
(pdf)
... • Given any formula F, the negation ¬F is a formula; • For any formulae F and G, each of F ∨ G, F ∧ G and F → G is a formula. Definition 2.3. For a set of propositional variables P and a Boolean algebra B, a valuation is a function V : P → B such that V (>) = 1, V (⊥) = 0, V (P ∧ Q) = V (P ) ∩ V (Q) ...
... • Given any formula F, the negation ¬F is a formula; • For any formulae F and G, each of F ∨ G, F ∧ G and F → G is a formula. Definition 2.3. For a set of propositional variables P and a Boolean algebra B, a valuation is a function V : P → B such that V (>) = 1, V (⊥) = 0, V (P ∧ Q) = V (P ) ∩ V (Q) ...
Document
... Arguments in Proposi:onal Logic • A argument in proposi:onal logic is a sequence of proposi:ons. All but the final proposi:on are called premises. The last statement is the conclusion. • The argument is valid if the premises imply the conclusion. An argument form is an argument that is ...
... Arguments in Proposi:onal Logic • A argument in proposi:onal logic is a sequence of proposi:ons. All but the final proposi:on are called premises. The last statement is the conclusion. • The argument is valid if the premises imply the conclusion. An argument form is an argument that is ...
Supplemental Reading (Kunen)
... recognize some new valid principle outside of ZFC. A Finitist believes only in finite objects; one is not justified in forming the set of rational numbers, let alone the set of real numbers, so CH is a meaningless statement. There is some merit in the Finitist’s position, since all objects in known ...
... recognize some new valid principle outside of ZFC. A Finitist believes only in finite objects; one is not justified in forming the set of rational numbers, let alone the set of real numbers, so CH is a meaningless statement. There is some merit in the Finitist’s position, since all objects in known ...
Section 1: Propositional Logic
... You may wonder why we’re concerned with statement forms since we’re not concerned with function forms in other areas of mathematics but just their values. That is a misconception. We are concerned with function forms in algebra. It’s just that you’re so used to the equality of different forms that y ...
... You may wonder why we’re concerned with statement forms since we’re not concerned with function forms in other areas of mathematics but just their values. That is a misconception. We are concerned with function forms in algebra. It’s just that you’re so used to the equality of different forms that y ...
here
... Proof. Suppose we are given some sentence φ. By completeness of T , either T |= φ or T |= ¬φ. Suppose T |= φ. Then φ follows from some finite number of sentences ψ1 , . . . , ψs ∈ T (by compactness). But each ψi holds almost surely among C, so φ holds almost surely among C. If, on the other hand, T ...
... Proof. Suppose we are given some sentence φ. By completeness of T , either T |= φ or T |= ¬φ. Suppose T |= φ. Then φ follows from some finite number of sentences ψ1 , . . . , ψs ∈ T (by compactness). But each ψi holds almost surely among C, so φ holds almost surely among C. If, on the other hand, T ...
A Cut-Free Calculus for Second
... Schütte in [14]). Then, it was left to show that from every three-valued non-deterministic counter-model, one can extract a usual (two-valued) counter-model, without losing comprehension (this was done first by Tait in [15]). Our proof has basically a similar general structure. Thus, in Section 5, ...
... Schütte in [14]). Then, it was left to show that from every three-valued non-deterministic counter-model, one can extract a usual (two-valued) counter-model, without losing comprehension (this was done first by Tait in [15]). Our proof has basically a similar general structure. Thus, in Section 5, ...
Proof Theory for Propositional Logic
... particular the fact that a conditional is counted as true whenever the antecedent (the first term, above) is false. Again, let’s just get comfortable doing the proofs for now. When we do truth tables we will discuss why this is the case for propositional logic. In both cases, the problem reveals f ...
... particular the fact that a conditional is counted as true whenever the antecedent (the first term, above) is false. Again, let’s just get comfortable doing the proofs for now. When we do truth tables we will discuss why this is the case for propositional logic. In both cases, the problem reveals f ...
Logic Programming, Functional Programming, and Inductive
... rules in logic programs. The rules in an inductive definition contain no variables. A schematic rule (like the rule for cousin) abbreviates an infinite set of rules: all ground instances under the Herbrand universe. In the semantics of logic programming, such theory has long been used as a technical ...
... rules in logic programs. The rules in an inductive definition contain no variables. A schematic rule (like the rule for cousin) abbreviates an infinite set of rules: all ground instances under the Herbrand universe. In the semantics of logic programming, such theory has long been used as a technical ...
PROVING THE CORRECTNESS OF REGULA DETERMINISTIC
... In this paper we provide a uniform description of some of the central works in proving the correctness of programs. The tas!k becomes manageable by adopting an ultra-simple programming language, namely, that of deterministic whik programs. In this way, problems appearing.in the presence of recursive ...
... In this paper we provide a uniform description of some of the central works in proving the correctness of programs. The tas!k becomes manageable by adopting an ultra-simple programming language, namely, that of deterministic whik programs. In this way, problems appearing.in the presence of recursive ...
A Generalization of St˚almarck`s Method
... variables {pi } is true for all assignments of truth values to {pi }. Validity checking is dual to satisfiability checking; validity of ϕ can be determined using a SAT solver by checking whether ¬ϕ is satisfiable and complementing the answer: VALIDITY(ϕ) = ¬SAT(¬ϕ). With the advent of SAT-solvers ba ...
... variables {pi } is true for all assignments of truth values to {pi }. Validity checking is dual to satisfiability checking; validity of ϕ can be determined using a SAT solver by checking whether ¬ϕ is satisfiable and complementing the answer: VALIDITY(ϕ) = ¬SAT(¬ϕ). With the advent of SAT-solvers ba ...
Ascribing beliefs to resource bounded agents
... and is usually defined as the agent knowing all logical tautologies and all the consequences of its knowledge. Logical omniscience is problematic when attempting to build realistic models of agent behaviour, as closure under logical consequence implies that deliberation takes no time. Most logical ...
... and is usually defined as the agent knowing all logical tautologies and all the consequences of its knowledge. Logical omniscience is problematic when attempting to build realistic models of agent behaviour, as closure under logical consequence implies that deliberation takes no time. Most logical ...
On the Expressive Power of QLTL⋆
... QLT L extends LT L by quantifications over atomic propositions. While the expressive power of LT L and its fragments have been made relatively clear, there are few results on the expressive power of QLT L and its fragments (besides those of LT L). A well-known result is that ω-regular languages can ...
... QLT L extends LT L by quantifications over atomic propositions. While the expressive power of LT L and its fragments have been made relatively clear, there are few results on the expressive power of QLT L and its fragments (besides those of LT L). A well-known result is that ω-regular languages can ...
SOME AXIOMS FOR CONSTRUCTIVE ANALYSIS Introduction
... are defined inductively, using the connectives &, ∨, →, ¬, quantifiers ∀, ∃ of both sorts, and parentheses (often omitted under the usual conventions on scope). Using one-place number-theoretic function variables for the choice sequences makes intuitionistic analysis expressible in the same language ...
... are defined inductively, using the connectives &, ∨, →, ¬, quantifiers ∀, ∃ of both sorts, and parentheses (often omitted under the usual conventions on scope). Using one-place number-theoretic function variables for the choice sequences makes intuitionistic analysis expressible in the same language ...
Algebraic foundations for the semantic treatment of inquisitive content
... sentences should be defined in a compositional way. In particular, if we limit ourselves to a first-order language, what is the role of connectives and quantifiers in this richer setting? How do we define [¬ϕ], [ϕ ∧ ψ], [ϕ ∨ ψ], etcetera, in terms of [ϕ] and [ψ]? This issue has been addressed quite ...
... sentences should be defined in a compositional way. In particular, if we limit ourselves to a first-order language, what is the role of connectives and quantifiers in this richer setting? How do we define [¬ϕ], [ϕ ∧ ψ], [ϕ ∨ ψ], etcetera, in terms of [ϕ] and [ψ]? This issue has been addressed quite ...
On the use of fuzzy stable models for inconsistent classical logic
... then every finite normal program P defined over L has at least a stable model. Proof: The idea is to apply Brouwer’s fix-point theorem. Specifically, we show that the operator assigning each interpretation I the interpretation R(I) = lfp(TPI ) is continuous. Note that this operator can be seen as a ...
... then every finite normal program P defined over L has at least a stable model. Proof: The idea is to apply Brouwer’s fix-point theorem. Specifically, we show that the operator assigning each interpretation I the interpretation R(I) = lfp(TPI ) is continuous. Note that this operator can be seen as a ...