Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
A NEW IMAGE OF SCIENCE AND NATURE Joe Rouse, Wesleyan University Talk at Calvin College, April 20, 2006 DRAFT: Do not cite, quote, or circulate without written permission of author. Some understanding of the natural sciences is now integral to many aspects of human self-understanding. In universities, disciplines outside the natural sciences often define themselves by comparison to science. Some disciplines aspire to become a science; some emphasize how they differ from the sciences, and a few smugly proclaim their own scientific status. Outside the academy, however, such questions arise with comparable urgency. Practices and ideals of democratic self-governance co-exist uneasily with the prominent role of scientific expertise in shaping public policy, judicial review, and political conflict. Response to this tension partly depends upon how one understands science and scientific expertise. Relations to science also now divide some Christian religious denominations. Do religious beliefs accommodate a scientific account of nature and human nature, or do theocentric and scientific conceptions conflict? Religion may encounter science not only at human and cosmological origins, but also over ethical issues, from conceptions of the beginning and the end of life to norms of environmental responsibility. How do we acquire the conceptions of science that sustain such comparisons and encounters between the sciences and other domains? Do not imagine theologians, politicians, or scholars eagerly reading Physical Review or Nature, observing research laboratories, or vaguely recalling their high school chemistry to see how their own activities accord with what scientists do. They are instead informed by a widespread conversation about science, offering familiar images of the sciences’ aims, methods and achievements. This popular discussion has been mostly continuous with contemporary philosophy of science, although the popular 2 images sometimes run roughshod over philosophers’ careful distinctions and qualifications. My aim today is to challenge some central features of the familiar popular and philosophical images of science. The familiar images are in some respects misleading, and obscure some important aspects of science. I will begin briefly with some features of the familiar conceptions that concern me, but afterwards, my argument will be indirect. My primary aim is to outline an alternative image of science and of nature. In doing so, I will highlight some important features of the sciences that familiar conceptions overlook or obscure, and why they are important. I will also show how this alternative conception can accommodate what is right about the traditional images, for they are not completely mistaken. The result should give us better resources to see why the natural sciences are so important to so much of what we do, and to think about the sciences as integral to culture and society. Scientific knowledge is central to the familiar images of science that I will challenge. Science is supposedly distinctive for the quality and the quantity of its knowledge. Scientific knowledge is thought to be especially reliable knowledge, and in any case, the sciences produce so much more knowledge than any other human enterprise. There are multiple versions of why the sciences succeed in knowledge production. Some ascribe to science a distinctive, general method, however vaguely described; others emphasize scientists’ critical or skeptical attitude, or their respect for evidence; more cynical versions mention the enormous financial resources devoted to science. I am dubious about any attempt at a wholesale account of the epistemic authority of science, but that is not my primary concern about the familiar image of science as a knowledge-producing enterprise. What troubles me instead is the underlying conception of science as a relation between knower and known. Our dominant conceptions of knowledge 3 suggest a spectator’s stance toward the world. Knowers are here, the world is out there, and knowledge involves correctly representing in here (the mind, or scientific language) what the world “out there” is like. Moreover, such conceptions sometimes suggest that knowledge stands between us and the world. That suggestion falsely implies that we understand our thoughts and our concepts better than we understand the world. It also suggests misleading metaphors for how we relate to the world: from a visual perspective, or through a more or less transparent lens or “conceptual scheme.” Taken to an extreme, such images account for the apparent intelligibility of skepticism or relativism about scientific knowledge. This point needs highlighting. Conceptions of science in terms of knowledge grip us so strongly that skepticism or relativism may seem the only alternative. But skepticism and relativism are not alternatives at all. Skeptics or cultural relativists also make knowledge central to their understanding of science. Skeptics and relativists doubt the authority or the universality of scientific knowledge, but the significance of those claims depends upon a shared sense that what matters about science is the achievement of knowledge. By contrast to skeptics or relativists, I happily recognize that we know a great deal about the world through scientific work. That knowledge is also often reliable, well-justified, and culture-crossing. Placing a general conception of knowledge at the forefront may nevertheless yield a misleading image of science. Familiar images of scientific knowledge convey complementary images of nature as its object. Sigmund Freud once proclaimed that The naive self-love of [humanity] has had to submit to two major blows at the hands of science. The first was when they learned that our earth was not the center of the universe. ... The second blow fell when biological research destroyed man’s supposedly privileged place in creation and proved his descent from the animal kingdom. (Intro. Lect. in Psychoanal., 1917, 326) 4 Max Weber famously extended the non-anthropocentric character of scientific understanding as the modern “disenchantment” of nature, which strips nature of meaning, value or significance. Nature becomes a cold, impersonal, inexorable domain, whose causes or laws grind on indifferent to our concerns or understanding. Such a disenchanted nature does not leave us bereft of meanings or norms, but does throw us back upon our own resources. As philosopher Bob Brandom put it, The Enlightenment disenchantment of the world and its assignment to us of responsibility for the norms, values, and significance we nonetheless find in the world are two sides of one coin. Meaningless objects and meaninggenerating subjects are two aspects of one picture. (MIE, 49) That is the picture I seek to replace. There is, of course, much more to our familiar conception of the sciences than just the paired images of us as knowing subjects and nature as independent, “external” object of knowledge. Other features of the familiar images will emerge in my talk. They will do so indirectly, however, by comparison to an alternative conception of the sciences. My alternative conception focuses upon scientific practices rather than scientific knowledge. Several initial distinctions between these two conceptions will do work throughout my talk. Scientific practice is something we do rather than something we achieve or possess. It involves ongoing interaction with our surroundings rather than spectatorial observation and representation. You may think of scientific practice narrowly as only including what scientists do, but I urge a more expansive conception. Scientific practices are pervasive in our lives, and throughout our culture. With these initial observations in the background, my talk will address six aspects of a reconception of science and nature in terms of sciences as practices. My six themes are the temporal orientation of scientific research toward the future; the topical selectivity of science; how the sciences intervene and materially 5 transform the world; how science articulates the world conceptually; the place of science in a broader culture; and the resulting reconception of nature and our place within it. The first two and the last two themes I will discuss relatively briefly. The heart of my talk is the third and fourth points together. I begin with the temporal orientation of science. Concern with scientific knowledge is primarily retrospective. It looks back at what we (already) know, with what justification or reliability. If you ask where to find a compilation of established scientific knowledge, however, an answer would be elusive. Scientific journals carry research reports, but many of these are contested, and most will never again be cited, used, or critically assessed. The review literature does not so much survey what is now known, as organize and preview where the field is going. Textbooks and scientific handbooks are also not comprehensive, but are instead highly selective documents organized for the likely needs of later users. Moreover, scientific work in active fields quickly outruns any such compilations. Scientific practice, by contrast, is oriented toward the future rather than the past. If you ask a research scientist about her field, she is unlikely to recount what is now known in this domain. She will instead tell you about its outstanding problems, interesting issues, and important topics that indicate where the field is going. A research area is not a sum of accumulated knowledge, but a field of possibilities, with a sense of direction beyond its current achievements. The direction of a research field can be fairly definite, yet also vague and not-fullyarticulated, since its core concepts and concerns are in flux. If one could say with complete clarity what the field is now doing, it would have already been done, and the field would have moved on. Yet this indefinite sense of possibilities and directions organizes and guides research. Biologist and philosopher Hans-J rg Rheinberger coined the term “epistemic thing” for the aim of a research program: The objects of inquiry [are material entities or processes that] present 6 themselves in a characteristic, irreducible vagueness. This vagueness is inevitable because, paradoxically, [these] epistemic things embody what one does not yet know. (1997, 28) The direction of research is of course guided by past results, and depends upon their reliability. Yet these results are continually reinterpreted in light of the possibilities they disclose. They are no longer what matters in their own right, but are reconceived as tools, models, or indicators of how to proceed beyond them. The familiar conception of science as achieved knowledge can also partially accommodate the sciences’ openness to a different future. What is now known helps outline areas of ignorance which science hopes to dispel. Moreover, any sensible conception of scientific knowledge recognizes its fallibility. Yet even if this recognition of fallibility is specified by degrees of confidence, neither fallibility nor ignorance are sufficient to express the future-directedness of scientific research. Scientific research is organized not by its actual achievements, but by its field of possibilities and its sense of direction forward. A retrospective assessment of knowledge provides a static conception of what is not yet known or might need revision, but not a dynamic orientation toward what lies ahead. In place of familiar images of an accumulating stock of scientific knowledge, I suggest biologist Francois Jacob’s counter-image of science as “a machine for making the future.” Consider now my second point, the topical selectivity of scientific practice. Most truths about the natural world have no scientific significance whatsoever. Many truths are trivial. No doubt there have been some black dogs, but that truth is no part of science. More revealing examples of scientific insignificance reflect changes in scientific interest over time. Theodore Richards of Harvard won the Nobel Prize for Chemistry in 1914 for very precise measurements of the atomic weights of many elements. The Prize signifies its apparent importance to 7 chemistry. The discovery of chemical isotopes, however, demolished the scientific significance of Richards’s measurements. A precise determination of the atomic weight of chlorine gives no insight into its chemical properties, but only shows, indirectly, the relative proportions of its two isotopes on earth. Had that been understood, Richards would not have bothered with his measurements, and would have received no Prize if he had. Consider now a different kind of example. Biologists know an extraordinary amount about a tiny number of the millions of species of organisms past and present. The fruit fly, Drosophila melanogaster, yeast, the nematode worm C. elegans, the South African frog Xenopus, and the K12 strain of the intestinal bacterium E. Coli, and a very few others, have been intensively investigated, including the sequencing of some entire genomes. By comparison, all other species are abysses of human ignorance. There is nothing intrinsically important about these species, however. They are well-known only as useful and familiar laboratory models. Biologists now know a lot about these organisms, partly from using them extensively, and partly because they need to know it to understand their experiments. The significance of model organisms also changes, however. The ciliate Paramecium was the original model organism for microbial genetics, extensively studied from the 1930's to the 1950's. Afterwards it virtually disappeared from research laboratories. Two developments led to Paramecium‘s scientific demise. First, it was unsuitable for the newly emerging scientific focus upon biochemical genetics. Second, the topic it was well suited to study, the supposedly distinctive mechanisms of cytoplasmic inheritance, turned out not to be distinctive at all. Why are these shifts in scientific significance important for my topic? They emphasize that science is not merely a widespread accumulation of knowledge about the many facets of the natural world. Science is instead a highly focused and 8 often idiosyncratic effort to understand those features or aspects of the world that matter to us. Sometimes they matter for practical reasons. Petroleum geology is the largest subfield in the earth sciences not because it provides fundamental insights, but because it feeds the energy gluttony of industrial civilization. In many cases, however, scientific significance is self-generated. Scientific inquiry is often highly selective for distinctively scientific reasons. Only by understanding the trajectory and direction of a scientific practice can one grasp why some esoteric topics are highly interesting scientifically, whereas most aspects of nature are matters of mere curiosity but not scientific concern. These first two themes, the sciences’ future-directedness and their topical selectivity, are crucially important issues that I could nevertheless introduce fairly briefly. My next two themes require more extensive treatment. I first take up the importance of understanding the sciences as practices that intervene in the world. One side of this theme is very well-known to administrators and bureaucrats; sciences are more expensive and administratively complex than other scholarly disciplines, because they need laboratories, instruments, special research materials, and teams of trained researchers. On traditional conceptions of science as knowledge, these facilities are merely instrumental to science. Although often indispensable means to knowledge of nature, they are not integral to that knowledge. Scientific knowledge claims, and the evidence and reasoning that justify them, are linguistic or mathematical expressions whose relations to one another are inferential and rational rather than causal or lawlike. The practical conception of science that I recommend, by contrast, recognizes the centrality of scientific intervention in the world. Science does not take the world as we find it. Scientists must instead re-arrange parts of the world to allow it to show itself intelligibly. Note the shift in emphasis from traditional empiricism: the important point is not what we can observe in nature, but what the 9 phenomena can show us. Philosopher Ian Hacking once remarked that Old science on every continent [began] with the stars, because only the skies afford some phenomena on display, with many more [obtainable] by careful observation... Only the planets and more distant bodies have the right combination of complex regularity against a background. (1983, 227) Science began with astronomy, but it obviously did not stop there. Where scientists did not find phenomena in nature that manifested a significant pattern against a background, they worked hard to create them. When Hacking or I say that scientists create phenomena, we don’t mean that they “make them up,” or that such work is dubious or unreliable. On the contrary, creating significant and revealing patterns in the world is hard work, and only succeeds if nature cooperates. Nature will nevertheless not cooperate unless scientists bring about the right circumstances. The effort involved in creating scientifically revealing phenomena is extraordinary. Start by preparing materials, such as isolating and purifying standard chemicals; breeding simplified and standardized model organisms in biology; or inventing batteries, wired circuits, electromagnets, microwave cavities, lasers, and so many other electromagnetic or electronic systems. Subject these materials to novel circumstances: vacuum pumps or high-pressure chambers; extreme low or high temperatures; intense magnetic fields; pulses of high–energy radiation; or just carefully regulated light, humidity, or nutrients for plants. Introduce some new ways for hitherto invisible things to produce discernible signs. These may include stains for transparent biological materials; labeling with radioactive isotopes or plasmids for antibiotic resistance; diffusion through gels or filters; displaying diffraction patterns of light; or reflections of high explosive shock waves. Provide some novel detectors, such as instruments for infrared, radio, or X-radiation; breeding stocks to cross with mutant organisms; control groups for 10 a target population; or coincidence circuits that only fire when two events occur in rapid succession. Introduce standardized measures, for distances, temperatures, electrical resistance, and much more, and build instruments calibrated to those measures. Finally, shield these interactions from unknown or unexpected confounding influences. With sufficient care and ingenuity, you may then produce an interesting and revealing outcome, by producing an unprecedented by reproducible situation. Otherwise, however, the typical outcome is not error but noise and confusion. Moreover, the hardest part of research is often telling the difference between signal, noise, and error. In front-line research, there are no answers at the back of the book. To sum up this point, science starts off trying to understand what is happening in the world around us. At its best, however, what it typically produces is a remarkably clear and precise grasp of what happens in the much more regulated and sanitized setting of the laboratory. I do not denigrate that achievement, which is extraordinary. Rather, I emphasize the two primary ways that the clean and orderly space of the laboratory gives insight into the messy, complicated world outside. First, it allows us to see new aspects of that world through a glass, darkly, that is, by comparison to laboratory settings and practices. Seeing the outcomes of a drug regimen in a carefully controlled clinical trial, for example, tells us something important about what happens when people take it more haphazardly, with more varied bodily regimens, lifestyles, and diagnoses. Knowing how radiation affects cells in tissue culture or animals in older experiments that no longer meet our ethical scruples, likewise tells us something important about the biological significance of radiation. It says much less about what happened when the Chernobyl reactor blew large quantities of diverse radioactive debris to the winds. The general point is clear: experimental models inevitably ignore or obscure some effects due to messier circumstances outside the 11 lab. Fortunately, laboratory science enables us to understand the world in a second way. Laboratory practices guide a massive, continuing effort to reconstruct the world in the image of the laboratory. Our everyday lives are now surrounded, for example, by myriad substances that have been synthesized, purified, enclosed, and/or chemically analyzed; just look around a supermarket, Home Depot, pharmacy, factory or gas station. Electricity was transformed from a laboratory curiosity to an indispensable component of everyday life by insulated copper wires, batteries, and AC transformers, and their correlated motors, bulbs, and coils. You can hear a pin drop through the telephone a thousand miles away because precisely correlated laser beams and fiberglass cables counter-balance the diffusion and compression of light pulses. Hybrid plant varieties yield extraordinary crops, if their fields are fertilized, irrigated, and sprayed with pesticides and herbicides to match their sensitivities. These devices and practices only circulate reliably, however, when preceded by standardized units of measure and measuring devices. Standard meters, ohms and nanoseconds, along with thermometers, clocks, and scales, make possible a world of things made to measure. To sum up, what is done in the laboratory yields extensive and precise understanding wherever aspects of laboratory order and precision travel alongside and reliably stay put. My fourth theme, the sciences’ conceptual articulation of the world, is perhaps the hardest to grasp. Consider the familiar idea that the history of science has frequently replaced error and superstition with more accurate beliefs. People mostly no longer identify disease with demonic possession, think combustion gives off phlogiston, or believe the earth to be flat and 4000 years old. Such judgments of past error are sometimes appropriate, if we also acknowledge our own fallibility in turn. Yet current scientific practice mostly licenses a different comparison. In most domains of science we can now say things about which earlier generations 12 had no beliefs at all, rather than false beliefs. Being able to say what others cannot is not just a matter of learning new words; it presupposes being able to “tell” what you are talking about with those words. As philosopher John Haugeland noted, Telling [in the sense of telling what something is, telling things apart, or telling the differences between them] can often be expressed in words, but is not in itself essentially verbal. ... People can tell things for which they have no words, including things that are hard to tell. (1998, 313) Science allows us to talk about an extraordinary range of things, by enabling us to “tell” about them. To pick some random examples, people can now tell, and therefore talk, about mitochondria, the pre-Cambrian Era, subatomic particles, tectonic plates, retroviruses, spiral galaxies, and amino acid sequences. One need not go back very far historically to find not error, but silence on these and many more scientific topics. How was that silence broken? To express beliefs about something, we need concepts in which to express them. Again, to have a concept is not just to have a word, but to be able to “tell” something. That is what I mean by conceptual articulation. In slightly different terms, the philosopher Martin Heidegger emphasized the importance of this achievement for science: Every forging-ahead [in science] requires, in advance, an open region within which it operates. But precisely the opening up of such a region constitutes the fundamental occurrence in research. (AWP, 59) Opening up a scientific domain, in this sense, involves being able to tell what’s going on there. But I still have not said how this happens. One philosopher, W.v.O. Quine, expressed a traditional view of this process metaphorically: [Science] is a human-made fabric which impinges upon experience only along the edges, or a field of force whose boundary conditions are 13 experience. A conflict with experience at the periphery occasions readjustments in the interior of the field. (Two Dogmas, 42) For Quine, concepts are thus components of a systematic theory. They are developed or changed strictly by internal adjustments in that theory. I call this traditional because it regards knowledge as a relation between a system of verbal representation, and something unconceptualized (experience, nature, or “the world”). The world impinges upon us from outside, compelling us to readjust the internal relations among our sentences or thoughts. On the traditional view, it is having a theory that allows us to be “articulate,” to express thoughts in words. The word “articulate” now primarily describes a verbal capacity, but it has a more fundamental meaning. Something is “articulated” when it is jointed, like the human skeleton. Conceptual articulation is simply our most powerful and fine-grained way of finding, or better, telling “joints” or boundaries in the world. Traditional views of science regard the primary work of articulation as verbal. On one version of this claim, the world is already articulated into kinds of things and properties. Verbal articulation just tries to match those kinds. On other versions, the world comes more-or-less adaptable to different verbal articulations. I think we will not adequately understand scientific practice unless we reject both versions. More fundamentally, we need to reject the underlying distinction between how the world already is, and how we represent it in words. Science articulates the world, allowing us to tell about it, by developing new patterns of interacting and new ways of talking, together. This claim is fairly abstract, so let’s consider examples. Cell biology has a rich vocabulary for the internal components of cells and their functions. Modern cell biology began, many historians would argue, when Albert Claude spun pulverized chicken sarcoma cells in the ultracentrifuge at 28,000 rpm for a week. Different materials gradually precipitated; eventually there were multiple layers of 14 cellular debris beneath a liquid. Claude could only initially describe the layers as “small particles” or “large granules,” and note when each precipitated. So far, one might as well try to understand a car by blowing it up, and sorting the pieces by size or where they land. That doesn’t allow you to say much about the car. Cell biology could do better by connecting multiple interactions with these components. Claude analyzed the different fragments biochemically. Later, he could identify layers in the ultracentrifuge with some structures discernible through light microscopes, and then others discerned with electrons. Eventually, the various experimental, structural, and biochemical interactions with cell components could be interconnected to localize biological functions such as respiration or protein synthesis, and cell biology was off to an exciting start. The key work may seem to come earlier, when some cell structures showed up in the light microscope, but not so. Microscopes alone cannot indicate whether and how the boundaries they make visible are biologically meaningful. Without multiply interconnected articulations, the visually identifiable elements might well be artifacts, either of the stains and instruments that make them visible, or of the prejudices that equate visibility to us with importance. Consider now another, deceptively simple case. What does it mean for one thing to be hotter than another? We distinguish quantity of heat from intensity of heat, but what is the latter, what we now call “temperature?” Recognizing that degrees of heat correlate with expansion and contraction, we might identify temperature with what a thermometer measures, but that won’t do. Set aside the many difficulties of defining some fixed points, such as the freezing and boiling points of water. Having fixed these points, suppose we divide the linear distance between them into 100 identical units. Here are some different measures of “temperature” that you would get with mercury, alcohol, and water thermometers: Mercury 0o 25o 50o 75o 100o 15 Alcohol Water 0o 0o 5o 22o 26o 44o 57o 70o 100o 100o (taken from Chang, 2004, 58) Is there one concept of temperature, or many, or none? Or is temperature a purely conventional concept, such that we could just agree upon mercury or alcohol as a canonical measure? Finally, we want to understand temperature when these thermometers would melt, or their contents freeze. What is a “degree,” and what it is a degree of, at 1000o, 1,000,000o or -250o? I want to make three points about this example. First, scientists were able to define a unified scale of temperature, and critically assess the performance of various thermometers, experimentally. This was never merely or even primarily a matter of internal adjustment within theory. Second, when that concept was eventually defined more tightly, it was through triangulation with a very different experimental and practical domain. Steam engines allow us to correlate heat with a capacity for mechanical work. Finally, the unity and coherence that thermodynamics then gives to the concept of temperature is highly unusual among empirical concepts. As just one example, consider the analogous question of what it is for one solid material to be harder than another. As with temperature, there are multiple, partly conflicting empirical measures of hardness. Is hardness best displayed by resistance to denting, to scratching, to cutting, or to frictional wear? Here there is no prospect of unifying different measures into a single scale. Materials can be harder or softer in many ways, which only partly overlap. Yet like temperature, articulating the concept of hardness involved creating phenomena as much or more than redefining words or formulating theories. A defender of more traditional conceptions of scientific knowledge might now raise an objection. Not all, or even most, conceptual developments in the sciences are as straightforwardly empirical as temperature, hardness, or cell structure. Internal adjustments within theories might therefore still be the 16 predominant mode of conceptual articulation in science. I accept the premise, but reject the conclusion, because we also need to think differently about scientific theory. Theoretical understanding is not a relation between a general verbal representation and a phenomenon in the world. Scientific theorizing is better understood as a practice of modeling various actual or possible circumstances. Although we sometimes formulate general theories in the physical sciences, from Newton’s Laws to thermodynamics, we learn what those theories and their equations say by developing families of models. We do not know what the relevant forces, masses and accelerations are in Newton’s F=ma, for example, except by modeling specific kinds of situation, such as free fall, harmonic oscillators, or planetary orbits. We then understand more complex circumstances by comparing them to the models, with appropriate corrections or complicating factors. Models are even more important in sciences that describe complicated circumstances. When we think about the workings of a cell on a small scale, or the dynamics of global climate on a much larger one, models virtually become stand-ins for the actual systems we seek to understand. We have no way to comprehend such complex patterns of interaction except via more simplified models. The reason theoretical modeling is important for how we think about science is that models and experimental systems play remarkably similar roles in articulating concepts. Whether theoretical or experimental, model systems provide simplified, idealized settings in which concepts and their relations to one another can be clearly defined as telling differences. On the one hand, differences among various components or factors in a situation can be identified and highlighted by their relations within a model. On the other hand, their dominant modes of interaction stand out more clearly within the simplified or idealized circumstances of the model. By understanding how the model works, we get some indication in 17 “real” circumstances of where to look and how to intervene for scientific or practical purposes. My discussion of conceptual articulation has been long and complicated. Here is why it matters to my larger aim to understand science in terms of practices rather than knowledge. Traditional images of science focus upon comparing knowledge claims to the world. The underlying presumption is that the meaning and the truth of these claims can be independently determined. Understanding meaning is supposedly a verbal matter; assessing truth requires looking at the world. There is, however, no clear separation here. We only understand new scientific concepts by interacting with the world in new ways. Understanding what these concepts say, and understanding the world in those terms, go hand in hand. Moreover, by creating and using experimental systems and theoretical models, we transform the world in ways that allow it to be intelligible to us. Indeed, if you have understood what I have been saying, my third and fourth themes are really the same point from different angles. Sciences are material practices of interaction with the world that articulate it conceptually. My final two themes also raise large, complicated issues, but I shall be brief. My aim is to indicate how these themes fit within my larger picture, not to address them more extensively. Let’s first consider the place of scientific practices in culture and society. We tend to think of the sciences as relatively self-enclosed disciplines that only interact with the broader culture in limited, well-defined ways. That image is reinforced by the university curriculum. Most students and faculty regard courses in science as having little to do with the humanities or social sciences. Such isolation accords well with the dominant image of science as knowledge-accumulation. We say that scientific knowledge influences culture and society. Influence also runs in the other direction, when social needs call for “applied” research, or when politics, religion, or culture impinge upon scientific 18 fields of inquiry. But the notion of “influence” suggests only limited causal interactions between relatively distinct and autonomous domains. There are many reasons to doubt the separability of science from culture, in either direction. My earlier discussion of extending laboratory practices into the world should have already generated doubts. If you recognize the extent to which the materials, practices, and disciplinary order of the laboratory now permeate everyday life, it is hard to maintain the illusion of science and society as separate spheres. That becomes harder still keeping in mind the entanglement of the sciences in politics, education, the economy, or the self-understanding of a “modern” rationalized industrial society. Yet even on a more fine-grained scale, science and culture are more intimately interconnected in multi-dimensional ways. I can illustrate this briefly with two examples of scientific-cultural entanglement around the concept of a gene and the discipline of genetics. Understanding the history of the concept of a ‘gene’, in its scientific uses and its wider cultural significance, requires reference to the familiar JudaeoChristian concept of an immortal, immaterial soul. Genes were first postulated as abstract “factors” unchanged throughout the life of an organism and their passage into later generations. Even as genes acquired spatial location and chemical specificity, they were increasingly conceived in terms of “information” separable from their material embodiment. Genes and the soul were both conceived as immaterial forms “informing” bodily matter. Within the culture at large, genes are widely regarded as an unchanging essence and identity persisting through developmental changes in body and mind. Moreover, genes have acquired overtones of the sacred, such that gene therapy, genetic engineering, or gene cloning are criticized not as imprudent or dangerous, but as “tampering,” “messing,” or “unnatural,” in short, as sacrilege. This 1994 Time magazine cover illustrates how the visual iconography of genetics often relies upon religious and 19 spiritual associations. The traffic in meaning between genes and souls shows up in biology as well as popular culture, however. I think biologists’ initial resistance to recognizing the dynamics of genes, in phenomena such as transposition, posttranscriptional splicing and editing, and DNA repair reflected genes’ conceptual heritage as secular surrogates to the soul. These connotations also informed biologists’ frequent talk of “gene action.” Embryology and development almost disappeared as biological fields at mid-century, as supposedly derivative fields that only show “how genes produce their effects.” Indeed, the language of gene action, genetic determination, and genes as unchanging essences still recurs unthinkingly in the talk and writing of many biologists who now know better. The fate of the Human Genome Diversity Project offers a second illustration of the multi-dimensional traffic in meanings between science and culture. When the Human Genome Project was first underway in the early 90's, some anti-racist geneticists were concerned about the Project’s apparent indifference to human genetic variation. They also worried that important traces of human evolutionary history were disappearing as formerly isolated human groups become part of a single global population. Their response was a global program of genetic sampling that would help recognize, celebrate, and better understand human genetic diversity. These scientists were astonished when their proposal was itself attacked as arrogant, racist, neo-colonialist, and exploitative. In the ensuing controversy, the Human Genome Diversity Project collapsed. The point of its failure for my talk today is the conceptual complexity of understanding human diversity. What constitutes a human population or “race”? Should it be defined geographically, ethnically, linguistically, or in terms of its own political or cultural sovereignty? The biologists hoped to define diversity genetically. They discovered that they could not do so without taking the partially conflicting alternatives into account. Moreover, their own activities of genetic sampling and testing could not be 20 understood simply as a scientific procedure of evidence gathering. Genetics is a complex practice, whose meanings and consequences are economic, political, ethical, and cultural, as well as technical. Different actors with different locations in that practice raised different issues, with different stakes. With the best of intentions, biologists thought they could disentangle their scientific goals from the cultural and political complications of achieving them. They were wrong. As anthropologist Jenny Reardon concluded from studying the controversy, Phenomena such as human genetic diversity cannot emerge as objects of study independent of moral and social decisions about who we are and what we want to know. ... Debates about natural (or biological) human difference cannot be disconnected from these historically entrenched debates about how to characterize human diversity in society ... and [from] the emotionally and politically charged discourses of population, race, ethnicity and colonization that structured them. (Reardon 2005, 162, 160) These two examples of the cultural entanglement of scientific practice lead directly to my concluding theme, the reconception of nature that complements a reconception of science as practices. Again, I shall be brief about a large, complex theme. Familiar views draw a fairly sharp separation between nature and the social world. The sciences seek to know nature as independent of and indifferent to us, whereas we make society, and are more or less at home there. Nature is seen as disenchanted, devoid of human meaning and value; social action, by contrast, establishes the meanings and norms we live by. My talk has suggested another way to think about nature and our place within it. Our scientific culture does not present nature as the disenchanted object of spectatorial knowledge, but as our environment. We do not observe our natural environment, but interact with it and live in it, even when we do science. An organism’s environment is not given, but is partially made by it. Moisture-loving 21 insects flourish in deserts, for example, because their environment is not the dry desert air, but the moist layer of air within a millimeter of a leaf. Earthworms live in the crumbly soils bequeathed by past generations of earthworms. Human beings in modern industrial and scientific societies remake our environments much more dramatically. Just look around you, and also recall the many ways we have remade the world in the image of a laboratories. But the human environment is also replete with linguistic and other symbolic practices. We dwell in a meaningfully articulated world, and words are among the most salient and pervasive features of our environment. Do not think of language as meanings we impose from “outside” upon an inherently meaningless nature. Language only becomes meaningful within articulated patterns of interaction with our surroundings: word and world become articulate together. Physicist Niels Bohr once rightly remarked that, “We are suspended in language in such a way that we cannot say what is up and what is down,” but the word “language” here is short for a linguistically articulated world. Without practical involvement in the world, the words would be empty; without the words, the world would be mute and inarticulate. This conception of nature emphasizes that we cannot get “outside” of our language and practices to see the world with the distant eye of a stranger or the allencompassing eye sometimes attributed to God. It nevertheless avoids two failings that often drive people toward traditional views of nature as a world apart. First, we cannot think of or remake nature in any way we please. On the contrary, I am emphasizing our interdependence with nature, and even our inability to think and act except as part of the natural world. Traditional views wrongly assume that conceptual articulation comes only from within the mind, and hence requires an “external” world to constrain our theoretical flights of fancy. The error was in not recognizing thought and language as worldly from the start. Second, this 22 conception does not encourage an anthropocentric complacency. To be sure, we mostly live our lives in a human-tailored environment, and the world is only intelligible to us through practices and concepts that habituate us here. Yet our scientific culture thereby enables us to articulate, in terms intelligible to us, here and now, how limited and idiosyncratic are the earthly circumstances in which we dwell. The traditional view of nature and science is after all right to acknowledge, with wonder and awe, how wildly the earth and the heavens can differ from the tiny environmental niche to which we cling so precariously. It only to fails to recognize that we do so, as we must, without ever leaving home.