Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
doi 10.1515/janeh-2013-0003 JANEH 2014; 1(1): 37–60 Francesca Rochberg* The History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia Abstract: This paper views the relevance of cuneiform texts to the history of science from inside, i.e., from the perspective of the available sources, as well as from outside, i.e., from the perspective of historians of science outside the field of Assyriology. It reviews some of the methodological problems that beset the reconstruction of science in the ancient Near East as well as a way forward, which acknowledges localism and pluralism as well the compelling continuity from cuneiform traditions of knowledge to later counterparts (astronomy, astrology, magic, astral-medicine). Cuneiform texts will not instantiate a universal or transcultural science but are essential if science is to be seen as embedded in culture and history. Keywords: astronomy, astrology, magic, medicine, episteme, science, localism, pluralism, nature, ṭupšarrūtu *Corresponding author: Francesca Rochberg, Department of Near Eastern Studies, University of California, Berkeley, USA, E-mail: [email protected] I do not believe that there is any single approach to the history of science which could not be replaced by very different methods of attack; only trivialities permit but one interpretation. Otto Neugebauer (1945) 1 The view from inside Ancient Mesopotamia became relevant to the history of science with the rediscovery in the 1880s of the mathematical astronomy of the Late Babylonian period. The Golden Age of decipherment and analysis, associated with the Jesuit fathers Joseph Epping, Johann Nepomuk Strassmaier, and Franz Xavier Kugler, was followed by the work of Otto Neugebauer, whose 1955 critical edition of the corpus of cuneiform lunar and planetary tables and procedure texts from Babylon and Uruk (Astronomical Cuneiform Texts, ACT) and theoretical presentation of the two methods of calculation, now known as Systems A and B (Systems II and I in Kugler 1900) established a new foundation for the Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 38 F. Rochberg field. In 1975 A History of Ancient Mathematical Astronomy (HAMA) placed Babylonian astronomy firmly in line with the tradition of Ptolemy’s Almagest, and by extension all later Western astronomy up to Copernicus. Neugebauer (1975: 349 and note 6) pointed out that Epping fully realized the significance of his discoveries. The two columns from a lunar ephemeris which he had deciphered, he said, “give us more information about Babylonian science than all the notices from classical antiquity combined”–a fact which cannot be emphasized too often. And he foresaw clearly that the new material would become of great importance for ancient chronology, for Assyriology in general, and even for modern astronomy. During the 20-year period between ACT and HAMA, the fruitful collaboration of Neugebauer and Abe Sachs in the heyday of the Brown School of ancient astronomy, as it can be informally called, together with the collaboration of Asger Aaboe (1955, 1964, 1980, 2001) at Yale, saw further work on the mathematical structures, parameters, and methods of Babylonian astronomical texts, both of mathematical and non-mathematical description, including Diaries, Almanacs, Normal Star Almanacs, Eclipse Reports and Observational texts, the so-called Non-mathematical astronomical texts (NMAT). Neugebauer and Sachs’ terminology mathematical and non-mathematical astronomy has by now become standard in the field. The unfinished editions of the NMATs were passed from Sachs to Hermann Hunger, who completed the herculean task of publication now available in Sachs–Hunger (1988, 1989, 1996) and Hunger (2001 and 2006) (see also Hunger 1999), the copies in Sachs–Pinches (1955). A snapshot of the entire trajectory of the history of Babylonian astronomy from the heroic times of the founding Fathers to the present is given in chapter 1 of Mathieu Ossendrijver (2012: section 1.1.3). Accordingly, phase one ran from the discovery and decipherment of cuneiform astronomical texts in 1881–1935, when Neugebauer and B.L. van der Waerden entered the field, and then to the beginning of the most recent phase in 1990, when an understanding of Babylonian science as including omen divination and horoscopes, as well as mathematics and astronomy came to the fore. Social, cultural, and epistemological questions began to be asked of the astronomical material with the goal of reconstructing not only the mathematical methods of Babylonian astronomy but its nature as a cultural phenomenon, and as well, the role, status, and place of its scribes in cuneiform intellectual history (Rochberg 2000, 2004; Ossendrijver 2011a and 2011b). Continuing this development, in tandem with the direction the history of science as a whole has taken in the generation of scholarship since the 1970s, it becomes increasingly clear that not only divinatory but also magical and medical texts belong to the scope of cuneiform science. Parallel and concurrent with the increasing acceptance of divinatory, magical, and astral Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 39 medical texts into the framework of cuneiform sciences is another recent surge in the explication of mathematical astronomy by John P. Britton (1987–2010), Lis Brack-Bernsen (1969–2010), John M. Steele (2000–2011), Noel M. Swerdlow (1998), and Mathieu Ossendrijver (2011–2012). Certainly, one of the great advantages for the cuneiformist interested in the history of science is the fact of the many extant and contemporaneous written sources stemming from the Old Babylonian period through to the end of cuneiform writing itself in the first century C.E. and represented both in Mesopotamian scribal centers and to the west (see especially the divinatory texts from Emar, Rutz 2013, and the short descriptions in Rochberg-Halton 1988: 30–35 and Koch-Westenholz 1995: 44–51), north (Hittite omens, see Güterbock 1987 and 1988; Rochberg-Halton 1988: 33–34, and Koch-Westenholz 1993), and east (Susa). The bulk of the Nineveh collection of scholarly texts, generally referred to as the library of Assurbanipal, estimated in the many thousands of clay tablets (excluding writing boards and other media), is of the essence for the history of cuneiform science. Many of the tablets of the Babylon Collection now housed in the British Museum and the Vorderasiatisches Museum Berlin, as well as the tablets from Assur, the religious capital of the Assyrian Empire, are also relevant, as are the Uruk texts of the Seleucid Rēš Temple to the sky-god from the Achaemenid and Hellenistic periods. These collections shed light on the principal way in which observed or observable phenomena were of interest to the scribes as divinatory knowledge, to do largely with astral omens and extispicy, the inspection of the sheep’s entrails, other forms of divination, astronomy and astrology. In particular, astral divination and extispicy were the two scholarly disciplines supported by the Neo-Assyrian imperial state and then preserved, to a greater or lesser extent, within the Late Babylonian temples of Babylon and Uruk during the Achaemenid, Seleucid, and Arsacid periods. Publication of many of these sources can be found in Hunger (1992), Reiner and Pingree (1975, 1981 and 1998), Koch(-Westenholz) (2000 and 2005), van Soldt (1995), Verderame (2002), and Rochberg(-Halton) (1988). In addition to the astronomical, astrological, and other divinatory sources, we might also include the tradition of lexical texts within a cuneiform intellectual history that bears on the history of science. Although different in focus and scope from any other scholarly corpora, lexical lists were also collections of knowledge, that is, of terms, synonyms, grammatical forms, and other categories of lexical information, both Sumerian and Akkadian, essential to the work of cuneiform scribes (Veldhuis in press). They certainly formed a large part of the repertoire that was serialized and passed down as an essential part of scribal scholarship. The many diagnostic and therapeutic medical texts must also be included as part of a broad base of sources relevant to a study of the cultural formulation of Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 40 F. Rochberg knowledge in the cuneiform context (e.g., Biggs 1990; Finkel 2000; Heeßel 2000, 2005 and 2008; Geller 2010a and 2010b; Finkel and Geller 2007; Scurlock 2006; Scurlock and Andersen 2005). Related thematically and in aim both to the medical and to the divinatory repertoires, magical texts, including such text types as namburbis (Maul 1994) and incantations were integrally connected to the whole of scribal knowledge. Understanding the intersections of omen divination, magic, medicine, and the hermeneutics that methodologically join these disciplines to the lexical material and to each other will be key to writing a history of cuneiform science in the future. In essence, the totality of scribal learning, kullat ṭupšarrūti “everything pertaining to the scribal art,” is source material for the history of cuneiform science as seen from a more or less internal perspective. The entry of ancient Mesopotamia into the history of science from the point of view of the sources, therefore, began with astronomy because, being quantitative and rigorously predictive, those materials were found to be continuous with the later tradition of exact science and could be fitted to a somewhat modern model of scientific knowledge. At the time of cuneiform astronomy’s rediscovery, the history of science was oriented toward an account of how modern science came to be, thus setting the tone for a mid-century admission of Babylon to its ranks. Later, however, the view of science in history expanded and a wider set of evidence became relevant to that broader conception. The content and methods of cuneiform astronomical texts then came to be viewed as part of the practices and purposes of scribal-scholarly learning as a whole. The resulting holistic approach to cuneiform intellectual historical sources, therefore, sees astronomy together with divinatory texts, horoscopes (Rochberg 1998), astral-medicine, and other kinds of divination (extispicy, morphoscopy, terrestrial omens, etc.), all representative of a system aimed at understanding the interconnection of human, divine, and world, both in its physical aspect and its textual representation. Essential to this historiographical approach is the dissolution of former demarcations between science and other forms of knowledge or practice, to be discussed at greater length below (Section 4), which need to be set aside for a reconstruction based on the contents of a cuneiform, not the modern, scientific imagination. 2 Methodological problems for a cuneiform history of science There are, however, a number of problems that attend the history of science in the ancient Near East methodologically. One is the lacunose nature of the Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 41 abundant texts–and this pertains not only to the tablets themselves, which are frequently broken and fragmentary, but also to the great gaps in chronology and geography in between groups of sources. Astronomical texts are a case in point, as the corpus of ephemerides and procedures that formed the foundation of our knowledge of Babylonian astronomy cluster in the Seleucid Period, with few texts bridging the gap to earlier periods, such as the earlier first millennium compendium MUL.APIN (Hunger and Pingree 1989). Scattered astronomical texts from the 6th to the 4th centuries analyzed most recently by John Britton (2008, 2009, 2010) represent intermediate stages before the fully developed systems of Babylonian mathematical astronomy emerged, but a continuous narrative for the history of astronomy in ancient Mesopotamia is far from attainable. If other traditions are taken into consideration, for example the divinatory texts, gaps in continuity are also the rule. Another problem of methodological approach is how to understand the relationship of the cuneiform scientific texts to the history of Western science. There is no question that the whole complex of the Babylonian celestial sciences were important foundation stones for the astrologia, astronomia, and mathematike of the Hellenistic period (Bowen 2013: 299 note 1) known from Greek and Latin texts, as the founding fathers of the modern decipherment of Babylonian astronomy made clear. The mathematical astronomical texts from late Babylonia (from ca. 500 BCE onward) are now considered an indisputable part of Western astronomy, and the astrological tradition of the Babylonians, which was also clearly known to Greco-Roman writers, is a significant part of that science. In fact, however, some traditions of knowledge represented in cuneiform texts can be seen as ancestral to both Western (geographically west of the “Near East” and including the Western Mediterranean regions and Europe) and Eastern (geographically from the Hellespont and the eastern coast of the Mediterranean to the Indus Valley) sciences, therefore including Byzantine, Islamic, and Indian sciences (Pingree 1997). It bears mention in the context of the history of science that despite the evidence of continuity from the ancient Near East to the later West, to the biblical and the classical worlds, ancient Mesopotamia is not reducible to a Western framework, indeed has a somewhat ambiguous identity as Western. In the preface to his Ancient Mesopotamia: Portrait of a Dead Civilization, A.L. Oppenheim (1977: 1–2) drew attention not to kinship with The West but rather to the unique and alien nature of the civilization reflected in cuneiform sources. Other Assyriologists have made similar remarks, such as Simo Parpola’s comment on “deep cultural differences” in the introduction to his edition of the Neo-Assyrian royal letters (1970: xviii). “No translation,” he said, echoing Landsberger’s notion of conceptual autonomy, Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 42 F. Rochberg no matter how good it is, can make these texts familiar or immediately understandable to a modern non-technical reader. One is bound to admit the existence of a cultural barrier which can be–even partially–removed only through a more thorough acquaintance of the texts themselves or related documents from the same period. Against the grain of those who emphasize continuity and familiarity over discontinuity and strangeness, some cuneiform evidence was included in Helaine Selin’s Encyclopedia of the History of Science, Technology, and Medicine in NonWestern Cultures (2008). There are entries on “Astrology in Babylonia,” “Medicine in ancient Mesopotamia,” “Mathematics in Mesopotamia,” and “Geometry in the Near and Middle East.” Coverage of the ancient Near East in the volume is uneven, and the authors of the entries, with the exception of Jens Høyrup (“Geometry in the Near and Middle East”), are not specialists in cuneiform texts. Selin, however, understood this material as appropriate within a non-Western framework, and the inclusion of those entries, as well as Eleanor Robson’s “The uses of mathematics in ancient Iraq, 6000–600 BC” in the other of Selin’s edited reference works, Mathematics Across Cultures: the History of Non-Western Mathematics (2000), is indicative of a shift in thinking about the cultural identity of ancient Iraq, or Mesopotamia. Among the writers on ancient Iraq in Selin’s encyclopedias of Non-Western science and mathematics only Robson addressed the question of the ambiguity of Mesopotamia’s cultural identity, saying (2000: 95), with respect to mathematical texts, “since its discovery in the early twentieth century AD, this mathematics has been treated implicitly as part of the ‘Western’ tradition; even now one finds ‘Mesopotamian’ mathematics categorized as ‘Early Western mathematics’, while Iraqi mathematics in Arabic, some of which is directly related to its compatriot precursors, appears under ‘other traditions’ (e.g., Cooke 1997).” In addition to the fragmentary or lacunose nature of the cuneiform sources and the question of how to position the evidence vis-à-vis the West is the historiographical question of the very nature of the investigation of “the history of science” in the ancient Near East. That is, if the project is defined as a reconstruction of science in Babylonia and Assyria, what exactly is being reconstructed? Of course, the question is not new. Peter Dear’s “What is the History of Science the History of?” comes to mind. As he said (2005: 390), Rather than studying the history of something that we always knew in advance how to identify, historians of science have turned more and more to studying how that “something” itself has been formed as a historical object, with no permanent, transcendental identity. Everything thus becomes historicized and contingent, and the days of the history of science as an apologetic or celebratory enterprise serving present-day science have become, so to speak, a thing of the past. Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 43 Unlike the sciences derived from the classical tradition, it is an even more awkward kind of history where the very category for identifying what evidence is relevant or not is not an internal or native category at all, but an artifact of a different time and a different culture. In using this non-native category, we must be conscious of our own filtration of the evidence and realize that, rather than aiming to discover in ancient Mesopotamia that which we always knew to be science, we have the opportunity to allow cuneiform texts to suggest other ways in which knowledge was valued and phenomena were understood, and so to further expand our ideas about the nature of science historically. Because there is no science, whether taken as knowledge, practice, or method, to bring back from cuneiform texts as something to which the scribescholars themselves were consciously committed, we cannot, strictly speaking, extract from these sources a narrative about what kind of, or how, science happened there from anything like a “native” point of view. Again, this problem is not at all new. Peter Harrison (1998: 8–9) remarked already that “historians of science … frequently concern themselves with ‘an imaginary object’, constructing it from a variety of texts and heterogenous disciplines … it needs to be recognized that ‘science’, as we understand it, does not have a history which can be traced back beyond the seventeenth century.” Science, therefore, from a historical viewpoint, is something other than what we now understand it to be. Consequently, whatever we imagine for the ancient Near East must be congruent with its historical evidence, but what we deem relevant as evidence has clearly shifted over time as modernist demarcation programs emphasizing dichotomies of science/non-science and the rational/irrational have been laid to rest. If, in good postmodern fashion, we have given up our commitment to absolutes, facts, and a continuous teleological narrative with all its potential for anachronistic distortion of historical evidence, we need not give up trying to understand what various historical actors’ interest in the phenomenal world was. And if interest in phenomena–physical, metaphysical, observable and imaginary–is the stuff of a newly historicized and redefined science, then we still have work to do for cuneiform texts. There are cuneiform texts that can still be approached with the conceptual tools we bring to the study of other scientific corpora, i.e., observation, explanation, rationality, and prediction, if only to delimit their differences and attend to their particular orientation toward phenomena. More specifically, if celestial and other forms of divination, as well as magical texts and related knowledge compendia, the plant compendium (šammu šikinšu, see Stadhouders 2011 and 2012) and stone compendium (abnu šikinšu, see Schuster-Brandis 2008) for example, are to be taken into account with the totality of “the history of science” in the cuneiform world, a standard of Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 44 F. Rochberg criteria for knowledge that is discontinuous with that of science as defined from the early modern period onward must be recognized. What we want to know now is what the ancient scholars’ epistemic criteria were, as well as their motivations and aims, not necessarily as measured against modern counterparts, but, when there are resonances, obviously, we take note. The first millennium scholars’ very construal of the set of phenomena appropriate to their interests sometimes diverges rather radically from what we would expect from physical science. In omen texts, we are confronted both with physical and with non-physical things, i.e., imaginary or otherwise unobservable celestial or terrestrial phenomena (Rochberg 2009, 2010). We must resolve this divergence from our sense of the purpose of scientific inquiry by investigating the aims of this and other corpora of knowledge. Observation of phenomena was motivated largely by an interest in ominous signs, not the desire to causally account for those phenomena. And because there was no conception of nature to provide a framework of laws or forces to account for such causes, the scribes did not seek to explain phenomena in a causal way (Rochberg 2011). Explanation in the cuneiform intellectual world had other aims, generally hermeneutic in character (Frahm 2011). From a methodological point of view, therefore, the history of science for the cuneiform world, since the heroic era of the Jesuit Fathers, Neugebauer, and the exact sciences, has begun to accommodate multiple sets of sources, requiring multiple approaches to the material, in keeping with Neugebauer’s own reflections on the matter, as expressed in the statement quoted in the epigraph, above. 3 The view from outside The historiography of Babylonian astronomy not only deals within the framework of the cuneiform corpora of knowledge (ṭupšarrūtu) but also belongs to a wider “scientific oikumene” constructed of the ancient Near East, the Western Mediterranean, Egypt, and India (Pingree 1978, 1998). Analytic and synthetic treatments of Babylonian scientific texts by cuneiformists are therefore of value from outside the immediate field of cuneiform studies. Arne Hessenbruch’s Readers’s Guide to the History of Science (2000: 196) took note of “Egypt and Mesopotamia” with the following statement: Mesopotamia and Egypt used to be poor relations in the history of science, useful only as a foil for the so-called Greek miracle, the birth of real science and mathematics. However, new archaeological discoveries, the study of newly-uncovered texts, and reappraisals of Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 45 those already known from the point of view of an enlarged range of questions have changed this image in the last few decades. More than in other areas of the history of science, older syntheses and the popular expositions based on them may prove to be at best obsolete, or even misleading. By the turn of the millennium the field had indeed entered a new phase, one changed by some new sources but principally by a new historiographical sensibility, alluded to in Section 2, above. But Near Eastern knowledge corpora, certainly no longer a foil for their Greek counterparts, still present us with problems of understanding, because that mass of textual source material does not speak in our customary language of science, that is, of the kind of knowledge scientia or episteme are supposed to represent, nor of nature or a clearly defined notion of the physical. In the same Reader’s Guide to the History of Science, under “Greece: General Works,” the position of Near Eastern science vis-à-vis Greek is mentioned again. There, Elmer Yglesias (2000: 311) pointed out that the period just post-WWII saw a marked increase in the attention given to ancient Greek science, and soon thereafter, according to the general outlines of the entry, ancient Near Eastern science was introduced to the field by Neugebauer, whose Exact Sciences in Antiquity of 1969 Iglesias, I think unfairly, deemed “narrowly internalistic.” From the late 1960s and early 1970s to the early 1990s, Geoffrey Lloyd established a new foundation for the study of Greek science with a series of books from Polarity and Analogy: Two Types of Argumentation in Early Greek Thought to Demystifying Mentalities and Problems and Methods in Greek Science (1966–1991). With reference to Lloyd’s work, Yglesias pointed to the progressive engagement of the history of science with anthropology, philosophy, and social history, that is to say, not the internalist work of those interested in Babylonian astronomy. Lloyd’s attention to methodological and historiographical issues set an intellectual stage for the special issue of Isis in 1992 entitled “The Cultures of Ancient Science,” with contributions by Pingree, Lloyd, Martin Bernal, Heinrich von Staden, and Rochberg. This collection of papers was something of a breakout piece, in which the ancient Near East was given a hearing in the premiere journal of the American History of Science Society alongside ancient Greece. There von Staden offered a key methodological critique for the very approach to Greek science still valuable today for ancient science in general which he termed the problem of “affinities and elisions.” He showed that historians of ancient science privileged Greek science over that of other Mediterranean and Near Eastern cultures at their own risk of distortion, particularly when it resulted in the claim to the invention of science and the scientific method. These claims, he argued, would not have sat well with the ancient Greeks themselves, whose scientific writers show an awareness of, interest in, Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 46 F. Rochberg and influence by what Arnaldo Momigliano (1990) famously termed “alien wisdom,” most notably but not only that of Egyptians and Chaldeans. Von Staden’s paper, however, was not only aimed at Hellenocentrists. As he said (1992: 582), “‘Hellenocentrism’ is but one manifestation” of more fundamental problems that “arise from the oft-tacit interpretative deployment of ‘affinity,’ ‘continuity,’ and ‘origin’–notions conditioned in part by the history of the modern reception of classical antiquity.” These problems, we can say now in looking back, are the consequence of a modernist history of science geared to accounting ultimately for the origins, roots, and rise of modern science. Pingree developed his argument against this position, calling it “Hellenophilia,” providing, as he put it (1992: 554), “an apologia for my claim to be a historian of science with as serious and thorough a purpose as are the topics that we usually find discussed in history of science classrooms or in the pages of Isis.” While affinities, continuities, and origins became important from the point of view of writing the history of science backwards, so to speak, from the modern perspective, the essential asymmetry and difference between the modern and the premodern eras created a gap, an intelligibility gap – what Ernest Gellner called the Big Ditch – between two “worlds,” in the sense that we find a plurality of invalid world systems of traditional cultures before the Ditch but a single true world system of science after (1979: 145–47).1 One of the major missing ingredients in the cultures that do not see the world as we do is the recognition of the discrete nature of nature with its own operative forces and laws. Though the absence of a notion of nature means that the cuneiform cultural perspective on the physical world and its phenomena has some fundamental differences from that of later Western science, the kinship between these traditions, particularly in the astral sciences, can enlarge our view of the scientific enterprise. Iglesias took the 1992 Isis symposium as indicative of a changing perspective, where Greece would be viewed in the larger context of the whole of the ancient Mediterranean, including the ancient Near East, or really, Babylonia and Egypt. “The Cultures of Ancient Science,” as the issue was called, did point toward an emergent pluralism, as well as an enlarged framework for thinking about science in antiquity that has become normative since that time. China too, already of course a subject for the history of science in its own right, took on added importance, as Lloyd (1996, 2006) and his collaboration with Nathan Sivin (Lloyd and Sivin, 2003) showed, in reaching out beyond the boundaries of Hellas for a broader understanding of the nature of ancient science as a whole. 1 He called it (p. 146) “one colossal, or should I say, abysmal, chasm,” and see also, idem (1982: 188–200). Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 47 It is not only that the history of ancient science has come to recognize a wider geographical framework for its evidence, one that sets both the cuneiform and the classical and Hellenistic Greek sciences within a wider cultural ambit, indeed within the framework of West and East writ large, but the progressively historicized view of what science knows, does, and is, has changed the way we identify, read, and understand ancient texts relevant to what we think of as the history of science. 4 Local knowledge and pluralism The change in the conception of ancient science is the result of broader intellectual trends, the so-called interpretive, social, and linguistic turns, the work of new historicists, post-structuralists, the sociology of scientific knowledge, constructivism, local knowledge, science as practice, concerns about presentism, and, generally speaking, an all around drift toward various pluralisms. For the historian of premodern and non-Western sciences, the most important turn is the turn away from both a universal notion of science as transcendent of culture and the assumption that such a universal science is instantiated by Western science. Thomas Kuhn looms very large in this process. No doubt he was the single greatest game changer, as many have said many times. Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962) explicitly committed to granting other people their “worlds,” particularly how their historical and cultural ways of knowing and describing created variable “worlds.” This shift of focus on difference and discontinuity in the content and values of knowledge over time and across geographical boundaries raised new questions for the interpretation of ancient science, and insisted that it be understood on its own terms, not simply as a precursor, certainly not an immature version of later science. Clifford Geertz deserves mention in this context as well, as his thoroughgoing pluralism and focus on the local mirrored this change in the history of science. Referring to the aim of science he said (2000: x): The notion that the surer grasp of unshapely and incongruent, even unique, particulars is as proper an aim of science as the abstractive formulation of exceptionless regularities– and is, often enough, more illuminating as well–has grown steadily more acceptable over the last quarter century [referring to the period from 1975 to 2000] as rationalism stumbled, positivism evaporated, and the “prism face of Newton” (the image is Wordsworth’s) faded from view. The notion that all knowledge aspires to the condition of mathematical physics … lacks the air of simple obviousness that it had even a few short years ago. Everything, from the philosophical reconsideration of the nature of natural law to the Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 48 F. Rochberg spread of perspectival, observer-dependent explanation, has strengthened the claims of case-based knowledge to scientific standing. He was referring here to the nature of science, but the implications for its history are clear. One of the major effects of the change in the game is that the aim and focus of the history of ancient science is no longer simply to trace the ultimate origins and roots of modern science. Cuneiform astronomical texts, in their role as directly antecedent to Western astronomy, may once have earned their place in the history of science precisely on the basis of this intimate and significant connection between ancient and modern. But the singling out of astronomy, particularly mathematical astronomy, as the Mesopotamian contribution to the history of science did its share in reinforcing the conception of the history of science backward from modernity to antiquity. Late Babylonian astronomy became a powerful symbol of what the ancients could accomplish, and seemed on the face of it to testify to the fact that Babylonian scientific aims were consistent with ours, i.e., to obtain knowledge and predictive control of phenomena and to discover their autonomous “laws.” Because the ancients were attempting to describe or predict the same phenomena as later astronomers did, viz., the periodic synodic appearances of planets, the first visibility of the moon, etc., the question of what it was the ancients observed and perceived about these natural objects, and why, was not, in the modernist historiographical mode, raised as a historical problem. The value of Babylonian astronomy to the history of science, once tied to its status as the earliest chapter in a story of the development of Western planetary theory is now rather that it can show how much more complex the relations among various aspects of the Babylonian intellectual culture were. And the aspects we used to identify as scientific and those we did not suddenly do not appear so dichotomous. Late Babylonian astronomy is no longer viewed as an isolated corpus of scientific mathematical ephemerides, more or less easily translatable to Western counterparts. The Babylonian theory of the planets, as Noel Swerdlow pointed out in the introduction to his 1998 book of the same name, had its cultural place in a world of diviners and temple benefices. The multiple epistemic values of Babylonian astronomical science, therefore, especially those not obviously congruent with later astronomical science, are the ones now most in need of explication. The turn away from what is essentially an ahistorical presumption of scientific universalism became the postmodern turn to localism and an interest not only in the culturally embedded nature of knowledge of all kinds, scientific included, but in various practices that can be classified as scientific in some way Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 49 as well. The postmodern strategy to historicize, to challenge absolute standards or criteria, and to recognize pluralities is seeing an even further normalization and intensification for the history of ancient science. Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen, in an article dramatically entitled “I am Knowledge. Get Me Out of Here! On Localism and the Universality of Science” (2011: 590) pointed out that the construction of science as a local phenomenon not only implies its representation of that locality and how it may differ from others, but that this perspective has necessitated changes in what we count as scientific practice. What may be even more important for historians of the local domain we call the ancient Near East, however, was his (2011: 590, my emphasis) statement, that “rather than referring to some universally shared internal logic of science and invoking the existence of ‘nature’ and neutral empirical data derived from it as non-problematic explanatory notions, science is now explained by reference to the factors that can be found … in particular localities.” The idea that cultures can be relative but science, and with it nature, is universal does not go without saying and has in fact been challenged in the historiography of science going back, once again, to Kuhn, who voiced the need to render even nature in accordance with historical context, as we see in a statement published in Conant and Haugeland’s Road Since Structure (2000: 220–21, my emphasis): …the gap that I have here described as separating the Greek heavens from our own is the sort that could only have resulted from what I earlier called a scientific revolution. The violence and misrepresentation consequent on describing their heavens in the conceptual vocabulary required to describe our own is an example of what I then called incommensurability. And the shock generated by substituting their conceptual spectacles for our own is the one I ascribed, however inadequately, to their living in a different world. Where the social world of another culture is at issue, we have learned, against our own deep-seated ethnocentric resistance, to take shock for granted. We can, and in my view must, learn to do the same for their natural worlds. This, however, lacked the force with which Bruno Latour (1993: 106) proclaimed, manifestolike: “From cultural relativism we move on to ‘natural’ relativism.” Of course it could be suggested that a relativity about nature is subsumable under a thoroughgoing cultural relativism. No matter. Latour worked this subject persuasively in his provocative We Have Never Been Modern and seems to have been the first to employ the term “natures” to represent a plurality of conceptions derived from anthropological and historical approaches to science. But the idea was in the air, as we see in a statement of Joseph Rouse, in an article two years prior to We Have Never Been Modern that questioned why “narratives of modernity” in the history and philosophy of science were so difficult to root out Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 50 F. Rochberg and overcome. There (1991: 162) Rouse went so far as to suggest that “the idea that there is a ‘natural world’ for natural science to be about, entirely distinct from the ways human beings as knowers and agents interact with it, must … be abandoned.” Countering the picture of an ahistorical and abstract authoritative canon of science, local knowledge within a variety of historical and social contexts has been in the foreground now for a generation of historians. In part, this was a consequence of the very shift in aim from determining how our present scientific state of the art came to be, to what the nature of knowledge was in former periods. With greater refinement and subtlety in the approach to the history of knowledge, there comes a recognition that what episteme meant to Aristotle or scientia to Augustine, or the Scholastics, was different in each case. Similarly, knowledge for the cuneiform scribes in the Sumerian or Akkadian idiom is not the equivalent of, or counterpart to, episteme or scientia. Instead, the crux for a cuneiform epistemology is in what was considered the object of knowledge, especially when words and signs were of central interest. Nevertheless, whatever we can reconstruct or infer even partially about what knowledge was in the cuneiform context should take its place alongside other staples of the history of premodern science and epistemology. 5 The order of nature and the object(s) of scientific knowledge in ancient mesopotamia Both nature’s definition and its attachment to science, especially to modern science, have been at the foundation of the history of science since its inception, when the goal of the field was to formulate an account of the origins and rise of modern science. But how, a priori, can we assume that all historical science had nature as its object of inquiry and the understanding of how nature operates as its goal? I do not think enough has been done yet to answer this question, though Lloyd has certainly taken us further in several recent monographs, principally in his Cognitive Variations (Lloyd 2007) and Being, Humanity, and Understanding (Lloyd 2012), where (2012: 64) he challenges the claim that an explicit concept of nature was necessary to all scientific inquiry, citing precisely Mesopotamia and China as examples of how science could exist, even thrive, without it. Historians of science cannot afford to take the nature of nature as selfevident. What we make of the natural world is a direct function of our historical and cultural ways of knowing, and our linguistic ways of describing. Nature Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 51 functions as a category with varying boundaries and contents cross-culturally and historically, yet seems to be particularly endemic to Western cultures descended from the classical world. In ancient Mesopotamia, as in any number of premodern and non-Western cultures, engagement with the natural world did not give rise to a term for nature, nor to a conception of nature as an independent objective reality. While it is true that a separate domain, equivalent to what we call nature did not have its own word in the perceptual/conceptual/linguistic world of the ancient Near East, a variety of texts reflect various ways of systematically looking at what we call natural phenomena in that cuneiform world. If indeed the compendia of ominous signs, medical therapies and incantations, pharmacological ingredients (URUANNA ¼ maštakal), plant and stone lists, as well as astronomical texts both mathematical and non-mathematical, and later astrological and astro-medical works belong to science in ancient Mesopotamia, the objective of that knowledge can neither be defined in terms of nor reduced to a desire to know or explain nature. Nor can the practices associated with these handbooks and compendia be assimilated to the various objectives of later natural sciences, or even natural philosophy, namely, to understand the order of nature, nature’s laws and causes, or the relationship between nature, man, and God. These are not epistemic motives or scientific values that fit the picture created by cuneiform sources of “knowledge,” or science, nor of its practices, whether associated with divination at the NeoAssyrian court, or with the nightly watch of the heavens in Babylon from the Eighth to the First centuries B.C.E., or with the complex tradition of medical treatment, fully integrated with the use of “magic.” In sum, with regard to pre-modern sciences not derived from the classical tradition, fundamental assumptions about science as a form of thought, a method of inquiry, a set of practices, or indeed as an inquiry whose object is nature and natural phenomena construed in a particular (Western) way, are ripe for reassessment. For the premodern and non-Western context, a historicized, pluralized, and relativized view of science with an equally historicized, pluralized, and relativized notion of nature is key to taking account of other cultures’ ways of thinking about and describing the phenomena of interest to them, be they heavenly bodies, sheep entrails, plants, stones, or the behavior of animals. In his recent defense of pluralism in the history and philosophy of science, Hasok Chang (2012) rejects both monism and reductionism in scientific theory on the basis of the utter complexity of nature and our attempts to understand it. He has offered that the monistic view of nature was but a stage, if a necessary stage, in the development of science. He said (2012: 255, emphasis in the original): Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 52 F. Rochberg It is possible that science needed to be launched on the strength of hubris, which made the whole enterprise seem both doable and worth doing: that we could grasp the truth about nature! Perhaps early scientists needed to believe that nature was fundamentally simple enough for them to be able to understand it. Newton had God on his side and proceeded with the faith that there was one truth about God’s creation and with the grace of God he could find it–how else would anyone muster the conviction that one simple equation could cover all the universe? And so it makes sense as one looks at the progress of science since the Scientific Revolution, using the term here as a convenient chronological marker, to question the utility and even validity of such monism and/or reductionism. For the ancient Near East, though, we are in even less familiar terrain, both before God and before Nature. So, if cuneiform materials are to be included in the history of science, the whole framework that joins science to nature, whether monistically (à la Newton) or pluralistically (à la Chang), must be altered. What seems unavoidable is that whereas no assumption seems more fundamental to our conception of science than nature, if we are to embrace a pluralism about science, we also ought to consider a pluralism about nature, and to acknowledge the anachronistic nature of referring to it in the context of the ancient Near East. In order to get inside the culture of cuneiform science, or knowledge, and to be able to redefine a conception of science (or knowledge) in Babylonian and Assyrian texts, what may once have been considered epiphenomenal – things like the use of divination as a legitimizing tool of the state, the scope of the late Babylonian scribes’ expertise in texts from incantations to ephemerides, the continuous preservation of millennia-old traditions of omens, not to mention reconstructing familial connections and networks among the scribes of Uruk or of Babylon – all these things should be taken into ever greater account as we further explore the cuneiform texts and contexts in which it makes sense to speak of culturally embedded knowledge (science). Peter Harrison noted (1998: 8–9) that “for virtually the first fifteen hundred years of the common era the study of natural objects took place within the humanities, as part of an all-encompassing science of interpretation which sought to expound the meanings of words and things.” The contexts and methods that characterize ancient Mesopotamian knowledge of what Harrison called “natural objects,” roughly for the fifteen hundred years before the Common Era, have quite a number of parallels to what he described for the first fifteen hundred years. That is, natural objects–or what we call natural objects–were classified within a framework of things and kinds that had significance as signs coming from the divine for the benefit of human society. Cuneiform testimony about signs and portents did not yet draw lines between or around the natural, Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 53 supernatural, or preternatural, none of which domains can exist in the absence of a conception of nature itself. However, the body of objects of inquiry found in cuneiform divinatory or other texts, indicating what was regular and what irregular and within what sort of ontological framework such distinctions were meaningful, will contribute to, once we have pieced this together more comprehensively, a historical epistemology useful both for a better, or more culturally oriented, understanding of the relation of ancient Mesopotamia to science, and for the history of science as a whole. A final point: To invoke the notion of “the history of science as a whole” would seem to belie my postmodern commitment to pluralism and skepticism about the meaning of any sort of decontextualized or universalized science. However, there is much about the cuneiform investigation of phenomena that resonates with later traditions of natural philosophy and science. After all, other cultures, the Greek and the Indian most directly, adopted any number of ideas and practices from the body of knowledge and its practices attested in cuneiform, from omens to astronomy and astrology. Therefore, despite localism and pluralism, there is as well a compelling continuity about some traditions in the history of science, suggesting that there may be a (post-postmodern?) historiographical position to be found between two extremes – a “Third Way” – where we relinquish the idea of science as a universal or transcendent fact, yet we do not reduce it to nominalistic particulars, where we give up on the grand narrative of the steadily progressive rise of a reified science, but acknowledge where transmission occurred and where continuities exist, and where we can agree, with the sociologists of scientific knowledge, that a science as defined by modernist philosophers never existed, but find that many kinds of science have existed, instantiated by the evidence from many periods and cultures of history, including ancient Mesopotamia. The postmodern irony of there being no science in ancient Mesopotamia because there was no word for it nor conception of it does not mean that we cannot try to understand what about its textual remains resonates with, even contributes to, what for us is a more culturally embedded notion of science and its history. Bibliography Aaboe, A. 1955. On the Babylonian Origin of Some Hipparchian Parameters. Centaurus 4: 122–25. Aaboe, A. 1964. On Period Relations in Babylonian Astronomy. Centaurus 10: 213–23. Aaboe, A. 1980. Observation and Theory in Babylonian Astronomy. Centaurus 24: 14–35. Aaboe, A. 2001. Episodes from the Early History of Astronomy. New York: Springer Verlag. Bernal, M. 1992. Animadversions on the Origins of Western Science. Isis 83: 596–607. Biggs, R. D. 1990. Medizin. RLA 3: 625–26. Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 54 F. Rochberg Bowen, A. C. 2013. Three Introductions to Celestial Science in the First Century BC. Pp. 299–327 in Writing Science: Medical and Mathematical Authorship in Ancient Greece, ed. M. Asper. Berlin: De Gruyter. Brack-Bernsen, L. 1969. On the Construction of Column B in System A of the Astronomical Cuneiform Texts. Centaurus 14: 23–28. Brack-Bernsen, L. 1980. Some Investigations on the Ephemerides of the Babylonian Moon Texts System A. Centaurus 24: 36–50. Brack-Bernsen, L. 1990. On the Babylonian Lunar Theory A: Construction of Column Φ from Horizontal Observations. Centaurus 33: 39–56. Brack-Bernsen, L. 1997. Zur Entstehung Der Babylonischen Mondtheorie: Beobachtung Und Theoretische Berechnung Von Mondphasen. Boethius Series, 40. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag. Brack-Bernsen, L. 1999. Goal Year Tablets: Lunar Data and Predictions. Pp. 149–77 in Ancient Astronomy and Celestial Divination, ed. N. M. Swerdlow. Publications of the Dibner Institute for the History of Science and Technology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Brack-Bernsen, L. 2003. The Path of the Moon, the Rising Points of the Sun, and the Oblique Great Circle on the Celestial Sphere. Centaurus 45: 16–31. Brack-Bernsen, L. 2005. The “Days in Excess” from MUL.APIN: On the “First Intercalation” and “Water Clock” Schemes from MUL.APIN. Centaurus 47: 1–29. Brack-Bernsen, L. 2007. The 360-Day Year in Mesopotamia. Pp. 83–100 in Calendars and Years: Astronomy and Time in Ancient Mesopotamia, ed. John M. Steele. Oxford: Oxbow Books. Brack-Bernsen, L. 2010a. Prediction of Days and Pattern of the Babylonian Lunar Six. AfO 52: 156–78. Brack-Bernsen, L. 2010b. Methods for Understanding and Reconstructing Babylonian Predicting Rules. Pp. 277–97 in Writings of Early Scholars in the Ancient Near East, Egypt, Rome, and Greece, eds. A. Imhausen and T. Pommerening. Beiträge zur Altertumskunde, 286. Berlin: de Gruyter. Brack-Bernsen, L, and J. M. Steele. 2004. Babylonian Mathemagics: Two Mathematical Astronomical-Astrological Texts. Pp. 95–125 in Studies in the History of the Exact Sciences in Honour of David Pingree, eds. Charles Burnett, J. P. Hogendijk, K. Plofker, and M. Yano. Leiden: Brill. Britton, J. P. 1987. The Structure and Parameters of Column φ. Pp. 23–26 in From Ancient Omens to Statistical Mechanics: Essays on the Exact Sciences Presented to Asger Aaboe, eds. J. L. Berggren and B. R. Goldstein. Acta Historica Scientiarum Series, 39. Copenhagen: University Library. Britton, J. P. 1989. An Early Function for Eclipse Magnitudes in Babylonian Astronomy. Centaurus 32: 1–52. Britton, J. P. 1990. A Tale of Two Cycles: Remarks on Column φ. Centaurus 33: 57–69. Britton, J. P. 1993a. Scientific Astronomy in Pre-Seleucid Babylon. Pp. 61–76 in Die Rolle Der Astronomie in Den Kulturen Mesopotamiens, ed. Hannes D. Galter. Grazer Morgenländische Studien, 3. Graz: GrazKult. Britton, J. P. 1993b. A Table of Fourth Powers and Related Texts from Seleucid Babylon. JCS 43–45: 71–88. Britton, J. P. 1998. Planetary Theory in Babylon. Journal for the History of Astronomy 29: 381–85. Britton, J. P. 2002. Treatments of Annual Phenomena in Cuneiform Sources. Pp. 21–78 in Under One Sky: Astronomy and Mathematics in the Ancient Near East, eds. John M. Steele and Annette Imhausen. AOAT, 297. Münster: Ugarit Verlag. Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 55 Britton, J. P. 2007a. Calendars, Intercalations and Year-Lengths in Mesopotmian Astronomy. Pp. 115–32 in Calendars and Years: Astronomy and Time in the Ancient Near East, ed. John M. Steele. Oxford: Oxbow Books. Britton, J. P. 2007b. Studies in Babylonian Lunar Theory: Part I. Empirical Elements for Modeling Lunar and Solar Anomalies. Archive for History of Exact Sciences 61: 83–145. Britton, J. P. 2008. Remarks on Strassmaier Cambyses 400. Pp. 7–33 in From the Banks of the Euphrates: Studies in Honor of Alice Slotsky, ed. Micah Ross. Winona Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns. Britton, J. P. 2009. Studies in Babylonian Lunar Theory: Part II. Treatments of Lunar Anomaly. Archive for History of Exact Sciences 63: 357–431. Britton, J. P. 2010. Studies in Babylonian Lunar Theory: Part III. The Introduction of the Uniform Zodiac. Archive for History of Exact Sciences 64: 617–63. Britton, J. P., and C. B. F. Walker. 1991. A Fourth Century Babylonian Model for Venus: BM 33552. Centaurus 34: 97–118. Chang, H. 2012. Is Water H2O?: Evidence, Realism and Pluralism. New York: Springer. Conant, J., and J. Haugeland, eds. 2000. The Road Since Structure: Thomas S. Kuhn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Cooke, R. 1997. The History of Mathematics: A Brief Course. New York: Wiley. Dear, P. 2005. What Is the History of Science the History of? Early Modern Roots of the Ideology of Modern Science. Isis 96: 390–406. Finkel, I. L. 2000. On Late Babylonian Medical Training. Pp. 137–224 in Wisdom, God and Literature: Studies in Assyriology in Honor of W.G. Lambert, eds. A. R. George and I. L. Finkel. Winona Lake, IN: Eisenbrauns. Finkel, I. L., and M. J. Geller (eds.). 2007. Disease in Babylonia. Leiden: Brill. Frahm, E. 2011. Babylonian and Assyrian Text Commentaries, GMTR 5. Münster: Ugarit-Verlag. Geertz, C. 1983, 2000. Local Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpretive Anthropology. 2nd ed. New York: Basic Books. Geller, M. J. 2010a. Ancient Babylonian Medicine: Theory and Practice. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. Geller, M. J. 2010b. Look to the Stars: Babylonian Medicine, Magic, Astrology and Melothesia. Max Planck Preprint, 401. Berlin: Max Planck Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte. Gellner, E. 1979. Spectacles and Predicaments: Essays in Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gellner, E. 1982. Relativism and Universals. Pp. 188–200 in Rationality and Relativism, eds. Martin Hollis and Steven Lukes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Goldstein, C. 2000. Egypt and Mesopotamia. Pp. 195–97 in Reader’s Guide to the History of Science, ed. Arne Hessenbruch. London: Fitzroy Dearborn Publishers. Güterbock, H. G. 1987. Hittite Liver Models. Pp. 147–53 in Language, Literature, and History: Philological and Historical Studies Presented to Erica Reiner, ed. F. Rochberg-Halton. New Haven, CT: American Oriental Society. Güterbock, H. G. 1988. Bilingual Moon Omens from Boghazköy. Pp. 161–74 in A Scientific Humanist: Studies in Memory of Abraham Sachs, eds. E. Leichty, M. deJ. Ellis, and P. Gerardi. Philadelphia, PA: University Museum. Harrison, P. 1998. The Bible: Protestantism and the Rise of Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Heeßel, N. 2000. Babylonisch-Assyrische Diagnostik. AOAT, 43. Münster: Ugarit Verlag. Heeßel, N. 2005. Stein, Pflanze, Und Holz, Ein Neuer Text Zur “Medizinischen Astrologie.” Orientalia 74: 1–22. Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 56 F. Rochberg Heeßel, N. 2008. Astrological Medicine in Babylonia. Pp. 1–16 in Astro-Medicine, Astrology and Medicine, East and West, eds. Anna Akasoy, Charles Burnett, and Ronit Yoeli-Tlalim. Micrologus’ Library, 25. Florence: Sismel–Edizioni del Galluzzo. Hessenbruch, A. 2000. Readers’s Guide to the History of Science. London: Routledge. Hunger, H. 1992. Astrological Reports to Assyrian Kings. State Archives of Assyria, 8. Helsinki: Helsinki University Press. Hunger, H. 1999. Non-Mathematical Astronomical Texts and Their Relationships. Pp. 77–96 in Ancient Astronomy and Celestial Divination, ed. Noel M. Swerdlow. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hunger, H. 2001. Astronomical Diaries and Related Texts from Babylonia. Vol. 5: Lunar and Planetary Texts. Vienna: Österreichische Akkademie der Wissenschaften. Hunger, H. 2006. Astronomical Diaries and Related Texts from Babylonia. Vol.6: Goal Year Texts. Vienna: Österreichische Akkademie der Wissenschaften. Hunger, H., and D. Pingree. 1989. MUL.APIN: An Astronomical Compendium in Cuneiform. AfO Beiheft, 24. Horn: F. Berger. Koch, U. S. 2005. Secrets of Extispicy: The Chapter Multābiltu of the Babylonian Extispicy Series and Niṣirti Bārûti Texts Mainly from Aššurbanipal’s Library. AOAT, 326. Münster: Ugarit Verlag. Koch-Westenholz, U. 1993. Mesopotamian Astrology at Hattusas. Pp. 231–46 in Die Rolle Der Astronomie in Den Kulturen Mesopotamiens, ed. Hannes D. Galter. Grazer Moergenländische Studien, 3. Graz: GrazKult. Koch-Westenholz, U. 1995. Mesopotamian Astrology: An Introduction to Babylonian and Assyrian Celestial Divination. Carsten Niebuhr Institute Publications, 19. Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum Press. Koch-Westenholz, U. 2000. Babylonian Liver Omens: The Chapters Manzazu, Padanu and Pan Takalti of the Babylonian Extispicy Series Mainly From Assurbanipals’s Library. Carsten Niebuhr Institute Publications, 25. Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum Press. Kugler, F. X. 1900. Die Babylonische Mondrechnung: Zwei Systeme Der Chaldäer Über Den Lauf Des Mondes Und Der Sonne. Freiburg im Breisgau: Herder’sche Verlagshandlung. Kuhn, T. 1962, 1996. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 3rd ed. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Kuukkanen, J.-M. 2011. I Am Knowledge: Get Me Out Of Here! on Localism and the Universality of Science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 42: 590–601. Latour, B. 1993. We Have Never Been Modern, translated by Catherine Porter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1966. Polarity and Analogy: Two Types of Argumentation in Early Greek Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 2007. Cognitive Variations: Reflections on the Unity and Diversity of the Human Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1968. Aristotle: The Growth and Structure of His Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1970. Early Greek Science: Thales to Aristotle. New York: W.W. Norton & Co. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1973. Greek Science After Aristotle. New York: W.W. Norton & Co. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1978. Aristotle on Mind and the Senses. Cambridge Classical Studies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1979. Magic Reason and Experience: Studies in the Origin and Development of Greek Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 57 Lloyd, G. E. R. 1983. Science, Folklore and Ideology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1987. The Revolutions of Wisdom: Studies in the Claims and Practice of Ancient Greek Science. Sather Classical Lectures, 52. Berkeley: University of California Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1990. Demystifying Mentalities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1991. Methods and Problems in Greek Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1992. Methods and Problems in the History of Ancient Science: The Greek Case. Isis 83: 564–77. Lloyd, G. E. R. 1996. Adversaries and Authorities: Investigations into Ancient Greek and Chinese Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 2004. Ancient Worlds, Modern Reflections: Philosophical Perspectives on Greek and Chinese Science and Culture. New York: Oxford University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 2005. The Delusions of Invulnerability: Wisdom and Morality in Ancient Greece, China and Today. London: Duckworth. Lloyd, G. E. R. 2006. Principles and Practices in Ancient Greek and Chinese Science. Variorum Collected Studies Series. Aldershot: Ashgate. Lloyd, G. E. R. 2008. The Varying Agenda of the Study of the Heavens: Mesopotamia, Greece, China. Pp. 69–88 in Star Gazing, Fire Phasing, and Healing in China: Essays in Honor of Nathan Sivin, ed. Michael Nylan. Asia Major 3, 21/1. Taipei Academica Sinica, Institute of History and Philology. Lloyd, G. E. R. 2009. Cognitive Variations: Reflections on the Unity and Diversity of the Human Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R. 2012. Being, Humanity, and Understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lloyd, G. E. R, and N. Sivin. 2003. The Way and the Word: Science and Medicine in Early China and Greece. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Maul, S. M. 1994. Zukunftsbewältigung: Eine Untersuchung Altorientalischen Denkens Anhand Der Babylonisch-Assyrischen Löserituale (Namburbi). Baghdader Forschungen, 18. Mainz: Phillipp von Zabern. Momigliano, A. 1990. Alien Wisdom: The Limits of Hellenization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Neugebauer, O. 1945. The History of Ancient Astronomy: Problems and Methods. JNES 4: 1–38. Neugebauer, O. 1955, 1983. Astronomical Cuneiform Texts (3 vols). London: Lund Humphries. 2nd ed., New York: Springer. Neugebauer, O. 1969. The Exact Sciences in Antiquity. New York: Dover Publications. Neugebauer, O. 1975. A History of Ancient Mathematical Astronomy (3 vols). New York: Springer Verlag. Oppenheim, A. L. 1977. Ancient Mesopotamia: Portrait of a Dead Civilization. Rev. ed. Erica Reiner. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ossendrijver, M. 2011a. Exzellente Netzwerke: Die Astronomen Von Uruk. Pp. 631–44 in The Empirical Dimension of Ancient Near Eastern Studies, eds. G. J. Selz and K. Wagensonner. Wiener Offene Orientalistik, 8. Vienna: LIT Verlag. Ossendrijver, M. 2011b. Science in Action: Networks in Babylonian Astronomy. Pp. 213–21 in Proceedings of the Conference “Babylon–Wissenskultur Zwischen Orient Und Okzident”, Pergamon Museum, Berlin 26-28/6/2008, eds. Eva Cancik-Kirschbaum, Margarete van Ess, and Joachim Marzahn. Berlin: De Gruyter. Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 58 F. Rochberg Ossendrijver, M. 2012. Babylonian Mathematical Astronomy: Procedure Texts. New York: Springer Verlag. Parpola, S. 1970. Letters from Assyrian Scholars to the Kings Esarhaddon and Assurbanipal (vol I). AOAT, 5/1. Kevelaer: Butzon & Bercker. Pingree, D. 1978. The Yavanajātaka of Sphujidhvaja. Harvard Oriental Series, 48. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Pingree, D. 1982. Mesopotamian Astronomy and Astral Omens in Other Civilizations. Pp. 613–31 in Mesopotamien Und Seine Nachbarn. Politische Und Kulturelle Wechselbezeihungen Im Alten Vorderasien Vom 4. Bis 1. Jahrtausend v. Chr, eds. H. Nissen and J. Renger. RAI, 25. Berlin: Reimer. Pingree, D. 1987. Venus Omens in India and Babylon. Pp. 293–315 in Language, Literature, and History: Philological and Historical Studies Presented to Erica Reiner, ed. F. RochbergHalton. AOS, 67. New Haven, CT: American Oriental Society. Pingree, D. 1992. Hellenophilia versus the History of Science. Isis 83: 554–63. Pingree, D. 1997. From Astral Omens to Astrology: From Babylon to Bikaner. Serie Orientale Roma, 78. Rome: Istituto Italiano per l’Africa e l’Oriente. Pingree, D. 1998. Legacies in Astronomy and Celestial Omens. Pp. 125–37 in The Legacy of Mesopotamia, ed. Stephanie Dalley. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Reiner, E., and D. Pingree. 1975. The Venus Tablet of Ammiæaduqa. Babylonian Planetary Omens Part I. Malibu: Undena Publications. Reiner, E., and D. Pingree. 1981. Enūma Anu Enlil, Tablets 50–51. Babylonian Planetary Omens Part II. Malibu: Undena Publications. Reiner, E., and D. Pingree. 1998. Babylonian Planetary Omens. Part III. Cuneiform Monographs, 11. Groningen: Styx Publications. Robson, E. 2001. The Uses of Mathematics in Ancient Iraq (6000–600 BC). Pp. 93–114 in Mathematics Across Cultures: The History of Non-Western Mathematics, ed. Helaine Selin. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Robson, E. 2011. The Production and Dissemination of Scholarly Knowledge. Pp. 557–76 in Handbook of Cuneiform Culture, eds. Karen Radner and Eleanor Robson. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rochberg, F. 1992. The Cultures of Ancient Science: Some Historical Reflections. Isis 83: 547–53. Rochberg, F. 1998. Babyonian Horoscopes. Transactions of the American Philosophical Society, 88. Philadelphia, PA: American Philosophical Society. Rochberg, F. 2000. Scribes and Scholars: The Tupšār Enūma Anu Enlil. Pp. 359–75 in Assyriologica Et Semitica, Festschrift Für Joachim Oelsner Anläßich Seines 65. Geburtstages Am 18. Februar 1997, eds. Joachim Marzahn and Hans Neumann. AOAT, 267. Münster: Ugarit Verlag. Rochberg, F. 2004. The Heavenly Writing. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press. Rochberg, F. 2009. Inference, Conditionals, and Possibility in Ancient Mesopotamian Science. Science in Context 22: 4–25. Rochberg, F. 2010. If P, Then Q: Form, Reasoning and Truth in Babylonian Divination. Pp. 19–27 in Divination and Interpretation of Signs in Antiquity, ed. A. Annus. Chicago: Oriental Institute Publications. Rochberg, F. 2011. Divine Causality and Cuneiform Divination. Pp. 189–203 in A Common Cultural Heritage: Studies in Mesopotamia and the Biblical World in Honor of Barry L. Eichler, eds. Grant Frame, Erle Leichty, Jeffery Tigay, and Steve Tinney. Bethesda, MD: CDL Press. Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM History of Science and Ancient Mesopotamia 59 Rochberg-Halton, F. 1988. Aspects of Babylonian Celestial Divination: The Lunar Eclipse Tablets of Enūma Anu Enlil. AfO Beiheft, 22. Horn: Berger & Söhne. Rouse, J. 1991. Philosophy of Science and the Persistent Narratives of Modernity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 22: 141–62. Rutz, M. 2013. Bodies of Knowledge in Ancient Mesopotamia: The Diviners of Late Bronze Age Emar and Their Tablet Collection. Ancient Magic and Divination, 9. Leiden and Boston: Brill. Sachs, A. J. with the cooperation of J. Schaumberger. 1955. Late Babylonian Astronomical and Related Texts Copied by T.G. Pinches and J.N. Strassmaier. Providence: Brown University Press. Sachs, A. J., and H. Hunger. 1988. Astronomical Diaries and Related Texts from Babylonia, Volume 1 – Diaries from 652 B.C. to 262 B.C., Denkschriften (Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften. Philosophisch-Historische Klasse) 195. Bd. Wien: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Sachs, A. J., and H. Hunger. 1989. Astronomical Diaries and Related Texts from Babylonia, Volume 2 – Diaries from 261 B.C. to 165 B.C., Denkschriften (Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften. Philosophisch-Historische Klasse) 210. Bd. Wien: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Sachs, A. J., and H. Hunger. 1996. Astronomical Diaries and Related Texts from Babylonia, Volume 3 – Diaries from 164 B.C. to 61 B.C., Denkschriften (Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften. Philosophisch-Historische Klasse) 246. Bd. Wien: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Schuster-Brandis, A. 2008. Steine Als Schutz- Und Heilmittel: Untersuchung Zu Ihrer Verwendung in Der Beschwörungskunst Mesopotamiens Im 1. Jt. v. Chr. Münster: UgaritVerlag. Scurlock, J. 2006. Magico-Medical Means of Treating Ghost-Induced Illnesses in Ancient Mesopotamia. Ancient Magic and Divination, 3. Leiden: Brill. Scurlock, J, and B. Andersen. 2005. Diagnoses in Assyrian and Babylonian Medicine: Ancient Sources, Translations, and Modern Medical Analyses. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press. Selin, H. (ed.). 2000. Mathematics across cultures: the history of non-western mathematics, Science Across Cultures: The History of Non-Western Science, Vol. 2. Dordrecht; Boston: Kluwer Academic. Selin, H. (ed.). 2008. Encyclopedia of the History of Science, Technology, and Medicine in NonWestern Cultures. 2nd ed. New York: Springer Verlag. van Soldt, W. 1995. Solar Omens of Enūma Anu Enlil: Tablets 23 (24)-29 (30). Uitgaven van het Nederlands Historisch-Archaeologisch Instituut te Istanbul, 73. Leiden: Nederlands Instituut voor het Nabije Oosten. von Staden, H. 1992. Affinities and Elisions: Helen and Hellenocentrism. Isis 83: 578–95. Stadhouders, H. 2011. The Pharmacopoeial Handbook Šammu Šikinšu: An Edition. Journal Des Médecines Cunéiformes 18: 3–51. Stadhouders, H. 2012. The Pharmacopoeial Handbook Šammu Šikinšu: A Translation. Journal Des Médecines Cunéiformes 19: 1–20. Steele, J. M. 2000a. Observations and Predictions of Eclipse Times by Early Astronomers. Archimedes, 4. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Steele, J. M. 2000b. Eclipse Prediction in Mesopotamia. Archive for History of Exact Sciences 54: 421–54. Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM 60 F. Rochberg Steele, J. M. 2007a. The Length of the Month in Mesopotamian Calendars of the First Millennium BC. Pp. 133–48 in Calendars and Years: Astronomy and Time in the Ancient Near East, ed. John M. Steele. Oxford: Oxbow Books. Steele, J. M. 2007b. Celestial Measurement in Babylonian Astronomy. Annals of Science 64: 293–325. Steele, J. M. 2011a. Making Sense of Time: Observational and Theoretical Calendars. Pp. 470–85 in Oxford Handbook of Cuneiform Culture, eds. Karen Radner and Eleanor Robson. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Steele, J. M. 2011b. Goal-Year Periods and Their Use in Predicting Planetary Phenomena. Pp. 101–10 in The Empirical Dimension of Ancient Near Eastern Studies, eds. Gebhard J. Selz and Klaus Wagensonner. Berlin: LIT Verlag. Steele, J. M., and A. Imhausen. 2002. Under One Sky: Astronomy and Mathematics in the Ancient Near East. Münster: Ugarit Verlag. Swerdlow, N. M. 1998. The Babylonian Theory of the Planets. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Veldhuis, N. in press. History of the Cuneiform Lexical Tradition. GMTR, 6. Münster: Ugarit Verlag. Verderame, L. 2002. Le Tavole I-VI Della Serie Astrologica Enūma Anu Enlil. Nisaba, 2. Messina: DiScAM. Yglesias, E. 2000. Greece: General Works. Pp. 311–12 in Reader’s Guide to the History of Science, ed. Arne Hessenbruch. London: Routledge. Unauthenticated Download Date | 6/16/17 1:59 AM