* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Presentation
Survey
Document related concepts
Transcript
Drawn into an intellectual maelstrom. The vulnerability of the naïve researcher encountering idiosyncrasy: strategies for evaluating contribution to scholarship Cedric C. Gilson MSc LLM DipEdTech School of Law University of Westminster, London, UK Introduction This paper concerns methodology more than substance. Its arguments and reasoning could have universal application to problems experienced in researching for a PhD. Essentially, it is about reflexivity and discernment in analysing scholarship for its contribution to research aims, and the problems that arise when unusual and diverting work is encountered in the literature. My position in relation to my PhD is that of a researcher trying to enlarge the boundaries of knowledge to answer my research question, and so I am keeping an open mind about the theories and propositions that I encounter. However, while there is certainty and safety in relying on the archive of accumulated conventional literature, this is dislodged when the discourse of scholars with novel opinions appears abruptly in the field of knowledge, and without apparent history. Lacking the assurance of the archive and with only a scant opportunity for the community of peers to form an opinion (that might well be critical), one is thrown onto one’s own resources in order to evaluate the new material. In this a naïve researcher like me can become unsettled. Procedure for presentation My research topic concerns finding resources to mediate the incommensurability of science and law in legal contexts. Conventional wisdom is that these are functionally differentiated fields, representing closed or partly closed systems that cannot communicate. However, law relies on science in the modern age to assist its decisions and some means of them being able to comprehend one another is essential. The outline for presentations at this conference, that Henry Rothstein sent we research students, is straightforward and I attempted to connect my research to the headings he gave. The first heading—the research question— is simple and I have already mentioned it. Second, the literature to which I hope to contribute is in the area of socio-legal studies. Third, my research design and methods centre on library-based studies in all related fields, with strong emphasis on the philosophy and sociology of science and law, aided by high input from associated studies and, as it transpires in practice, valuable interactive supervision meetings. However, when considering the fourth and fifth headings in the protocol—findings, interpretations and outlook— I found in my case that a fracture occurred in the list because the difficulty experienced over the work of idiosyncratic scholars makes exactly those features of research open to question. The thrust of this paper, therefore, is how the inexperienced research student can form strategies to evaluate such work for its contribution to knowledge, and eventually to be able to satisfy the last two elements in Henry Rothstein’s list. 1 Given the research task of my degree it is natural to look for systems of observing science and law that are independent of the way they each understand themselves, and that can reframe these knowledges in their own terms. Of the social sciences, the discipline and methods of sociology offer appropriate means, and in this regard, I encountered the unusual work of Bruno Latour. Laboratory Life: Bruno Latour Professor Latour employs ethnographic and highly participative research methods in his studies. Rather than dwell on the methods of ethnography, it is more important to focus on Latour's findings, because these accentuate contrasts. In the first of the two studies that I shall discuss today, he sought to examine the culture and practice of a scientific institution from the inside, The Salk Institute in San Diego, producing his results in the publication with Steve Woolgar entitled Laboratory Life—The construction of scientific facts. This novel approach to research into the workings of science, in which interactions between scientists in their daily work were studied minutely, produced interesting observation and comment. Latour and Woolgar found it impossible to separate the social and scientific world because science is merely the result of many operations in the social realm. More significantly, at least I thought so, there was a sense in which their observation of the processes of biological science risked colonizing their ethnographic analysis. Paradoxically, the recontextualisation of ethnography as part of the wider scientific process could have a unifying effect between the natural and social sciences. I shall return to this later. Creating a world of laboratories: the administrative court of France, scientific objects and legal objectivity While Laboratory Life was an unusual piece of research, it represented simply the application of a system of observation to another discipline. Its findings were largely descriptive but credible. A second study, undertaken by Bruno Latour alone, involved ethnographic study of the French Supreme Court in Administrative Law, the Conseil d’Etat. Adapting the French translation of the work, I have called the resulting opus ‘Creating a World of Laboratories: scientific objects and legal objectivity’. Latour attempted what I call the intussusception of two disciplines, namely importing scientific methods into the operation of a court of law so as to make it resemble a laboratory and, conversely, reflecting legal processes into the arena of science to make fresh evaluations of them. This represented a leap from the practicality of Laboratory Life with, some might say, bizarre consequences. Latour re-characterized scientific research by likening its claims to claims made in legal proceedings but contrasted science’s provisional assertions with law’s need for closure. He commented on lawyers’ ability to distance themselves from case substance, but that was not replicated in scientists’ passionate involvement, which never diminished. This opposed the traditional vision of the objectivity of scientists and instead credited this to lawyers. On the question of truth, Latour indicated that science pursued it everlastingly, while law was obliged to curtail the search in order to conclude. Bruno Latour drew a useful distinction between researchers, and experts called as witnesses in trials. Signifying that whereas, for the researcher, 2 experimental findings serve only as the catalyst for a new inquiry, experts expect to convey irrevocability because they are imbued with responsibility for certainty. While he cautions that expert witness opinion must not form a warrant for judgment, Latour’s observation resonates with recent instances in English courts where the opinions of medical experts have led to unsafe convictions for parental murder of young children. The redepiction of fact simply as a knowledge claim, enables Latour to cast science in a forum where negotiation is possible. Attributing the confusion of the rôles of science and law to early empiricism, Professor Latour comments that the conceptualisation of sense data was responsible for inappropriately crossing the view of science as the purveyor of incontrovertible fact, with the objectivity that law dispenses. He concludes that the distinction of science and law should reside in the functions they perform and that therefore science should not be asked to judge, and law not to decide the truth. Latour's intussusception of science into law in the French Administrative Court, questions whether incommensurability devolving from the autonomy they both enjoy as functionally differentiated knowledge systems, is disturbed. The extreme position of autopoiesis applied by Niklas Luhmann to law is that it is a totally closed, self-referential system. Latour's penetrative and transformative enterprise reconstructs law in science’s own province. If systematically successful, this exploit could undermine autopoietic assertions. However, Latour uses his method only to reaffirm science and law’s distinctions in terms of their societal rôles, albeit with an unjustified confidence that from henceforth science should never depict its opinions as final and law likewise should never task science with responsibility for the truth. Whether epistemological intussusception can mediate incommensurability, demands deeper study. Intellectual Impostures: Sokal and Bricmont In their unforgiving critique of the work of several contemporary philosophers and sociologists of science under the title Intellectual Impostures, Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont ardently disapprove of Bruno Latour's postmodern outlook with its implicit flight from the canons of empiricism, due to what they call the ‘relativistic drift’. They attribute this to failure of the Vienna Circle to complete the task of formalizing science, thereby sowing scepticism. Sokal and Bricmont object to the prospectus of Barry Barnes and David Bloor, subscribed to by Bruno Latour, that is referred to as the ‘strong programme’ in the sociology of science, that marks a shift from sociologists’ contentment with explaining the social context of scientific activity, to the more ambitious explanation in sociological contexts the content of scientific theories. Coincidentally with Thomas Kuhn’s work,i Latour and Woolgar refer in Laboratory Life to the shift of the concern of sociologists of science from the stuff of socially-constructed science to the sociology of scientific knowledge. Bruno Latour directed this stratagem into the arena of scientific opinion, venturing on one occasion into astrophysics and theory concerning the emission of neutrinos from the sun. He posited nature as the knower of its own truths but relegated the efforts of research to that of a socially-constructed power game.ii This ignored empirical findings and Sokal and Bricmont felt that Latour played on confusion between facts and our knowledge of them. A further foray into special relativity theory that appeared to reinterpret the function of Einstein’s frames of reference, and misconstrue the meaning of 3 observers, left Sokal and Bricmont appalled at Latour's audacity in challenging such universally accepted theories. Sokal and Bricmont resoundingly indict Latour's assertions as either true but banal or surprising but manifestly false. In the quest for knowledge, every researcher hopes for revelations that are surprising but true while discarding the banal and false. Strategies for evaluating contribution to scholarship For the naïve researcher it is essential to formulate personal strategies to evaluate unconventional theories. Patently, it is a prime task to determine the extent to which scholar’s ideas engage usefully with the research question, and to admit or deny them from the study on that basis. This gatekeeping function demands deep personal reflexivity, and one even has to reflect on how to construct this. My responsibility is to improve my own methodology and thinking. But, first, the new assertions must be analysed. The transition from sociology of scientific practice to that of scientific knowledge moves the observing rôle of sociology towards epistemological studies, that could signify a new kind of knowledge, but its limitations should be understood. In Laboratory Life, Latour's participative study showed that the anthropological probe risked being colonized by the object, but it is also possible that Latour rehabilitates sociology by reconceptualizing it within biology as part of the totality of life’s organisation. This would tend to unify the natural and social sciences. Compare this with the analysis of the sociologist of law, Roger Cotterrell, that sociological inquiry can subvert, rather than unify, the social sciences, that the knowledge claims of other disciplines become part of its own subject-matter, that its observations are at best mere sociological data and it has no distinctive subject-matter of its own. The nexus of the philosophical account of empiricism and the emergence of the expert is neither a banal nor a false opinion, and the distinction of experts and researchers is instructive rather than surprising. This reading also has relevance in current legal contexts. Latour's associations and distinctions are grounded in accepted theory, and here his perceptions sharpen understanding. However his attempts to redefine science through analysis of scientists’ activity in the neutrino debate, fails to clarify nature, and thereby they invoke Sokal and Bricmont’s censure. His new perspectives on relativity theory are thoughtprovoking but inconsistent with classical theory. In these last instances, Latour has transgressed the interpretive boundaries of the new sociology of scientific knowledge. Systems theories are well grounded and acknowledged in many fields of study. Communication between systems is possible by means of transcendental vehicles, exemplified importantly by trans-science. In this the insurmountable problems of science are dealt with by law using an adversarial technique. Adversarialism therefore becomes an agent that negotiates the outcome. The strong programme in the sociology of science does not represent a transcendental vehicle, but entails instead a shift of aspect for sociological inquiry. Latour crosses system boundaries unapologetically, encouraged by the strong programme. He endows the nature of problems with a surprise value but in his probing fails to ask the right questions, which sometimes leads to manifestly false conclusions. A critique of Latour's novel perspectives can be developed through the standard of the Pragmatic Attachment, after C.S. Pierce, through its 4 prescription that knowledge consists of valid explanations that, when applied to problem-situations, make a difference to our evaluation of them. Explanations that fail in this respect are not valued. Relatedly, the Realist view says that there is an objective reality that exists solely by virtue of how the world is, and in principle is discoverable by the methods of science. Adopted as advance strategies, these could avoid entanglement with postmodern theories but, utilizing pragmatism and realism as comparators, the naïve researcher can consider philosophies that locate rationality in judgment of what appears practical, and assists in problem-solving. The importance of a scholar’s work is gauged by whether it has any social effect. As a researcher, I perform a critical function in determining the acceptability of scientific theories in my work. Ultimately, all assertions, including those of law, must prove socially acceptable. Defining the ‘line’ I take between my problems and my reading of science relies on comparing my feelings on social acceptability as an individual member of society. This should be supplemented by a sense of the achievements intended for my thesis, combined with selecting standards by which to judge intellectual challenges. As part of this reflexive exercise, I have considered the followingCotterrell’s account of the subversion of social science disciplines by sociological inquiry, and the tension between unification and colonization in Latour's studies The strong programme in the sociology of science, which meshes with Latour's impulses and leads him to surprising conclusions The issue of the intussusception of disciplines which, if systematically successful, could undermine autopoiesis Comparisons with truly transcendental vehicles that support communication between systems by mechanism or agency The use of non-postmodern perspectives that offer a different rationality against which to compare unorthodox claims My problem is characterized by capture, struggle and release. Can a PhD researcher avoid becoming colonized by theory? Bruno Latour’s idiosyncrasy alarmed me initially but it was highly seductive; now I understand him better, I see interesting ways in which his perspectives will augment my inquiry. I can detect from Latour's later work that these kinds of studies founded ActorNetwork Theory that lays at the centre of Science and Technology Studies. These ideas are enjoying an increased following among philosophers and sociologists of science. But I perceive an experimentalism in other ideas, the findings of which might never enter settled opinion. However, as a now slightly less naïve researcher, I do not feel so vulnerable, and am more equipped to avoid being captured unawares by nonconformist theories. See Kuhn, T. (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Chicago: Chicago University Press, p.238. “…Kuhn’s insistence that the way in which we are able to discover the nature of science is “intrinsically sociological” and is to be accomplished by “examining the nature of the scientific group, discovering what it tolerates and what it disdains”, also leads to relativism if it transpires that different groups value, tolerate and disdain different things. This, indeed, is how proponents of the sociology of science currently in vogue commonly interpret Kuhn, developing his views into an explicit relativism. [In. Chalmers, AF, (1999) 3e. What is this thing called science? Buckingham: Open University Press]. ii But see Pinch, T. (1986) Confronting nature – the sociology of solar-neutrino detection, (Dordrecht: Reidel) i 5