of R? Is U’() convex/concave? Depends on third derivative of U()! N.B: For U(c)=ln c, U’(sR)R=1/s does not depend on R. Slide 04 04--66 Fin 501: Asset Pricing P -cautionary PrePre ti Saving S i (extra material) 2 effects: Tomorrow consumption is more volatile • consume more today, since it’s not risky • save more for precautionary reasons ~ ~ R R Theorem 4.7 (Rothschild and Stiglitz,1971) : Let A , B be ~ two ~ return distributions with identical means such that RB = RA + e, (where e is white noise) and let s and s be, A B respectively, the savings out of Y0 corresponding to the ~ ~ return distributions R and .B R A If R ' R ( Y ) ≤ 0 and RR(Y) > 1, then sA < sB ; If R ' R ( Y ) ≥ 0 and RR(Y) < 1, then sA > sB Slide 04 04--67 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Prudence & PrePre-cautionary Saving P(c) = − U ' ' ' (c) U ' ' (c) − cU ' ' ' (c) P(c)c = U ' ' (c) ~ ~ Th Theorem 4.8 4 8 : Let L tR , be b two t return t distributions di t ib ti suchh A RB ~ SSD ~ , and let s and s be, respectively, the that R RB A B A savings out of Y0 corresponding to the return distributions ~ ~ R Aand R B. Then, s A ≥ s B iff cP(c) ≤ 2, and conversely, iff cP(c) > 2 sA < sB Slide 04 04--68 Fin 501: Asset Pricing O Overview: i Ri k Preferences Risk P f 1. State State--byby-state dominance 2. Stochastic dominance 3. vNM expected utility theory a) Intuition b) Axiomatic A i ti foundations f d ti [DD4] [L4] [DD3] 4. Risk aversion coefficients and portfolio choice [DD4,5,L4] 5 Prudence coefficient and precautionary savings [DD5] 5. 6. Mean Mean--variance preferences [L4.6] Slide 04 04--69 Fin 501: Asset Pricing M -variance MeanMean i Preferences P f Early researchers in finance, such as Markowitz and Sharpe, used just the mean and the variance of the return rate of an asset to describe it. Mean-variance characterization is often easier than using an vNM utility function But is it compatible with vNM theory? The answer is yes … approximately … under some conditions. Slide 04 04--70 Fin 501: Asset Pricing M -Variance: MeanMean V i quadratic d ti utility tilit Suppose utility is quadratic, u(y) = ay–by2. Expected utility is then 2 E [u ( y )] = aE [ y ] − bE [ y ] = aE E [ y ] − b ( E [ y ] 2 + var[[ y ]). ]) Thus, expected utility is a function of the Thus mean, E[y], and the variance, var[y], only. Slide 04 04--71 Fin 501: Asset Pricing M -Variance: MeanMean V i joint j i t normals l Suppose all lotteries in the domain have normally distributed prized. (independence is not needed). This Thi requires i an infinite i fi i state space. Any linear combination of normals is also normal. The normal distribution is completely described by its first two moments. Hence, expected utility can be expressed as a function of just these two numbers as well. Slide 04 04--72 Fin 501: Asset Pricing MeanMean e -V Variance: ce: linear distribution classes Generalization of joint nomarls. Consider a class of distributions F1, …, Fn with the f ll i property: following for all i there exists (m,s) such that Fi(x) = F1(a+bx) for all x. Thi This iis called ll d a li linear di distribution t ib ti class. l It means that any Fi can be transformed into an Fj by an appropriate shift (a) and stretch (b). (b) Let yi be a random variable drawn from Fi. Let μi = E{yi} and σi2 = E{(yi–μi)2} denote the mean and the var of yi. Slide 04 04--73 Fin 501: Asset Pricing MeanMean e -V Variance: ce: linear distribution classes Define then the random variable x = (yi–μi)/σi. We denote the distribution of x with F. Note that the mean of x is 0 and the variance is 1, and F is p part of the same linear distribution class. Moreover, the distribution of x is independent of which i we start with. Ê We want to evaluate the expected utility of yi , +∞ ∫− ∞ v(z)dFi (z). Slide 04 04--74 Fin 501: Asset Pricing MeanMean e -V Variance: ce: linear distribution classes But yi = μi + σi x, thus +∞ +∞ ∫− ∞ v(z)dFi (z) = ∫− ∞ v(μi + σi z)dF (z) =: u(μ i , σi ). The expected utility of all random variables d drawn ffrom the h same linear l distribution d b class can be expressed as functions of the mean and the standard deviation only. only Slide 04 04--75 Fin 501: Asset Pricing M -Variance: MeanMean V i small ll risks ik Justification for mean-variance for the case of small risks. use a second order (local) Taylor approximation of vNM U(c). ( ) is concave,, second order Taylor y approximation pp is a If U(c) quadratic function with a negative coefficient on the quadratic term. Expectation E i off a quadratic d i utility ili function f i can be b evaluated with the mean and variance. Slide 04 04--76 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Mean--Variance: small risks Mean Let f : R Æ R be a smooth function. function The Taylor approximation is ( x − x0 )1 ( x − x0 )2 + f ' ' ( x0 ) + f ( x ) ≈ f ( x0 ) + f ' ( x0 ) 1! 2! ( x − x0 )3 +L f ' ' ' ( x0 ) 3! Use Taylor approximation for E[u(x)]. Slide 04 04--77 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Mean--Variance: small risks Mean Since E[u(w+x)] = u(cCE), this simplifies to var( x) w − cCE ≈ RA( w) . 2 Ê w – cCE is the risk premium. Ê We see here W h that th t the th risk i k premium i is i approximately a linear function of the variance of the additive risk risk, with the slope of the effect equal to half the coefficient of absolute risk. Slide 04 04--78 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Mean--Variance: small risks Mean The same exercise can be done with a multiplicative risk. Let y = gw, where g is a positive random variable with unit mean. Doing D i the th same steps t as before b f leads l d to t var( g ) 1 − κ ≈ RR ( w) , 2 where κ is the certainty equivalent growth rate, u( w) = E[u(gw)]. u(κw) E[u(gw)] The coefficient of relative risk aversion is relevant for multiplicative risk risk, absolute risk aversion for additive risk. Slide 04 04--79 12:30 Lecture Risk Aversion Ê Fin 501: Asset Pricing E t material Extra t i l follows! f ll ! Slide 04 04--80 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Joint savingsaving-portfolio problem • Consumption at t=0 and t=1. (savings decision) • Asset structure – One risk free bond with net return rf – One riskyy asset ((a = quantity q y of riskyy assets)) max U ( Y0 − s ) + δEU ( s(1 + rf ) + a ( ~r − rf )) { a ,s } FOC: s: a: ((4.7)) U’(ct) = δ E[U’(ct+1)(1+rf)] E[U’(c E[U (ct+1)(r-r )(r rf)] = 0 Slide 04 04--81 Fin 501: Asset Pricing for CRRA utility functions s: a: ( Y0 − s) − γ ( −1) + δE ([s(1 + rf ) + a ( ~r − rf )]− γ (1 + rf ) ) = 0 [ ] E (s(1 + rf ) + a ( ~r − rf )) − γ ( ~r − rf ) = 0 Where s is total saving and a is amount invested in risky asset. asset Slide 04 04--82 Fin 501: Asset Pricing MultiM lti-period Multi i d Setting S tti Canonical framework (exponential discounting) U(c) = E[ ∑ βt u(ct)] prefers earlier uncertainty resolution if it affect action indifferent, if it does not affect action Time-inconsistent (hyperbolic discounting) Special case: β−δ formulation U(c) = E[u(c0) + β ∑ δt u(ct)] Preference for the timing of uncertainty resolution recursive utility formulation (Kreps-Porteus (Kreps Porteus 1978) Slide 04 04--83 Fin 501: Asset Pricing MultiM lti-period Multi i d Portfolio P tf li Choice Ch i Theorem 4.10 ((Merton, 1971): ) Consider the above canonical multi-period consumption-saving-portfolio allocation problem. Suppose U() displays CRRA, rf is constant and {r} is i.i.d. Then a/st is time invariant. invariant Slide 04 04--84 Fin 501: Asset Pricing Preference e e e ce for o thee timing of uncertainty resolution Digression: g ess o : π 0 $100 $150 $100 $ 25 $150 $100 Kreps-Porteus π $ 25 Early (late) resolution if W(P1,…) is convex (concave) Marginal rate of temporal substitution risk aversion Slide 04 04--85