* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Multiproduct Retailing - Rotman School of Management
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
Multiproduct Retailing Andrew Rhodes∗ November 2013 We study the pricing behavior of a multiproduct retailer, when consumers must pay a search cost to learn its prices. Equilibrium prices are high, because consumers understand that visiting a store exposes them to a hold-up problem. However a firm with more products charges lower prices, because it attracts consumers who are more price-sensitive. When a firm advertises a low price on one product, consumers rationally expect it to charge somewhat lower prices on its other products as well. Low-price advertising can therefore be used to build a ‘low price image’. In equilibrium, retailers randomize over both their advertised and unadvertised prices. The model therefore generates price dispersion in a simple way. Keywords: retailing, multiproduct search, advertising JEL: D83, M37 ∗ Contact: [email protected] Toulouse School of Economics, Manufacture des Tabacs, Toulouse 31000, France. Earlier versions of this paper were circulated under the title “Multiproduct Pricing and the Diamond Paradox”. I would like to thank Marco Ottaviani and three referees for their many helpful comments, which have significantly improved the paper. Thanks are also due to Mark Armstrong, Heski Bar-Isaac, Ian Jewitt, Paul Klemperer, David Myatt, Freddy Poeschel, John Quah, Charles Roddie, Mladen Savov, Sandro Shelegia, John Thanassoulis, Mike Waterson, Chris Wilson and Jidong Zhou, as well as several seminar audiences including those at Essex, Manchester, Mannheim, McGill, Nottingham, Oxford, Rochester Simon, Toulouse, UPF, Washington and Yale SOM. Funding from the Economic and Social Research Council (UK) and the British Academy is also gratefully acknowledged. All remaining errors are mine alone. 1 1 Introduction Retailing is inherently a multiproduct phenomenon. Most firms sell a wide range of products, and consumers frequently visit a store with the intention of purchasing several items. Whilst consumers often know a lot about a retailer’s products, they are poorly-informed about the prices of individual items unless they buy them on a regular basis. Therefore a consumer must spend time visiting a retailer in order to learn its prices. The theoretical literature has mainly focused on single-product retailing. However once we take into account the multiproduct nature of retailing, a whole new set of important questions arises. For example, what are the advantages to a retailer from stocking a wider range of products? How do pricing incentives change when a firm sells more products? Some retailers eschew advertising and charge ‘everyday low prices’ (EDLP) across the whole store. Others use a so-called HiLo strategy, charging high prices on many products but advertising steep discounts on others. When is one strategy better than the other? In addition, advertisements usually can only contain information about the prices of a small proportion of a retailer’s overall product range. This naturally raises the question of how much information consumers can learn from an advert, about the firm’s overall pricing strategy. Related, when an advertisement contains a good deal on one product, should consumers expect the firm to compensate by raising the prices of other goods? In order to answer these questions, we begin by looking at the pricing behavior of a multiproduct monopolist. This delivers all of the first-order intuition. Later in the paper, we generalize our results to the case of duopolists who sell the same range of products. In our model, consumers have different valuations for different products, and would like to buy one unit of each. Every consumer is privately informed about how much she values the products, but does not know their prices. Retailers can inform consumers about one of their prices by paying a cost and sending out an advert. Consumers use the contents of these adverts to form (rational) expectations about the price of every product in each store. Consumers then decide whether or not to search, and in the case of duopoly also decide where to search. After searching a retailer, a consumer learns actual prices and makes her purchase decisions. We think 2 this set-up closely approximates several important product markets. For instance, local convenience shops and drugstores sell mainly standardized products which do not change much over time. A consumer’s main reason for visiting them is not to learn whether their products are a good ‘match’, but instead to buy products that she already knows are suitable. In addition, as surveyed by Monroe and Lee (1999), studies have repeatedly found that consumers have only limited recall of the prices of products which they have bought, and so in many cases, consumers are unlikely to be well-informed about prices before they go shopping. We first examine the relationship between the size of a firm’s product range, and the prices it charges on individual items. There is lots of evidence, both empirical and anecdotal, that larger stores generally charge lower prices. For example in the United Kingdom, the two major supermarket chains charge higher prices in their small stores (Competition Commission 2008). A similar negative relationship between store size and prices is also documented by Asplund and Friberg (2002) for Sweden, and by Kaufman et al (1997) for the United States. Our model provides a novel explanation for this phenomenon, that is unrelated to production costs or store differentiation. We show that larger stores should charge lower prices, because they attract consumers who on average have more low product valuations. This result is best understood within the context of the “Diamond Paradox” (Diamond 1971). Suppose for a moment that firms sell just one product. Also suppose that consumers have unit demand for that product, and that travelling to each firm costs some amount s > 0. Under these assumptions no consumer will search, and firms gets zero profit. The reason is that if consumers expect retailers to charge a price pe , only people with a valuation above pe + s will search. Therefore consumers will buy in the first store they visit without searching further, so long as that store does not charge a price exceeding pe + s. Hence there cannot be an equilibrium in which some consumers search, because retailers would always hold consumers up by charging more than they expected. This happens irrespective of how many retailers there are in the market. We show that this ‘no search problem’ disappears when retailers sell multiple 3 products.1 Intuitively in the single-product case, only consumers with a high valuation decide to search, so retailers exploit this and charge a high price. However in the multiproduct case, somebody with a low valuation on one product may still search because she has a high valuation on another. Retailers then have an incentive to charge lower prices, in order to sell products to low-valuation consumers. Nevertheless - and crucially for our results - the hold-up problem persists, albeit in a weaker form. In particular only consumers with relatively high valuations search, and this leads to high equilibrium prices. This explains the importance of product range. A larger retailer attracts more consumers, who are more representative of the general population, and who therefore have a higher number of low product valuations. Consequently, the consumers who search a larger retailer tend to be more price-elastic.2 We then characterize a multiproduct retailer’s optimal advertising strategy. Typically adverts can only contain information on a very small number of prices. Although there is a large literature on advertising (see Bagwell 2007), an important but much-neglected question, is how a retailer’s few (but typically very low) advertised prices are related to the prices that it charges on its other products. In order to answer this question, we introduce costly advertising whereby a firm can directly inform consumers about one of its prices. We show that when a firm cuts its ad1 Many papers have offered other resolutions. For example, consumers might learn prices from several firms during a single search (Burdett and Judd 1983). Alternatively some consumers may enjoy shopping, or know all retailers’ prices before searching (Varian 1980, Stahl 1989). In both cases competition for the better-informed consumers leads to somewhat lower prices. Secondly firms might send out adverts which commit them to charging a particular price, and thereby guarantee consumers some surplus (Wernerfelt 1994, Anderson and Renault 2006). Thirdly consumers might only learn their match for a product after searching for it. In this case, Anderson and Renault (1999) show that the market does not collapse provided there is enough preference for variety. 2 Two other papers which look at the relationship between product range and price, are VillasBoas (2009) and Zhou (2012). Villas-Boas shows that a monopolist charges a higher price when it stocks more substitute products, because it is more likely to provide consumers with a better match. In Zhou’s model firms sell two independent products, and matches are independent across firms. He also finds that multiproduct firms compete more aggressively. However unlike in our model, the reason is that firms find it more valuable to stop consumers searching further. 4 vertised price, some new consumers with relatively low valuations decide to search it. The firm then finds it optimal to also reduce its unadvertised prices, in order to sell more products to these new searchers. Therefore consumers (rationally) expect a positive relationship between a firm’s advertised and unadvertised prices. Whilst firms cannot commit in advance to their unadvertised prices, they can indirectly convey information about them via their advertised price. This implies that a low advertised price on one product can build a store-wide ‘low price-image’, even on completely unrelated products. This result is related to but different from Lal and Matutes (1994) and Ellison (2005), in which two firms are located on a Hotelling line and sell two products but advertise only one of them. In Lal and Matutes all consumers have an identical willingness to pay H for one unit of each good. In Ellison all consumers value the advertised (base) product the same, but have either a high or a low valuation for the unadvertised (add-on) product. As in Diamond’s model, the unadvertised price is driven up to H in Lal and Matutes, and (typically) up to the high-types’ willingness to pay in Ellison’s model. Firms use their advertised price to compete for store traffic, but unlike in our model, cannot use it to credibly convey information about their unadvertised price. The difference arises because in our paper, valuations are heterogeneous and continuously distributed. Therefore when a firm changes its advertised price, the pool of searchers also changes and this alters the firm’s pricing incentives on its other products. In another line of work, Simester (1995) also finds that prices are positively correlated, but this is due to a different, cost-related mechanism. In his model, a low-cost firm may charge a low advertised price in order to signal its cost advantage to consumers. Our model also provides a simple explanation for price dispersion, especially dispersion of unadvertised prices. We show that sometimes a retailer charges a high ‘regular’ price on each product, and does not advertise. At other times, it decides to hold a promotion. During the promotion, it advertises a low but random price on one of its products.3 Moreover as explained above, unadvertised prices are positively 3 The retailer also chooses at random which product to promote. Lal and Rao (1997) reach the same conclusion in a different model. However DeGraba (2006) shows that when some consumers 5 related to a firm’s advertised price.4 Hence our model generates dispersion, even in the prices of products which neither firm is advertising. This is unlike existing papers such as Lal and Matutes, Robert and Stahl (1993), and Baye and Morgan (2001), which also differentiate between advertised and unadvertised products, but which all predict that unadvertised prices should be non-dispersed. Our model also predicts the coexistence of small (unadvertised) and large (advertised) price discounts. As such it suggests that price distributions should have a mass point (at the regular price) as well as at least two gaps. This differs from other models such as Varian (1980) and Baye and Morgan, which predict no gap, and from Narasimhan (1988) and Robert and Stahl, which predict a single gap. Finally we extend our results in several directions. This includes relaxing the assumption that consumers are interested in buying all of a retailer’s products. In particular we consider a richer setting, where the retailer has categories of products, and consumers wish to buy at most one good from each category. As in the main model, we show that when a firm has more product categories, its prices are lower. However we also show that when a firm stocks more products within each category, its prices are not necessarily lower. This allows us to derive more precise predictions about the relationship between product range and price, and we then offer some empirical evidence in their favor. The rest of the paper proceeds as follows. Section 2 outlines the main model, which has only one retailer. Section 3 characterizes prices when the firm decides not to advertise, whilst Section 4 characterizes the optimal advertising strategy. Section 5 repeats these steps for multiproduct duopolists, and demonstrates a close are more profitable than others, firms should disproportionately advertise products which are (primarily) bought by those consumers. Chen and Rey (2012) find that when retailers are asymmetric, competition for one-stop shoppers causes them to offer their best deal on different products. 4 McAfee (1995) and Hosken and Reiffen (2007) find that multiproduct firms’ prices are negatively correlated, whilst Shelegia (2012) finds them to be uncorrelated. These papers differ from us, because they look at markets in which all prices are unadvertised, but some consumers can search costlessly. On the other hand, Bliss (1988) and Ambrus and Weinstein (2008) suppose that consumers are informed about all of a retailer’s prices. Bliss shows that firms use Ramsey pricing, and as such may charge low prices on some products but high prices on others. However Ambrus and Weinstein prove that this is only possible when there are certain demand complementarities. 6 connection with the monopoly analysis. Section 6 then extends the model in several directions, and Section 7 concludes. 2 Main model There is a unit mass of consumers interested in buying N products. These N products are neither substitutes nor complements, and consumers demand at most one unit of each. We let vj denote a typical consumer’s valuation for product j. Each vj is drawn independently across both products and consumers, using a distribution function F (vj ) whose support is [a, b] ⊂ R+ . The corresponding density f (vj ) is strictly positive, continuously differentiable, and logconcave.5 The marginal cost of producing each product is c, where 0 ≤ c < b. We also define pm = arg max (p − c) [1 − F (p)]; for expositional simplicity we focus on the case pm > a, although our results also hold when pm = a. There is one retailer, who has a local monopoly over the supply of n ≤ N of the products. (This assumption is relaxed later on.) Consumers have full information about which n products the retailer stocks. Each consumer also knows her individual valuations (v1 , v2 , ..., vn ), but initially does not know any of the firm’s prices. In order to buy anything consumers must travel to the store at cost s > 0; once inside the store they learn all the retailer’s prices. We can therefore interpret s as both a search and a shopping cost. The model has three stages. In the first stage the retailer privately chooses the prices of every product, which we denote by p = (p1 , p2 , .....pn ). It also has the opportunity to inform consumers about the price of one its products, by buying an advertisement at cost κ > 0. The advert must be truthful, and is received by all consumers. In the second stage consumers observe whether or not an advert was sent (and if so, learn the advertised price) and then form expectations pe = (pe1 , pe2 , .....pen ) about the prices of each product. Consumers then decide whether or not to incur the search cost and visit the retailer. Finally in the third stage, consumers who have 5 Bagnoli and Bergstrom (2005) show that many common densities (and their truncations) are logconcave. Logconcavity ensures that the hazard rate f (vj )/ (1 − F (vj )) is increasing. 7 travelled to the store learn actual prices and make their purchases. 3 No advertising We first analyze the benchmark case, where the retailer has decided not to advertise. 3.1 Solving for equilibrium prices Consumers learn that the firm has not advertised, and form expectations pe = (pe1 , pe2 , . . . , pen ) about the price of each product. Consumers then visit the retailer if P their expected surplus nj=1 max vj − pej , 0 exceeds the search cost s. As a preliminary step, we note that there is a continuum of equilibria whose prices P satisfy nj=1 max b − pej , 0 ≤ s. Consumers anticipate these very high prices, and therefore do not search. The retailer consequently earns zero profit, and is therefore willing to set p = pe . Moreover when n = 1 this is the unique equilibrium outcome; in particular, we cannot construct an equilibrium in which consumers search. The intuition for this result can be traced back to Diamond (1971) and Stiglitz (1979). Suppose to the contrary that pe < b − s, in which case all consumers with v1 ≥ pe1 + s would find it worthwhile to visit the retailer. The problem is that since all the consumers in the store would be willing to pay at least pe1 + s for the product, the retailer would hold them up by charging p1 > pe1 . This hold-up problem can only be avoided when pe1 ∈ [b − s, b], i.e. when the expected price is so high that no consumer wishes to search. Clearly in order to construct a theory of retailing, firms must ordinarily make positive sales. What we now show is that when a retailer stocks multiple products, the above ‘no search problem’ can be resolved in a very natural and straightforward P manner. To this end let us now suppose that nj=1 max b − pej , 0 > s, in which case some consumers visit the retailer. Once a consumer has searched, she buys any product for which her valuation exceeds the price. Therefore we can write the 8 demand for product i as Di (pi ; pe ) = Zb f (vi ) Pr pi n X j=1 ! e max vj − pj , 0 ≥ s vi dvi (1) The firm chooses the actual price pi to maximize its profit (pi − c) Di (pi ; pe ) on good i. In equilibrium consumer price expectations must be correct, so we require that pei = argmax (pi − c) Di (pi ; pe ). Imposing this condition, we have the following pi lemma. (Note that proofs generally appear in the appendices.) Lemma 1 The equilibrium price of unadvertised good i satisfies ! Di (pi = pei ; pe ) − (pei − c) f (pei ) Pr X max vj − pej , 0 ≥ s =0 (2) j6=i Equation (2) can be interpreted as follows. Suppose the firm charges slightly more for product i than consumers were expecting. The retailer gains extra revenue from the consumers who buy the product, and they have mass equal to demand. The retailer loses margin pei −c on each consumer who stops buying the good, and they have mass P e , 0 ≥ s . Intuitively, each consumer who stops buying max v − p f (pei ) Pr j j j6=i the good a). has a marginal valuation vi = pei for it, and b). has searched. Any consumer who is marginal for good i only searches if her expected surplus on the P remaining n − 1 goods, j6=i max vj − pej , 0 , exceeds the search cost s. Figure 1 illustrates this when n = 2 and consumers rationally anticipate prices pe1 and pe2 . Consumers in the top-right corner have both a high v1 and a high v2 , and therefore definitely search and buy both products. Consumers in the bottom-right corner have v2 ≤ pe2 and therefore do not expect to buy product 2; however they still search because v1 ≥ pe1 + s and therefore product 1 alone is expected to give enough surplus. Demand for product 1 therefore equals the mass of consumers located in those two regions. Thickness of demand for product 1 is given by the thick line, that is consumers with v1 = pe1 and v2 ≥ pe2 + s. Proposition 2 If n is sufficiently large, there exists at least one equilibrium in which consumers search and the retailer makes positive profit. 9 v2 b Search and buy product 2 only Search and buy both products pe2 +s pe2 Marginal consumers for product 1 who search a a Search and buy product 1 only pe1 pe1 +s v1 b Figure 1: Search behavior when n = 2. Once we take seriously the multiproduct nature of retailing, the ‘no search problem’ which we discussed earlier, can be resolved. Intuitively a multiproduct firm attracts a broad mix of consumers, not all of whom have high valuations for every product in the store. In particular some consumers who are marginal for product 1 (say), search because they want to buy other goods. If the retailer increases p1 it will lose the demand of these marginal consumers. Now, when the firm’s product range is large, many consumers who are marginal for product 1, find it worthwhile to search. Therefore the firm’s incentive to hold-up buyers of product 1 is weak, and this allows us to support a rational expectations equilibrium with search. Notice that consumer heterogeneity plays an important role in this argument. If consumers had the same valuation v̄ for each product, the firm could (and would) extract all the surplus from any consumer who decided to search. Therefore consumer heterogeneity and multiple products are both important features of our set-up.6 6 We are also assuming here that the search cost does not increase in store size. However this assumption is not crucial for the result. Let us define a general search cost s (n), and let Rb µpm ≡ pm (x − pm ) f (x) dx be average per-product surplus when price is pm . We can prove that Proposition 2 still holds, provided there exists δ > 0 and an n0 , such that s (n) /n ≤ µpm − δ for all 10 Table 1: Number of products required for an equilibrium with search. Support of (uniformly distributed) valuations c= c= 1 4 1 2 [0, 1] [1/2, 3/2] [1, 2] [0, 2] [1, 3] [0, 3] s = 10−6 3 2 2 3 2 3 s = 1/2 12 6 4 6 3 4 s=1 20 9 6 9 5 7 s=2 36 15 9 15 8 11 s = 10−6 4 3 2 3 2 3 s = 1/2 22 8 5 7 4 4 s=1 39 13 7 12 6 7 s=2 73 22 11 20 9 12 According to Proposition 2 only retailers with sufficiently many products, are able to attract consumers and make a positive profit. We can show that the critical number of products needed for this to happen, varies with underlying parameters of the model in a natural way (provided f (v) increases or does not decrease too rapidly). Firstly we can show that more products are required when either the search or production cost is higher. Intuitively fewer marginal consumers search when s is higher, so the firm’s incentive to hold-up consumers is greater. Similarly marginal consumers are less valuable to the firm when c is higher, so raising prices is again more attractive. The retailer must therefore stock more products, in order to offset its increased desire to hold-up consumers. Secondly suppose valuations are drawn from [a + q, b + q] using distribution function F (v − q). q can loosely be interpreted as a measure of product quality. We can also show that when q is higher, the hold-up problem is less severe, so the retailer need not stock so many products. Table 1 gives the critical number of products referred to in Proposition 2, for different combinations of parameters, when valuations are uniformly distributed. For example a retailer with two or more products can make positive profit, when valuations are uniform on [1, 2], and c = 1/2 and s = 10−6 . However the critical n ≥ n0 . Therefore a search-equilibrium exists even when s0 (n) > 0, so long as the average search cost is not too large. 11 number of products can also exceed two, and varies with s, c, and q as described above. Henceforth we assume that n is large enough to support a search-equilibrium. We now want to gain more understanding of how a retailer chooses its prices. To do this, it is convenient to introduce the notation tj ≡ max vj − pej , 0 for the expected P surplus on good j. Only consumers with nj=1 tj ≥ s actually visit the store, and can therefore respond to changes in the actual price of product i. These consumers naturally split into two groups. We borrow some terminology from the existing literature, and use the term ‘shoppers for product i’ to denote those consumers P with j6=i tj ≥ s. They search irrespective of how much they value product i. We use the term ‘Diamond consumers for product i’ to denote those people with Pn P j=1 tj ≥ s > j6=i tj . They only search because they anticipate a strictly positive surplus on product i. Equation (2), which is the first order condition for product i, can be rewritten as: ! ! ! n X X X Pr tj ≥ s [1 − F (pei ) − (pei − c) f (pei )] +Pr tj ≥ s − Pr tj ≥ s = 0 j=1 j6=i | {z } Probability of a shopper | j6=i {z } Probability of a Diamond consumer (3) The lefthand side of this equation decomposes into two parts, the change in profits caused by a small change in pi around pei . Firstly shoppers for product i search irrespective of their vi , which therefore continues to be distributed on [a, b] with the usual density f (vi ). Consequently profits on shoppers are simply (pi − c) [1 − F (pi )] (the same as in a standard zero-search-cost monopoly problem), and so small changes in pi around pei affect profits by 1 − F (pei ) − (pei − c) f (pei ). Secondly Diamond consumers for product i have vi − pei > 0, so they would all buy product i even if the price were slightly higher than expected. Consequently a small increase in pi above pei , causes profits on Diamond consumers to increase by 1. Just like consumers at a single-product retailer, their demand is locally perfectly inelastic. Recall from earlier that pm = arg max (p − c) [1 − F (p)] is the standard monopoly price which arises when there is no search cost. Remark 3 The equilibrium price of any unadvertised good i strictly exceeds pm . 12 Equation (3) can only be satisfied if 1 − Fi (pei ) − (pei − c) f (pei ) < 0. Using the quasiconcavity of (pi − c) [1 − F (pi )], this is equivalent to saying that pei > pm . Intuitively only consumers with relatively high valuations search, and the retailer will naturally try to somewhat exploit this ex post. Hence there is still a partial hold-up problem, and this drives equilibrium prices above pm . 3.2 Equilibrium multiplicity and selection As discussed earlier our model has a whole continuum of high-price equilibria, in which no consumer finds it worthwhile to search. However a priori we rule out these equilibria, for the following two reasons. Firstly these equilibria are Paretodominated, because they generate zero surplus for both consumers and the retailer. Secondly if the firm has to pay a small fixed cost, it would not enter the industry if it expected to play one of these equilibria. A simple forward induction argument (see below for a formal discussion) therefore suggests that when a retailer enters, consumers should infer they are not playing one of these no-search equilibria. This leaves us with search-equilibria, whose existence was proved in Proposition 2. Henceforth when we talk about ‘equilibrium’, we are referring to one in which consumers search. However, there is no reason why the model should have a unique equilibrium. Intuitively, suppose that we have already found one equilibrium price vector p0 . If consumers suddenly expect a different price vector p00 , the pool of searchers changes. As such the firm’s optimization problem also changes, and in principle its new optimal price vector could be p00 , in which case p00 is also an equilibrium. Fortunately if multiple equilibria exist, there is a natural way to select amongst them. In particular consider two equilibrium price vectors p0 and p00 , and suppose for a moment that p00j < p0j for each j = 1, . . . , n (the relevance of this supposition will become clear shortly). Consumers are clearly better off if the ‘lower’ equilibrium p00 is played, and surprisingly so too is the firm. Intuitively this is because prices are already too high from the firm’s perspective. More formally if 13 the p0 equilibrium is played, the firm’s total profit is ! b Z n n X X 0 max vj − p0j , 0 ≥ s dvi (pi − c) × f (vi ) Pr i=1 p0i (4) j=1 When consumers expect the p00 equilibrium they search if Pn 00 , 0 ≥ s, max v − p j j j=1 and then buy product i provided that it gives positive surplus. Therefore if the firm ‘deviates’ and sets its prices equal to p0 rather than to p00 , its total profit equals ! b Z n n X X 0 max vj − p00j , 0 ≥ s dvi (5) (pi − c) × f (vi ) Pr i=1 p0i j=1 which strictly exceeds (4). However when consumers expect the p00 equilibrium, by definition the firm prefers to set prices equal to p00 rather than to p0 . So by revealed preference profits in the lower p00 equilibrium must exceed (5), and therefore also exceed profits in the p0 equilibrium. In fact our model always has a lowest equilibrium. It is simple to prove that, since valuations are drawn from the same distribution, each equilibrium has pe1 = ... = pen . Existence of a lowest equilibrium then follows immediately. However it is possible to relax the assumption of identical distributions, and still have a lowest equilibrium. Suppose for a moment that each vi is drawn independently according to its own (strictly positive, continuous and logconcave) density fi (vi ). At least one equilibrium exists whenever n is sufficiently large, although of course different products will generally have different prices. Nevertheless provided the search cost is sufficiently small, we can prove that one equilibrium is lower than all the others (and therefore is also Pareto dominant). We will select the lowest-price equilibrium. One justification is that this equilibrium is Pareto-dominant, and therefore it is natural that everyone would coordinate on it. A second justification is that the firm might signal its intention to play this equilibrium. In particular, suppose that the firm must pay a cost F to enter the market (or otherwise stay out, and earn zero). Suppose further that F ∈ (Π0 , Π00 ) where Π00 is profit in the lowest equilibrium, and Π0 is the highest profit achievable in any other equilibrium. There is one subgame perfect equilibrium in which the firm 14 enters and gets Π00 − F ; in all other subgame perfect equilibria the firm stays out of the market and gets zero. Therefore in the spirit of forward induction, once the firm enters, consumers should rationalize this as a signal that the firm will play the lowest-price equilibrium. Since Π00 − F > 0 it is in the firm’s interest to enter and send this signal. Numerical simulations also suggest that Π00 − Π0 can be relatively large, so this argument may apply widely. 3.3 Comparative statics We now study how the (lowest) equilibrium price p∗ is affected by changes in the search cost and product range. To do this recall that tj ≡ max (vj − p∗ , 0) is the (equilibrium) expected surplus on good j. Substituting pej = p∗ for j = 1, 2, . . . , n into equation (3) and then rearranging, p∗ satisfies P P n n Pr j=2 tj ≥ s j=1 tj ≥ s − Pr P 1 − F (p∗ ) − (p∗ − c) f (p∗ ) + =0 n t ≥ s Pr j j=2 (6) The final term in equation (6) is the ratio of Diamond consumers to shoppers for a single product. We use Karlin’s (1968) Variation Diminishing Property to prove . P P n n t ≥ s is increasing in s, or t ≥ s Pr in the appendix that Pr j=2 j j=1 j P n equivalently that Pr j=1 tj ≥ s is log-supermodular in s and n. This means that as search becomes costlier, the ratio of Diamond consumers to shoppers increases, and demand for each product becomes less elastic. It is therefore intuitive that: Proposition 4 The equilibrium price (i). increases in the search cost and (ii). decreases in the number of products stocked. According to part (i). of the proposition, a multiproduct retailer charges higher prices when search is more costly.7 This is a very natural result, which is also found in single-product search models such as Anderson and Renault (1999). The usual intuition is that higher search costs deter consumers from looking around for 7 As discussed earlier, we are assuming that the shopping cost is independent of the number of products. However the result would still hold for a general search cost s (n), provided that it did not increase too rapidly in the size of the firm’s product range. 15 a better deal, which gives firms more market power. However the mechanism which drives Proposition 4 is different. In our model, when s increases some consumers stop searching. Importantly, those who stop searching are people with relatively low valuations. Consequently the retailer’s potential customers now have, in some sense, higher average valuations than before. This makes it optimal for the retailer to raise its prices. According to part (ii). of the proposition, a retailer charges lower prices when it has a larger product range. In more detail, suppose that initially n < N i.e. the retailer does not stock all the products which consumers wish to buy. Then suppose that it adds an extra product to its range, which is not available elsewhere. We expect that, ceteris paribus, some new consumers will search because they like the n + 1th product. Intuitively these new searchers must have relatively low valuations for the other n goods, or they would have already been searching. This means that if the firm now reduces p1 (say), demand for product 1 will increase (proportionately) more than it would have before. Equivalently, a larger retailer faces a more elastic demand curve on each product that it stocks; consequently it charges lower prices. As noted in the introduction, empirical evidence suggests that larger retailers do generally have lower prices. One explanation for this might be that they have lower costs - for example due to buyer power or economies of scale. However Proposition 4 says that even after controlling for costs, larger stores should still charge lower prices, because they have more elastic demand. Hoch et al (1995) offer some evidence which is consistent with this. They find that after controlling for demographic factors, stores with higher sales volumes (which they use to proxy store size) have more elastic demand. Along similar lines, Shankar and Krishnamurthi (1996) show that EDLP stores attract consumers who are more sensitive to unadvertised prices; Ellickson and Misra (2008) then demonstrate that the EDLP format is favored by larger retailers. Now consider the relationship between product range and profitability. When the retailer sells n0 products and the equilibrium price is p0 , the profit from any 16 individual product is (p0 − c) × Zb 0 f (vi ) Pr ! n X max (vj − p0 , 0) ≥ s dvi (7) j=1 p0 Now suppose instead that the firm sells n00 > n0 products, and that the corresponding equilibrium price is p00 < p0 . Consumers expect prices to be p00 and therefore search on that basis. However once inside the store, they will buy any product which they value more than its price. Therefore if the firm ‘deviates’ and charges p0 , it earns (p0 − c) × Zb 00 f (vi ) Pr p0 n X ! max (vj − p00 , 0) ≥ s dvi (8) j=1 on each product. Clearly this strictly exceeds (7). However by definition, when consumers expect p00 the retailer’s optimal response is to charge p00 . Therefore by revealed preference, when n = n00 the profit earned on each product must exceed (8) and therefore also exceed (7). Equivalently, the model predicts that a larger retailer earns more profit on each product that it sells. Intuitively even though it charges lower prices, it is also searched by more consumers and therefore makes higher sales. Since equilibrium prices exceed pm , selling more units at a lower price is good for profits. On the other hand smaller retailers are ‘trapped’ into charging high prices and earning relatively low profits. This may help explain why firms co-locate near to each other, for example in shopping malls and highstreets. In particular we could interpret the multiproduct monopolist as a cluster of n single-product firms, each of which sells a different and unrelated product. Dudey (1990) and others have already shown that sellers of similar or identical products may cluster together. This commits the firms to fiercer competition, which then encourages more consumers to search, and ultimately increases the profits of each firm in the cluster. However our model suggests a stronger result: even single-product firms that sell completely unrelated goods, can also commit to charging lower prices (and therefore earn higher profits) by clustering together. This is despite the absence of any competition between firms in the cluster. 17 4 Advertising We now consider the case where the retailer has decided to advertise one of its products. Without loss of generality suppose that the firm advertises the price of product n, and denote it by pan . The timing is as follows. Firstly the firm decides on pan and sends the advert. The retailer then chooses its other prices p1 , ..., pn−1 , but cannot communicate these to consumers.8 Secondly consumers receive the advert, and form price expectations (pe1 , ..., pen ). Notice that pen = pan because advertising is (by assumption) truthful. Consumers then decide whether or not to search, and make their purchases. Our first task is to understand how the retailer’s choice of pan , affects the prices which it charges for its other products. Clearly consumers still search if and only P if nj=1 max vj − pej , 0 ≥ s, therefore demand for any unadvertised product i < n remains Di (pi ; pe ) = Zb f (vi ) Pr pi n X j=1 ! max vj − pej , 0 ≥ s vi dvi (1) Since the retailer again wants to maxpi (pi − c) Di (pi ; pe ), the equilibrium price of any product i < n satisfies ! Di (pi = pei ; pe ) − (pei − c) f (pei ) Pr X max vj − pej , 0 ≥ s =0 (2) j6=i Consequently we again infer that when n is sufficiently large, there exists a rational expectations equilibrium with search. Unadvertised prices still weakly exceed pm , because the firm attracts consumers with predominantly high valuations. Moreover fixing a particular pan there is no guarantee that the equilibrium price vector is 8 We could instead assume that the firm chooses unadvertised prices at the same time as (or even before) it chooses pan . We would then need to specify consumers’ beliefs in more detail. In particular consumers would now expect a particular pan to be played, and would have associated beliefs about (p1 , ..., pn−1 ); consumers would also have off-equilibrium beliefs about (p1 , ..., pn−1 ), in case the firm advertised a price that was different from what they expected. Clearly the equilibrium price vector pe1 , ..., pen−1 , pan which we identify in the main text, would still be an equilibrium. However freedom in how to choose off-path beliefs, would generate additional equilibria as well. Nevertheless In and Wright (2012) argue that a natural way to deal with this multiplicity, would be to reorder the timing of the game as we have chosen to do here. 18 unique. However there again exists a lowest-price equilibrium. Consumers clearly prefer playing this equilibrium. However the retailer’s preferences are more subtle. On the one hand, profits from unadvertised goods are maximized by playing the lowest-price equilibrium. On the other hand, playing this equilibrium also maximizes sales of the advertised product, and this is bad for profits if pan − c < 0. Nevertheless we can show that total profits are highest in the lowest-price equilibrium, if either (i). the search cost is small, or (ii). pan −c is not too negative. Under these conditions we have a Pareto dominant equilibrium, and we therefore select it. Lemma 5 The equilibrium price of products (1, ..., n − 1) is an increasing function of the advertised price pan . This result is explained as follows. Firstly note that when pan ≤ a−s all consumers find it worthwhile to search. There is no hold-up problem, and the retailer charges p1 = ... = pn−1 = pm . Secondly note that when pan > a − s not everybody searches, and unadvertised prices strictly exceed pm . A small increase in pan will ceteris paribus cause fewer consumers to search. Moreover those who stop searching, are people with predominantly low product valuations. Therefore the composition of the pool of searchers is now different. In particular the retailer now attracts consumers who on average have higher valuations. Consequently it has more incentive to hold them up by charging higher prices. Consumers anticipate this, and therefore expect a positive relationship between advertised and unadvertised prices. Notice that consumer heterogeneity is crucial for this result. If instead consumers all had the same valuation v̄ for an unadvertised good (as is effectively the case in Lal and Matutes 1994 and Ellison 2005), the retailer would charge v̄ for it, irrespective of what it charged for its advertised product. Lemma 5 shows how a low advertised price on one product, ‘signals’ a retailer’s intention to charge relatively low prices on other products. This happens even though products are completely independent, and there is no private information about production costs. Accordingly, consumers should use store flyers to update their beliefs about a retailer’s overall price level. Consistent with this, Brown (1969) surveyed consumers, and found that they associated low-price advertising with a low 19 general price level. Cox and Cox (1990) constructed some supermarket circulars; they too found that consumers associate reduced price specials with low overall store prices. More broadly, Alba et al (1994) show that a flyer’s composition can affect consumer perceptions about a retailer’s overall offering. Our next task is to understand how the retailer optimally chooses its advertised price. Demand for the advertised product itself is Dn (pan ; pe ) = Zb f (vn ) Pr n−1 X ! max vj − pej , 0 + vn − pan ≥ s dvn (9) j=1 pa n A small reduction in pan affects demand for the product in two ways. Firstly some marginal consumers who would have searched anyway, now buy the product. Secondly some above-marginal consumers who would not have searched, now find it worthwhile to visit the retailer and buy this product precisely because they know its price is lower. Comparing with equation (1), only the first of these effects is present when the product is not advertised. Therefore demand becomes more elastic, when a product’s price is advertised. Kaul and Wittink (1995) argue on the basis of previous empirical studies that this is true, and call it an ‘empirical generalization’. Chintagunta et al (2003) similarly find that price sensitivity rises for promoted items. Proposition 6 The optimal advertised price is strictly below pm . Proof. Let Πj (pan ; pe ) be the equilibrium profit earned on good j. Differentiating P total profit nj=1 Πj (pan ; pe ) with respect to pan and using the envelope theorem, we get a first order condition: dΠn (pan ; pe ) dpan n−1 X + i=1 + n−1 X i=1 (pei − c) Zb f (vi ) n−1 X ∂ Pr P ∂pek k=1 pei ! X tj = 0 (pei − c) −f (pei + s) Pr j6=i n j=1 tj ∂pei + ∂pan ≥ s ∂pe k dvi a ∂pn Zb ∂ Pr f (vi ) pei P n j=1 tj ∂pan ≥s dvi = 0 (10) 20 We claim that the first term in (10) is negative when pan ≥ pm . To prove this, first note that for any i = 1, . . . n − 1, ∂Πn /∂pei < 0 and ∂pei /∂pan > 0. Then, to prove Pn−1 that ∂Πn /∂pan < 0, define T = j=1 max vj − pej , 0 and note that Z s Z ∞ a a a [1 − F (pn )] dµ (y) (11) [1 − F (pn + s − z)] dµ (z) + Πn = (pn − c) s 0 where µ is a measure over T with mass at zero. Since f (p) is logconcave, it is straightforward to prove that (p − c) [1 − F (p + s − z)] is (weakly) decreasing in p whenever p ≥ pm . Therefore dΠn /dpan < 0 as claimed. Since the remaining terms in (10) are also negative, (10) cannot hold for any pan weakly above pm . Therefore profit must be maximized at some pan < pm . The firm chooses pan to maximize profits across the whole of its product range. There are three different forces which lead the firm to choose pan < pm . Firstly the search cost deters consumers from visiting the retailer. This reduces demand for the advertised good, and (as explained above) also makes it more price-elastic. Therefore even if the firm cared only about profits from good n, it would optimally choose some pan < pm . Secondly the search cost also depresses demand for unadvertised products. A low pan encourages more consumers who like good n to search; once inside the store, these extra consumers also buy some of the (high-margin) unadvertised goods.9 Thirdly, recall that unadvertised prices are high because of the hold-up problem. The retailer would be better off, if it could convince consumers that its unadvertised prices were lower. According to Lemma 5, a low pan helps it to somewhat achieve this goal, and build a ‘low price image’. The retailer therefore uses a low advertised price (below pm ) to attract consumers into the store, and then charges them a high price (above pm ) on its remaining products. Depending upon parameters it may even set its advertised price below marginal cost, i.e. engage in loss-leader pricing. A similar pattern of low advertised but high unadvertised prices, also arises in other models such as those by Hess and Gerstner (1987) and Lal and Matutes (1994). However there are several differences with our analysis. Firstly in our model consumer valuations are heterogeneous, 9 Ailawadi et al (2006) offer some empirical evidence in favor of this second channel. Using data for a U.S. drug store, they show that a promotion in one category leads to higher sales in other categories. 21 whereas these other papers assume them to be homogeneous. Secondly therefore, unadvertised prices are in some sense lower in our model. More precisely, in our model consumer surplus from the unadvertised products is strictly positive; however in the other papers, unadvertised prices are so high that consumers are left with zero surplus. Thirdly, our paper offers an additional explanation for low advertised prices, namely the desire to build a store-wide low price image (the third force, in the previous paragraph). This is absent from the other papers. 4.1 When should the retailer advertise? The retailer must decide whether or not to pay the cost κ and send out an advert. When it does not advertise, it plays the equilibrium in Section 3 and charges a price vector (pu , ..., pu ) where pu > pm . When it does advertise, it chooses pan < pu , and therefore by revealed preference earns higher gross profits. Consequently the retailer has an incentive to advertise whenever the cost κ is not too high.10 Of more interest, is the question of how a retailer’s product range affects its advertising strategy. For example fixing κ, is a firm with a broader product range more likely to advertise? How does the optimal advertised price vary with the number of products stocked? It turns out that neither question has a clear-cut answer. Figures 2 and 3 show by example that the optimal advertised price and the gains from advertising, are both non-monotonic in the size of the firm’s product range. Intuitively advertising ‘works’ because (i). it commits the retailer to charging lower prices, and (ii). it increases store traffic, which leads to sales of unrelated products. Now on the one hand, larger n means that consumers who search, end up buying more products. This suggests that the retailer should try harder to boost store traffic i.e. advertising is more desirable, as is a lower advertised price. On the other hand, larger n also means that even in the absence of advertising, more consumers would search anyway (and unadvertised prices would be lower). This suggests that 10 Notice that the retailer’s decision of whether to advertise, and at what price, is deterministic. This contrasts with Bester’s (1994) model, in which a single-product monopolist can choose how many consumers receive its advert. He shows that the retailer might then randomize over both its price and advertising reach. 22 Optimal pan 0.87 0.86 0.85 0.84 0.83 5 10 15 20 n Figure 2: Non-monotonicity of the optimal advertised price. Advertising Gains 0.06 0.05 0.04 0.03 0.02 0.01 0.00 5 10 15 Figure 3: Non-monotonicity of the gains from advertising 23 20 n the retailer has less need to further boost store traffic i.e. advertising is less desirable, as is a lower advertised price. This tension causes the non-monotonicity in Figures 2 and 3. We can also say something more precise about the advertising strategy of a large retailer. We can prove that for any > 0 there exists an n̄ such that for all n > n̄, (i). the gains from advertising are less than , and (ii). the optimal advertised price exceeds pm − . Intuitively when the firm’s product range is large, most consumers search anyway, so advertising is of limited value. The model therefore predicts that a large retailer should follow an ‘everyday low-price’ (EDLP) strategy: it should charge low prices, but either eschew advertising completely, or else barely offer any discount on its advertised product. The model also predicts that a smaller retailer is more likely to follow a ‘Hi-Lo’ strategy: it should charge generally high prices, but advertise a very low price on one product (or more generally on a few products - see below). Empirical evidence largely supports these predictions. For example Ellickson and Misra (2008) find that larger US grocery stores, are more likely to report being an everyday low-pricer. Shankar and Krishnamurthi (1996) also find that people who shop at EDLP stores, are more responsive to regular (i.e. nonpromotional) price changes; this is again consistent with our model. On the other hand Shankar and Bolton (2004) show that after controlling for whether a store is EDLP or HiLo, larger stores are more likely to price-promote. However this result is difficult to interpret, because according to our model store size and pricing strategy are highly correlated. Finally drawing together some earlier results, our model predicts that advertising is associated with low prices: Remark 7 When a retailer chooses to advertise, it charges strictly lower prices on every product. Proof. Without advertising the firm charges some pu > pm on every product. With advertising it chooses some pan < pu (c.f. Proposition 6), and therefore by Lemma 5 unadvertised prices are less than pu as well. 24 In his survey article Bagwell (2007) says there is “substantial evidence” that advertising leads to lower prices. For example Devine and Marion (1979) publicized the prices of some randomly selected grocery products in local newspapers; retailers responded by reducing their prices on those products. However our model makes a stronger prediction: even non-advertised prices should be lower. To the best of our knowledge, almost no empirical work tests this prediction. Indeed Bagwell says that “the effect of advertising on the prices of advertised and non-advertised products warrants greater attention”. One exception is Milyo and Waldfogel (1999), which looks at the lifting of a ban on alcohol advertising in Rhode Island. They find that some stores began advertising, and that their other unadvertised prices fell but not by a statistically significant amount (Table 5, page 1091). However the authors note that during their sample period, relatively few stores advertised (in newspapers), and that the long-run impact of advertising could be different. A comment on multiple advertised prices Suppose the retailer can now advertise up to k of its prices, each at a cost of κ > 0. For example, advertising more products requires a longer (and therefore more expensive) flyer or TV commercial, but consumers only have time to inspect k products. To make the model tractable, we focus only the case of a very small search cost. Consider the equilibrium price of unadvertised product i. We can show that as s → 0, pei → p̄ei ≥ pm where 1 (p̄ei − c) f (p̄ei ) Q = e 1 − F (p̄i ) 1 − j6=i F pej (12) Moreover a small increase in pan (whilst fixing any other advertised prices) leads the retailer to charge more on each of its unadvertised products. Optimal advertised prices are also below pm , for the reasons given earlier. In addition, if κ were arbitrarily small the retailer would choose to advertise as many prices as it could, because it would then have more control over them. However fixing κ, we can show that a very large firm would not find it worthwhile to advertise even one price. Therefore again firms with very large product selections find an EDLP strategy to be optimal; small retailers are more likely to follow a HiLo strategy and advertise several low prices, but also have higher prices on their remaining unadvertised goods. 25 5 Competition We now suppose there are two retailers A and B, each of whom sells the same n products. In the spirit of Varian (1980), we divide consumers into two groups. A fraction γ of consumers are ‘loyals’. They have a strong affinity towards one (randomly selected) retailer, and make any purchases there. The remaining fraction 1−γ of consumers are ‘non-loyals’. They have no preference for where they purchase their goods, and are able to multi-stop shop. All consumers must pay a cost s > 0 in order to search one retailer. Non-loyal consumers may then visit the other retailer, by paying an additional s. As explained below, we have in mind a situation where s is not too large, such that some non-loyal consumers do end up multistop shopping. We also make the standard assumption that non-loyals have passive beliefs, and we allow them to go back and purchase from a previously-searched retailer, by paying a small cost. The timing is now as follows. Firstly retailers simultaneously decide whether or not to pay κ and send out an advertisement. Conditional on sending an advert, the retailer picks one product to advertise and chooses its price. Secondly adverts and their contents are observed by all agents. Retailers then set unadvertised prices, whilst consumers form (rational) expectations about those prices. Consumers then search and make purchases. We believe this timing is appropriate because in practice retailers usually decide their promotions in advance; other prices are chosen later and are made conditional on any promotional activity (see for example Chintagunta et al 2003). As we demonstrate below, there is a close connection with the previous monopoly analysis. To this end we introduce the following notation. We let pu be the price that a non-advertising monopolist charges, and let π u be the corresponding profit. For simplicity we assume π u > 0 for all n ≥ 2. If a monopolist advertises one product at price q, we let φ (q) be the price it charges on each of the remaining n − 1 products, and let π (q) be the total profit it earns. Recall from earlier that φ (q) is increasing and that by definition pu = φ (pu ). 26 5.1 Two-product case We first solve for equilibrium when the retailers sell two products. Lemma 8 At the second stage of the game, there exists an equilibrium where (i). if a firm does not advertise, it charges pu on both products and (ii). if a firm advertises a price q < pm on one good, it charges φ (q) on the other. As usual if a firm chooses not to advertise, there exist equilibria in which consumers expect it to charge very high prices and therefore do not search it. Excluding this possibility, Lemma 8 gives the unique pure strategy equilibrium. Interestingly unadvertised prices are the same under both monopoly and duopoly. This is reminiscent of Diamond (1971) - the difference being that our result holds in a multiproduct context, and allows for one of the products to be advertised.11 The intuition for why the prices in the lemma constitute an equilibrium, is as follows. Firstly suppose that neither firm has advertised. If consumers expect both P firms to charge pu , they search if and only if 2j=1 max (vj − pu , 0) ≥ s: loyals go to their favorite store, whilst non-loyals choose one at random. Therefore in terms of the joint distribution over (v1 , v2 ), consumers who search a duopolist look exactly the same as those who search a monopolist. Hence (by definition) neither firm can do better than charge pu . Secondly suppose that both firms have advertised the same product. Suppose also that consumers expect a firm with advertised price q, to charge φ (q) on its other product. Since φ (q) is increasing, one firm is then expected to be weakly cheaper on both products. Therefore all non-loyals who search, will go to that retailer. It is again easy to see that, in terms of the joint distribution over (v1 , v2 ), each firm attracts the same mix of consumers as it would if it were a monopolist. Hence it cannot do better than charge φ (q) on its unadvertised good, as consumers were expecting. A similar logic can be used to understand 11 To simplify the exposition, the lemma only deals with the case in which advertised prices are below pm . Our approach is to look for first-stage equilibria in which this is true, and then verify that no firm wishes to deviate by advertising a price that exceeds pm . It turns out that sometimes, such a deviation induces firms to charge unadvertised prices which differ from those given in the lemma. Further details are provided in the appendix. 27 equilibrium pricing when only one of the two retailers has chosen to advertise. Third and finally, suppose that the retailers have advertised different products. If a firm with advertised price q < pm charges unadvertised price φ (q), there exists a search cost s sufficiently small, such that non-loyal consumers ‘cherry-pick’ each retailer’s advertised product. This implies that in the putative equilibrium, a firm only sells its unadvertised product to loyal consumers. Conditional on this it is clear that charging φ (q) on the unadvertised product is optimal. However since some nonloyal consumers visit both retailers, a firm could sell its unadvertised good to some of them, if it reduces the price by a sufficiently large amount. Nevertheless such a deviation is not profitable whenever the fraction of loyals γ is sufficiently large. Thus charging φ (q) on the unadvertised good is indeed an equilibrium. We are now in a position to analyze the first stage of the game. We first note that under certain conditions, there can exist equilibria in which only one retailer chooses to advertise. However empirically, Ellickson and Misra (2008) find that competing retailers tend to coordinate on their broad advertising strategy, as measured by their choice between EDLP and HiLo pricing. For this reason we focus attention on equilibria in which retailers advertise with the same (positive) probability. Our first result is a negative one. It is not an equilibrium for retailers to advertise the same product. To gain some intuition, suppose to the contrary that both firms advertise product 1 with probability one. It follows from Lemma 8 that whichever firm has the lowest advertised price, captures all non-loyal consumers. Consequently the first-stage of the game does not have a pure strategy equilibrium. Instead each firm should draw its advertised price from an interval p, p using an atomless distribution function, where c < p̄ < pm whenever the search cost is relatively small. The expected profit from following this strategy is γπ (p) /2, because a firm with advertised price p sells only to loyal consumers. However a firm can do even better than this, by deviating and advertising product 2. For example, suppose firm A advertises product 2 at a price p̄. According to Lemma 8 it will then charge φ (p̄) for product 1. Therefore after deviating, firm A can (i). still earn γπ (p) /2 from its loyal consumers, but (ii). now has the lowest price for product 2, and so can earn 28 additional profit by selling it to non-loyals. Consequently it is not an equilibrium for the two retailers to advertise the same product. Alternatively retailers might try to differentiate themselves by advertising different products. For example A could advertise good 1 and B could advertise good 2. Unfortunately this is also unlikely to be an equilibrium. To see this, let paA1 , paB2 < pm be the two advertised prices. When s is sufficiently small, non-loyal consumers can cherry-pick from each store, and therefore retailer A earns γ π (paA1 ) + (1 − γ) (paA1 − c) [1 − F (paA1 + s)] − κ 2 (13) Let p∗ be the price which maximizes (13), and which therefore also maximizes B’s analogous profit function. Notice that c < p∗ < pm whenever the search cost is relatively small. Then consider the following deviation: suppose that A advertises product 2 at a price just below p∗ . We know from Lemma 8 that A will charge φ (p∗ ) on product 1 and will undercut its rival. Compared to advertising p∗ on product 1, A will therefore (i). earn the same profit on its loyal customers, but (ii). will sell two products to non-loyals instead of just one. This deviation is therefore profitable, so long as the search cost is not too large. We cannot usually have an equilibrium in which retailers deliberately advertise different goods, because it is too easy for one of them to deviate and steal demand from the other. We now turn to our main result: Proposition 9 For any α ∈ [0, 1) there exists an advertising cost κ such that (i). With probability α, a retailer does not advertise. It charges pu on all products. (ii). With probability 1 − α, a retailer sends out an advert, containing the price of one randomly chosen product. This advertised price q is strictly below pm and drawn from a distribution. The firm charges φ (q) on its other product. In this equilibrium each retailer randomly chooses which product to advertise. Once one firm randomizes in this way, the other cannot do better than follow the same strategy. Firms also randomize over their advertised price. This is necessary because with positive probability the two firms advertise the same product, in which case all non-loyal consumers buy from whomever has the lowest advertised price. 29 Randomization prevents a rival firm from undercutting and stealing these non-loyal consumers. This intuition is familiar from single-product models such as Varian (1980). However our multiproduct framework also provides some new insights. Firstly, it offers a simple explanation for price dispersion, especially dispersion of unadvertised prices. As discussed in the introduction, existing models that differentiate between advertised and unadvertised prices, predict no dispersion of unadvertised prices. However in our model, such dispersion arises very naturally. In particular, for the same reasons as in the monopoly model, there is correlation between a firm’s advertised and unadvertised prices. Since a retailer must randomize over its advertised price, this generates indirect dispersion even in prices which it does not advertise. Second and related, our model predicts an aggregate price distribution which has both a mass point and multiple gaps. According to Proposition 9 products have a ‘regular price’ pu , and stay at that level for a fraction α of the time. Retailers then randomly hold a promotion, during which time they mark down the price of one product by a random amount; the discount on this product exceeds pu − pm and can therefore be relatively large. At the same time, retailers also reduce their other prices by a smaller yet still discrete amount. Hence within the same framework, we have both high regular prices, as well as the coexistence of small (unadvertised) and large (advertised) price discounts. Consistent with Proposition 9, Pesendorfer (2002) and Hosken and Reiffen (2004) document that grocery products have a regular price, and stay at that price for long periods of time; deviations from this regular price are generally downward, and potentially of sizeable magnitude. Klenow and Malin (2010) also stress the prevalence of small price changes, across a wide range of studies. There is also some support for our prediction that retailers randomly choose which product to promote. Rao et al (1995) conclude that promotions on ketchup and detergent are independent across competitors, as are the promotional prices themselves. Lloyd et al (2009) have data on UK supermarket prices, and find that over a two and a half year period, roughly two-thirds of the products in their sample experience a sale. This suggests that sales are applied across a wide range of products, and is consistent our intuition that rivals 30 should find it hard to predict which products a retailer is going to promote. Finally, an additional feature of our model is that some consumers multistop shop, and end up cherry-picking advertised specials from each retailer. Fox and Hoch (2005) document significant heterogeneity in household cherry-picking behavior. Using a rather strict definition, they find that 8% of shopping trips involve cherry-picking, and that cherry-pickers buy significantly more advertised and discounted products.12 5.2 Many-product case We again begin by solving for unadvertised prices in the second stage of the game. Lemma 8 can be straightforwardly generalized, except when the firms have advertised the same product. In particular we can prove the following. (1). If neither firm has advertised, it is an equilibrium for both to charge pu on all products. (2). If both firms have advertised the same product, it is an equilibrium for a firm with advertised price q to charge φ (q) on its remaining n − 1 products. (3). If only one firm advertised: it is an equilibrium for the retailer with advertised price q to charge φ (q) on its remaining products, and for the non-advertising firm to charge pu on all products. Although we have not been able to prove that these equilibria are unique, nor have we been able to construct alternative equilibria. The remaining scenario to consider is (4). where the retailers have advertised different products. Unlike in the n = 2 analysis, we expect that now some non-loyal consumers will buy a product which neither firm has promoted. As a result the retailers face quite different demand curves compared to when n = 2, and so equilibrium unadvertised prices might be quite different. We therefore simplify the problem, by assuming that if non-loyal consumers search, they first visit the retailer with the lowest advertised price (and can then pay s and visit the other firm, if they wish).13 We are then able 12 Earlier we mentioned the empirical paper by Milyo and Waldfogel (1999). They find that when one firm advertises, a non-advertising firm does not change its prices. This is consistent with Proposition 9. 13 There are equilibria which do not require this additional assumption. For example when n is sufficiently large, there exists a continuum of equilibria in which the two retailers price-match on the n − 2 products which neither of them has advertised. However we think these equilibria are less natural than the one given in Lemma 10. Further details are available upon request. 31 to prove: Lemma 10 Suppose the firms have advertised prices pl and ph ∈ [pl , pm ) on different products. There exists an equilibrium in which (i). firm h charges φ (ph ) on all its products, (ii). firm l charges between pm and φ (ph ) on its unadvertised products, and (iii). if non-loyal consumers multistop shop and are indifferent about where to buy a good, they buy it at store l. Non-loyal consumers usually buy most products at the first store they visit. They may then travel to the other retailer and cherry-pick its advertised special. Hence this second retailer understands that it can only sell its unadvertised products to loyal consumers, and therefore it acts like a monopolist when choosing the prices of those products. We are now in a position to characterize first-stage behavior. As a preliminary step, we investigate conditions under which no advertising occurs. Notice that if neither firm advertises during the first stage, we are in scenario (1). At the second stage both firms charge pu on all products and earn a profit of π u /2 each. If one firm deviates during the first stage and advertises, we are in scenario (3). Clearly the best deviation would be to advertise the same price as would a monopolist, namely the solution to equation (10) from earlier. Denote this optimal advertised price by q ∗ < pm . At the second stage the deviant captures all non-loyal consumers, and earns a total profit of (1 − γ/2) π (q ∗ ) − κ. Hence there is a first-stage equilibrium in which neither retailer advertises, provided that 1 1−γ (π (q ∗ ) − π u ) + π (q ∗ ) ≤ κ 2 2 (14) An interesting question is how product assortment affects this condition. Recall that when a monopolist chooses to advertise, its profits increase by π (q ∗ ) − π u . Since this is very small when n is large, we concluded that a monopolist with a large product range is unlikely to advertise. The intuition is that when a retailer faces little or no competition, it draws its customers from a fixed pool. When its product range is large, most consumers search anyway and advertising is not very effective. However it is clear from (14) that under duopoly there is a countervailing effect, 32 because π (q ∗ ) increases in n. Intuitively with duopoly, a firm’s pool of consumers is not fixed. In particular by advertising a low price, a firm is able to steal nonloyal consumers from its rival. Since the profit earned on these extra consumers is increasing in n, so are the incentives to advertise. Our model therefore suggests that the degree of competition, as proxied by the fraction of non-loyal consumers, is also crucial for determining whether a retailer uses an EDLP or a HiLo pricing strategy. Now consider equilibria in which advertising occurs with positive probability. We can again show that, in general, it is not possible to have an equilibrium where firms either advertise the same product, or where they deliberately advertise different products. The explanation is very close to the one we gave for the two-product case, and so for brevity is omitted. Moreover Remark 11 There exists an equilibrium which is qualitatively the same as that in Proposition 9. Retailers randomly choose whether to advertise, which product to advertise, and what price to advertise. With some probability, a retailer again decides not to advertise, and charges a regular price pu on each product. With complementary probability it offers a (potentially large) discount on one advertised product, and also offers smaller discounts on its other products. Note that the regular price pu , is exactly what a non-advertising monopolist would charge. Therefore according to Proposition 4 from earlier on, a larger retailer has a lower regular price. In addition this suggests that, at least for very large competing retailers, their regular price will already be close to pm , such that the discounts they offer on unadvertised goods will typically be quite small. The main role of advertising is therefore to try and attract customers away from the rival firm. 6 6.1 Extensions Substitutes Thus far we have assumed that a retailer sells n independent products. However in practice, some of a firm’s products might be substitutes for one another. For 33 example a grocery store might stock several different types of milk and detergent. Although a consumer’s demand for milk and detergent may be roughly independent, her demand for two different detergents would not be. The aim of this section is to show that many of our earlier results, generalize to this sort of environment. In particular we extend our main model as follows. The retailer now stocks n independent product categories, each of which contains z substitute products. Consumers wish to buy at most one product from each category. We let vi,j denote a typical consumer’s valuation for product i in category j; each vi,j is drawn independently, using the same distribution function F (vi,j ). We also assume that all products within a given category have the same price.14 Notice that we can interpret n as measuring the breadth and z as measuring the depth, of the retailer’s product selection. Given our assumptions, a consumer who buys from category j gets a gross surplus of max {v1,j , ..., vz,j }. This surplus has distribution function G (v; z) ≡ F z (v) and corresponding logconcave density function g (v; z) ≡ zF z−1 (v) f (v). Without search costs, the firm would charge a monopoly price pm (z) = arg max (p − c) [1 − G (p; z)], and this can be shown to monotonically increase in z. Notice that in general, the retailer will behave as if it sells n independent products, whose valuations are drawn from G (v; z). Therefore all of our earlier analysis can be straightforwardly applied. In particular firstly, a search-equilibrium fails to exist if the retailer stocks only one category of products.15 Secondly however, such an equilibrium does exist, if the retailer offers products in a sufficiently large number of categories. Thirdly, unadvertised prices exceed pm (z), increase in the search cost, but decrease in n i.e. in 14 Shankar and Bolton (2004) and Draganska and Jain (2006) note that in practice, differentiated versions of a product or brand often have the same price. 15 This holds in a much more general setting, in which the retailer stocks one category, and valuations (v1,1 , ..., vz,1 ) are drawn from an arbitrary distribution. This is because if consumers expect prices pe1,1 , ..., pez,1 the firm can always charge pi,1 = pei,1 + s on each product; consumers who search will buy precisely the product they intended to, but at a higher price. Consumers again anticipate this hold-up problem, expect pei,1 ≥ max vi,1 − s and therefore do not search. Notice that since we place no restrictions on the distribution of valuations, this nests for example the case where v1,1 =, ..., = vz,1 i.e. perfect substitutes. 34 the breadth of the product range. Moreover fourthly, when the firm offers discounts on one product category, it optimally reacts by charging less on other, unrelated, product categories.16 Thus our main insights are robust to having substitute products. We can also gain some new insights, into the relationship between price and product depth. To do this we focus on the limiting case s → 0, and also assume that the density f (v) is either increasing or not decreasing too rapidly. We can then prove existence of a threshold n̂, such that a search-equilibrium exists if and only if n > n̂. Moreover: Proposition 12 There exists a critical product breadth ñ such that (i). if n ∈ (n̂, ñ) the equilibrium price is U-shaped in product depth, and (ii). if n > ñ the equilibrium price is strictly increasing in product depth. Intuitively an increase in z has two opposing effects. Firstly at the level of an individual category, it improves a consumer’s match value. This is a force towards higher prices, since the retailer can take advantage of this. Secondly however, because category-level matches are better, ceteris paribus more consumers will search. By the usual intuition these additional searchers have relatively low valuations, and this is a force towards lower prices. Proposition 12 demonstrates that this second effect dominates when n and z are small, whilst the first effect dominates otherwise. Therefore our model offers two predictions concerning the relationship between product range and prices. Firstly, retailers with a broad product range should have low prices. Consistent with this, Leibtag et al (2010) have UPC-level data on grocery prices, for both traditional retailers such as supermarkets and drugstores, and also 16 Unfortunately it is unclear what would happen to prices, if the firm advertised only one product in one category. This stems from the fact that even if n = 1 and there is no search cost, the prices of individual products are not always positively related. Nevertheless, somewhat in the spirit of our earlier results, Konishi and Sandfort (2002) show in a related model with substitute products, that a firm might advertise a low price on one product, hoping that after searching, consumers will buy a more expensive substitute instead. We also note that there are several other interesting issues which we do not pursue here, including limited availability of advertised products (Rosato 2013), and obfuscation of some substitute products (Petrikaitė 2013). 35 for non-traditional outlets such as supercenters. The latter usually stock a broader range of products, and also have significantly lower prices. Secondly, our model suggests that medium-sized retailers which offer little within-category variety, might also have low prices. Consistent with this, Cleeren et al (2010) report that so-called hard discounters stock only a limited selection of products, but also offer significantly lower prices as compared with traditional retailers. 6.2 Downward-sloping demands The search literature often assumes that a retailer sells only one product, but that each consumer wishes to buy multiple units of it, i.e. consumers have a downwardsloping demand. This differs from but is clearly related to our assumption, that consumers have a unit-demand for multiple products. We believe that our modelling choice is more appropriate in many retail contexts. However to show how our results fit into the wider search literature, we now allow for downward-sloping demands. As a first step consider the following alternative model, which is a monopoly version of Stiglitz (1979). There is a single retailer who sells one product. Consumers are identical, and faced with a price p, wish to buy 1 − F (p) units of the product. If consumers were informed about price, the retailer would charge pm = arg max (p − c) [1 − F (p)]. Now suppose that the price can only be learnt by paying a search cost s > 0. Stiglitz shows that provided s is not too large, there exists an equilibrium in which all consumers search and the firm charges pm . Intuitively consumers all search, because they anticipate earning positive surplus on inframarginal units. The firm then faces the same demand as it would if s = 0, and so charges pm as expected. Proposition 2 of our model is clearly related. We show that a search-equilibrium exists in a multiproduct world, because surplus on one product attracts consumers who are marginal for another. The difference is that in our model, consumers are heterogeneous. Indeed if this were not the case, the retailer would be able to extract all surplus, and a search-equilibrium would fail to exist. As explained earlier, consumer heterogeneity has at least two important implications. Firstly, prices in our model (almost always) strictly exceed pm . Secondly, equilibrium prices respond to changes in s (and also product range and advertising 36 strategy) in a way that is both intuitive and economically interesting. This does not happen in Stiglitz’s model - consumers are homogeneous, and equilibrium price always equals pm . To illustrate this point further, we now depart from Stiglitz’s approach, and allow for heterogeneous downward-sloping demands. To do this as simply as possible, we model consumer heterogeneity using a single parameter θ which is drawn from θ, θ using a strictly positive density function g (θ). A consumer’s demand for any one product is p = θ + P (q) where q is the quantity consumed and P (q) is continuously differentiable, strictly decreasing and concave. Consequently consumers with higher θ both earn higher surplus and have less elastic demands. When there is no search cost and types are not too different, the firm sells to everybody and charges the standard monopoly price pm , which is now defined as Z θ m p = argmax g (θ) (x − c) P −1 (x − θ) dθ x (15) θ Henceforth assume that there is a search cost, that the retailer sells n ≥ 1 products, and that (for simplicity) their prices are unadvertised. The nature of equilibrium depends on two thresholds sn and sn which satisfy 0 < sn < sn . Firstly when s ≤ sn there is an equilibrium where each good is priced at pm . Since the search cost is relatively small, every consumer finds it worthwhile to search. The firm then faces the same problem as it does when s = 0, and consequently charges pm . This is qualitatively the same as in Stiglitz. Intuitively, a relatively small amount of heterogeneity does not prevent the firm from standard monopoly pricing. Secondly however when s > sn , such an equilibrium is no longer possible. This is because even if consumers expect to pay pm on each product, those with low θ cannot earn enough surplus to make search worthwhile. Since the firm is only searched by consumers with relatively high θ, the firm has an incentive to charge strictly more than pm . Proposition 13 When s ∈ (sn , sn ) there exists an equilibrium in which some consumers search and the price strictly exceeds pm . The firm charges (i). more when search is costlier, but (ii) less when its product range is larger. Once we introduce heterogeneity, we get results which differ from Stiglitz, but which are essentially the same as those from our earlier unit-demand model. The intuition 37 is by now familiar. Consumers are heterogeneous, and only high-types find it worthwhile to search. The retailer therefore exploits this by charging prices which exceed pm . However a reduction in the search cost or an expansion of the product range, induces new lower-type consumers to search. The retailer’s demand becomes more elastic, and so it charges lower prices. This again highlights the important role which consumer heterogeneity plays in our results. (For completeness, when s ≥ sn the search cost is too high to support a search-equilibrium.) 6.3 Alternative retailing strategies Thus far we have assumed that firms use simple pricing and advertising strategies. We now discuss whether a monopolist should use alternative strategies. A retailer could choose to bundle its products. To maintain tractability, we ask whether or not it should use pure bundling. Note that when a firm bundles its P products in this way, it effectively sells one good whose valuation is nj=1 vj ; this means that if consumers anticipate bundling, they will not search. Now suppose that the retailer is expected not to bundle. Consumers believe that prices will be the same as they were in Sections 3 and 4, and therefore search provided that Pn e , 0 ≥ s. After consumers have sunk the search cost, the firm has max v − p j j j=1 two options. Firstly it could set pi = pei on each product as expected. But secondly it could deviate and use bundling, in which case it would choose the bundle price pb to max (pb − nc) Pr pb n X j=1 ! n X v j ≥ pb max vj − pej , 0 ≥ s (16) j=1 We can show that this deviation is not profitable whenever average valuations are relatively low, and the number of products stocked is relatively high. Intuitively under these conditions the retailer would not sell many units of the bundle, unless it set pb very low. However in that case it would do better to just sell the products separately, as consumers were expecting. A firm might also charge consumers a fee τ ≥ 0 to enter its store and browse its products. In this case it is convenient to split the search cost into two parts: a cost s̃ ∈ (0, s) of physically travelling to the store, and a further cost s − s̃ of going inside 38 and learning prices. The timing of the game is then as follows. Firstly consumers form an expectation of the entry fee τ e and of the price pe of each product. They then decide whether or not to travel to the store. Secondly if a consumer goes to the store, she learns the actual entry fee τ . At this point she can update her belief about the price, which we denote by p̃e . She then decides whether or not to pay τ and go inside the store. Thirdly after entering the store, a consumer observes actual prices and makes her purchases. Remark 14 There exists an equilibrium in which the retailer sets an entry fee τ (= τ e ) ≥ 0, and charges pe on each product where pe solves Zb f (vi ) Pr pe n X j=1 ! max (vj − pe , 0) ≥ s + τ e vi dvi ! − (pe − c) f (pe ) Pr X max (vj − pe , 0) ≥ s + τ e = 0 (17) j6=i Proof. Consider the following strategy on the part of consumers. (a). Travel to P the retailer if and only if nj=1 max (vj − pe , 0) ≥ s + τ e . (b). After travelling to the retailer, if τ ≤ τ e then set p̃e = pe , otherwise expect price to be some p̃e which P satisfies nj=1 max (b − p̃e , 0) ≤ s − s̃ + τ . (c). Then enter the store if expected surplus exceeds s − s̃ + τ . Given this strategy, the retailer (weakly) prefers to set τ = τ e . Demand for any product is exactly the same as in equation (1) except that s is replaced by s + τ e . Equation (17) then follows. The pricing condition (17) is the same as equation (2) except that s is replaced by s + τ e . Intuitively this is because the entry fee acts like an extra search cost. There is always an equilibrium where τ e = 0; however typically there exist other equilibria with τ e > 0 as well. Nevertheless in practice, a retailer who imposes a positive entry fee would find it hard to prevent consumers from reselling its products. This arbitrage problem suggests that in practice, τ e = 0 is the natural outcome. Finally, we have focused on price advertising. However an alternative promotional strategy is to send consumers a coupon, which gives them a small discount τ 0 < s off their shopping bill. This coupon acts like a negative entry fee, so the equilibrium price would solve equation (17) but with τ e replaced by −τ 0 . Applying 39 Proposition 4 from earlier, prices are decreasing in the size of the coupon. Therefore in theory, coupons provide an alternative way to commit to lower prices. However again in practice, coupons might be subject to an arbitrage problem. Our intuition is that if the arbitrage problem could be solved, smaller retailers would be more likely to use coupons compared to large retailers. However it is unclear (and not possible to show analytically) whether or not coupons would dominate price advertising. 7 Conclusion Consumers are often poorly-informed about prices, and must spend time and effort in order to learn them. Our paper has sought to understand how this affects a multiproduct retailer’s pricing and advertising strategy. We showed that consumers can use cues, such as product range and information contained within adverts, to form an impression about a retailer’s overall price image. This price image then influences consumer search, and ultimately also purchase behavior. We noted that retailers with broader product ranges, generally charge lower prices. Our model provides a novel explanation for this phenomenon, that is unrelated to production costs or store differentiation. In particular, we showed that these firms charge less, because they are searched by consumers who are endogenously more price-sensitive. However we also proved that product depth has an ambiguous impact on prices. As such, our model suggests that prices are lowest at stores which sell a wide range of products, but which offer relatively little choice within individual product categories. We also demonstrated that the breadth of a retailer’s product range, determines how it chooses to position itself. In particular, it influences whether a firm chooses an ‘every day low pricing’ strategy or whether it uses more of a HiLo pricing strategy. We showed that when a monopolist has a broader product range, it is more likely to eschew advertising. To the extent that it does advertise, it offers little or no discount on any of its products. We also demonstrated that this result could change in a competitive market, but only if the number of non-captive consumers was large enough. Usually a retailer can only inform consumers about a small number of its prices. 40 Nevertheless, we showed that price-advertising can still be informative. In contrast to much previous work, we demonstrated that if a firm advertises a low price on one product, this induces consumers to rationally anticipate somewhat lower prices on other products as well. Competing firms try to prevent their rival from secondguessing their advertising strategy. This leads them to randomize over whether to hold a promotion, which product to promote, and what price to charge for it. Therefore an interesting feature of our model, is that it generates equilibrium price dispersion, even for products which no firm is advertising. This again contrasts with lots of previous work, which finds that unadvertised prices should be non-dispersed. We believe that our paper demonstrates some of the advantages that can be gained, by explicitly modelling the multiproduct nature of a retailer’s offering. We also hope that it will encourage more research on this topic, both empirical and theoretical. On the empirical side, our model generates a number of testable predictions. One implication, is that advertising should lead to a reduction even in the prices of unadvertised products. However as discussed earlier, there is currently little empirical research on this topic. We hope that our paper will generate renewed empirical interest, in understanding how pricing and advertising on one product category, affects other unrelated categories. On the theoretical side, we think that our paper opens up several avenues for future research. It would be interesting, for example, to endogenize retailers’ product selections, and investigate under what conditions they choose to compete head-to-head. It would also be interesting to allow repeated interaction between firms and consumers. We plan to think more about these and other related issues, in future work. 41 References [1] Ailawadi, K., Harlam, B., César, J. and Trounce, D. (2006): ‘Promotion Profitability for a Retailer: The Role of Promotion, Brand, Category, and Store Characteristics’, Journal of Marketing Research 43(4), 518-535. [2] Alba, J., Broniarczyk, S., Shimp, T. and Urbany, J. (1994): ‘The Influence of Prior Beliefs, Frequency Cues, and Magnitude Cues on Consumers’ Perceptions of Comparative Price Data’, Journal of Consumer Research 21(2), 219-35. [3] Ambrus, A. and Weinstein, J. (2008): ‘Price dispersion and loss leaders’, Theoretical Economics 3, 525-537. [4] Anderson, S. and Renault, R. (1999): ‘Pricing, Product Diversity, and Search Costs: A Bertrand-Chamberlin-Diamond Model’, The RAND Journal of Economics 30(4), 719-735. [5] Anderson, S. and Renault, R. (2006): ‘Advertising Content’, American Economic Review 96(1), 93–113. [6] Asplund, M. and Friberg, R. (2002): ‘Food Prices and Market Structure in Sweden’, The Scandinavian Journal of Economics 104(4), 547-566. [7] Bagnoli, M. and Bergstrom, T. (2005): ‘Log-concave probability and its applications’, Economic Theory 26(2), 445-469. [8] Bagwell, K. (2007): ‘The Economic Analysis of Advertising’, in Mark Armstrong and Rob Porter (eds.), Handbook of Industrial Organization, Vol. 3, North-Holland: Amsterdam 1701-1844. [9] Baye, M. and Morgan, J. (2001): ‘Information Gatekeepers on the Internet and the Competitiveness of Homogeneous Product Markets’, The American Economic Review 91(3), 454-474. [10] Bester, H. (1994): ‘Random advertising and monopolistic price dispersion’, Journal of Economics & Management Strategy 3(3), 545-559. 42 [11] Bliss, C. (1988): ‘A Theory of Retail Pricing’, The Journal of Industrial Economics 36(4), 375-391. [12] Brown, F. (1969): ‘Price Image versus Price Reality’, Journal of Marketing Research 6(2), 185-191. [13] Burdett, K. and Judd, K. (1983): ‘Equilibrium Price Dispersion’, Econometrica 51(4), 955-969. [14] Chen, Z. and Rey, P. (2012): ‘Competitive Cross-Subsidization’. [15] Chintagunta, P., Dubé, J-P. and Singh, V. (2003): ‘Balancing Profitability and Customer Welfare in a Supermarket Chain’, Quantitative Marketing and Economics 1(1), 111-147. [16] Cleeren, K., Verboven, F., Dekimpe, M. and Gielens, K. (2010): ‘Intra- and Interformat Competition Among Discounters and Supermarkets’, Marketing Science 29(3), 456-473. [17] Competition Commission (2008): ‘The supply of groceries in the UK market investigation’. [18] Cox, A. and Cox, D. (1990): ‘Competing on Price: The Role of Retail Price Advertisements in Shaping Store-Price Image’, Journal of Retailing 66(4), 428445. [19] Dasgupta, P. and Maskin, E. (1986): ‘The Existence of Equilibrium in Discontinuous Economic Games, I: Theory’, Review of Economic Studies 53(1), 1-26. [20] DeGraba, P. (2006): ‘The loss leader is a turkey: Targeted discounts from multi-product competitors’, International Journal of Industrial Organization 24(3), 613-628. [21] Devine, G. and Marion, B. (1979): ‘The influence of consumer price information on retail pricing and consumer behavior’, American Journal of Agricultural Economics 61(2), 228-237. 43 [22] Diamond, P. (1971): ‘A Model of Price Adjustment’, Journal of Economic Theory 3, 156-168. [23] Draganska, M. and Jain, D. (2006): ‘Consumer Preferences and Product-Line Pricing Strategies: An Empirical Analysis’, Marketing Science 25(2), 164-174. [24] Dudey, M. (1990): ‘Competition by Choice: The Effect of Consumer Search on Firm Location Decisions’, American Economic Review 80(5), 1092-1104. [25] Ellickson, P. and Misra, S. (2008): ‘Supermarket Pricing Strategies’, Marketing Science 27(5), 811-828. [26] Ellison, G. (2005): ‘A Model of Add-On Pricing’, The Quarterly Journal of Economics 120(2), 585-637. [27] Fox, E. and Hoch, S. (2005): ‘Cherry-picking’, Journal of Marketing 69, 46-62. [28] Hess, J. and Gerstner, E. (1987): ‘Loss leader pricing and rain check policy’, Marketing Science 6(4), 358-374. [29] Hoch, S., Kim, B-D. , Montgomery, A. and Rossi, P. (1995): ‘Determinants of Store-Level Price Elasticity’, Journal of Marketing Research 32(1), 17-29. [30] Hoeffding, W. (1963): ‘Probability Inequalities for Sums of Bounded Random Variables’, Journal of the American Statistical Association 58(301), 13-30. [31] Hosken, D. and Reiffen, D. (2004): ‘Patterns of Retail Price Variation’, RAND Journal of Economics 35(1), 128-146. [32] Hosken, D. and Reiffen, D. (2007): ‘Pricing Behavior of Multiproduct Retailers’, The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics 7(1). [33] In, Y. and Wright, J. (2012): ‘Signaling Private Choices’. [34] Karlin, S. (1968), Total Positivity, Stanford University Press. [35] Kaufman, P., MacDonald, J., Lutz, S. and Smallwood, D. (1997): ‘Do the Poor Pay More for Food? Item Selection and Price Differences Affect Low-Income Household Food Costs’, Agricultural Economics Report No. 759. 44 [36] Kaul, A. and Wittink, D. (1995): ‘Empirical Generalizations About the Impact of Advertising on Price Sensitivity and Price’, Marketing Science 14(3), G151G160. [37] Klenow, P. and Malin, B. (2010): ‘Microeconomic Evidence on Price-setting’. [38] Konishi, H. and Sandfort, M. (2002): ‘Expanding demand through price advertisement’, International Journal of Industrial Organization 20, 965-994. [39] Lal, R. and Matutes, C. (1994): ‘Retail Pricing and Advertising Strategies’, The Journal of Business 67(3), 345-370. [40] Lal, R. and Rao, R. (1997):‘Supermarket Competition: The Case of Every Day Low Pricing’, Marketing Science 16(1), 60-80. [41] Leibtag, E., Barker, C. and Dutko, P. (2010): ‘How Much Lower Are Prices at Discount Stores?’. [42] Lloyd, T., Morgan, C., McCorriston, S. and Zgovu, E. (2009): ‘Do Sales Matter? An Exploration of Price Discounting in UK Food Retailing’. [43] McAfee, P. (1995): ‘Multiproduct Equilibrium Price Dispersion’, Journal of Economic Theory 67(1), 83-105. [44] Milyo, J. and Waldfogel, J. (1999): ‘The Effect of Price Advertising on Prices: Evidence in the Wake of 4 Liquormart’, The American Economic Review 89(5), 1081-1096. [45] Monroe, K. and Lee, A. (1999): ‘Remembering Versus Knowing: Issues in Buyers’ Processing of Price Information’, Journal of the Academy of Marketing Science 27, 207-225. [46] Narasimhan, C. (1988): ‘Competitive Promotional Strategies’, The Journal of Business 61(4), 427-449. [47] Pesendorfer, M. (2002): ‘Retail sales: A study of pricing behavior in supermarkets’, Journal of Business 75(1), 33-66. 45 [48] Petrikaitė, V. (2013): ‘Consumer Obfuscation by a Multiproduct Firm’. [49] Rao, R., Arjunji, R. and Murthi, B. (1995): ‘Game Theory and Empirical Generalizations concerning Competitive Promotions’, Marketing Science 14(3), G89-G100. [50] Robert, J. and Stahl, D. (1993): ‘Informative Price Advertising in a Sequential Search Model’, Econometrica 61(3), 657-686. [51] Rosato, A. (2013): ‘Selling Substitute Goods to Loss-Averse Consumers: Limited Availability, Bargains and Rip-offs’. [52] Shankar, V. and Bolton, R. (2004): ‘An Empirical Analysis of Determinants of Retailer Pricing Strategy’, Marketing Science 23(1), 2004. [53] Shankar, V. and Krishnamurthi, L. (1996): ‘Relating price sensitivity to retailer promotional variables and pricing policy: an empirical analysis’, Journal of Retailing 72(3), 249–272. [54] Shelegia, S. (2012): ‘Multiproduct Pricing In Oligopoly’, International Journal of Industrial Organization 30(2), 231–242. [55] Simester, D. (1995): ‘Signalling Price Image Using Advertised Prices’, Marketing Science 14(2), 166-188. [56] Stahl, D. (1989): ‘Oligopolistic Pricing with Sequential Consumer Search’, The American Economic Review 79(4), 700-712. [57] Stiglitz, J. (1979): ‘Equilibrium in Product Markets with Imperfect Information’, The American Economic Review 69(2) Papers and Proceedings, 339-345. [58] Varian, H. (1980): ‘A Model of Sales’, The American Economic Review 70(4), 651-659. [59] Villas-Boas, M. (2009): ‘Product Variety and Endogenous Pricing with Evaluation Costs’, Management Science 55(8), 1338-1346. 46 [60] Wernerfelt, B. (1994): ‘Selling Formats for Search Goods’, Marketing Science 13(3), 298-309. [61] Zhou, J. (2012): ‘Multiproduct Search’. 47 A A.1 Main Proofs Useful lemmas Lemma 15 If pei is an equilibrium price, then 1 − F (p) − (p − c) f (p) is weakly decreasing in p for all p ∈ [pm , pei ). Proof. We prove the contrapositive of this statement. Suppose that 1 − F (p) − (p − c) f (p) is not weakly decreasing in p for all p ∈ [pm , pei ). Step 1. Note that for all p > c, the derivative of 1−F (p)−(p − c) f (p) is proportional to −2/ (p − c) − f 0 (p) /f (p), which is strictly increasing in p for all p > c. This follows because f (p) is logconcave and therefore f 0 (p) /f (p) decreases in p. Step 2. Since by assumption 1−F (p)−(p − c) f (p) is not weakly decreasing in p for every p ∈ [pm , pei ), there will exist a p̄ ∈ [pm , pei ) such that −2/ (p̄ − c)−f 0 (p̄) /f (p̄) > 0. Step 1 then implies that −2/ (p − c) − f 0 (p) /f (p) > 0 for all p ∈ [p̄, pei ). Step 3. When pi < pei the derivative of (21) with respect to pi is [−2f (pi ) − (pi − c) f 0 (pi )] Pr (T ≥ s) (18) Step 2 implies that (18) is strictly positive for every pi ∈ [p̄, pei ). However by definition (21) is zero when pi = pei , so (21) is strictly negative for every pi ∈ [p̄, pei ). Given the definition of (21), this means that (pi − c) Di (pi ; pe ) is strictly decreasing in pi for every pi ∈ [p̄, pei ) - so the firm would do better to charge some pi ∈ [p̄, pei ) rather than charge pei . This implies that pei cannot be an equilibrium price. Lemma 16 (pi − c) Di (pi ; pe ) is quasiconcave in pi if either: 1. 1 − F (p) − (p − c) f (p) is strictly decreasing in p for all p ∈ [a, b]. Densities which do not decrease too rapidly - such as the uniform - satisfy this. 2. Pr (T ≥ s) > 1/2, where T = P j6=i max vj − pej , 0 as defined earlier. Proof. We must show that (pi − c) Di (pi ; pe ) strictly increases in pi when pi ∈ [a, pei ), and strictly decreases in pi when pi ∈ (pei , b]. Equivalently we must check that (21) is strictly positive when pi ∈ [a, pei ) and strictly negative when pi ∈ (pei , b]. 48 Condition 1. Rewrite (21) as Di (pi ; pe ) − (pi − c) f (pi ) Pr (T ≥ s) + (pi − c) f (pi ) [Pr (T ≥ s) − Pr (T + max (pi − pei , 0) ≥ s)] (19) The derivative of the first term with respect to pi is −f (pi ) Pr (T + max (pi − pei , 0) ≥ s) − [f (pi ) + (pi − c) f 0 (pi )] Pr (T ≥ s) ≤ Pr (T ≥ s) [−2f (pi ) − (pi − c) f 0 (pi )] which is strictly negative because 1 − F (p) − (p − c) f (p) is strictly decreasing in p by assumption.17 Since by definition the first term in (19) is zero when pi = pei , it must be strictly positive when pi ∈ [a, pei ) and strictly negative when pi ∈ (pei , b]. The second term of (19) is 0 when pi ≤ pei , and negative otherwise. Therefore (21) is strictly positive when pi ∈ [a, pei ) and strictly negative when pi ∈ (pei , b], as required. Condition 2. Note that (19) is proportional to: Di (pi ; pe ) − (pi − c) Pr (T ≥ s) +(pi − c) [Pr (T ≥ s) − Pr (T + max (pi − pei , 0) ≥ s)] f (pi ) (20) The second term is again 0 when pi ≤ pei , and negative otherwise. The derivative of the first term with respect to pi is − Pr (T + max (pi − pei , 0) ≥ s)−Pr (T ≥ s)− Di (pi ; pe ) f 0 (pi ) Di (pi ; pe ) < −1+ ≤0 1 − F (pi ) f (pi )2 where the first inequality follows because Pr (T ≥ s) > 1/2 (by assumption), and because vi has an increasing hazard rate and this implies that −f 0 (pi ) /f (pi )2 ≤ 1/ [1 − F (pi )]. The second inequality follows because Di (pi ; pe ) ≤ 1 − F (pi ). Using the same arguments as for Condition 1, the fact that the first term of (20) is strictly decreasing in pi , means that (21) is strictly positive when pi ∈ [a, pei ) and strictly negative when pi ∈ [a, pei ). Lemma 17 In a search-equilibrium all unadvertised prices are the same. 17 Note that the first term is differentiable everywhere except at the point pi = pei + s (assuming pei + s < b), because Di (pi ; pe ) kinks at that point. However this does not affect the argument that the first term of (19) is strictly decreasing in pi . 49 Proof. Suppose to the contrary that there exists an equilibrium where two different goods g and h have prices satisfying peg < peh . Applying Lemma 15 1 − F (peh ) − peh f (peh ) is (weakly) less than 1 − F peg − peg f peg , which is itself negative since (as P P proved in the text) peg > pm . Clearly also Pr t ≥ s > Pr t ≥ s . j j j6=h j6=g Therefore equation (3) cannot hold for both i = g and i = h - a contradiction. A.2 Proofs for Section 3 (no advertising) Proof of Lemma 1. Differentiate (pi − c) Di (pi ; pe ) with respect to pi to get Di (pi ; pe ) − (pi − c) f (pi ) Pr (T + max (pi − pei , 0) ≥ s) where T = (21) e , 0 . Substitute pi = pei and set (21) to zero. Lemma 16 max v − p j j j6=i P (above) provides sufficient conditions under which (pi − c) Di (pi ; pe ) is quasiconcave in pi . Proof of Proposition 2. Let p̃ be the unique solution to 1−F (p)−pf (p) /2 = 0, P n and ñ be the smallest n such that Pr j=2 max (vj − p̃, 0) ≥ s > 1/2. According to Lemma 17 (above) we must look for a symmetric equilibrium in which pej = pe ∀j. Using equation (2) pe satisfies ! Di (pi = pe ; pe ) − (pe − c) f (pe ) Pr X max (vj − pe , 0) ≥ s =0 (22) j6=i The lefthand side of (22) is strictly positive when evaluated at pe = pm , be P e cause Di (pi = pe ; pe ) > [1 − F (pe )] Pr max (v − p , 0) ≥ s and 1−F (pm )− j j6=i (pm − c) f (pm ) = 0. Assuming n ≥ ñ, the lefthand side of (22) is strictly negative when evaluated at pe = p̃, because Di (pi = pe ; pe ) ≤ 1 − F (pe ) and 1 − F (p̃) − p̃f (p̃) /2 = 0. Therefore since the lefthand side is continuous in pe , there exists (at least one) pe ∈ (pm , p̃) which solves (22). According to Lemma 16 the profit on each P n e good is quasiconcave because Pr max (v − p , 0) ≥ s > 1/2. j j=2 Proof of Proposition 4. Equation (6) is copied here for convenience P n Pr t ≥ s j j=1 P −1=0 φ (p∗ ; s, n) = 1 − F (p∗ ) − (p∗ − c) f (p∗ ) + n Pr t ≥ s j=2 j where tj ≡ max (vj − p∗ , 0). Firstly fix n and decrease s from s0 to s1 < s0 . Let p∗s0 denote the lowest solution to φ (p∗ ; s0 , n) = 0. Lemma 18 (below) shows that 50 φ (p∗ ; s, n) increases in s, so we conclude that φ p∗s0 ; s1 , n ≤ 0. Since φ (pm ; s1 , n) > 0 and φ (p∗ ; s1 , n) is continuous in p∗ , this implies that when s = s1 the lowest equilibrium price is (weakly) below p∗s0 . So the lowest equilibrium price increases in s. Secondly fix s and increase n from n0 to n1 . Let p∗n0 be the lowest solution to φ (p∗ ; s, n0 ). Lemma 19 (below) shows that φ (p∗ ; s, n) decreases in n, so we conclude that φ p∗n0 ; s, n1 ≤ 0. This again implies that when n = n1 , the lowest equilibrium price is (weakly) below p∗n0 , so the lowest equilibrium price falls in n. Lemma 18 φ (p∗ ; s, n) increases in s. Define ṽj = vj − p∗ , and note that ṽj has a logconcave h i density function f˜ (ṽj ) defined on the interval ã, b̃ where ã = a − p∗ and b̃ = b − p∗ . Proof of Lemma 18. Recall that the ṽj are iid and that tj ≡ max (ṽj , 0). . P P n n ∗ Pr Define Ω (s, n) = Pr j=2 tj ≥ s . φ (p ; s, n) increases in s if j=1 tj ≥ s and only if Ω (s, n) increases in s. We now prove that Ω (s, n) increases in s. Begin with n = 2 Consider Pr (t1 + t2 ≥ x) for some x > 0. If ṽ1 ≥ x then t1 + t2 ≥ x since t2 ≥ 0; if ṽ1 ∈ (0, x) then t1 + t2 ≥ x if and only if t2 = ṽ2 ≥ x − ṽ1 ; if ṽ1 ≤ 0 then t1 + t2 ≥ x if and only if t2 = ṽ2 ≥ x. Therefore Rx Pr (ṽ1 ≤ 0) Pr (ṽ2 ≥ x) + 0 f˜ (z) Pr (ṽ2 ≥ x − z) dz + Pr (ṽ1 ≥ x) Pr (t1 + t2 ≥ x) = (23) Pr (t2 ≥ x) Pr (ṽ2 ≥ x) Z x Pr (ṽ2 ≥ x − z) = Pr (ṽ1 ≤ 0) + f˜ (z) dz + 1 Pr (ṽ2 ≥ x) 0 which increases in x. This is because ṽ2 is logconcave and so has an increasing hazard rate, which means that Pr (ṽ2 ≥ x − z) / Pr (ṽ2 ≥ x) increases in x. Now proceed by induction We show that if Ω (w, n − 1) increases in w, then Ω (s, n) increases in s. To prove this, let k > 1 and write: P P P n n n Pr t ≥ s Pr t ≥ s − k Pr t ≥ s j=1 j j=2 j j=1 j P −k = P Ω (s, n) − k = n n Pr Pr j=2 tj ≥ s j=2 tj ≥ s (24) Then using the same principles used to derive equation (23), expand only the top of 51 equation (24) to get P n−1 ≥ s − k Pr t ≥ s j j=2 P Ω (s, n) − k = Pr (ṽn ≤ 0) n Pr j=2 tj ≥ s h i R b̃ Rs Pn−1 Pn−1 ˜ f˜ (z) [1 − k] dz f (z) Pr t ≥ s − z − k Pr t ≥ s − z dz + j j j=1 j=2 s 0 + Pn Pr j=2 tj ≥ s Pr P n−1 j=1 tj (25) Since t1 and tn are iid, the first term in (25) simplifies to Pr (ṽn ≤ 0) [1 − k/Ω (s, n − 1)], which is weakly increasing in s because of the inductive assumption that Ω (w, n − 1) increases in w. The second term in (25) is proportional to " ! !# Z b̃ Z s n−1 n−1 X X ˜ f˜ (z) [1 − k] dz dz + f (z) Pr tj ≥ s − z − k Pr tj ≥ s − z 0 j=1 s j=2 Using the change of variables y = s − z, this can be rewritten as " ! !# Z 0 Z s n−1 n−1 X X f˜ (s − y) [1 − k] dy + f˜ (s − y) Pr tj ≥ y − k Pr tj ≥ y dy s−b̃ 0 j=1 j=2 and then written more compactly as Z ∞ 10≤s−y≤b̃ f˜ (s − y) Γ (y) dy (26) −∞ where 10≤s−y≤b̃ is an indicator function taking value 1 when 0 ≤ s − y ≤ b̃, and 0 otherwise; and where 1−k if y ≤ 0 P P Γ (y) = n−1 n−1 Pr if y > 0 j=2 tj ≥ y j=1 tj ≥ y − k Pr P n−1 Now let S be an interval in R++ such that Pr t ≥ s > 0∀s ∈ S, and j=1 j choose s0 , s1 ∈ S where s1 > s0 . Also choose a constant k0 such that (26) is zero when evaluated at s = s0 and k = k0 . (Zero terms being discarded) Γ (y) has one sign-change from negative to positive: this follows directly from the definition of k0 (> 1) and the inductive assumption that Ω (w, n − 1) increases in w. Using the definition in Karlin (1968) §1.1, 10≤s−y≤b̃ is totally positive of order 2 (T P2 ) in (s, y). Since f˜ (z) is logconcave, f˜ (s − y) is also T P2 in (s, y). Therefore 10≤s−y≤b̃ f˜ (s − y) is also T P2 in (s, y). 52 Applying Karlin’s Variation Diminishing Property (Karlin §1.3, Theorem 3.1), (26) changes sign once in s (and from negative to positive) when it is evaluated at k = k0 . Since by assumption (26) is zero when evaluated at s = s0 and k = k0 , it is positive when evaluated at s = s1 and k = k0 . Therefore returning to equation (25) it follows that Ω (s1 , n) − k0 ≥ Ω (s0 , n) − k0 , or equivalently that Ω (s, n) increases in s. In summary we have shown that if Ω (w, n − 1) increases in w, then Ω (s, n) increases in s. Since Ω (w, n) increases in w for n = 2, Ω (s, n) increases in s for any integer-valued n. Lemma 19 φ (p∗ ; s, n) decreases in n. Proof of Lemma 19. φ (p∗ ; s, n) decreases in n if and only if Ω (s, n) decreases in n. To show that Ω (s, n) decreases in n, write out Ω (s, n) as P P Rs n−1 n−1 t ≥ s t ≥ s − ṽ dṽ + Pr (ṽ ≤ 0) Pr Pr (ṽn ≥ s) + 0 f˜ (ṽn ) Pr j j n n n j=1 j=1 P P Rs n−1 n−1 t ≥ s t ≥ s − ṽ dṽ + Pr (ṽ ≤ 0) Pr Pr (ṽn ≥ s) + 0 f˜ (ṽn ) Pr j j n n n j=2 j=2 This is less than Ω (s, n − 1) because Pr P n−1 j=1 tj ≥x . Pr P n−1 j=2 tj ≥ x exceeds 1 and (from Lemma 18) is increasing in x. Therefore we know that Ω (s, n) ≤ Ω (s, n − 1) for any n, or alternatively Ω (s, n) decreases in n. A.3 Proof of Lemma 5 (effect of advertising on unadvertised prices) Proof. Let p0 be the equilibrium unadvertised price. Let tj = max (vj − p0 , 0) for j < n, and tn = max (vn − pan , 0). Then using equation (6) again, p0 satisfies P n−1 Pr t + t ≥ s n j=1 j P −1=0 Φ (p0 ; pan ) = 1 − F (p0 ) − (p0 − c) f (p0 ) + n−1 Pr j=2 tj + tn ≥ s We focus on the smallest p0 which solves Φ (p0 ; pan ) = 0. Note that Φ (p0 ; pan ) is continuous in p0 , and that Φ (pm ; pan ) ≥ 0. Therefore as with comparative statP . P n n ics in s and n, if Pr Pr increases in pan , the lowj=1 tj ≥ s j=2 tj ≥ s est p0 (that solves Φ (p0 ; pan ) = 0) also increases in pan . To prove that ω (pan ) = 53 Pr P n j=1 tj ≥s . Pr P n j=2 tj ω (pan ) − k = Pr ≥ s increases in pan , write: P P n ≥ s − k Pr t ≥ s j=2 j P n Pr j=2 tj ≥ s n j=1 tj (27) Just as in the proof of Lemma 18, the numerator of (27) can be rewritten as " ! !# Z pan n−1 n−1 X X f (vn ) Pr tj ≥ s − k Pr tj ≥ s dvn a j=1 Z pa n +s " f (vn ) Pr + pa n j=2 n−1 X ! tj ≥ s + pan − vn n−1 X − k Pr j=1 !# tj ≥ s + pan − vn dvn j=2 Z b f (vn ) [1 − k] dvn (28) + pa n +s Using the change of variables y = pan − z (28) can be written as Z ∞ 1a≤pan −y≤b f (pan − y) γ (y) dy (29) −∞ 1−k if P P n−1 n−1 where γ (y) = if Pr j=2 tj ≥ s + y j=1 tj ≥ s + y − k Pr Pr Pn−1 t ≥ s − k Pr Pn−1 t ≥ s if j=2 j j=1 j a and 1a≤pan −y≤b is again an indicator function that is T P2 in (pn , y). y ≤ −s y ∈ (−s, 0) y≥0 Now choose a,1 a,0 a,1 pa,0 n , pn ∈ [a − s, b] such that pn < pn . Also define k0 such that (29) is zero when evaluated at pan = pa,0 n and k = k0 . (Zero terms being discarded) γ (y) is piecewise continuous and changes sign once from negative to positive: this follows from the P . P n−1 n−1 definition of k0 (> 1), and because Pr t ≥ x Pr t ≥ x increases j j j=2 j=1 in x (from Lemma 18). Karlin’s variation diminishing property says that (29) is a,0 single-crossing from negative to positive in pan . Therefore ω (pa,1 n ) − k0 ≥ ω (pn ) − k0 , or equivalently ω (pan ) increases in pan as required. A.4 Proof of Proposition 9 (competition) Proof. First modify the timing of the game as follows. Stage 1: firms randomly choose a product to advertise and pick an advertised price. Stage 2: Nature decides whether a firm can advertise or not (advertising happens with probability 1 − α, and is chosen independently for the two firms). If a firm advertises, the advert contains 54 the price chosen at stage 1. If a firm does not advertise, the price from stage 1 is abandoned and never observed by anybody else. Stage 3: adverts are observed by all parties, unadvertised prices are chosen, then search and purchase decisions taken. We first prove that advertised prices in Stage 1 are chosen using a mixed strategy. We then prove that during Stage 2, a firm is indifferent about advertising and therefore happy to (let Nature) randomize. Suppose the two retailers have chosen advertised prices qA and qB where qA , qB < pm . Suppose also that during Stage 2 Nature decides that firm i can advertise. Provided s is sufficiently small to permit multistop shopping, firm i’s profit is γ −κ + + α (1 − γ) π (qi ) + Z + 1−α (1 − γ) π (qi ) if qi < q−i 2 2 y 1−γ Πi (qi , q−i ) −κ + γ2 + α (1 − γ) π (qi ) + Z + 1−α π (qi ) if qi = q−i 2 2 −κ + γ + α (1 − γ) π (q ) + Z if q > q i 2 i −i (30) where Z= 1−α (1 − γ) (qi − c) [1 − F (qi + s)] 2 (31) Equation (30) follows directly from Lemma 8. Firstly i earns π (qi ) on its loyal consumers, who have mass γ/2. Secondly i also earns π (qi ) on non-loyal consumers, in the event that rival firm −i does not advertise. Thirdly, the Z term arises when the retailers advertise different products, which happens with probability (1 − α) /2. In this case non-loyal consumers cherry-pick, so firm i sells them its advertised good. Fourthly with probability (1 − α) /2 the two firms advertise the same product. Nonloyal consumers are all captured by the firm with the lowest advertised price, or shared if advertised prices are tied. Suppose instead that during Stage 2 Nature decides that firm i cannot advertise. i’s profits are then Πni = γ + α (1 − γ) u π 2 (32) because it charges pu and earns π u on its loyal consumers, and also on half of the non-loyal consumers if the rival −i has also decided not to advertise. During the first stage, retailer i chooses qi to maximize its expected profits αΠni + (1 − α) Πyi . Equivalently since Πni is independent of qi , the retailer chooses qi to maximize Πyi . The latter is discontinuous and so a pure strategy equilibrium 55 does not exist. We now use Dasgupta and Maskin (1986) to prove that qi and q−i are chosen using a mixed strategy. Let q be the solution to π (q) = 0 and for simplicity assume it is unique (this can be easily relaxed). Define each firm’s action space as q, pm . Notice that Πyi (qi , q−i ) is continuous except on a measure-zero subset of the action space, namely where qi = q−i . Moreover whilst individual payoffs are discontinuous, Πyi (qi , q−i ) + Πy−i (qi , q−i ) is continuous and therefore also upper semi-continuous. In addition Πyi (qi , q−i ) is bounded and satisfies lim inf q̃i →qi− Πyi (q̃i , qj ) ≥ Πyi (qi , qj ). This means that Πyi (qi , q−i ) is weakly lower semi-continuous in the sense described by Dasgupta and Maskin (1986). Consequently applying Theorem 5 of their paper, there exists a mixed-strategy Nash equilibrium. Since payoff functions are symmetric, applying Lemma 7 of their paper, there exists a symmetric mixed strategy Nash equilibrium. The lower support of this mixed strategy is above q. This is because if firm i advertises a price qi < q, it must be true that qi < c in which case Πyi (qi , q−i ) < 0. However the firm can earn strictly more than this by not advertising at all. The upper support of this mixed strategy is strictly below pm . Firstly suppose that (30) gives i’s profits for all qi , q−i , not just for qi , q−i < pm . It is straightforward to argue that if qi ≥ pm then (i). each line of (30) is decreasing in qi , and (ii). the first line strictly exceeds the second which strictly exceeds the third. Therefore it is never optimal for i to advertise a price qi ≥ pm since by reducing it his profits must strictly increase. Hence the mixed strategy that we have derived must have firms randomizing over advertised prices which are strictly below pm . Secondly, in fact if firm −i randomizes over prices strictly below pm and firm i deviates to a price above pm , the third line of (30) provides an upper bound on i’s profits. Hence firm i has no incentive to make such a deviation. We now prove that profits are bounded in this way. Suppose firm i advertises a price qi ≥ pm . It is simple to show that if either (1). firm −i does not advertise or (2). both firms advertise the same product, then there is an equilibrium in which firm i charges φ (qi ) on its unadvertised product. (3). Suppose instead that the two firms advertise different products. (i). If qi > φ (q−i ) there is an equilibrium in which each firm charges φ (.) on its unadvertised product, and firm i makes no sales to non-loyals. (ii). If 56 qi < φ (q−i ) − s there is an equilibrium in which non-loyal consumers who multi-stop shop all start by searching firm i, and each firm charges φ (.) on its unadvertised product. (iii). If qi ∈ [φ (q−i ) − s, φ (q−i )] there is an equilibrium in which i charges φ (qi ) on its unadvertised product and sells it only to loyals, and firm −i charges a price on [qi , φ (q−i )) on its unadvertised product. Firm i therefore sells less units of its advertised product to loyals, than it would as given by Z in equation (31). Bringing these three steps together, we conclude that i’s deviation profit is less than the third line of (30), as originally stated. It only remains to check that firms are willing to randomize during Stage 2. This is easily done by noting that for any symmetric mixed strategy equilibrium, conditional on advertising both firms earn the same expected payoff, and that this payoff shifts one-for-one in κ (in other words, κ does not affect the distribution of prices). Therefore for any α and associated mixed strategy equilibrium, we can find a κ such that Πyi (qi , q−i ) = Πni . 57 B B.1 Additional proofs Proof of Lemma 10 (many-product competition) Proof. Let pij be the price charged by firm i on product j, and let peij be consumers’ expectation of it. Also let Tj denote the expected surplus from shopping only at store j, and TAB denote the expected surplus from shopping at both firms. Suppose without loss of generality that A advertises good 1 at a price paA1 , and B advertises good 2 at a price paB2 ∈ [paA1 , pm ). If firm B is expected to charge φ (paB2 ) on its unadvertised products, only loyal consumers will buy them. These loyal consumers search if and only if TB ≥ s. Therefore using our monopoly analysis, it is clear that firm B cannot do better than charge φ (paB2 ) as expected. Now consider firm A’s pricing problem. According to Lemma 10, A is more expensive on product 2 and therefore for sufficiently small s, will sell it only to loyal consumers. Loyals search if and only if TA ≥ s and hence peA2 is determined exactly as in the monopoly model. Retailer A sells its other unadvertised products to both loyal and non-loyal consumers. Demand for a typical product j > 2 is Z b hγ i DAj = f (vj ) Pr (TA ≥ s) + (1 − γ) Pr (max {TA , TAB } ≥ s) dvj 2 pAj (33) whenever pAj ≤ peBj . The derivative of profit with respect to the actual price pAj , evaluated at pAj = peAj , is hγ i DAj |pAj =pe − peAj − c f peAj Pr TA ≥ s|vj = peAj Aj 2 − peAj − c f peAj (1 − γ) Pr max {TA , TAB } ≥ s|vj = peAj (34) There are two possibilities to consider. Firstly equation (34) may be zero for some peAj < peBj . In this case, peAj is the equilibrium price. Secondly (34) may be strictly positive for all peAj < peBj . In this case the equilibrium price is peAj = peBj . This is explained as follows. Some non-loyal consumers multistop shop because they like both advertised products. If firm A charges more than peBj , all these multistop shoppers will immediately buy product j from firm B. Hence a small price increase triggers a discrete drop in demand. We can show that this makes it unprofitable for A to charge more than peBj , whenever the number of products sold is sufficiently 58 large.18 Moreover when s is sufficiently small, it is straightforward to prove that peA2 < φ (paB2 ). B.2 Proof of Proposition 12 (substitute products) We start with some preliminary results. Adapting equation (12) on page 25, the first order condition is 1 − G (pe ; z) − (pe − c) g (pe ; z) 1 − G (pe ; z)n−1 = 0 Using the definition of G (v; z) this can be rewritten as 1 − F (pe )z 1 e e z−1 − (p − c) f (p ) = 0 z(n−1) e e zF (p ) 1 − F (p ) (35) Lemma 20 A search-equilibrium exists if and only if n > n̂, where n̂ solves 1 − z (n̂ − 1) (b − c) f (b) = 0. This equilibrium is unique, and its price decreases in n. Proof. The first part of (35) decreases in pe whenever n ≥ 2, whilst the second part of (35) decreases so long as f (v) is not decreasing too rapidly. Therefore if an equilibrium exists it must be unique. Moreover since the lefthand side of (35) is strictly positive when pe = pm (z), an equilibrium exists if and only the lefthand side of (35) is negative when pe = b. Applying L’hôpital’s rule, the latter holds if and only if 1 − z (n − 1) (b − c) f (b) < 0. Since the lefthand side of (35) is decreasing in n, so must be the equilibrium price. Lemma 21 There exists a rotation point F̄ such that after a small increase in z, the lefthand side of (35) increases if F (pe ) < F̄ and decreases for F (pe ) > F̄ . Moreover this rotation point F̄ is increasing in both n and z, and tending to 1 as either n → ∞ or z → ∞. 18 It is straightforward to show that firm A’s profits on each product j > 2 are quasiconcave, under very similar conditions to the monopoly model. To check that firm A’s profits on product 2 are also quasiconcave, we must verify that the retailer does not wish to set a price pA2 ≤ paB2 + s and prevent non-loyals from travelling on to the rival. This is shown to be true if either (i). the fraction of non-loyals is sufficiently small, or (ii). non-loyals do not check pA2 because they believe they can get the product much more cheaply at the other store. Similarly retailer B’s profits are shown to be quasiconcave if either (i). the fraction of non-loyals is sufficiently small, or (ii). non-loyals who shop there, only check the price of the advertised special which they intend to buy. 59 Proof. Differentiating the lefthand side of (35) gives an expression which for all F (pe ) ∈ (0, 1) is proportional to − −1 + F (pe )z + F (pe )z(n−1) − F (pe )zn −1 + nF (pe )z(n−1) − (n − 1)F (pe )zn ! + z ln F (pe ) (36) Step 1. Note that (36) is strictly positive as F (pe ) → 0, and by L’hôpital’s rule is strictly negative as F (pe ) → 1. We can also prove that (36) strictly decreases in F (pe ). (The algebra is omitted and is available on request.) This immediately implies that (36) is strictly positive for F (pe ) < F̄ and strictly negative for F (pe ) > F̄ . This in turn implies existence of a unique rotation point. Step 2. Since (36) is strictly decreasing in F (pe ), the rotation point F̄ increases in n and z if and only if (36) increases in n and z. This is again easily shown to hold. To prove that limn→∞ F̄ = limz→∞ F̄ = 1 simply take limits of (36) then set each expression to zero and solve for F̄ . Lemma 22 There exists a critical ñ (> n̂) such that the equilibrium price is above F̄ if n < ñ, and below F̄ if n > ñ. Proof. When n = n̂ the equilibrium price equals b whilst the rotation point is strictly below b. Fixing z, as n increases the equilibrium price decreases (Lemma 20) whilst the rotation point increases (Lemma 21). Moreover as n → ∞ the rotation point converges to F̄ = 1 whilst the equilibrium price converges to pm (z) < b. Thus there is a unique ñ such that the equilibrium price p∗ satisfies F (p∗ ) = F̄ . For n 6= ñ the relationship between p∗ and F̄ is as described in the lemma. Proof of Proposition 12. Note that if we substitute F (pe ) = F̄ into equation (35), the resulting expression is decreasing in z. (1). Suppose to begin with n ∈ (n̂, ñ). According to Lemma 22 the equilibrium price exceeds the rotation point, so by Lemma 21 the equilibrium price decreases in z. Since ñ depends positively on z, eventually the equilibrium price p∗ satisfies F (p∗ ) = F̄ . Notice that for higher z, the lefthand side of (35) is negative when evaluated at the rotation point; equivalently, F (p∗ ) < F̄ . Thus by Lemma 21 the equilibrium price now increases monotonically in z. (2). Suppose that to begin with n > ñ. Then a similar argument shows that the equilibrium price increases monotonically in z. 60 B.3 Proofs of Proposition 13 (downward-sloping demand) Define Q (z) ≡ P −1 (z) and note that Q0 , Q00 < 0. Also define Π (p; θ) = (p − c) Q (p − θ), p∗ (θ) = arg maxx (x − c) Q (x − θ), and let CS (pj ; θ) be the consumer surplus of a θ-type on one product when its price is pj . Lemma 23 p∗ (θ) and CS (p∗ (θ) ; θ) are both strictly increasing in θ. Proof. Differentiate (p − c) Q (p − θ) with respect to p to get a first order condition Q (p − θ) + (p − c) Q0 (p − θ) = 0. Then totally differentiate with respect to θ to get ∂p∗ (θ) Q0 (p∗ (θ) − θ) + (p∗ (θ) − c) Q00 (p∗ (θ) − θ) = ∈ (0, 1) ∂θ 2Q0 (p∗ (θ) − θ) + (p∗ (θ) − c) Q00 (p∗ (θ) − θ) Since ∂p∗ (θ)/ ∂θ ∈ (0, 1) and P 0 < 0 and (by definition) p∗ (θ) = θ + P (q ∗ (θ)), it follows that ∂q ∗ (θ)/ ∂θ > 0. We can write consumer surplus as Z ∗ q ∗ (θ) Z ∗ q ∗ (θ) [pj − p (θ)] dqj = CS (p (θ) ; θ) = [P (qj ) − P (q ∗ (θ))] dqj 0 0 which is strictly increasing in θ because P 0 < 0 and ∂q ∗ (θ)/ ∂θ > 0. In equilibrium each good will have the same price - let p be the actual price and pe the expected price. Consumers search if and only if θ ≥ θ̃ where θ̃ as the minimum θ ∈ θ, θ such that n × CS (pe ; θ) ≥ s. Profit on good j is therefore Rθ g (θ) {(p − c) Q (p − θ)} dθ. Differentiating with respect to p and imposing p = pe , θ̃ we find that pe satisfies19 Z θ 0 e Z g (θ) Π (p ; θ) dθ = θ̃ θ g (θ) {Q (pe − θ) + (pe − c) Q0 (pe − θ)} dθ = 0 (37) θ̃ Since ∂Π0 (pe ; θ) /∂θ > 0 equation (37) implies Π0 pe ; θ̃ < 0, which further implies Rθ Rθ that Π0 (pe ; θ) < 0∀θ ≤ θ̃. Consequently θ̃ g (θ) Π0 (pe ; θ) dθ ≥ θ g (θ) Π0 (pe ; θ) dθ. Lemma 24 In any equilibrium with trade, pe ≥ pm . Rθ Proof. Proceed by contradiction and suppose that pe < pm . θ g (θ) Π0 (pe ; θ) dθ > Rθ 0 because θ g (θ) Π (p; θ) dθ is concave and maximized at p = pm . This implies that Rθ Rθ 0 e g (θ) Π (p ; θ) dθ > 0 because (from the previous paragraph) g (θ) Π0 (pe ; θ) dθ ≥ θ̃ θ̃ 19 Since Q0 , Q00 < 0 profit is quasiconcave in p provided that types are not too different. 61 Rθ θ g (θ) Π0 (pe ; θ) dθ. However this contradicts (37) and thus the supposition that pe < pm . Define sn = n × CS (pm ; θ) and sn = n × CS p∗ θ ; θ and note that sn < sn .20 It follows immediately that when s ≤ sn there is an equilibrium where the retailer charges pm on every product. Proof of Proposition 13. Existence is proved as follows. Firstly since s > s0 then θ̃ > θ. Adapting the proof of Lemma 24 the lefthand side of equation (37) is strictly positive when evaluated at pe = pm . Secondly since s < s0 consumers with θ = θ search, and by continuity so do nearby types. Adapting the proof of Lemma 24 we can also conclude that Π0 p∗ θ ; θ < 0 for all θ < θ. Therefore the lefthand side of equation (37) is strictly negative when evaluated at pe = p∗ θ . Thirdly putting these two facts together, and using the fact that the lefthand side of (37) is continuous in pe , there exists at least one pe ∈ pm , p∗ θ such that (37) holds. Lemma 24 already shows that pe ≥ pm . Now suppose that the number of products stocked increases from n0 to n1 (the proof for an increase in s is virtually identical and is omitted). Let pe0 be the lowest equilibrium price when n = n0 , and θ̃0,0 be the lowest type that searches when n = n0 and price pe0 is expected. Let θ̃0,1 < θ̃0,0 be the lowest type who searches when n = n1 but price pe0 is still expected. Adapting earlier arguments we know that a). θ̃0,0 > θ and b). Π0 (pe0 ; θ) < 0 for all θ < θ̃0,0 . Therefore the lefthand side of (37) when evaluated at pe = pe0 but n = n1 is Z θ 0 g (θ) Π θ̃0,1 (pe0 ; θ) dθ Z θ < θ̃0,0 g (θ) Π0 (pe0 ; θ) dθ = 0 i.e. strictly negative. At the same time (37) is still weakly positive when evaluated at pe = pm and n = n1 . Therefore (by continuity) the lowest solution to (37) when n = n1 , must be strictly lower than the lowest solution when n = n0 . It is straightforward to show that pm > p∗ (θ) which then implies CS (p∗ (θ) ; θ) > CS (pm ; θ). Since CS p∗ θ ; θ exceeds CS (p∗ (θ) ; θ) by Lemma 23, sn exceeds sn . 20 62