* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Hypothesis of Disease Causation - Wk 1-2
Chagas disease wikipedia , lookup
Schistosomiasis wikipedia , lookup
Whooping cough wikipedia , lookup
Brucellosis wikipedia , lookup
Onchocerciasis wikipedia , lookup
Leptospirosis wikipedia , lookup
Meningococcal disease wikipedia , lookup
Eradication of infectious diseases wikipedia , lookup
African trypanosomiasis wikipedia , lookup
Hypothesis of Disease Causation 1. Proving Hypotheses & Disease Causation (History & Philosophy of Science and Medicine) When proving hypothesis and disease causation, the principle model that is used is the Bradford Hill Criteria. Sir Bradford Hill established the following nine criteria for causation, outlining the minimal conditions needed to establish a causal relationship between two items. Although developed for use in the field of occupational medicine (ie does factor A cause disorder B), these criteria can be used in most situations. The nine factors to consider include; 1. Strength of the association. How large is the effect? This is defined by the size of the association as measured by appropriate statistical tests. The stronger the association, the more likely it is that the relation of "A" to "B" is causal. 2. The consistency of the association. Has the same association been observed by others, in different populations, using a different method? The association is consistent when results are replicated in studies in different settings using different methods. That is, if a relationship is causal, we would expect to find it consistently in different studies and in different populations. This is why numerous experiments have to be done before meaningful statements can be made about the causal relationship between two or more factors 3. Specificity. Does altering only the cause alter the effect? This is established when a single putative cause produces a specific effect. Can be determined if altering only the cause alters the effect. 4. Temporal relationship. Does the cause precede the effect? Exposure always precedes the outcome. If factor "A" is believed to cause a disease, then it is clear that factor "A" must necessarily always precede the occurrence of the disease. 5. Biological gradient. Is there a dose response? An increasing amount of exposure increases the risk. If a dose-response relationship is present, it is strong evidence for a causal relationship 6. Biological plausibility. Does it make sense? The association agrees with currently accepted understanding of pathological processes. In other words, there needs to be some theoretical basis for positing an association between a vector and disease, or one social phenomenon and another. 7. Coherence. Does the evidence fit with what is known regarding the natural history and biology of the outcome? The association should be compatible with existing theory and knowledge. In other words, it is necessary to evaluate claims of causality within the context of the current state of knowledge within a given field and in related fields. 8. Experimental evidence. Are there any clinical studies supporting the association and can the condition be altered (prevented or ameliorated) by an appropriate experimental regimen? 9. Reasoning by analogy. Is the observed association supported by similar associations? In judging whether a reported association is causal, it is necessary to determine the extent to which researchers have taken other possible explanations into account and have effectively ruled out such alternate explanations. In other words, it is always necessary to consider multiple hypotheses before making conclusions about the causal relationship between any two items under investigation. Historically speaking, discussions of causal criteria arose from the recognised limitations of the Henle-Koch postulates, formalised in the late 19th century to establish causation for infectious agents. These postulates required the causal factor to be necessary and present, applied only to a subset of infectious organisms, and conflict with multifactorial causal explanations. The non-specificity of causal agents was of particular concern Two lists of criteria published before 1960 did not include specificity, and instead included consistency and replication, strength, dose-response, experimentation, temporality and biological reasonableness. The term ‘criteria for causation’ applied to Hill’s list of factors to consider before inferring causation from an observed association. Hill himself however never called these considerations criteria, but rather referred to them as viewpoints and never saw them as the ‘hardand-fast’ rules of evidence. Nevertheless, the publication of his landmark address to the Royal Society of Medicine is frequently cited as the authorative source for causal criteria in epidemiological practice. (NB- Guys, I know this is kind of the same as the LO Ash did in wk 15 but this is what I understood the LO to be about and from what I asked other ppl about this is what they said to do. If you think it is wrong or want me to do something else let me know!) 2. Identify and Discuss Ethical Issues in Immunization While there are many views on what constitutes acceptable child rearing, in Australia parental discretion is limited primarily by legislation against abuse or neglect. In decisions involving medical treatment, the legal starting point is that the united view of both parents is correct in identifying the child's welfare. Parental decisions are usually overridden when the court feels that the child's life is endangered. While vaccine administration is not considered in the category of immediately life saving, vaccinations satisfy criteria for preventive interventions in children. So in essence, should vaccinations be compulsory? Ethical Considerations A need to balance the rights of individuals in deciding whether to be vaccinated with rights of society to be protected from infectious disease If people believe they have the right to be free from infectious disease, then they should just vaccinate themselves. Transmission from an un-vaccinated person to a vaccinated person is very low. The community at large may have a right to be able to receive immunisation if a vaccine is available, the risk of contracting disease is high, and the cost is not prohibitive If parents do not wish for their child to be immunised, can health care workers be justified in vaccinating anyway as they believe it to be in the Childs best interests? Dealing with issues of capacity and competence Paternalism It can be argued that parents have the right to raise their children without interference from others. Also, the family has a right to privacy Putting child at risk as child is not yet autonomous A child has the right to vaccination if the danger of severe infection is great and a safe vaccine is available. Parents must maintain a minimum level of care for their children Risk Perception Informed consent Risks may seem more real than advantages Risks are more visible than disease when vaccination rates are high There is a perceived low risk of illness, even if not immunised (but this is actually dependant on maintaining herd immunity through high immunisation levels). Individuals and the Community Herd immunity requires high vaccination rates. Where this exists, unvaccinated people get benefits without risk. - Herd immunity is in essence a type of common good. There is an obligation to contribute to common good. Failure to immunise can lead to harm to others. - As herd immunity fails the benefits of vaccination are once again seen.