Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND SCHOOL OF PUBLIC POLICY COMPREHENSIVE EXAMINATION IN CORE SUBJECTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY NORMATIVE ANALYSIS Monday, June 2, 2008 This examination tests your understanding of topics in normative analysis drawn from the reading list assigned to help you prepare for this examination. Be sure to make use of the readings, as appropriate, in framing your answers. A point weighting is listed beside each question, along with a suggested time allocation. Answer the question in Section One and three of four questions in Section Two. Section One: General Question (40 points; roughly 3 hours) Rawls’s Theory of Justice renewed political philosophy, as well ethics and public policy in English-speaking countries and elsewhere. Discuss what you take to be Rawls’s most important claims or arguments about distributive justice. Now take two political philosophers – one classical and one contemporary -- and analyze how the two would criticize Rawls’s position on distributive justice. How would (or did) Rawls respond to these critics? Finally, in your view to what extent can Rawls answer his critics and to what extent have they uncovered serious weaknesses in his thought? What ways, if any, might a Rawlsian employ to overcome these weaknesses? The Contribution of Rawls Rawls has been hailed as one of the most important modern contributors to ethics and public policy. He is often contributed with reviving liberal political philosophy since at the time many believed the dominant concept behind the liberty of an individual was only possible at the expense of social ills such as inequality. Rawls’s theory, called “justice as fairness”, attempts to demonstrate that it is possible to reconcile the liberty of the individual and society’s ability to redress inequality and injustice. Traditional social contract theory includes a hypothesized “state of nature” prior to the formation of government and society. This state of nature is commonly used to demonstrate the reason 1 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 behind joining one another and forming society, “the legitimacy of government derives, thus, from the consent of the governed, and the social contract approach provides a vehicle for attempting to specify the proper role of government, its purpose and limits (Arther and Shaw).” Rawls believes each person possesses an inherent right to liberty that cannot be overruled even for the betterment of the society as a whole. In a just society, he argues, the liberties of equal citizenship are taken as settled. In forming the original position, he is concerned with the basic structure of society, in other words the major social institutions that distribute fundamental rights and determine the division of advantages among citizens. His focus is the distribution of inequalities that exist based on merit or desert, meaning those who are favored in some societies simply because they enjoy a better starting place than others. Rawls uses the social contract model to propose principles he believes free and rational persons would choose to govern their society if they were brought together in an imaginary “original position”. For Rawls, the original position of equality corresponds to the state of nature in traditional social contract theory. The original position is used to create a situation where all present are under a “veil of ignorance” in regards to their position in society, thereby making each equal. This will set up a fair procedure in order to allow the formation of just principles to be agreed upon. "Since all are similarly situated [in the original position] and no one is able to design principles to favor his particular condition, the principles of justice are the result of a fair agreement or bargain ... This explains the propriety of the name 'justice as fairness': it conveys the idea that the principles of justice are agreed to in an initial situation that is fair." Race, gender, class, income, intelligence, social position etc. are all unknown under the veil of ignorance. Parties also do not know the conditions of their society; instead “the only particular facts which the parties know is that their society is subject to the circumstances of justice and whatever this implies.” In addition, they know general facts about human society including political affairs and principles of economic theory. Rawls assumes those in the original position to be rational persons, connecting his theory of justice to the theory of rational choice. The original position assures that these rational persons will not make decisions based on his or her personal status or conception of the good since in the original position that information is not known. “The assumptions of mutually disinterested rationality, then, comes to this: the persons in the original position try to acknowledge principles which advance their system of ends as far as possible.” Initially, Rawls maintains that persons in the original position under the veil of ignorance will choose two principles of justice: “First: each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive basic liberty for others. Second: social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both (a) reasonably expected to be to everyone’s advantage, and (b) attached to positions and offices open to all.” These principles are prioritized and the first principle cannot be overridden by other 2 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 considerations. This priority maintains that those in the original position have no desire to try for greater gains at the expense of equal liberties. The second principle, part b, called the fair equality of opportunity, cannot be overridden by any circumstances of social or economic advantage. Part a cannot be overridden by considerations of efficiency or maximization of social welfare. In other words, not only does Rawls formulate principles of justice but he stipulates rules and priority in conjunction with them. In addition, these principles are concerned with the distribution of primary goods, “things that every rational man is presumed to want”, and those in the original position are determining the distribution of social primary goods rather than natural goods. Rawls gave names to each of the four possible systems produced by combining these possible combinations, but argued that “Democratic Equality” was the one that people would choose behind the “veil of ignorance.” “Everyone’s Advantage” “Equally Open” Principle of Efficiency Difference Principle Careers open to talents System of Natural Liberty Natural Aristocracy Equality of fair opportunity Liberal Equality Democratic Equality The democratic interpretation is arrived at by combining the principle of fair equality of opportunity and the difference principle. The difference principle is the idea that “the higher expectations of those better situated are just if and only if they work as part of a scheme which improves the expectations of the least advantaged members of society.” Society should not work to establish and secure the prospects of those better off unless doing so is to the advantage of those less fortunate. After consideration, he reformulates the Second Principle as “Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity.” Criticism of Rawls: Hobbes Hobbes insists that the state of nature, or a condition of no government, is one that deteriorates into a war of all of against all. In this state of nature, people enjoy equality of liberty and scarce resources, a world where there in only concern for oneself and no way to mediate disputes. In order to survive, Hobbes maintains that people will go to any means to survive and obtain their 3 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 objects of desire. According to Hobbes, all members will live in “continual fear, and danger of violent death; and the life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” Despite the view that men are selfish and dangerous, Hobbes also believes that men are intelligent and will recognize the benefits of peace. He argues that several laws will come out of this desire for security; first and foremost, men will “lay down” their rights in order to achieve a state of peace. Since words are not enough to bind such an agreement, the only answer is coercive power in the form of a monarch. Hobbes argues that the only way to achieve a successful state is for everyone to select, relinquish their rights to, and obey a sovereign. In this state, liberty is not viewed as individual liberty but the liberty of the commonwealth. The state must be free to do as it sees fit, the sovereign’s power is absolute. Any redistribution of goods is up to the discretion of the monarch. In other words, if the King sees fit to redistribute wealth to the poor, then the rich must surrender their goods in order to fulfill the mandate. But citizens are not a part of the deliberation or decision when it comes to distribution, since in order to achieve peace they agreed to forfeit their rights to the sovereign. Individual liberty is restricted only to areas in which the monarch has not seen fit to create rules. In addition, justice is entrusted to an arbitrator to determine what is due. Hobbes claims that this person will provide “equal distribution to each man of that which in reason belongs to him.” This reason has to do with past promises and the notion of merit. While Rawls and Hobbes both utilize social contract for their foundation of justice and society, their view on human nature and the elements of a secure state vary widely. Hobbes would invariably maintain that Rawls is naïve in his understanding of humans and discount the original position as implausible. Humans are driven by “a perpetual and restless desire of power after power” that must be controlled. Hobbes believes the only way to create a secure society is through absolute power and sovereignty, absent this there will be disagreements, paralysis of effective government, and ultimately degeneration into a civil war over these disputes. Criticism of Rawls: Nozick Robert Nozick values liberty above all things. His work, Anarchy, State and Utopia, considers whether economic inequality warrants or justifies coercive action by the state and provides an extensive critique of Rawls’s theory of justice. In general, Nozick contends that distribution is just if it adheres to three characteristics: The original acquisition of a holding is just; Subsequent acquisition of this holding is just, i.e. the transfer is just; No one else is entitled to that holding. And in sum, if each person’s holdings are just, then the total set (or distribution) of holdings is just. He argues that as long as there is liberty, people will make transactions that alter whatever distribution exists, using his famous Wilt Chamberlain example to demonstrate this point. He 4 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 states, “no end-state principle or distributional patterned principle of justice can be continuously realized without continuous interference with people’s lives”. In the end, Nozick believes no distribution freely arrived at will likely fit a pattern of distribution and is thus a violation of people’s rights. He believes end-state principles, such as taxation, give individuals in society a claim on the products produced by others, regardless of how the producer wants to dispose of the holdings. He rejects any interference with the process of free exchange by the government and believes only redistribution resulting from free transfers of legitimately acquired property will be just. In his critique of Rawls, Nozick begins with his issues around the original position. While Rawls is concerned with showing what is just for the least advantaged in society, Nozick is concerned with why the most advantaged in society would agree to such a system. He argues that the difference principle is not realistic, and would only apply in the special case where distribution of holdings “fell from heaven like manna”. He argues that more commonly the size of the pie is not fixed, but instead can be enlarged due to the unequal application of effort by members of society, in which case unequal distribution seems just. He accuses Rawls’s conception of only considering end-state principles since it does not allow for any consideration of historical or entitlement principles. While Rawls rejects unequal distribution of national assets as being “arbitrary from a moral point of view”, Nozick believes such rejection rejects national liberty. He says this will serve to “denigrate a person’s autonomy and prime responsibilities for his actions” in the process. In addition, Nozick takes exception to Rawls’s “distribution of the treatment of natural abilities as viewed as a ‘collective asset’”. He contends that such an approach “does not take seriously the distinction between persons”. In sum, Nozick states, “People’s talents and abilities are an asset to a free community; others in the community benefit from their presence and are better off because they are there rather than elsewhere or nowhere.” Rawls’s Response Rawls disagrees with Hobbes on the fundamental characteristics of human nature. He contends humans are not irredeemably self-centered or singularly driven by power but instead have the capacity for toleration and mutual respect. This leads Rawls to believe that humans will ultimately endorse and accept a democratic regime rather than a monarchy made of absolute power. He maintains that citizens are reasonable and would therefore accept diversity within reason, such as religious tolerance. In addition, he believes the focal point for all reasonable citizens is liberty, and given its place of protection in justice as fairness people will act in ways that are just if place under the veil of ignorance in the original position. In addition, Rawls would take exception of Hobbes’s view that the only stable society is one ruled by an absolute sovereign. Rawls will maintain that a society whose conception of justice is justice as fairness will be more stable since it promotes people’s natural inclination toward 5 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 reciprocity. He assumes three things about the conditions under which humans form reciprocal relationships with one another: (1) When family institutions are just, children will come to love their parents because they promote their children’s good in ways that are obvious to them. (2) When social arrangements are just and publicly known, people will develop a sense of goodwill and trust toward one another as they will realize that others will honor their obligation as defined by this public conception of justice. (3) When social arrangements are just and publicly known, people will endorse this concept of justice when they and the people they care for benefit from those social arrangements. Upon seeing these benefits, people will come to endorse the system of justice and work to protect the system. This in turn promotes stability. These conditions all hold under Rawls’s theory of justice as fairness. Rawls has often been criticized by Nozick and others for the assumption that those in the original position would realistically agree to his system of justice. He contends however, that those in the original position are unaware of not only their position in society but are also the probabilities surrounding these positions once the veil of ignorance is lifted. The “maximin” rule directs them to consider the worst possible outcome that can happen under a proposed course of action. These are grave consequences, with extreme situations like abject poverty, slavery, etc., and are therefore outcomes that no rational person could accept for themselves. Since the rule takes no account of the likelihood of being the one to live under those conditions, and the outcomes are so severe, no rational human is going to risk that they will be on the extreme upper end of society versus the extreme lower end. In response to Nozick’s notion of autonomy and abilities, Rawls would agree people should be able to do what they want with their natural abilities (unless using those talents in a certain way violates other people’s rights), but disagrees with the fact that people are entitled to everything they produce or acquire. He argues that people do not deserve their talents and abilities; thus, there is no reason people deserve everything they produce using these abilities. Rawls maintains that it is not a violation of liberty or autonomy for the state to require you to live up to your moral responsibilities for those less fortunate than you are. For example, if the government requires employers to pay “fair” wages, the state is not only treating employees as ends rather than means but also the employers as well since the wages reflect the value of the employees’ marginal contribution to their product. If an employer exploits his employees by treating them unfairly he does not have any right to the profit that results from that exploitation, even if these employees voluntarily chose to work for them (rather than starving). Regulating economic transfers to promote distributive justice therefore does not violate anyone’s rights, as Nozick would maintain. In other words, Rawls would argue that the notion of “voluntary” transfer is simply too thin and assumes a formal notion of autonomy. He takes issue with Nozick’s assumption that unless someone is holding a gun to your head, then your action if voluntary. When people are in radically different positions of power, one cannot say those in the lower position are always making a voluntary choice if the options are subsistence wage or starving. To ensure justice, we must ensure that choices are made voluntarily and freely. 6 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 An Evaluation of the Critics and Rawls In my view Rawls has sufficiently answered much of the criticism outlined above; however, there does still seem to be areas for improvement. It should be noted that our reading list contained Rawls’s Theory of Justice as part of Arthur and Shaw’s Justice and Distribution, so I have not read other works by Rawls such as Law of Peoples. Therefore, I am hesitant to make blanket statements on Rawls’s shortcomings and I hope you will allow for some ignorance on my part when reading my assertions. First, Rawls does not seem to fully answer the question of natural abilities and their place in society. Can looking only at social primary goods be the best way to assess people’s overall well being? What about those with severe handicaps or disabilities? Someone with special needs may require a greater portion of certain primary goods like medicine and special equipment in order to have the same quality of life as those without special needs. Rawls’s discount of natural goods would seem to indicate that it is unjust to compensate them in this way as he is only concerned with social primary goods. Secondly, Rawlsians should also answer more fully the recognition of the influence of ambition in his theory of justice. If one person in society works extremely hard to maximize is earning and output, should that person be taxed to subsidize habits of those with equal abilities but less ambition to work for their living? Personally, I believe this is an oversimplification of Rawls’s theory, but it is a common critique of which I have not seen a thorough response. Finally, Sen argues that the issue with Rawls Theory of Justice is not “the comparative importance of rights, but their absolute priority.” He argues that while liberty should be a priority, it should not have more prominence than other rights as it misses the need to evaluate the overall individual’s own personal advantage. In other words, the Rawlsian Difference Principle is good but not good enough. Sen agrees with the critique above that a strict equation cannot be drawn between primary goods and well-being because the former cannot always be converted into the latter. In general, Rawls’s theory of justice, the difference principle and the idea of the original position has made an enormous contribution to ethics and public policy. It is difficult to find a theory that is perfect, but this work provides an important framework and foundation for justice and distribution in society. 7 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 Section Two: Special Topics (20 points each; roughly 1 1/2 hours per question.) Remember: answer three out of four. 1. Identify and explain the moral or ethical issues—in contrast to the economic or political issues—implicit or explicit in the current US debate or global debate about one of the following topics: the world food crisis, terrorism, or the logging of the Amazon. Use this debate to clarify the value but also the limits of normative or ethical analysis in public policy formation. Anticipate and respond to at least one objection to your argument. I will address the issue of the world food crisis and the ethical debate surrounding it. First, since “world food crisis” is somewhat vague, for the purposes of my discussion I will discuss this in terms of the increase in incidences of hunger and famine in the world’s poorest countries due to the rising costs of food. Ethical and moral questions are raised in regards to our responsibilities to those affected. Do we have a moral obligation to the world’s poor who are starving as a result of this crisis? In my opinion, the ethical and moral issues are many and in some ways outweigh the economic or political ones. If we have a responsibility to assist, is that responsibility one of charity (or beneficence) on the part of those countries able to assist? Or is it one of justice and human rights? These are difficult but important questions when it comes to issues such as this. Libertarians such as Robert Nozick would argue that we have no responsibility other than perhaps charity to assist in the world food crisis. Charity is morally good but not required by justice as he would say it would infringe on economic rights of those in the wealthier countries to tax them or use their money to assist in this crisis. In effect you are treating those citizens a means to an end and that is unjust. Since citizens are born autonomous with the ability to provide for themselves, you do not have a right to interfere with one for the benefit of another. On the other hand one could argue that our goal should be to maximize global utility, and the marginal benefit of our aid dollars to those in poverty is far greater than it is to those in affluent countries, therefore total utility is raised by our giving a great deal of development aid or humanitarian aid. Utilitarians such as Singer would contend that “if it in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it.” If we accept the Utilitarian approach, we would solve this problem by working out which of the many courses of action we might take produce the most happiness or utility. However O’Neill argues that this approach, given its dependence on results, would not be useful without accurate information. Since the many different reasons for the world food crisis as well as various studies debating the best course of action, we do not have sufficient information to approach the problem from a purely utilitarian perspective. In terms of the debate between beneficence and justice, O’Neill argues that “we may not be able to pick out any central core of perfect duties to which utilitarians are stringently bound. When all duties are fundamentally a matter of beneficence, our only obligation is to do whatever is needed to maximize happiness.” In other words, utilitarians would argue we may have an imperfect duty to charity (as Nozick notes above) but not a perfect duty of justice to assist in cases of hunger and famine. “If utilitarians cannot draw a clear distinction between the requirements of 8 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 beneficence and those of justice, we cannot hope for more accuracy in matters of justice than the theory as a whole offers us.” Kant on the other hand posits a theory of human obligations. O’Neill mentions the “Formula of the End in Itself: Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means but always at the same time as an end.” Kant believes we should judge the underlying principles of the act and those principles should follow the above formula. You will have different principles as long as they avoid treating people as mere means. Kant believes that we cannot use others as mere means if what we do reflects some principle to which they could not consent. O’Neill posits, “The more vulnerable the other party in any transaction or negotiation the less that party’s scope for refusal, and the more demanding it is likely to ensure that action is non coercive… In Kant’s view acts done on maxims that endanger, coerce, or deceive others, and thus cannot in principle have the consent of those others, are wrong.” Thus, she concludes that Kantians are required to do what they can to “avert, reduce and remedy hunger.” In Kant’s reasoning, we have a duty of beneficence rather than justice, but he defines beneficence as more than charity. He believes that justice is a perfect duty and beneficence is an imperfect duty, but he does not believe beneficence is any less a duty; rather, he holds that it has (unlike justice) to be selective. “Duties of beneficence arise whenever destitution puts the possibility of autonomous action in question for the more vulnerable.” Finally, O’Neill concludes that both theories, utilitarian and Kantian, will get us to the same conclusion; that is, we must be concerned about these issues of hunger and put our efforts where they would bear fruit. In addition, she argues that we must be concerned both locally and globally. She contends that helping our neighbors does not excuse us from helping those in distant countries as well. “In a world in which action affects distant others, justice cannot be local or national boundaries: there is no such thing as social justice in one country.” O’Neill’s last point raises an additional argument among human rights theorists. What responsibility do we have to those outside our borders? Nationalists would argue that we have none. The nationalist view contends there are few causal connections between different countries. Walzer (as stated by Orend) calls this the “relative self-enclosure” thesis, meaning that since nations are relatively self-enclosed they have little causal impact on one another. It follows that little can then be demanded from foreign nations in terms of assisting citizens from other countries with human rights. Beitz lists skeptics as those who view international relations the same as the Hobbsian state of nature, a constant state of war where international morality is national self-interest only. He also notes the statist argument, meaning states are viewed as autonomous and the only morality is national sovereignty. Beitz’s view (which I endorse), also called the cosmopolitan view, would argue that today states are interdependent therefore international morality should be distributive justice. Orend agrees with Beitz’s view of international relations as do I. While it may have been true in 9 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 the past that nations are mainly independent, it is definitely untrue now given our global society. Today countries have significant impact on one another, both those nearby and across the globe. Orend argues that if our actions impact the human rights of those outside our borders we should bear duties correlative to such rights. While the heaviest burden falls on the country’s national government, this does not mean we have no moral obligations at all. Since there are causal connections that cross borders, then there are moral demands do a swell. Referring to Walzer’s universally shared thin moral code, Orend notes that one can assume that we share a sense of morality and human rights around the globe. In other words, the most important and fundamental requirements of morality and justice are shared worldwide and are not altered dramatically across borders as the traditionalist view suggests. While this does not suggest we owe citizens of other countries the same as we do our own, it does imply that we owe them something. In summary, all of us, individuals and institutions, bear duties in regards to human rights and these duties stretch beyond our borders throughout the globe. “The general principle is this: the more power and influence one has over the objects of another’s vital needs, the greater the degree of responsibility one has in connection with that person’s human rights.” Orend notes, in regard to our duty to the poorest of the poor, we have a responsibility to a global realization of human rights. As citizens of comparatively privileged countries, we have an international responsibility do our fair share to ensure that poor countries at least have enough to fund a minimally decent life for all their people. In other words, establish genuinely global protections for everyone against the infliction of grievous and unjust harm, which may imply a duty of development assistance, or resource transfer, form the wealthiest nations to the poorest. This is not to establish dependence, but instead to create a stable and sustainable human rights respecting institution within the countries genuinely needing the assistance. He cites Sen’s assertion that the main cause behind famine has been corrupt local and evil local institutions, not a genuine lack of food to argue for international monitoring of aid as well as the need for human rights respecting institutions. One can see that a moral discussion around our responsibility regarding the world food crisis in imperative to determining actions and policy. But one can also see that there is little agreement on our best course of action and the level of involvement required. Even moral theories that resolve our responsibility to assist differ widely on how to proceed in that assistance. But despite these difficulties, can one argue that our analysis of an issue such as the world food crisis should be on political and economic methods alone? I strongly pose the answer is no. Without dialog around moral obligations our decisions would be greatly flawed and the outcomes perhaps unacceptable. 10 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 2. Compare and contrast the views of two thinkers, one classical and one contemporary, on the question of humanitarian military intervention. Articulate what these thinkers said (or would say) on the subject, and explain why their views differ, and what policy implications that difference would have in the contemporary context. When, if ever, is it in fact morally right or obligatory for one or more states to use military force within a sovereign state (without that state's consent) where human rights abuses are occurring or have occurred? What are the strengths and weaknesses of each approach and which do you think is on balance best? Why? Anticipate and respond to one objection to your argument. Machiavelli Machiavelli argues that authority and power are equal and that whoever has power has the right to command. The only real concern for a ruler is the acquisition and maintenance of power and the use of this power to maintain the state. In terms of morality, he believes there is no moral basis to judge legitimate and illegitimate power. Goodness and right (to authority) is not sufficient to win and maintain political power. The ruler must maintain the safety and security of the state and should use any means of power necessary to do so (including the use of force). Machiavelli poses that the legitimacy of law rest entirely on the threat of coercive force so rulers must have the ability to use it in order to maintain authority. Machiavelli shares a very pessimistic view of mankind with Hobbes and observes that “one can say this in general of men: they are ungrateful, disloyal, insincere and deceitful, timid of danger and avid of profit…. Love is a bond of obligation which these miserable creatures break whenever it suits them to do so; but fear holds them fast by a dread of punishment that never passes”. In order to maintain order and stability, the Prince as a head of state ought to do good if he can, but must be prepared to commit evil if he must. Machiavelli has also been credited with formulating for the first time the modern concept of the state. In addition, his teachings are also closely related to many ideas behind the sovereign state. While he did not write explicitly about the concept, his ideas amounted in substance to important developments behind the idea. To many theorists, the idea of sovereignty applies both internally and externally. Sovereign authority is exercised both within borders and by definition against outsiders so they will not interfere with governance. This has been described as constitutional independence, or a state’s freedom from influence upon its rights. The concept is similar to the one describe by Beitz as the statist position, whereas states are autonomous and the basis of international morality is sovereignty. In terms of policy, there is no room for intervention unless that state’s sovereignty has been infringed upon. Walzer Michael Walzer agrees that states have territorial and sovereign rights. These rights are comparable to individual rights such as life and liberty. In other words, states have a right to self-determination. States, as with individuals, cannot be attacked by other states except with 11 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 their right of sovereignty have been forfeited. Any violation of these rights without cause can be deemed as aggression and that is not permissible. Unlike a Machiavellian framework of absolute sovereignty, Walzer’s theory of just war provides circumstances in which states lose their right to self-determination. “The ban on boundary crossings is subject to unilateral suspension” when the issue regards: 1. 2. 3. 4. aggression, which justifies a repellent of preemptive attack succession or national liberation counter-intervention cases of enslavement or massacre The fourth case is at issue in this question as it regards humanitarian intervention. A nation or state enjoys legitimacy based on its ability to maintain order in a political community. This community is made up of the people in that state. If the government turns savagely on its own people we have a reason to doubt the existence of such a community and must therefore doubt its legitimacy. In effect, the state loses its rights when it violates its political community. Walzer states, “If the dominant forces within a state are engaged in massive violations of human rights, the appeal to self-determination in the Millian sense of self-help is not very attractive… And when a government turns savagely upon its own people, we must doubt the very existence of a political community to which the idea of self-determination might apply.” Intervention is justified on a moral justification if the acts “shock the moral conscience of mankind”. Because it is a moral question, states do not need to wait for permission to invade and this includes waiting for the UN. Walzer summarizes, “The second, third, and fourth revisions of the paradigm have this form: states can be invaded and wars justly begun to assist secessionist movements (once they have demonstrated their representative character), to balance the prior interventions of other powers, and to rescue people threatened with massacre. In each of these cases we permit or, after the fact, we praise or don’t condemn these violations of the formal rules of sovereignty, because they uphold the values of individual life and communal liberty of which sovereignty itself is merely an expression.” The policy implications are clear unless the international community cannot or will not determine whether acts “shock the conscious of mankind”. Over 800,000 people died in Rwanda while the UN deliberated whether the case fell under the category of genocide. Walzer’s implications are clear; however, his definitions can be a source of debate. When Do We Intervene? Walzer suggests it is morally right and obligatory for states to use military force in the case of extreme acts against humanity. Of course, he posits that this intervention must be done in a way that supports the local population and is consistent with the rights of the population it is claiming to assist. 12 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 This argument is sufficient for the grossest human rights violations, but what about those that are less flagrant? For example, what about the instance of Burma who refuses to allow victims of the cyclone aid thus in some cases systematically starving them to death and exposing them to life-threatening diseases. Is that a case for intervention? Many human rights theorist propose that there is a universal moral code. Walzer in other works details the concept of thick and think morality. As cited in Orend, he contends individual rights to life and liberty underlie the most important judgments we make about how we should treat one another and how we create the society that we share. These rights, natural or invented, “are somehow entailed by our sense of what it means to be a human being.” He maintains that human rights are a palpable feature of our moral world, and they are obvious and elemental moral commitments shared by all humans. He lists two kinds of morally that we share in this moral world, thick and thin. “Thick, or “maximal”, morality is the sum total of the moral beliefs and ethical practices in a given country or culture.” Walzer contends it is relative to time and place and thus differs from one setting to another. Beliefs about sex and relationships are an example as this could be called a part of a culture’s moral code. The legal system is another example. Thin morality is “minimal and universal” according to Walzer. He believes there exists one universal thin moral code that is “largely negative” consisting of bans on the “the grossest injustices” like “murder, deception, betrayal, gross cruelty, torture, oppression, tyranny” etc. While this is not the one true or universal morality, it is “that core set of values we find reiterated in every thick moral and political code.” In short, it is those moral values that we as human share, everyone everywhere believes in them. Walzer understands human rights to be these universal and mainly negative core and primary entitlements we all have. He also believes that thin morality serves as a check on thick morality and insists that any government that violates thin morality is unjust. Appeal to thick cultural particularities cannot justify violations of the thin moral code. I Shue maintains that to enjoy many first-generation human rights requires the exercise of positive and costly duties. He agrees with the traditional definition of positive and negative duties, however he argues that correlative to any single human right is not just a negative or positive duty, but a mixture of duties. He argues for three: 1) negatively, not to deprive someone of the object of his/her right 2) positively, to protect someone in possession of the object of his/her right 3) positively, to aid the person, should someone still manage to violate her or her right. He maintains that the performance of these duties is mandatory to supply everyone of the object of their rights. Human rights are protected only when relevant actors and institutions fulfill the following duties: “1) all persons refrains from violating the right; 2) effective institutions exist to protect the object of the right 3) all those in a position to do so come to one’s aid in case such protection fails.” 13 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 Orend (and I concur) maintains that the duties correlative to human rights are all duties of justice, which are normatively negative duties that are considered imperative to perform. He rejects the idea that human rights are benevolent or normatively positive duties where one considers human rights as something we “ought” to do. I conclude therefore it is our moral obligation to intervene in the case of humanitarian intervention and in order to do so we must further define Walzer’s definition of “shock against humanity” and thin morality. Hampton advocates what she calls “convention consent” to the regime, that as along as their behavior supports or at least doesn’t undermine the consent of the people. A regime that receives what Hampton calls endorsement consent gets from its subjects not just activity that maintains it but also activity that conveys their endorsement and approval of it. She asks, “How can one defend political authority if it has a relationship with dissidents that cannot be morally defended?” The same can be asked of the relationship among its people in general. A minimally moral state should include more than protection from genocide, it should be protected from extreme neglect from its government, such as those that allow their citizens to starve while investing in senseless civil war, weapons, and personal riches. A place to start is Orend’s general principle that the more power and influence one has over the objects of another’s vital needs, the greater the degree of responsibility one has in connection with that person’s human rights. He argues for establishing genuinely global protections for everyone against the infliction of grievous and unjust harm, which can be used for intervention rules as well. Many of the arguments to this position have been outlined elsewhere in this essay and the previous one as well. This includes the objection that we are not responsible for citizens outside of our border and a stern commitment to state sovereignty as a right regardless of a government’s treatment of its people. Probably the argument most legitimate one is noted by Luban, who notes the average American does not necessarily believe we should sacrifice money, resources, and human lives for humanitarian reasons. Yet with education and a true international definition of human rights, citizens will become more accepting of our responsibility and regimes more reluctance to commit such atrocities. Without a true effort and commitment to intervention, there is no incentive for improvement around the gravest human rights violations. The condition of many in our society today are dependent on our furthering this issue and settling the debate. 14 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 3. What do you consider to be the most important (classical or contemporary) challenges to democracy as a mode of political governance? Now distinguish two ways in which defenders of democracy have sought to meet this challenge. Which way is most convincing? Why? Anticipate and respond to at least one objection to your position. Challenge to Democracy The most important challenge to democracy is the assertion that people are not qualified to run their own country. Plato’s argument is one of the most important in this regard. He saw both democracy (all the people ruled, the many) and oligarchy (few elite ruled) as both exploitative and in the self interest of the rulers. In the Republic, he shows that oligarchy and democracy could descend into tyranny. His objection to democracy is that it did not have an objective standard of value and does not require people to follow reason. It leaves it open for people to vote on the basis of their passions, their fears, their most irrational judgments, and for Plato the most important thing was to be governed by reason. It should try to aim at what is generally good not just what works best for the individual. He discussed the analogy of a ship where you would want the caption to be steering rather than the crew given his higher level of expertise. The same holds true for politics. In his opinion this led to the conclusion that we should be ruled by philosophers because of their love of reason and because it is they who wanted to rule the least. This absence of desire meant they could not be corrupted and would rule from the expertise of the good for all of society. He argues that this will benefit the people the best, that the point is not to control them but to give them enough discipline and order to set them free. While much of Plato’s conclusions in the Republic (like state controlled breeding, the raising of gold children and rampant censorship) is obviously disturbing, I could not help to see the value behind his argument around reason. As I watched our political candidates take shots and drink beer, be advised to sound “less intelligent” and disregard the “elite” opinion of economists, I could not help but wonder about our system of democracy. When did intelligence and reason become replaced by the need to woo the “white, working class voter?” Is this incentive to defy reason and experience when necessary best for our politics and our government? Dahl disagrees with Plato’s arguments and refutes the idea of guardianship in several ways. First he claims there is no common good, only the interests and “good” of the members of the community. These members are the only ones that know best what their interests include. Second, there is no science that combines all of the moral and intellectual knowledge necessary to run a complex modern state. No one person or small group of people can possibly have all of the knowledge needed around the complex issues of today. Third, the most important political decisions involve value questions, not technical questions, which are best left to the members of the community. Finally, leaders such as the philosopher kings described by Plato do not exist. Humans are fallible and there are limits to their knowledge. In addition, Dahl argues that an imperfect democracy is misfortune for its people, while an imperfect authoritarian regime is an “abomination”. If we seek to choose a strategy that seeks to choose the best of the worst outcomes, guardianship will not come close. 15 School of Public Policy Ph.D. First Year Comprehensive Examination, Normative Analysis, Spring 2008 109615822 Of these arguments, I believe the strongest is the argument surrounding a guardian’s ability to understand the common good. Individuals understand what is best for them and given the diversity of most countries, it is impossible for a philosopher king to know what is best for each individual and then determine a best outcome for the greater good. One could argue though that the general good is not simply an aggregation of individual interests and therefore takes understanding of how it differs. If it is true that most people are mainly concerned with their own self-interest, then isn’t also true that most people cannot be counted on to understand or act on the behalf of the greater good? If this is the case, then one can argue that it is better to entrust the task of deciding the general good to persons trained to understand how to bring it about. Again, this leads us back to Dahl’s argument that there is no such training and a difficulty finding a conclusive rational basis for judgments such as the general good. He argues that no set of guardians could reasonably sustain the claim that they possessed a “science of ruling” which consists of “objectively true” knowledge of the public good. In addition, Sen points to studies which have shown there is little evidence that authoritarian governments are beneficial to economic development, nor has there been shown a link to a general conflict between political freedoms and economic performance. He points democracy as the best form of government that allows people to express their needs and generate a response to those needs. Governmental response to the acute suffering of people often depends on the pressure that is put on government, or the exercising of political rights. This relates to the instrumental role in democracy as noted above and the incentives the system places on the actions of the government. In the end, democracy is founded on the concept of equality, or as Dahl calls it, the idea of intrinsic equality. In addition, he points to the principle of equal consideration which holds that since we are all of equal worth, our interests deserve equal consideration in the political process. Dahl contends democracy promotes individual and collective freedom, human development and is the surest process that allows people to protect and advance their interests and conceptions of the good. Hampton said it well when she stated, “Now we see the way in which a modern democratic regime accommodates rebels. It allows people to withdraw their consent, at regular intervals, from particular persons holding power and particular rules or offices in the regime, even while keeping them within the overall political structure of the regime. . . . In this kind of state, disgruntled residents are confronted not with tools of mastery but with procedures laid down by the governing convention for changing their rulers or the offices they hold or these procedures themselves” While our political system is sometimes frustrating and we inevitably elect flawed leaders, I believe democracy is our best opportunity for representation of the public good. I consider myself to be very left of center so it can be frustrating to see people more centered or slightly right of center. But our system protects me from “tyranny” of those extremely right of center (at least most of the time and/or short durations at a time!). 16