Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
THE MORAL NATURE OF ARTISTIC GENIUS by Brian Schampan Hughes Dissertation Committee: Professor John Baldacchino, Sponsor Professor Graeme Sullivan Approved by the Committee on the Degree of Doctor of Education Date_________________________ Submitted in partial fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Education in Teachers College, Columbia University 2006 © Brian Schampan Hughes 2006 Some Rights Reserved. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 2.5 License. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/2.5/ or send a letter to Creative Commons, 543 Howard Street, 5th Floor, San Francisco, California, 94105, USA. ii For all my teachers iii Acknowledgments My scholarship benefits from the generous support of my family, friends, and colleagues. Writing is both a pleasure and a chore, and I am lucky that there are so many people in my life who both value good writing and have standards for clarity of thought and prose to which I can only aspire. Professors Chris Higgins, John Baldacchino, Graeme Sullivan, David Hansen, Judy Burton, and John Broughton all contributed to this project with their expertise, insight, and patience. Additionally, I thank Professor Gary Natriello for supplementing my graduate education with the opportunity to be a part of his work. I am especially indebted to Chris Higgins for his impassioned philosophical guidance. His interests and expertise greatly influenced my course of graduate study as it was he who introduced me to MacIntyre and Gadamer. Where I have achieved success in understanding the problems of education, it is his success. I am grateful to my friends Brian Reilly and Matthew Slater for helping me learn how to live as a perpetual student of philosophyâthey are both great interlocutors on topics vast and colloquial. For teaching me what it means to live as an artist, I thank Hugo Ortega Lopez. His passion for inquiry is infectious, and without his example I would have abandoned this project for simpler pleasures. iv For always supporting me, no matter what career or life I envisaged for myself, I would like to thank my parents, my grandparents, and even my brother. One could not hope for a more caring and intellectual family, and I admire them greatly. I want especially to thank Suzanne, my wife, for her unwavering encouragement and inspiration. As a cellist, she carries forward a vibrant and poetic tradition, and my interest in artâs vital contributions to human flourishing redoubled when I first heard her play. I am, and will always remain, in awe of her artistic achievement. B. S. H. v Table of Contents Acknowledgments . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . iv Table of Contents . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . vi List of Figures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ix INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .1 PART IâWHY GENIUS MATTERS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7 IâMORAL DIMENSIONS OF ART PRACTICE . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8 1. On Excellence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8 1.1 Wolfâs Two Kinds of Moral Saints. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10 1.2 Problems with Wolfâs View. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14 1.3 Moral Philosophy for Common Sense. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 2. Gauguinâs Moral Life . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21 2.1 Painting and Morality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21 2.2 Reflections on Identity. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 26 2.3 Portrait of a Genius. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35 2.4 Summary. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38 3. A Subject of Moral Philosophy. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39 4. Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41 IIâARTISTIC ACHIEVEMENT . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43 1. An Artistâs Narrative Quest . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .43 1.1 The Turn to Philosophy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45 1.2 An Early Hypothesis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49 1.3 The Matter of Trust . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52 1.4 Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55 2. Elaboration of MacIntyreâs Project . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .56 2.1 Traditions and Anti-Traditions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59 3. Art as Inquiry. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62 3.1 Kinds of Inquiry . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 63 3.2 Aesthetic Experience . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 66 3.3 John Deweyâs Philosophy of Education . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 70 3.4 Art for Oneâs Self. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 72 4. Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .78 vi IIIâCONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .80 1. The Problem of Artistic Genius. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 80 1.1 A Brief Genealogy. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 80 1.2 Research Questions. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 87 2. Methodology. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .89 2.1 My Approach to the Problem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .89 2.2 My Analysis of the Problem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91 2.3 My Argument for Artists . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 94 2.4 My Aim as a Philosopher of Art Education . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .96 3. Limitations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .99 3.1 Moralities and Languages . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .102 3.2 Disciplinary Boundaries . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 104 PART IIâHOW WE THINK ABOUT ARTISTS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 107 IVâSOCIAL DIMENSIONS OF MORALITY. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108 1. Lessons From Psychology. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108 2. Attribution Theory. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .109 2.1 Epistemic Foundations of Morality. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 111 2.2 Minimal Persons. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 114 2.3 Attribution Biases. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .117 3. The Third Person Perspective. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 120 3.1 Genius as a Trait. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .123 4. Conclusion. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .126 VâACHIEVEMENT OF SUBORDINATION. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 128 1. Excellence in Practices. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .128 1.1 Philosophy of Education . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .133 2. The Value of Educational Goods . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .137 2.1 MacIntyreâs View of Subordination. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .137 2.2 The Development of Excellence. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139 2.3 Two Kinds of Goods . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 142 3. Education Without Virtue. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .145 3.1 Teachers and Students . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 145 3.2 The Practice of Education . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 150 4. Conclusion. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .156 VIâHERMENEUTIC EXCELLENCE. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 158 1. Gadamerâs Philosophical Hermeneutics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 158 1.1 Artworks as Examples . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 160 2. The Nature of Understanding . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .169 2.1 Subordination as Coming to an Agreement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 171 2.2 Subordination as a Path of Understanding. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 173 2.3 Subordination as a Traditionary Event . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .181 2.4 Subordination as Hermeneutic Excellence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .189 vii 3. Verticality in Practices. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .194 4. Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 195 PART IIIâCRITIQUE OF GENIUS. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .197 VIIâMORALITY AS SUCH . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .198 1. The Metaphysical Tradition. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 198 2. The Way Kant Saw Nature in the Subject . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .200 2.1 What Counts as Nature. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 204 2.2 Two Kinds of Beauty . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 208 3. Boundaries of the Concept of Genius. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 210 3.1 Two Kinds of Excellence. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 211 3.2 Originality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 215 3.3 Exemplarity. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 218 3.4 Summary. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 223 4. The Moral Wilderness. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 224 VIIIâWHY EDUCATION MATTERS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229 1. Where We Are Now. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .229 2. Awareness of Genius. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .230 3. Implications for Pedagogy. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .237 4. The Future of Art Education. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 241 REFERENCES. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .246 viii List of Figures Figure 1. Paul Gauguin, Self-Portrait with Portrait of Émile Bernard, 1888. . . . . . . . . .28 Figure 2. Paul Gauguin, Self-Portrait with Halo, 1889. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .31 Figure 3. Paul Gauguin, Self-Portrait with Yellow Christ, 1889. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .32 Figure 4. Paul Gauguin, Christ in the Garden of Olives, 1889. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .34 Figure 5. Pablo Picasso, Weeping Woman, 1937 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 161 Figure 6. Pablo Picasso, Weeping Woman, 1937 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 161 Figure 7. Pablo Picasso, Weeping Woman, 1937 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 163 Figure 8. Brian Hughes, Untitled (5 of 7), 2005. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 163 Figure 9. Photograph from War Images (Hughes, 2005). Artwork: Brian Hughes, Untitled (21 Images), 2005. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 165 Figure 10. Photograph from War Images (Hughes, 2005). Artworks: Brian Hughes, Untitled (9 Images), 2005 [left]. Brian Hughes, Untitled (6 of 7), 2005 [right] . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .166 Figure 11. Brian Hughes, Untitled (6 of 7), 2005. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .168 Figure 12. Brian Hughes, Untitled (7 of 7), 2005. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .168 ix 1 INTRODUCTION In addition to inquiry, history, and craftsmanship, art education should be about learning how to live as an artist. As such, it can be more than advisement about prudence or perseveranceâit can be about nurturing a young artistâs intellectual and emotional sense of himself or herself. Ultimately, this sense of self has many different aspects and therefore goes by many namesâself-esteem, self-knowledge, identity, critical awareness, critical consciousness, metacognition, and so onâbut I believe it is best understood more broadly as a feature of moral life. By this I mean to suggest that the cultivation of this sense of self is saddled with the array of philosophical problems that supervene on oneâs conception of morality, and pedagogy should therefore respond to those problems. This convergence of philosophy and education is the legacy of Western ethics in contemporary art practice. According to this view, art practice is a central feature of artistsâ lives. Though it is a contested matter as to how the terms âethicsâ and âmoralityâ should obtain to everyday life, here I follow a philosophical tradition that understands them both as pertaining (similarly) to âgoodnessâ as excellence. The notion of moral excellence is different than artistic excellence, and the purpose of philosophizing about art practice 2 in this way is to invite artists to reflect on the impact and significance of their ordinary endeavors. I believe Socrates was right in his assertion that such reflection is part of living a good life. Reflection as such often leads artists to consider how their projects and processes emerge from interactions with other artistsâone kind of artistic influence. Given that the lives of practicing artists are shaped by diverse interactions of this kind, given that these interactions inform ongoing dialogues about art, and given that these dialogues shape both the surrounding culture and the reception of art, artists should have a theoretical and practical interest in this aspect of art practice. Social interactions of this kind can be treated philosophically as a special kind of influence which will here be considered as an essential aspect of art practice, at least with respect to the aims and institutions of art education. There are many details about interpersonal relationships that artists can investigate, and many vibrant discourses in which these investigations can proceed: psychology, social psychology, sociology, and anthropology to name a few. For theorizing about more universal modes of interaction on a more abstract level, however, artists can and should turn to philosophy in general, and moral philosophy in particular. One overarching argument of my dissertation is that virtue ethicsâa particular discourse in moral philosophyâis useful for understanding art practice because it treats the evaluation of extraordinary achievements in diverse dimensions of social practices as a primary task of social life. It is well suited, therefore, as an 3 explanatory framework for practices whose contributions to social life can be amplified by the methodological rigor of the human sciences. Morality is one concept that intersects with art practice in many ways, and it is often invoked in discussions about artists and art practices by a wider community. To better regulate these discussions, and carve out a space for art in those communities, artists will benefit from understanding the various meanings of the concept and how they are deployed as rhetorical strategies. This understanding is not easily achieved, and artists will find themselves working alongside philosophers to untangle the long history and many aspects of morality. One helpful method, however, will be to understand the distinctive historical parts and features of the broader and more universal concept: notions, for example, such as âgoodnessâ and âmoral excellenceâ that resonate within particular moral traditions. Some virtue ethicistsâoften referred to as âcommunitariansââclaim that the meaning of moral excellence, like morality itself, is negotiated within a community. Here I will argue that the concept of âartistic geniusâ poses a great difficulty for artists affected by this negotiation. As a result, because of its association with âtalentâ as the ânaturalâ arbiter of artistic success as well as the entrenched and often perplexing philosophical discourse that seeks to explain it, the concept of genius is poised to unhinge young artists from traditionâa potential educational disruption that undermines art practice as a site of meaningful (and, therefore, fulfilling) activity. The aim of my dissertation is to rehabilitate the concept of genius for artists who seek to engage art practice despite widespread disagreement about what makes art 4 âgood.â I argue that the concept exerts a powerful influence on artists, and that its rehabilitation is seen partly as a debunking of what artists and philosophers have hitherto understood as genius, and partly as an explanation of the artistic activity that often coincides with that recognition. Part I of my dissertation explores the foundational elements of this critique beginning with an overview of the ongoing difficulties of moral theory. In Chapters I and II, I illustrate how the concept of artistic genius can impact artists and their art practices. I show how the concept of artistic genius influenced the life and art of Paul Gauguin. Gauguin serves as a useful example for moral philosophy because he achieved eminence in the artworld while ordering his life and values in an uncommon way according to prevailing social norms. His example shows how perceptions of excellence in one sphere of social life can conflict with what is deemed immoral in another. I make the case that supererogation is wrongly distinguished from moral goodness on the grounds that art practice is only one aspect of an artistâs âwhole lifeâ (as well as the society in which he or she lives). Susan Wolfâs discussion of moral saints prepares moral philosophers for this tension. Saintliness, she claims, is not a tenable moral ideal because it requires that ordinary people (and philosophers) hold the view that achievement in a specific and narrow set of human behaviors defines our conception of goodness. Her discussion of the possible outcomes for moral philosophy is ultimately not as interesting as her discussion of common sense, which she foregrounds as intertwined with assumptions about morality. If we take her argument one step further and take common sense seriously, we find that practical ideals are a 5 better indicator of social values, of which âsaintlinessâ is only one name for excellence among many. In this way, moral evaluation is shown to be practice-specific, and a conceptualization of the social qualities of art practice can proceed on a sturdier philosophical foundation. Starting a critique of genius with an eye to the problem of eminence and supererogation in a moral context, I then discuss genius as a conceptual problem in my own experience of art making and art practice in Chapter II. I reflect on how my engagement with artistic processes is complicated by philosophical discourses surrounding art, and how I am able to sustain artistic production only through those discourses by arriving at an understanding of art as inquiry. The view that art practice should be cultivated as a space for inquiry is articulated as a grounding assumption of the critique of genius that follows, and John Deweyâs philosophy of education serves as a touchstone for this naturalistic view. Chapter III presents a conceptual framework for my dissertation and shows 1) how a critique of genius fits with other research and 2) what are the aims and limitations of the critique. From the perspective of moral philosophy, the concept of genius is related to the relationship between individuals and tradition. Hans-Georg Gadamerâs philosophy speaks to these relationships, and Alasdair MacIntyreâs philosophy locates Gadamerâs theory of understanding as a moral one from the perspective of artists and art practice. In Part IIâChapters IV, V, and VIâI critique MacIntyreâs view of education, and put forward a framework for understanding moral excellence that is informed by the field of moral psychology. I argue that a studentâs relationship to a teacher can be analogous 6 to a mature practitionerâs experience of tradition, and that MacIntyreâs theory of âentering into practicesâ leads to a valuable and defensible philosophy of educationâ one that is grounded in the history of ethics, and therefore capable of sustaining the sense of artistic achievement as a social and historical process. Finally, I discuss Gadamerâs hermeneutic model of tradition as a model of moral excellence. I propose that hermeneutic excellenceâwhat I call an educational goodâdrives subordination and sustains vertical relationships among artists. In Part III of the dissertation, I turn to Immanuel Kantâs view of genius to test how well my model of hermeneutic excellence maps onto the historic concept of genius. Kant proposes that a genius is a creator of original and exemplary artworks, and in Chapter VII, I argue that Kantâs view of beauty leads to his misunderstanding of originality and exemplarity. My critique of genius ends with a discussion of its relevance for moral philosophy as a more elegant description of âforward-thinkingâ practitioners than has thus far been available to MacIntyrian virtue ethicists. Chapter VIII considers how subordination and hermeneutic excellence influence communities in which artists live and work, and draws out the implications of this conceptualization of genius for artists and art educators. 7 PART IâWHY GENIUS MATTERS Being an Art Student, we proudly recognized, entailed many diverse and complicated activities. The most important of these activities included: i) Wearing clothes that were made, or at least altered, at home. ii) Smoking lesser-known brands of cigarettes. iii) Drinking far more coffee than is good for someone your age, or any age for that matter. iv) Discussing the set design or lighting instead of the plot of any randomly chosen television show, including cartoons. v) Being unemployed, or if it was absolutely necessary for you to be employed, at least have the decency to do so sporadically. T. Gregory Argall, 2006, p. 1. 8 IâMORAL DIMENSIONS OF ART PRACTICE 1. On Excellence Artistic genius is rarely confused with saintliness. Pablo Picasso is widely believed to be the greatest painter of the twentieth century, but he was also an arrogant and belligerent womanizer. Recognizing genius or saintliness becomes more complex, however, when one tries to discern geniuses and saints among broader populations of artists or morally excellent persons. What makes a person suited for such recognition? How good must one be, and in what way? Though suspicion about the nature of genius and saintliness may arise, we have ways of negotiating this recognition in everyday life. We make judgments that emerge from various and diverse motivations, and the precision of our judgment is often of no great concern. Though this tells us nothing of our accuracy in such matters, it should serve to remind us that both concepts serve us in tangible, if different, ways. I offer the comparison between saints and geniuses because I am interested in understanding the concept of artistic genius within a moral framework. I am also, however, interested in a different framework for discerning âmoral excellenceâ than is 9 typical of our ordinary notion of morality,1 and Susan Wolfâs (1982) observations about moral saints help to open a normative discussion about moral excellence understood in this special way.2 Specificallyâand this is also an aim of my dissertationâshe demonstrates how identifying and characterizing a type or class of persons can impact the way philosophers do ethics. Wolf claims that the case of moral saintsâindividuals who are commonly understood to be âas morally worthy as can beâ (Wolf, 1982, p. 29)âpresents a problem for moral philosophers. By showing why, counter to intuition, sainthood is not a compelling ideal to which individuals should aspire, she aims to refine how philosophers can construct moral theories.3 Her argument helps both to foreground the conceptual complexity of genius, and opens a more fruitful dialogue about the intersection of art and morality than is typical of artworld discourses. 1 The use of a moral framework is motivated by my interest in expanding our moral vocabulary to include such things as excellence in the arts. I follow philosophers such as Bernard Williams (1985) who argue that âmoralityâ commonlyâand wronglyârefers only to a subset of ethical considerations. Thus, what Williams refers to as âethics,â I optimistically call âmoral life.â For an extended discussion of what counts as ethical consideration, see Williams (1985), especially Chapter I. 2 Flanagan (1991) helpfully cautions against Anscombeâs recommendation that the term âmoralâ be jettisoned by contrasting her Aristotelian vision of philosophical psychology with Kohlbergâs stark depiction of justice as the primary good of modernity (pp. 181-183). I will attempt to use the term with restraint, and discuss the terms âmoralityâ and âethicsâ at length below, especially in Chapter IV, Section 2.1. 3 Wolf orients her audience toward a thoughtful view of a relevant aspect of moralityâsaintlinessâ in the process of undertaking this other project. This educative, practical function of philosophy also motivates my project. 10 1.1 Wolfâs Two Kinds of Moral Saints Wolf distinguishes between two kinds of moral saints in Western culture: loving saints and rational saints. Each kind of saint is driven by a unique motivational system, she argues, even though all saints are committed to âimproving the welfare of others or of society as a wholeâ (Wolf, 1982, p. 30). The former is predisposed to enjoy the promotion of the welfare of others, while the latter promotes othersâ welfare by choice (p. 30). But Wolf quickly makes a distinction between these internal motivations and a saintâs public persona, thus arriving at a general definition of moral sainthood as the possession and cultivation of a disposition that enables one to act âas justly and kindly toward others as possibleâ (p. 31). In doing so, she arrives at a sensible, socialâ though somewhat thinâconception of saintliness that begins to tease apart the inner nature of âcommon senseâ morality as she understands it. The moral saint is contrasted with a person possessing a more moderate moral temperament. While an ordinary person can spend time âreading Victorian novels, playing the oboe, or improving his backhandâ (p. 31)âwhat she describes as nonmoral virtuesâthese activities are practically inaccessible to the saint, whose attention is concentrated on performing selfless acts. Indeed, as she articulates how the saint is different in scope and kind, the unlikelihood of sainthood becomes palpable. We are as impressed with the saintâs drive and devotion to othersâ needs as we are startled by the starkness of such a life. In this way, an essential characteristic of moral sainthood on 11 Wolfâs account is the narrowing of a life around a small set of what she calls âmoral virtuesââwhat are more commonly understood as selfless acts. It seems troublesome that our ordinary notion of morality is often governed by such extremes, yet this spectrum is practically definitive of morality. Indeed, Wolfâs depiction of sainthood along these lines colors the domain of morality from the outset. One could object, for example, that sainthood has nothing to do with degrees of selflessness. I believe Wolfâs response would be that this contradicts the fact that saints do exist and our awareness of their saintliness is clearly predicated on such characteristics. This situation, therefore, leaves us wanting alternative examples of moral excellence which will, if not contradict saintliness as vision of the good life, at least diversify the ends in view. To this effect, Wolf contrasts the moral saint with individuals who have high moral standards but are not similarly exemplary. These virtuous non-saints are defined by such qualities as âcoolnessâ and âgracefulness,â and Wolf elides a finer distinction between these and other virtue-like qualities, insisting that these qualities expand our conception of morality precisely because they are ânonmoralâ (1982, p. 32). 4 Either way, as nonmoral virtues or as the very kind of virtues that some moral theorists imagine, I agree with Wolf that such cases serve to 4 The notion of ânonmoral virtuesâ seems to confuse the matter more than it helps. On one hand, I take Wolf to be using the term âvirtueâ to be synonymous with a personal trait, which seems to beg the question of how virtue necessarily constitutes moral sainthood. Virtue and saintliness seem inseparable precisely because of her ordinary language approach which implies that virtues are essentially moral, even if we allow her use of the redundant term âmoral virtueâ to lend a philosophical punch to her argument. Lacking a distinction here, there is no immediately obvious connection between the case of moral saints and moral philosophy, insofar as moral philosophy would be completely unhinged from the history of virtue that gathers itself and makes sense of the narrow quality of saintliness. 12 orient us in an ever wider milieu of culture and expand our perception of degrees of goodness in persons. The problem that remains, then, is the way moral goodness is configured. That is, a virtuous non-saint is able to balance her commitments to competing ideals, but a saint cannot, as âthe desire to be as morally good as possible is apt to have the character not just of a stronger but of a higher desire, which does not merely successfully compete with oneâs other desires but which rather subsumes or demeans themâ (p. 32). Thus, according to Wolfâs understanding of common sense morality, the belief that selflessness is the highest moral good casts a long shadow over our shared conception of morality. Since we are likely (in a greater public) to encounter individuals who are predisposed toward saintliness or who actively choose selflessness as a way of life, we are forced from time to time to confront the inadequacies of this thin ideal. Though it seems counterintuitive, perhaps it should not surprise us that exemplary moral personalities, according to the ideal of moral saints, do not inspire us. As Wolf suggests, we have more nuanced standards for moral excellence that go unstated or unacknowledged when we esteem the moral saint as an exemplar of morality. Similarly, she cites the lack or denial of an identifiable, personal self as the key feature not only of the moral saint, but shared by âthe conception of the pure aesthete, by a certain kind of religious ideal, and, somewhat paradoxically, by the model of the thorough-going, self-conscious egoistâ (p. 33). Thus, she offers us a glimpse at a strange aspect of contemporary moralityâsome ideals of which short-circuit the possibilities for unique and differentiated (according to lifestyle) individuals. 13 Exemplary personalities such as moral saints, Wolf goes on to argue, do not serve to inspire us because they are not in fact exemplary. That is, she claims the common sense view that associates extremeness with exemplarity is sometimes misguided. She claims that these personalities often embody âways of comprehending the world⌠[that] compete with what we ordinarily mean by âmorality,ââ and that as personal ideals they are âstraightforwardly immoralâ (p. 33).5 This claim is based on her observation that it is ânot how much [the saint] loves morality, but⌠how little he loves⌠other thingsâ (p. 33). That is, because the saint is myopic in his actions, we can also interpret his behavior as the result of disinterestedness. Here, her strategy of deploying a thinly wrought depiction of moral saints as perfectly selfless pays offâthe saint cum straw man represented by few actual personalities transforms easily into a portrait of moral deformation. The matter of whether a saint is necessarily (or even possibly) morally good seems doubtfulâWolf carefully insulates the ideal of the saint from the realities that make it a less interesting concept to her. But how can this be right? By accounting for some âinadequaciesâ of common sense, she successfully avoids rejecting saintliness as an ideal (though she all but claims we are wrong to think of saints as exemplary), and shifts the discussion of morality to a different ground. She sacrifices the saint, figuratively speaking, to make room for a view of morality that recognizes diverse ends of personhood as on par with, and perhaps even preferable to, the moral worth of the 5 This claim reveals an agenda that accommodates complexity in everyday life, yet Wolf 14 myopic saint. She challenges the ordinary conception of the value of sainthood by claiming that a common sense view of moral excellence commits us to a different ideal. I will call this her expansionist argument. 1.2 Problems with Wolfâs View Wolfâs work to locate the discussion of saints in moral theory becomes a serious weakness for her account of morality. By simultaneously upholding saintliness as an ideal but criticizing it as a compelling model, her argument occupies a strange middle ground between widening the scope of moral theoryâto include such things as âstriving toward achieving any of a great variety of forms of personal excellenceâ (p. 34)âand restricting the scope of what âmoralityâ may describe. Moral philosophers are no strangers to the tension here. Wolf discusses how her attempt to depict the moral saint originates from âattitudes and beliefs about morality prevalent in contemporary, common sense thoughtâ (p. 34), and, aware of the tensions that arise, admits that âit is often claimed that the goal of moral philosophy is to correct and improve upon common sense moralityâ (p. 35). Wolf wants to apply moral philosophy to resolve conflicts between moralitiesâor within a moralityâand call this meta-ethics. Based on the irony about saints to which Wolf draws our attention, moral philosophy seems unlikely to achieve this goal, for it is not only a case of conceptual confusionâwhere an successfully avoids imputing the quality of well-roundedness as a more satisfactory âhighest good.â 15 ideal is really not an idealâbut it is also unclear that there would be room for improvement. For how, we might ask, should one go about correcting common sense? To no really fruitful end, she uses the case of the moral saint as a litmus test for both utilitarian and Kantian ethics, and claims these theories are woefully inadequate to take on complex issues of personhood (e.g., adopting a ready-made utilitarian discourse, she speculates that the moral saint is naturally suited to bringing about more âhappinessâ in the world than the average personâs disposition of wellroundedness). The best thing that could be said about this part of her essay is that it sounds the death-knoll for an unhelpful trend in moral philosophy, which is best articulated by Bernard Williams (whom she cites) as the over-simplification of the domain of morality. She âbegins againâ by taking Kantian and utilitarian theoriesââthe leading moral theories of our timeâ (p. 35)âas starting points, and her newly-wrought, two-pronged story of moral saints (i.e., the âcommon senseâ view) as a rival theory that will perhaps push against or support one of these theories. Wolf insists that her story of moral saints is not inconsistent with either theory, and that moral theories in general are overvalued as theories that tell us âwhat it would be good for a person to beâ (p. 40). By teasing apart the strong prescriptive aspects of Kantianism and utilitarianism from the merely descriptive aspects, she pushes back the question of how ideals compel us to act differently than we would otherwise act. We are left with theories that merely lump some people together according to the degree to which they act selflessly. Wolf seems unwilling to entertain moral theories that begin with a positive conception of the self. Thus, her response to 16 Aristotelian and Nietzschean approaches to morality falls flat.6 Instead of aligning morality with goodness, she characterizes it as âthe point of view one takes up insofar as one takes the recognition of the fact that one is just one person among others equally real and deserving of the good things in life as a fact with practical consequencesâ (p. 41)âan articulation that relies on a parochial, and particularly materialistic, attitude toward goodness. Morality would be born of a sense of commonality and a recognition of inequality. This resonates as a reasonable, contemporary, and Western definition of morality, but it does not follow from her earlier claim that moral philosophy is committed to correcting and improving upon common sense morality. What Wolf calls âthe point of view of individual perfectionâ is awkwardly divorced from âthe moral point of view,â and it seems disingenuous to treat individual perfection as a nonmoral component of common sense morality. Or at least, if morality is so theoretically restricted, then we should expect some greater payoff from moral philosophy. As if there were already enough goodwill in the world, even while we are not personally contributing time and energy to increase the welfare of others, Wolfâs reasoning simply affords us the chance to cast off our remaining pangs of guilt. 6 Wolf seems to miss the point of these alternative approaches entirely when she says, âit is doubtful that any single, or even any reasonable small number of substantial personal ideals could capture the full range of possible ways of realizing human potential or achieving human good which deserve encouragement or praiseâ (1982, p. 39). Refuting grand narratives and unified accounts of morality seems to be very much the point of these other theories. 17 With this strange turn of her argument in mind, it seems to me one has to abandon up front the notion that morality pertains to a special aspect of personhood (such as selflessness), and replace it with the notion that morality has to do with a broad conception of excellence.7 This cuts to the chase of the philosophical difficulty represented by moral saints. Instead of admitting that the moral saint represents the ideal of common sense morality up front, one can simply approach this as one ideal among others. As a philosophical approach, this more accurately reflects actually held idealsâthe preferences we have for the âBetsy Trotwoods and Father Browns,â who she cites as compelling figures for the ways their dispositions cut against the ideal of saintlinessâ as well as admit a lack of trustworthy data on the matter. For when moral philosophers start talking about âunequivocally compelling personal ideals,â it is perhaps best to be suspicious about the conversations that follow. What Wolf seems to desire from the outset is conceptual clarity about morality itself. For it is less a problem that moral saints are too selfless, than it is a problem of moral saints being actual ideals for moral philosophers in the business of both characterizing a shared vision of morality in a culture, or, conversely, classifying varieties of moral personality. By beginning with common sense morality as a framework, Wolf is limited to a particular philosophical registerâone that aims to leave 7 Excellence, even more than goodness, seems to capture the prescriptive nature of âcommon sense morality.â In doing so, it may also go hand-in-hand with a concern for, and emphasis of, the individual. I will return to this matter below in Chapter V, Section 1.1. 18 intact certain normative values and beliefs. Especially worrisome for me is the thought that moral philosophy is essentially limited by what can pass as common sense. Unlike Wolf, I would prefer there be more personal reasons for embarking on quests for conceptual clarity. I believe (along pragmatic and hermeneutic lines of thought) that oneâs initial trajectory has consequences for the whole affair. Without such an orientation in inquiry, one runs the risk of basing new hypotheses upon already doubtful conjecture (as Wolf achieves in the case of imagining the utilitarian and Kantian reactions to the moral saint), which then throws a dim light on the whole business of theorizing. Wolfâs essay demonstrates not only how bracketing out complexities can be instrumental for the meta-ethicist, but also how easily theory can lose traction on the problems that motivate theorists. That is, just because common sense morality can be backed into a corner (where it is swiftly shown to contain contradictory impulses), it does not follow that philosophers should aim to âpurifyâ the meaning or significance of our moralities. 1.3 Moral Philosophy for Common Sense Contrary to Wolfâs view, conceptual clarity about morality is not what is shown to be needed when confronting the case of moral saints, even (and especially) from the perspective of meta-ethics. The theory she calls for is too thinâuninterested in everyday (ânonmoralâ) human experiences and not sensitive enough to the history of ethics. Instead, analyses of our ideals seem to be in order, and a moral theory that is 19 attentive to the thick language of human activity is needed. Insofar as an ideal intersects with what is understood to be morality, such an analysis could explore tensions between the so-called morality of common sense and other moral theories in ways that aim to settle conceptual disputes. Her expansionist argument will be shown to be admirable in this regard. But recent work in moral philosophy may be beside the point when a more focused historical and conceptual analysis gets off the ground.8 It is just this kind of analysis I have in mind here. The ideal of the artistic genius, if not precisely represented by the notion of pure aestheticism, fits quite well on Wolfâs list of ideal types that problematically represent moral excellence. As Wolf shows, the nature of ideals raises many questions, so a rich discussion of genius is only possible if we begin with the complexities of ideals in view. We should ask, for example, if the genius is seen to be similar to the saint, how could he both represent and not represent moral excellence? And perhaps we can question, without conceiving of the work of moral philosophy as starkly hypothetical as Wolf does, what the concept of artistic genius means for morality. This is possible if we accept as a premise that artistic genius in a name for artistic excellence. If moral excellence is understood as achievement within a social sphere whether this means helping other people or making art, then moral philosophers can conceive of morality as a function of education. From an educational perspective, for example, the developmental picture of being a good person is similar to becoming a good artist. 8 If the aim of philosophy is to be prescriptive, then moral philosophy and âcommon sense moralityâ 20 Must this only imply a developmental similarity? To what extent do beauty and goodness, commonly understood as two different kinds of excellence, overlap?9 To what extent must they overlap? In surveying art history, we are forced to admit that many great artists have been less than excellent people in other aspects of life. Is this a problem for philosophy? Or is it a clue for better understanding excellence in art? As Wolf has shown, a philosopher must construct a moral theory that has something to say about supererogation while often remaining quiet about other ânonmoralâ ideals. I will follow these recommendations only in part. By developing a multifaceted conception and understanding of artistic development, I hope to highlight various aspects of education, as well as contribute to and modify the social imaginary of contemporary artists and art educators. In the following section, to make my interest in morality clearer still, I examine the effect of the concept of genius on the art practice of a person with uncommon senseâPaul Gauguin. By first looking at the effect of the concept, I show not how common sense contains contradictory views about morality (or even how moral philosophy is wrong about common sense), but how the concept is compatible with a common understanding of moral excellence. This section, an historical vignette, describes the intersection of art making and moral excellence. Gauguin, whose art is widely recognized as innovative and emotional, serves as an extreme example of the close relationship between an artistâs work, his should have more in common when both are done well. 9 I will discuss the relation between beauty and goodness at length below in Chapter VII, Section 3.1. 21 interpretation of his work, and the details of his life. Art critic Peter Schjeldahl observes, âGauguinâs contributions to painting were tremendous. His use of emotionally fraught secondary colorsâaromatic strains of green, orange, and purpleâ was innovative, as was his way of making paint and line practically independent of each otherâ (Schjeldahl, 2002, July 29, p. 83). Innovation such as this may prompt educational questions: Are these examples of the highest good that can be achieved in painting? How is it achieved, and at what cost? And moral questions may follow: Is a âgoodâ such as this the same as excellence? Is excellence the same as virtue (is virtue related to excellence or altogether different)? If not, can excellence be translated as some kind of virtue? Is excellence misunderstood in relation to virtue? What would all this mean for the concept of genius? A closer look at Gauguinâs art and life will show these to be helpful questions for considering the potential and value of art education. 2. Gauguinâs Moral Life 2.1 Painting and Morality The social currents in the Parisian artworld fed into Gauguinâs perception of himself as an artistâhe was, after all, first persuaded to take his painting seriously by his contemporaries (Perruchot, 1963, pp. 70-75). Romanticism and religion, two 22 influential social currents in the nineteenth century, are represented in Gauguinâs artworks. While these two features of artistic consciousness overlap, I propose that the concept of geniusâas an expression of Romanticismâespecially propelled Gauguinâs artistic and spiritual quests. Gauguin abandoned his family and social context in middle age to live as a poor, reclusive painter, ultimately living in Tahiti as an estranged and unhealthy expatriate until his untimely death. Gauguinâs artworks, in conjunction with his writing, are evidence that a conception of genius was an underlying feature of his art and lifeâa comprehensive good that shaped his reception of tradition and transformed his whole life into a mythic quest. We could presume to learn about Gauguinâs self-image from his letters to his wife and friends, but the man we encounter there is enigmatic; we see him as he presented himself differently to different people. The Gauguin we encounter through art appears equally enigmaticâhis diverse oeuvre contains conflicting ideas about his relation to artâbut the sheer intensity of the information gives our observations traction. Among his paintings we may analyze to gain insight into his self-image as an artist, there is a genre of painting that stands out: self-portraiture. That Gauguin was interested in self-portraiture is not easily overlooked: he made over forty different images of his own likeness in several different mediums, including more than twenty oil paintings. Looking closely at several examples of his self-portraiture reveals how a conception of genius shaped his life, but first we need to know how to look. To understand Gauguinâs formation as an artist, and his choice to pursue art making, we should consider the living tradition of painting in France in the 1880âs, 23 where Gauguin first entered the world of art more as a spectator than as an active practitioner. As a banker and part-time painter, he formed friendships with several impressionist painters, including Degas and Monet, who later convinced him to take his own art seriously. By the time he committed to living as an artist in 1883, Pissarro had become a major influence in his life; it was Pissarro who first invited him to show his landscapes with the Impressionists at the Salon of 1879 (Perruchot, 1963, p. 76). Pissarro âtaught Gauguin what he had already taught other painters; he was an enthusiastic upholder of the âclearâ paletteââ (p. 72). It was partly through Pissarro, therefore, that Gauguinâs work came to be identified with Impressionism. Gauguin became increasingly immersed in Impressionism, although there was as much variation among Impressionist artists as there were differences of opinion in the greater circle of French painting, and he would ultimately think of himself as moving beyond it. The Impressionists were transforming the style and content of painting by rejecting academic training; their paintings asserted the authenticity of the artistâs experience in the world. Furthermore, the Parisian artworldâs reception of these pictures reinforced the focusing of tradition on self-expression. This âpathway of discharge,â as Gombrich conceives it (cited by Theodore Reff, personal communication, April 10, 2002), irrevocably shaped Gauguin as a proponent of the first âmodernistâ avant-gardeâdemonstrated throughout his work, but particularly evident in his selling of erotic Tahitian imagery back to the Parisian public (Schjeldahl, 2002, July 29, p. 84). From this lineage, he inherited an approach to painting that prized the artistâs freedomâand desireâto pursue a personal vocabulary. 24 In the nineteenth century, an artistic genius was seen as exemplary because he was believed to create models that others followed.10 He was seen as a creator of original works of artâoriginal because these models were apparently created ex nihilo. Gauguin partly appeared as a genius because, in contrast to many of his contemporaries, he was able to create a distinctive visual and sensuous vernacular in his paintings. With some use of hyperbole, Collingwood (1938/1958) describes the effect this recognition of genius often had on artists: In the later nineteenth century the artist walked among us as a superior being, marked off even by his dress from common mortals; too high and ethereal to be questioned by others, too sure of his superiority to question himself, and resenting the suggestion that the mysteries of his craft should be analysed and theorized about by philosophers and other profane persons. (p. 5) The story of Post-Impressionism is not so simple. In contrast to Gauguinâs circle, there was another group of artists who developed more technical solutions to the problems of Impressionism (Theodore Reff, personal communication, April 10, 2002). Seurat, a main figure in this group of âNeo-Impressionists,â created more impersonal pictures. His innovative cross-hatching and pointillist techniques of applying paint to the canvas were used to construct images with more specific social and political themes. Even before these characteristics appear in paintings, like Sunday Afternoon on the Island of La Grande Jatte (1884-85, 1887), his interest in the descriptive aim of art appears in such improbably unemotional images as his aptly titled 10 I will discuss the history of this belief in Chapter III, Section 1. A note on gendered pronouns, however, is called for here. Women have been infrequently believed to be geniuses due, no doubt, to gender discrimination. While unfortunate, this has affected the meaning of the term, so I will 25 self-portrait An Artist in a Studio (1884). The first criterion of Romantic genius, originality, is fulfilled in Seuratâs work, but not in the form of a self-conscious vision of the artist we will see in Gauguinâs self-portraits. Seuratâs work may be a work of genius, but the subject of the work is not genius. In this way, the work of other artists frames Gauguinâs work as a particularly dramatic example of the effect of Romanticism on artistic consciousness. Seurat does meet the criterion of Gauguinâs conception of artistic greatness. In Gauguinâs opinion, âthe great artist is the embodiment of the greatest intelligence. The sentiments and renderings which occur to him are the most delicate and, consequently, the most invisible products of the human brainâ (as cited in Guérin, 1978, p. 4). Here he is speaking about color, tones, imaginative backgrounds, meaningful narratives, and the placement of the horizon (high) in Cézanneâs work. He continues, âin short, when you see a painting by Cézanne, you cry, âHow strange!ââ (as cited in Guérin, 1978, p. 4). The same could be said of Gauguinâs own work, and he often writes about his success as an artist. For example, in a letter to his then estranged wife, Mette, he writes, âI am a great artist and I know itâ (as cited in Mittelstädt, 1968, p. 29). In 1890, he describes himself as a âsearching and thinkingâ artist in a letter to Émile Bernard. It was this selfconfidence that became his greatest asset during his formation as an artist in the 1880âs; it propeled his development as a painter. often refer to a male subject for the critical part of my study, and to both male and female subjects for the positive part. In this way, I hope my dissertation will further the work of reparation. 26 2.2 Reflections on Identity Four of Gauguinâs self-portraits that help us distinguish between his Romantic and âreligiousâ impulses were painted within the time-span of approximately two years at the end of his formative period as a painter in the 1880âs. They are: Self-Portrait with Portrait of Émile Bernard, Les Misérables (â a lâami Vincent) (1888), Self-Portrait with Halo (1889), Christ in the Garden of Olives (1889), and Self-Portrait with Yellow Christ (1889-90). Taken together, they appear to be an intense meditation on the spiritual possibilities of art making. Gauguinâs excursions to Pont-Aven in 1888-89 mark a turning point for his art. Brittany seems to have fulfilled his appetite for a rich artistic environment, and made him anxious for an even greater kind: in his letters written in the following years, he would repeatedly speak of his desire to leave Europe for more distant shores (Thomson, 1993, p. 82). These excursions away from Paris come a little more than five years after he left his job at the stock market. During that time, an economic depression made it difficult to sell artwork or find part-time work in Paris, and Gauguin was often unemployed and living in severe poverty. His son Clovis often resided with him in Paris, and he was still emotionally and partly financially bound to his distant wife and children. In short, poverty concretized his devotion to art like Pissarro before him, but also severely inhibited his ability to focus on painting. In a notebook for his daughter Aline, he says of poverty: 27 What is terrible, is that it prevents one working and prevents the development of oneâs intellectual faculties⌠It is true, on the other hand, that suffering sharpens oneâs genius. (cited in Perruchot, 1963, p. 133) Indeed, it was true that on the heels of the flourishing art of Impressionism in France, a community of artists considered Gauguinâs art innovative. They fit the image of a cult to Gauguinâs genius. Pont-Aven would afford him a new opportunity to concentrate on painting, as well as a space to cultivate his sensibilities under the scrutiny of the group of artists who lived and worked there. Thriving as the center of attention, he writes Mette in a letter, âI am respected as the best painter in PontAven⌠Everyone discusses my adviceâ (cited in Perruchot, 1963, p. 126). He enjoyed the position of leadership he affected: âthis was all part of a new character he was creating for himself in the atmosphere of respect, indeed of fear, which now surrounded himâ (p. 127). His influence over this group emphasizes their mutual belief in art as a vehicle for a spiritual questâa professed metaphysical aim of Gauguinâs art. Self-Portrait with Portrait of Émile Bernard (Figure 1) is a work conceived with a purpose: it was made for Vincent Van Gogh who was in Arles at the time. Thus, it is intended to portray Gauguinâs self-image to his friend and fellow painter. But the simple, side-view of Émile Bernard in its right-hand cornerâa large, incongruous elementâbrings our attention to a telling story surrounding the paintingâs creation. It is included as a compromise, as originally Bernard and Gauguin were to paint each other, but this was ultimately not possible: Bernard was too intimidated to paint Gauguin, and Gauguin was not really interested in painting Bernard (Mittelstädt, 1968, 28 p. 11). They agreed to include an image of the other in their own self-portrait. In this way, its presence in Gauguinâs self-portrait came about because of his professional relationship with Bernard. That Bernard is rendered only as an outlined image, as if listening to a sermon, is telling. Their relationship, well illustrated by the paintingâs symbolism, is a good example of the type that fed Gauguinâs self-understanding as a spiritual leader. â[Gauguinâs] fecundity and creative power amazed Bernardâ (Perruchot, 1963, p. 155) who was much younger (in his early twenties) than the forty year-old Gauguin. Figure 1. Paul Gauguin, Self-Portrait with Portrait of Émile Bernard, 1888. 29 In a letter to Schuffenecker (October 8th, 1888), Gauguin says of this selfportrait, âI believe it is one of my best paintingsâ (cited in Mittelstädt, 1968, p. 55). In a letter the following week (October 18th), he responds to Schuffeneckerâs conservative response: What do you mean when you talk about my terrifying mysticism? Be an Impressionist all the way and donât let anything frighten you! Of course that appealing path is full of dangers, and so far I have only just begun to follow it, but as a matter of fact it suits my true being, and you must always go where your temperament takes you. (cited in Guérin, 1978, p. 25) The painting depicts him as the character Jean Valjean from Les Misérables, and therefore, he likens himselfâand, by extension, the community of artists with whom he identifiesâto a persecuted criminal (Theodore Reff, personal communication, April 10, 2002). This worries Van Gogh, who writes back to Gauguin in a letter âthis must not go onâ (Mittelstädt, 1968, p. 5). Along with Van Gogh, we understand this image as depicting Gauguinâs perception of himself as a social outcastâan outsider who perseveres against the social pressures of mainstream society. It is an image that pleases Gauguin. He portrays himself with a confident, if somewhat forlorn expression. The bold yellow-orange background and floral details representative of the Symbolist style give us insight into the emotional content, and it is better evidence of Gauguinâs confident attitude about his life as an artist rather than the brooding meditation that Van Gogh perceives. Self-Portrait with Halo (Figure 2) adds to our understanding of Gauguinâs selfperception. Here, Gauguin creates a very different kind of image, and we have to speculate about his purpose(s). Again he makes use of ornamental details to situate his 30 portrait in an abstract environment, but now he foregrounds an even more prominent representation of a serpent. With the halo above his head, this image has been understood to show Gauguin, ironically, as a âsynthetisticâ saint (Mittelstädt, 1968, p. 59). He was experimenting with different techniques during this period, and he identified with the goals of the Symbolists, as demonstrated by his lithograph of Jean Moréas (Be a Symbolist â Jean Moréas) he made in 1891. He uses bold, uniform colors and invented imagery to describe his inner life, while outwardly comparing his life to that of a saint contemplating a serpentâan image that is surprisingly similar in tone to the image of Gauguin behind the mask of Jean Valjean. It is also proposed that this is a satirical representation of himself as Christ (the physical similarity being noticed by his fellow painters in Brittany) (Mittelstädt, 1968, p. 59), and though this is based only on the presence of biblical imagery, it does gesture toward his subsequent identification with Christ in other paintings. At least, it situates this image in a dialectic of selfimagery: its immediate reception and surrounding dialogue is evidence of Gauguinâs interest in the nature of artistic consciousness. He seems to ask, âIs the artist a saint?â 31 Figure 2. Paul Gauguin, Self-Portrait with Halo, 1889. Self-Portrait with Yellow Christ (Figure 3) appears to us as a kind of protopsychoanalytic self-portrait, and it helps us to understand Gauguinâs resolution to this conflict between strikingly different identities. The image captures the artist affecting a reflective demeanor; he looks just beyond us, filling the space with a quiet, distant feeling. He is about to speak. Is he addressing us? He is positioned between objects of his own making: a painting, Yellow Christ (1888), and an earthenware jug, Jug in the 32 shape of a Grotesque Head (Self-portrait) (1889). The paintingâs reversed image leads us to believe that Gauguin is using a mirror to observe this scene, and he appears to be looking back over his shoulder at it. In this reflection, he is turned toward the jug conjoined with his face on the picture plane, creating a kind of double image: a looming orange mask that holds our gaze as it contrasts with his cool blue sweater. There is almost no detail in the surrounding space to suggest a setting, with the exception of the landscape in Yellow Christ. The composition is full of facesâGauguin surrounded by his self-portraiture. Figure 3. Paul Gauguin, Self-Portrait with Yellow Christ, 1889. 33 Another painting from 1889 makes the inclusion of the image of Yellow Christ more complex. Christ in the Garden of Olives (Figure 4) appears to be a self-portrait as well: the image of Christ has the characteristic angular nose we attribute to Gauguin (Theodore Reff, personal communication, April 10, 2002). The fact that these paintings are made in the same year makes a conjecture about the thematic continuity of his self-identification as Christ viableâthe biblical passageâs narrative becomes a telling element in his self-portraiture. Christ in the Garden of Olives depicts Christ in a moment of repose. The Gospels of Matthew, Mark, and Luke describe the significance of Christâs presence in the Garden of Olives. After supper (Christâs last), Jesus and his disciples went to the Garden of Olives to rest. With knowledge of his pending arrest and crucifixion, Jesus went farther into the Garden, alone, to pray. He kneeled down on the ground and prayed, ââFather, if you are willing, take this cup of suffering away from me. But do what you want, not what I wantââ (Luke 22:42). He prayed three times during the night, aware of the events to come. Thus, the image of Christ in this context portrays a recognition and overcoming of suffering. Gauguin clearly identified with this gesture: he imagines Jesus with his back turned to his friends, slightly askew at the edge of the picture as if confronted by an insurmountable boundary. His limp hands suggest introspection and his partly opened, occidental eyes seem to register an omniscient awareness of the circumstances. 34 Figure 4. Paul Gauguin, Christ in the Garden of Olives, 1889. There may be multiple kinds of identification at work, but Gauguinâs identification with Christâs suffering parallels the emotional testimony of his letters. The poverty and illness he endured throughout the 1880âs would not be so soon forgotten. Looking back on this period later in life, he would write in a letter to his friend William Mollard, âEverything has always turned against meâ (cited in Mittelstädt, 1968, p. 31). The significance of Jesusâ prayer in the Garden of Olives (see above) suggests that Gauguin was also interested in the possibility that oneâs suffering is in the hands 35 of fate, and not a matter of choice. Christâs prayer is an allegory about subordinating oneâs self to fate, so Christ becomes a vehicle for Gauguinâs Romantic belief that he is an artist by nature, and not necessarily by his own making; Christ in the Garden of Olives shows us that Gauguin saw his work as an artist on par with Christâs own acceptance. It is a further step to say that the image of Yellow Christ follows this selfidentification, but the persistence of this imagery in his artworks points in this direction. 2.3 Portrait of a Genius When interpreting Yellow Christâs presence in the self-portrait, we should consider a range of possible meanings from the matter of contemplation about oneâs self to a more immediate religious significance. The image of Christ on the cross, as an iconic symbol of Christianity, could reflect Gauguinâs concern with religion in general, or his own religious practice in particular. Either way it is unlikely, since we know he criticized Christianity for destroying âManâs faith in himself and in the beauty of primitive instincts, until [the instincts] became a Mythâ (Mittelstädt (1968), p. 11). Furthermore, it is not just any image of Christ he includes in his self-portrait, but an image of his own making â the same can be said for the earthenware jugâa fact that supports the argument that Self Portrait with Yellow Christ is a meditation on art making. As such, we see it as a peculiar kind of meditation: a psychological comparison between three kinds of selves. For brevityâs sake, I will discuss these selves in terms of 36 Freudian psychoanalysis, but this is not meant to be a Freudian interpretation of Gauguinâs work. Here, these terms serve as a quick way to disambiguate three psychological functions. As a symbol of the influence of culture, Yellow Christ appears to symbolically represent the superego; the primitive jug can be seen as the id; and the literal image of the artist appears as the ego. Thus, each element in Gauguinâs threepart self-portrait tells us something different about the artist, adding to our understanding of the whole. The function of the superego is to govern the ego in accordance with internalized standards of authority. It is significant that Gauguin included the portrait of Yellow Christ and not Christ in the Garden of Olives because the immediate association with Gauguin is disrupted. Here, Christ represents tradition, becoming a sort of âalternate selfâ that Gauguin sees as a looming figure of suffering. Christ does not literally represent what we would understand to be Gauguinâs superego, yet Gauguin distances himself symbolically from that inherited internalized authority. Christ no longer represents Gauguinâs suffering as he did in the Garden; Christ is an external representation of submission to societyâs ideals. This painting represents one way of being an artist. We can compare this position with the overt reverence that many of Gauguinâs contemporaries had for traditionâeven in the tradition of Impressionism. In the opposite corner, the jug represents a different kind of artist. As the id, the jug represents Gauguinâs instinctual drives; it is Gauguinâs âsavageâ self. He takes pride in this identity. He traveled to Panama and Martinique in 1887 âin order to live 37 there like a savageâ (Mittelstädt, 1968, p. 9), and apparently to revitalize the âIndianâ part of him that he once understood as a young child living in Lima, Peru. 11 The jug is a primitive self-portrait molded out of coarse material, giving form to a developing theme of his work: Gauguinâs belief that âMan and Nature, in their original, unadulterated state should be a revelation of Harmony and Beautyâ (cited in Mittelstädt, 1968, p. 9). Seeking this innocence that he believed existed in the South Seas,12 he traveled to Tahiti for the first time in 1891. In the summer of 1895, he returned to Tahiti to live there as a painter until his death. The jug represents this choice and its consequences. In seeking pleasure above all else, the id must be restrained by the ego. Thus, Gauguinâs literal image is the self that experiences the tension between the id and superegoâa self that perceives, thinks, and takes action. This is the image of Gauguin deciding how to be in the world. Self-Portrait with Yellow Christ is a depiction of a man who believes he is an artist by nature. He is turned away from tradition; he is closer to his savage self. Yet, he remains composed and reflective. He is a skepticâa bourgeois man in a blue sweater sitting on a precipice between two worlds. In June 1889, he writes to Mette from Le Pouldu, âWhat concerns me is art, it is my capital, my childrenâs future, the honor of the name I have given them⌠I live like a peasant, and 11 Although Gauguin takes pride in the fraction of his heritage that is Peruvian, he did not live anything like a savage during his stay in Peru. For more on this, see Perruchot (1963) for a description of his day-to-day habits. 12 Tahiti was not the âuncivilizedâ place he imagined, and already in 1891 it was becoming economically and politically assimilated into âmodernâ culture. Gauguin seems to have been initially persuaded of its innocence by a travel brochure. See Perruchot (1963), p. 195. 38 am known as a savageâ (cited in Guérin, 1978, p. 27). The image of the savage makes sense out of his life. His spiritual questâas a criminal, as a saint, or as Jesus Christâis sublimated into his work as an artist. To paraphrase his own description of his spiritual quest: his religion is instinct reigned in by reason. Christ has been flattened out and transformed into a stage propâthe background that sets the artistâs moral compass in accordance with a deep solipsism. The foregrounded image of the artist is a satirical portrait of mediocrity for an audience of admirers, and the symbolism of the painting exposes the insincerity of his humility. 2.4 Summary These portraits of Gauguinâs life serve as rich examples of the internal manifestation of a conception of genius. While artists may conceive of themselves as geniuses to some degree, we see in Gauguinâs example the consequences of an extreme case. The concept is at work in his self-understanding, distorting religiosity, and enacting its potential as a comprehensive goodâa good that aligns all other aspects of oneâs life toward its purpose. This example helps us pose new questions about the potential and effect of the concept of genius and its relation to moral excellence. What kind of relationships should artists cultivate? Is it possible to embark on a mythic quest if oneâs life is directed by a multitude of goods (e.g., not only as a practitioner of the arts, but as a member of a family, a citizen of democracy, etc.)? How would we evaluate that kind of life? Our reception of the concept of genius makes us sensitive to the 39 problem of sustaining and challenging tradition in the arts, but Gauguinâs life makes us wary of the potential consequences of this work. In his self-portraits, instead of a reflective figure, we see a tragic mirror image of our artistic selves, for who among us does not envy Gauguinâs conviction that painting constitutes oneâs salvation? 3. A Subject of Moral Philosophy There are two meanings I extract from Gauguinâs case. As I have argued, it is both the case that a conception of genius can deeply affect an artistâs life, and that an artist can be morally excellent without being âgood.â This recasting of morality follows from a dissatisfaction with the myopic view of morality that leaves us with saintliness, a way of life which few of us would intentionally adopt. Lauding Gauguin as morally excellent is a long way from rejecting saintliness as an ideal, but it does follow logically from the artistâs perspective and ultimately satisfies Wolfâs call for a moral theory that meshes with common sense. The meaning of excellence in art practice, and how we consider artists apart from their art, is not simple. It is not the same thing to speak of a moral saint and an artistic genius as good. Gauguin does not have to be generous, charitable, or even considered an excellent artist to be a good husband, father, or French citizen. But I am now claiming, by virtue of my reading of Wolfâs expansionist argument, that Gauguin should be considered morally admirable. That is, taking account of an artistâs behavior 40 beyond his ability, achievement, and success at making art need not be systematically integrated into moral evaluationâfor the artist stakes his identity in art, and art practice is a well-nested social sphere.13 This argument puts my critique of genius in a richer context. A key premise of my main argumentâthat the concept of genius plays a key role in artistsâ ability to become artists, remain artists, and thrive as artistsâis not uncontroversial. But I will further claim that an artistâs failure to understand the concept and actively overcome its problems counts as a moral failure. To wit, to claim it is simply âa failureâ carries much less force, and is an egregiously ahistorical and inhuman utterance. The example of Gauguin and his art suggests how genius can be an influential concept, and why a critique of genius is relevant for art education. For Gauguin, a concept of genius was intertwined with identity because he was recognized as a great painter during his life (or simply arrogant enough to believe it true, or act as if it were). Indeed, he may have acted no differently if the concept of genius had not been prevalent in France during his life. But it is hard to imagine nineteenth century Franceâor any other recent time and place in western cultureâwithout a similar fascination with excellence. Gauguin was blessed and cursed withâor simply saddled withâthe problem of integrating a notion of artistic excellence into his art practice. 13 According to Blackerâs (1999) political philosophy, art practice is a social âsphere.â This is a helpful metaphor and theory for conceiving of the social legitimacy of art practices. See Blacker (1999), especially his discussion of âspherical autonomyâ (pp. 189-199). Blacker argues that the democratic notion of complex equality must be vetted for a relationship to pluralism. In doing so, he discusses how âintra-sphericalâ and âextra-sphericalâ pressures regulate the autonomy of spheres. For a sphere to be âwell-nestedâ means it gains authority through extra-spherical relationships. 41 4. Conclusion For those artists who are not publicly recognized, the problem for art practice is a matter of coping with notions of artistic excellence. Such reconciliation is in itself unlikely to propel the kind of artistic production John Dewey will be shown to have in mind below in Chapter II, Section 3.4âart making as a social, communicative activity. We are likely to leave the work of art making for a lucky-someone-else to do. But as Gauguinâs story makes clear, situating oneâs self at the more favorable end of a spectrum of excellence is not only motivational, but also potentially educative in a sense of which Dewey would approve. Regardless of Gauguinâs anti-social tendencies, his spiritual quest led him to produce meaningful art that continues to garner an audience. In this way, an orientation toward excellence seems to partake in social life. That his spiritual quest coincided with external recognition of genius complicates the philosophical picture, as the matter of identity adds another layer of meaning to stories about artists and their work. There are objections to such a community-minded approach to artistic excellence, but they are not strong. For example, Zangwill (1999) argues that an audience is not an essential aspect of art, as his interest lies to the side of the first person experience. He says that âany plausible theory must involve some reference to an artistâs intentionâ (Zangwill, 1999, p. 315). This allows him to discard âpureâ audience theories that abuse an artist/audience distinction securing our notion of the 42 difference between art and non-art in the first place. So his rejection of audience-based theories of art must be seen in light of his larger project of advancing artist-based theories that promote the perspective of the artist at the cost of devaluing the ideal of community. His definition of art is, therefore, too narrow for the purposes of art education. Educators are presumably interested in the kind of art that is seen by an audience because they are interested in opportunities for individuals to engage in dialogues that potentially lead to ânew understandings.â Corroboration of oneâs opinion about genius is expected, and perhaps necessary. Ideally, opinions about genius would be unanimous, but this is seldomly the case. Thus, when it comes to oneâs opinion of oneâs self, the judgment that âI am a geniusâ should probably not be taken at face value. Circumstances are never so simple that oneâs excellence could be rightly judged this way, as it is not clear that proclaiming oneâs self a genius would be meaningful without substantial support from an audience. The engine of a âfirst personâ perspective of genius is, therefore, a âthird personâ perspectiveâan external concept of genius. I return to this predicament in Chapter IV where I discuss the growing body of psychological literature on the identification of character traits and its meaning for the critique of genius from the perspective of art education. What is needed prior to further scrutiny of the concept of genius is a better articulated and bounded inquiry. Chapters II and III identify characteristics of art education that frame my critique of genius, and outline a methodological strategy for locating subordination as a vital response to genius. 43 IIâARTISTIC ACHIEVEMENT 1. An Artistâs Narrative Quest A conception of artistic genius, complicated by the experience of making art in a complex social world, was antagonistic to my education as an artist. Skepticism shortcircuited my artistic identity and my experience of artistic influence; it was, for me at least, a symptom of my under ripened conception of art practice. As an art student, I wondered, âDo I have qualities that make me a genius?â Would I have been able to detect them even if I did? It seems reasonable to look at oneâs art for evidence of genius, but can one rightly detect it this way? Can one be a good judge of oneâs own work? (Can others?) Even if I believe I am a genius, can I explain or justify this belief? What difference would it make? I first encountered Alasdair MacIntyreâs moral philosophy during a vocational crisis. I wanted to be an artist, a storyteller, a philosopher, and a teacher all at once. Before entering graduate school to study the history of education, I attempted to wear all these hats as a filmmaker in Hollywood, California. I returned to school after failing to achieve success in all these ways and failing to choose one direction over another. It 44 struck me that my formal education, which had come to an end upon graduation from Dartmouth College only a year earlier, was the closest thing I knew to a place where one could do this kind of choosing. As an undergraduate, I majored in Studio Artâa course of study based on traditional visual art forms. This led to my interest in filmmaking and my eventual decision to travel westward. One year later, though my experience in Hollywood was rewarding, my interests continued to grow and broaden, and I wondered if I had made a good vocational decision. I recognized my desire to tell stories as a desire to educate. That is, the more I learned about filmmaking, the more I wanted to understand the features of social life that caused me to want to tell stories that were not only entertaining, but important. I was writing a screenplay at the time, and my mantra was a customary one: âwrite what you know.â At that time, what I believed I knew most about was my experience of education, but I needed to know more to tell a story. I moved back east, and, with the intention of learning more about education, I began taking courses at Teachers College, the graduate school of education at Columbia University in New York City. I wanted to better understand education, its various aims and structures, and how they are achieved (or who or what prevented such achievement). Reflecting on the scope of my studio education, I also wondered how the form of my education influenced my vocational decisions. Beyond the vaguely articulated goals of liberal education and the outward goals of art making (e.g., filling space with well-designed and attractive materials), I wondered what the other dimensions of the studio classroom might be, and how I was shaped by the curriculum. 45 I was also aware of the odd development of choosing to be a student once again, when for almost twenty years I had been a student with seemingly little choice in the matter. Back in school, I once again found philosophy compelling. As an undergraduate, I had taken several philosophy courses, from logic to literary theory, and my closest friends were philosophy majors who would go on to graduate programs in philosophy and join a rigorous academic community of professional philosophers. (While I enjoyed philosophical discussions, my friends were more consistently interested in rigorously analyzing and constructing arguments.) My first two classes at Teachers College were introductory courses, âPhilosophies of Educationâ and âThe History of American Education.â The following semester I took two more philosophy courses and subsequently became a Masterâs student in the Philosophy and Education Program. This was the term I read After Virtue (MacIntyre, 1984). 1.1 The Turn to Philosophy As many parts of his theory resonated with my experience as a student, MacIntyreâs (1984) account of ethics in After Virtue became a framework for my reflection on education. Practices, narrative quests, and moral traditions are three registers of moral life, he argues, that orient individuals and communities toward 46 âvirtueâ and âthe good.â 14 This view, an outgrowth of Aristotleâs theory of virtue, was a compelling account of what I understood to be the liberal aim of educationâit made sense of education in the terms of the Socratic quest for living a good life (Aristotle, 2000, pp. vii-x). MacIntyreâs tripartite theory of moral life helped me think about many aspects of education broadly, and it provided traction for reflecting about and remembering specific educational experiences. Between my experience as an art student and my goal of choosing a vocational direction, MacIntyreâs understanding of the role of practices in a personâs lifeâa focal point of After Virtueâwas an important touchstone. Practices, which for MacIntyre are sufficiently complex, socially established activities, involve a similarly complex relationship between individuals and a community (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 187). For example, it is in and through practices, MacIntyre says, that we partly come to know the virtues that are, in turn, instrumental in choosing how we live. I asked myself as I read: Do I have this kind of relationship to a community? What would taking this view seriously mean for how I work as an artist, philosopher, or teacher? MacIntyreâs special definition of a practice prompted me to examine my past relationship to the artworld, where my interest in painting developed alongside my familiarization with art history. As I first worked with oil paint as a sophomore in 14 Moral traditions, theorized by MacIntyre as one dimension of moral life that extends the human possibilities of meaning making, are established by communities that value and sustain a relationship to a practice over time. Narrative quests are the individual experiences of meaningseeking people. I will discuss all three parts of MacIntyreâs moral equation at length below in Chapter II, Section 2. 47 college, I was attracted to colorful abstractions and minimal representationâthe kind of imagery in Jim Dine or Richard Diebenkornâs oeuvre. I discovered (and was introduced to) other twentieth century Americans such as Fairfield Porter and Philip Guston, and their contemporaries and predecessors. The community of painters I came to know was complex and intriguingâthe actual (and imagined) connections and influences were hard to work out. But it was also clear that understanding these connections was a unique task compared to other artistic responses, and I came to appreciate that the historianâs work was different than the artistâs. Artists are often saddled with the historianâs task, however, as understanding history is one method by which artists may find meaning in art. My influences as a painter were heaped together, and to make matters somewhat more complicated, only some of those influences were other painters and/or their work (for example, Carl Saganâs televised Cosmos was, among other poetic and scientific creations, an inspiration for my work in the studio). Yet I was never specifically trained how to use, order, or conceptualize my influences. Even within the realm of âart historyâ my interests were diverse: I learned about thirteenth-century painting in Italy, the Renaissance, Modernism, Picasso, Impressionism, the tradition of landscape painting, realism, Abstract Expressionism, and moreâI learned so much about tradition that it was hard to make sense of it. It was, however, the presence of these historical influences that MacIntyreâs concept of practice touched upon. Studying education in graduate school, trying once again to return to the studio, I asked myself, âWas my undergraduate education good enough?â My work in 48 painting continued to be about exploring imagery, feelings, ideas, values, and beliefs. My interest in painting existed somewhat prior to my work in film, so I wondered: was there simply a constellation of mitigating factors that conspired to derail my work as a painter and launch my career in filmmaking? Or was my education wanting for something it should not have lacked? As an undergraduate I was exposed to a variety of art practices and many dimensions of art practice, but after a couple years and a dozen classes, my interest in drawing and painting waned. Learning to paint once again as a graduate student, I tried to understand MacIntyreâs perspective on the onset of education. Above all, perhaps, my return to the studio was motivated by an emergent sense of myself as an artist. As I will discuss below in Section 2, MacIntyreâs moral theory invokes a very different sense of tradition than the sense that is often discussed in the artworld. For many artists, there is little difference between having (and making known) oneâs influences and being a âtraditionalist.â Being beholden to tradition is not seen as a desirable disposition, and this makes tending to oneâs influences all the more difficult when establishing oneâs contributions to the artworld as unique is understood as paramount. Conceiving of tradition as an ongoing project, however, casts influences in a better lightâespecially when those influences are other artistsâ artworks. Oneâs influences turn out to be interpretive frameworks through which the meaning of oneâs artworks may be more fully disclosed. Yet the sense that an artist should not be limited by the achievements of the past is undeniably reasonable. For an artist, therefore, accepting that both oneâs influences and oneâs artworks are aspects of tradition can be 49 understood a turn to philosophy, and this was a consequence of my encounter with After Virtue. Yet this begs the question of what it means to conceive of the artist-cumtraditionalist as an excellent artist, and how one should conceive of tradition as a complex negotiation of the past and present is a question put forward here alongside the critique of the concept of genius. 1.2 An Early Hypothesis The details of my past education were on my mind as I began to re-examine my work as a painter.15 Having at least developed a new understanding of my former self as a practitioner who had ceased to strive for excellence, I began examining why I lost interest in (or did not cultivate interest in) painting while I was an undergraduate. It was impossible, at first, to account for all the possible variables embedded in the past. But it was clear that MacIntyreâs theory of the interconnectedness of three registers of moral life, however vaguely understood by me at the time, re-established my sense that art practice was an important part of my life and worth pursuing. After a critical engagement with a theory of âeducational goods,â I was able to identify and recall influences on my vocational decisions, andâperhaps inevitablyâa dominant line of thought about my past experience emerged. 15 I suspect a notion of âindividualityâ plays a large role in my sense of self. For more on the role of individuality in moral life, see Part I, Identity and the Good, in Taylor (1989). 50 I realized that my life as a painter was, at pivotal moments, distinguished by my opinion of my art teachers (my college professors). This simple insight became an important thread in my attempt to understand my actions, both past and present. Even then I knew that my teachers were important to my realization that education could sharpen my talents, but my opinions of them were varied, and often negative. The reasons for this are equally vague and complex, but one aspect still stands out to me today. I wanted my teachers to anchor my work and life to a meaningful tradition, but this never came to pass. My relationships with them were strangely impersonal. I doubt, for example, they would have guessed that I chose to major in art largely because I felt a strong sense of kinship with them. But then, I never told them. I guess I just expected them to know. My education also included relationships with art students, but I believe my relationships with my teachers had the greatest lasting effect on my art practice. I was indifferent to many of my teachers, and merely plodded through their curriculum and my time in the studio. But I felt, and continue to feel, particularly indebted to a few, and especially to one teacher for her insightful and challenging feedback on my drawings and paintings. She knew when and how to push me to try new ideas and experiment with new techniquesâher aesthetic style was well suited to my interests. Other teachers helped me in this and other ways, although less often and, I feel, with less care. But even my relationship with this teacher never deepened beyond the ordinary routines of the classroom. I believed her judgment was soundâjudgments that often came in the form of comments about my work, comments such as âsome yellow would 51 look good thereâ and â this is your best drawingââbut it was not enough. I could not detect any qualities in myself that secured my confidence that my contributions to the artworld would ever be appreciated, and I was less motivated to make art.16 As my Teachers College Masterâs Thesis explored, MacIntyre argues that subordination is a key moment in practices and that subordination to other practitioners is an essential condition of achieving excellence in a practice (Hughes, 2002). Several questions are foregrounded by this study and further reflection on my undergraduate experience. Did I fail to adequately subordinate myself to other practitioners? With my favorite teacher, had I begun down a path of subordination, but failed to seriously attempt to understand her practice? She never explicitly helped me with regard to this work. Was I inattentive to the excellence of her practices? Can one bypass a deep experience of subordination and still achieve excellence in a practice? Did I act as if one could? MacIntyreâs account of subordination implies that practitionersâ attachment to a practice can deepen over time, but armed only with his observation that the result of subordination is that we defer to othersâ judgments about the internal goods of a practice (MacIntyre, 1984, pp. 190-192), it is unclear what else subordination entails. My Masterâs Thesis allowed me pose these questions about my art practice, and led me to believe that answers could be sought by considering the nature of excellenceâwhere ethics gathers a broader picture of human behavior. 16 More specifically, I suspected my art would not be rightly appreciated. I remain deeply skeptical of othersâ opinions of my work, but I am painting my past self in too garish a light. The more sober way to put this is to say that I was more motivated when my teachers and other artists recognized my âtalent.â 52 As an explanation of excellence, MacIntyre argues there is a âlogical structureâ of the interconnectedness of the three registers of moral life he identifies. For example, he claims that the experience of excellence in practices is prior to the experience of excellence in moral traditions (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 189), and perhaps he is interested here in a defending an Aristotelian conception of virtue as part of a comprehensive moral theory. Nevertheless, his argument further complicates the matter of the achievement of excellence by not expanding the matter of subordination. What is needed as a corrective here is a philosophical perspective that is interested in practice. A more complex understanding of the process of entering into practices is needed, therefore, to better conceive of a âMacIntyrianâ theory of education. 1.3 The Matter of Trust I did not fully develop as an artist at Dartmouth College. I demonstrated artful talents and good habits in my studio classes, I was recognized by my teachers as a promising art student, but I never wanted to be considered an artist by anyone outside the classroom. When I graduated, I was not adequately prepared to join a larger community of artists, and I abandoned painting in favor of filmmaking. I returned to the studio in graduate school after developing a conception of the possible richness of studio practice to which I may have never attended adequately. My understanding of educational relationships according to MacIntyreâs articulation of practices thereby sharpened my interest in other artists and their work, and it also had the effect of 53 strengthening my rationale for being an artist by undercutting my skepticism about my own artistic potential. I could no longer use the thinly disguised, real question posed as a half-hearted excuse, âWhat do painters really do, anyway?â I developed a new appreciation for many respected artists, but I also cultivated a new respect for all artists who work within a tradition. With this renewed commitment to the arts, one aspect that continues to interest me most about the social milieu in which I find myself situated are the ways of which some artists are considered to be eminent, and how this privileging often trades on the notion of artistic genius. How do practitioners who are not recognized as geniuses remain reconciled with this reality? It is not just a problem for practitioners in general, but for teachers and students. I wonder, for example, how eminence shapes practitionersâ self-perceptions as well as perceptions of education. Why would a student want to learn from anyone other than a genius? Misunderstanding the nature of artistic genius may have been a major obstacle in my relationships with my art teachersâperhaps even a central feature of my past difficulties as an artist. For artists, the problem of genius stands at the intersection of practices, narrative quests, and moral traditions. Posed as an educational problem, therefore, genius can be related to a complex web of relationships, attitudes, and actions. For example, it may influence how one experiences subordination, and it is this matter that continues to resonate with me as I struggle to understand what it would mean to live as an artist. If one accepts the notion of genius as eminence, then one likely accepts that there are possibilities for subordination that meet MacIntyreâs claim 54 that judgments are sometimes deferred to other practitioners. But why would a practitioner defer his judgment, and about what matter? And if he does, would he not prefer to defer his judgment to someone he regards as a genius? This gestures toward a problem for teachers: whether or not genius is actually a fact of nature, it may change the nature of educational relationships. Alternately, one may believe there is no such thing as genius, in which case there may be some other feature or features of practice that warrants subordination. These features must come with their own reassurances that the person who defers his judgment is in good hands, and the same is true of the case with genius: there is an instantiation of trust.17 Philosophy helped me overcome my earlier experience of art education and adopt a rationale for making art as an adult. Exploring genius as an extreme case of excellence in the arts may shed light on the role of subordination in practices and render a salient picture of the role of trust in education. An expanded account of subordination offers insight about the essential qualities of a MacIntyrian experience of excellence, and a related theory of education may be applied in educative communities. A closer look at subordination may offer the notion of genius back to artists in a new, and more truthful way. 17 For more on the issue of âtrustâ from the perspective of social psychology, see Good (1988). 55 1.4 Summary It is understating the case to say that art practices draw on a rich range of ideas, processes, and institutions. These sources are comprised of entities that partake of the history of the arts, and also those associated with the arts for the first time. Today, there is nothing common to all art; âartâ means different things at different times in different places. And where art goes, art education follows. The continuing ideal of Modernism, however, means that there is a widespread hope of unity, and a complex network of people, conversations, and ideas that hang together as the basis of the philosophy of art. In the spirit of this unity, but not due to its perceived imminence, we should strive to understand the warp and weft of our social fabric. The story of my own difficulties with subordination make the implications for education clearer, and also demonstrates why I undertake the inquiry as a moral one. Without the larger frame of morality, the problem of defining genius collapses into a merely historical task. This task must still be undertaken, but personal experience guides it. The project cannot solely consist in this work (even if one were to exhaust completely the historical possibilities, which will not be accomplished here), because it calls for interpretation through a philosophical lens. âMoralityâ captures the richness and complexity of social, psychological, and historical forces. My inquiry will be a sustained analysis of minor features of MacIntyreâs theory, with implications for the greater whole. The philosophical problem of genius (to be discussed in depth in Chapter III) teases out aspects of MacIntyreâs theory that may 56 otherwise be overlooked, and weaves a significantly more complex picture of art practices in âgood working orderâ that I hope offers new insight into education. In the following section I turn to MacIntyreâs philosophy to make clear how his theory of virtue serves as a framework for my critique of genius, and sets aside those aspects of his work in which I am less expert. 2. Elaboration of MacIntyreâs Project As MacIntyre sets out to secure a foundation from which to generate social criticism in what is considered his mature work (Murphy, 2003)âof which After Virtue is the inaugural book. In this work, he takes on board multiple philosophical projects, not the least of which is a reformulation of Aristotelian ethics, and a central part of this project is recasting the concept of virtue in light of all the ethical and metaethical theory since ancient times, as well as in consideration of other cultures and their histories. To be sure, this is no small project, and MacIntyre insists that we read his account of virtue as tentative and incomplete (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 271).18 In MacIntyreâs terms, the âmoral natureâ of genius can be understood as a set of problems and relationships he aims to define in general with his description of virtue as the centerpiece of moral life. The problem with applying virtue theory to art practice, 18 MacIntyreâs work is subject to much criticism. See, for example, After MacIntyre (Horton & Mendus, 1994). 57 however, is twofold: 1) MacIntyre never attempts to apply his theory to a specific practice in great detail, and 2) it is unclear if his theory of virtue is sufficiently consistent or descriptive to allow for such an application. It is important, therefore, to understand the trade-off MacIntyre makes to generate a descriptive theory of moral life rather than formulate a prescriptive theory. To better define virtue, he identifies three major registers of the social life for which an account must be given: practices, narrative quests, and moral traditions. Each one of these matters becomes a focus for his future critics, as a failure to make sense of any single register undermines, to a greater or lesser extent, the whole project. It is the force (the ought) of morality that MacIntyre seeks to enlist as the voice of social criticism. If these three registers cannot be seen as contributing to an ought (morality, and therefore, an account of virtue), then by MacIntyreâs own reasoning there will be insurmountable resistance to social criticism. The methodological issue of developing a foundation for social criticism takes on a central role in MacIntyreâs books Whose Justice? Which Rationality? and Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry. He argues that a conception of âpractical reasonâ can be grounded in a âtraditionalistâ conception of knowledge that frames understanding as an inheritance of inquiry. This, in turn, recasts philosophy as defined by tradition, and he casts âanalyticâ moral philosophy per se as a peculiar remnant of a tradition that includes the Enlightenment belief that methodology can stand outside of tradition. That is, the conception of virtue that MacIntyre sets out to define is by definition an articulation of a particular tradition that comes with an established set of questions and 58 problems that demand the attention of its practitioners. Some meta-ethicists reject this claim on the grounds that there are universal moral principles, and believe that disputes about morality can be settled.19 I find myself in the middle: on the side of the traditionalist who acknowledges diversity, but with the hope that there are principles (perhaps not rightly understood as ethical principles) that will allow for disputes to be rationally settled. Such diversity, if recognized, not only pushes back on MacIntyreâs philosophy, but also the analytic tradition that arises in wake of the Enlightenment that posits an ahistorical rationality (i.e., objectivity and universality). It is actually a much worse problem for the former than for the latter. Analytic philosophy simply adopts a Pragmatic temperament going forward (as it often has). Either philosophizing leads to outcomes which we desire and of which we approve, or it does not (and there likely exists a horizon beyond which we simply cannot accurately guess the outcomes one way or other). Traditionalists, on the other hand, are stuck conceding that disagreements are either not disagreements at all, or represent insurmountable difference. Alas, on this view morality seems to once again be mired by the relativism MacIntyre seeks to escapeâthis is the glass as half empty. For the traditionalist, a world replete with competing traditions bodes very badly indeed. For even if social criticism is leveled from within a tradition, it is unlikely to 19 I am not convinced MacIntyreâs Neo-Thomist tradition is preferable over a more fragmented tradition that includes the Enlightenment conception of truth as objective and universal. MacIntyre is opting out of continuing dialogues that at least have the potential to establish new agreement about an ought, and therefore, agreement about the future. 59 find traction in the wider world without the accompaniment of an attractive philosophy. Such a philosophy would, by appealing to persons in rival traditions, be seen as successfully re-describing existent problems more powerfully. On the other hand, in a world where philosophers of all kinds work to arrive at agreement from the outset on matters thought to be inherently philosophical for one reason or anotherâ no matter how difficult and arduous the dialogue may be at timesâthe outcome at least has the potential to correspond to matters âon the groundâ and have a de facto appeal to non-philosophers. This is the glass as half full. 2.1 Traditions and Anti-Traditions Today, the matter of tradition is central to philosophers who attempt to understand art. Though I will discuss tradition further in Chapter VI, I want to briefly acknowledge the kinds of problems that arise when tradition is understood as a sideconstraint of inquiry. There are many traditions to choose from in the world, and this may lead artists to feel a sense of rootlessness. As with the often-repeated mantra of postmodernism, there is an underlying lack of awareness of the ongoing role of tradition. Gyorgy (1999), a philosopher who shares this view, declares that the contemporary artist dwells in a boundless state of possibility: There are no longer any obstacles before anyone, no obligation to any school behooves. Time no longer commands, it no longer prohibits, nor does it recommend. There is no longer any kind of era, no longer any school, there is no valid tradition, there is nothing but freedom. (p. 431) 60 This is an unbounded notion of art. Presumably Gyorgy comes to this conclusion by following a narrative of contemporary art that combines ideas from aesthetics, art criticism, and theory. Discussing and making art within institutions that are beholden to the western tradition is, to be sure, a complex matter. In his article âBetween and After Essentialism and Institutionalism,â Gyorgy responds to Dantoâs (1984) thesis that the history of art has ended, and says the problem at hand is âthe possibility of discussing art, with the experience of contemporary art behind us, after the end of art historyâ (Gyorgy, 1999, p. 421). Arthur Danto (1992) has since made clear that the claim that art history has ended does not mean that art making has ended. His claim pertained to the âWesternâ tradition that twentieth century artists are said to have transcended under the banner of postmodernism. Even so, the interests of art critics, historians, and theorists can be seen emerging as new perspectives in dialogues about art after its so-called âend.â20 Gyorgy seems eager to cast contemporary artists as practitioners who work on the cutting edge of theory, but, seeing artists as critics, historians, and theorists, he loses sight of the artist as a maker of art. In a sense, artists are free from tradition because âthe institutions necessary for the maintenance of the universalism of the essentialist theory of art [are] no longer availableâ (Gyorgy, 1999, p. 429). For example, âclassical categorization,â a conceptual 20 It is not that the transformation does not warrant a dramatic label, but that the label âthe endâ may evoke a break from tradition that is not desired or even possible. It draws artistsâ attention to a philosophy of art at the cost of jeopardizing conceptions of praxis. 61 task of defining art in relation to other art, is one of these institutions. This is the short list of dichotomies that were ready-at-hand to distinguish the capital âAâ art of art history from all other objects: high/low, European/non-European, artwork/artifact, and so on. Cultural anthropology gave the artworld a new vocabulary for thinking about how different communities represent culture, and this led to the ââanthropologizationâ of Western art . . . [where] the possibility of viewing our own culture from the outside emergedâ (Gyorgy, 1999, p. 430). This is the point at which Danto argues that art making became about art theory, but it is also the moment when art theorists divided along the line of âessentialistsâ and âinstitutionalists.â Essentialists proceed by arguing that some intrinsic quality or qualities define art, and institutionalists counter by arguing that art is defined by the people and institutions that value it. As the title of his essay suggests, Gyorgy says we have to go between essentialism and institutionalism to understand the present condition of art. Following Gadamerâs understanding of the subjectivization of aesthetics, he describes a turning point in the Western tradition that bears out his thesis that art has been relegated to a domain consisting mostly in personal truths and trivial entertainment. Gyorgy claims this undesirable transformation was slow and misguided. The end result is a view of art as evidence of cultural differenceââmassive traffic has begun between anthropology and art historyâ (Gyorgy, 1999, p. 427)âbut art is no longer seen as a source of truth as it was in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. 62 Gyorgy seems to have missed an important lesson of his own story of the end of art history when he says, âtoday, as far as art is concerned, just about every thought is possibleâ (Gyorgy, 1999, p. 431). Whereas he shows us how the artist and the artworld have undergone significant change in recent decades, he does not acknowledge the power of new overarching narratives taking the place of old ones. Nor does he allow for the possibility that art, artists, and institutions of art can undergo radical change and yet remain connected to a tradition. Gyorgyâs assessment of the symptoms of these changes is helpful, but his verdict that Danto or anyone else can rightly equate the end of âuniversal modernismâ with the end of art history is wrong. This is a dangerously false (at best, poetic) overstatement of the situation. To make my assumptions clearer, the following section locates John Deweyâs educational philosophy as a foundation of aesthetics. 3. Art as Inquiry As MacIntyre argues, practices need to be configured in a certain way to be significant in moral life. In this section, I attempt to articulate, if only partially, a view of art as inquiry that grounds my study of the moral nature of artistic genius. After comparing and contrasting several views of art, I turn to Deweyâs understanding of aesthetic experience as a foundation for art practice. In Chapter VIII, the critique of genius will be shown to amend this view as a paradigm for art practice. 63 3.1 Kinds of Inquiry To better understand how theorists conceive of the relation between art making and inquiry, perhaps we should consider their views of art education. Parsons (2002), an art educator, says that âthe idea [of the aesthetic] provides us a way of talking about artworks and our response to them that defines and justifies some goals for art education and influences our thinking about curriculumâ (p. 24). In so many words, he names two major projects of modern aesthetic philosophy: defining the essential characteristics of art and defining the aesthetic quality of experience. Both projects are complicated by the difficulty of talking about the effect of art on human experience.21 The status of art making and aesthetic philosophy as academic disciplines complicates the situation. As a philosopher worrying about the teaching of aesthetics, Marshall (1995) argues that a philosophical attitude helps students understand art, that aesthetic theories often âblur the boundaries between art and aesthetics,â and that this âopens an avenue of rapprochement between the worlds of the artist and the philosopherâ (Marshall, 1995, p. 50). Guided by these outcomes, he says that an impartial pedagogy should make the three following assumptions: [That] the purpose of the study of aesthetic theories is to discover which one is, in fact, true; âŚ[that] there are canons of reason or objective criteria or methods of thought according to which we can discern the truth; âŚ[and that] the 21 A brief note on nomenclature may preclude some potential confusion. âAestheticsâ often refers to a philosophical disciplineâa philosophical orientation towards art under which multiple philosophies of art are gathered. Here, I will treat aesthetics as referring to these philosophies. 64 pursuit of truth is valuable for its own sake or apart from whatever other ends these truths might serve. (p. 42) In contrast to Marshallâs pedagogy that treats aesthetics as an inquiry into the normative aspects of art, Niklas (1994) presents a more student-centered, constructivist approach. She says: My hermeneutical approach focuses on philosophical issues which emerge in the experience of art. It goes from art to philosophy and takes the work of art as a starting point, a doorway to philosophical questions and concepts whose significance reaches beyond the questions of art and beauty. (p. 2) This dialogical direction, from art to philosophy, begins with questions about art that can lead to questions about aesthetics. Even more than Marshall, Niklas seems to feel that aesthetics is valuable to students independent from its value as philosophy of art, as it is a discourse that leads to philosophical reflection. This kind of inquiry includes 1) responses to art and 2) posing philosophical questions. Another kind of inquiry is moral in nature. Awareness of the connections between academic disciplines leads some scholars to imagine a philosophical curriculum in the arts. Choi (2001) argues that aesthetic education should be understood as moral education, and that it is a necessary component of general education in the humanities. By claiming that education is the development of coherent intellectual, moral, and aesthetic values in the mind, he argues that the humanities and the arts are part of a tradition of examining, critiquing, and defining the good life (Choi, 2001). In line with this view, Costantino (2002) is a proponent of making aesthetic philosophy an explicit part of art education: âIf we expect students to have a substantive understanding of art and its contribution to human experience, it is not sufficient for aesthetic philosophies 65 to remain implicit in an art teacher's curriculumâ (p. 219). Davis (2000) also argues that educational theories should be made part of the metacognitive curriculum of the art classroom. Kindler (2000) finds that the social and political aspects of art often appear as primary values in art education and challenges this view by recognizing the immediacy of artâs emotional presence. I understand this claim as supporting the view that art is a repository of a distinct kind of knowledge. Hicks (1999) defines aesthetic education as a complex activity of both knowing the human environment and understanding the philosophy of the beautiful. He also finds that although American culture is a highly visual culture, Americans generally do not value aesthetic education (Hicks, 1999, p. 42). In contrast to this observation, Wilson (1998) argues that art making is essential to the survival of human communities. He adopts a perspective that finds cultural practices as primary means of creating shared knowledge, and he uses this theory to show the relevance of art education to society. The purpose of aesthetic education hinges upon the meaning of âaesthetic experience.â The notion of aesthetic experience, however, has been particularly problematic for philosophers of art. Some theorists have sought to define art by the concept of aesthetic experience, while others have resisted this kind of definition alongside a doubt about the nature and validity of the concept. Above all, its instrumental use as a way of thinking about art and experience must be balanced against possible misunderstandings. Shusterman (1997) develops a ground for aesthetic experience that serves as a useful framework from the perspective of art 66 educationâinformed as it is by both an awareness of the first person perspective and artworld discourses. 3.2 Aesthetic Experience In nineteenth and twentieth century art discourses, the notion of âaesthetic experienceâ emerged as a key evaluative framework for identifying art. As it has been crafted as an intellectual idea, aesthetic experience describes experience that is both individualistic and pertaining to characteristics of objects that are understood to transcend cultures and contexts. It does not just refer to oneâs experience of art. Shusterman (1997) says that âthough the concept of art (as a historically determined concept) can be somewhat reshaped, it cannot be convincingly defined in such a global way so as to be coextensive with aesthetic experienceâ (p. 34). But intense philosophical criticism of the concept of aesthetic experience is even more problematic, for âonce a potent embodiment of artâs sense and value, aesthetic experience is now âhermeneuteredââ (p. 38). Increased theoretical scrutiny, therefore, has drained the concept of its common sense value. Shusterman (1997) warns aesthetic philosophers, âperhaps aesthetic experience, and not just the philosophical value of its concept, has almost reached its endâ (p. 39). Though philosophers need not go this far to draw attention to the problems of aesthetics, this hypothesis emphasizes the potential connection between trends in philosophy and the human world. 67 The decreased philosophical value of aesthetic experience is a large enough problem for art education. Shusterman (1997) offers the following example of a turn away from aesthetic experience in the artworld: Goodman and Danto were sensitively reflecting developments in the artworld, which required ever more interpretation as art became more cerebrally conceptual in pursuing what Danto describes as its Hegelian quest to become its own philosophy: art as theory of art. (p. 38) On this view, art shares many of the problems of philosophyâmaybe even ethicsâbut other modernist projects come to mind as well: art as investment, fetish object, style, decoration, and so on. These projects lead art further away from ethics. The concept of aesthetic experience has widely fallen out of the lexicon of contemporary art, Shusterman argues, as a result of its historical ambiguity about its definition and a turn away from interest in phenomenology. The definitional problem stems from the concept of the aesthetic: âBenjaminâs critique does not deny the continuing importance of aesthetic experience, only its romantic conceptualization as pure immediacy of meaning and isolation from the rest of lifeâ (Shusterman, 1997, p. 31). This seems to be a weak objection to a phenomenological account of experienceâ an objection that points to a more general aversion to phenomenology. Critics such as Benjamin doubt that talk about aesthetic experience can hold up under scrutiny; it sounds too much like a loose way of talking about emotions, memory, physiognomy, and so on. But, as with a stronger objection phenomenology (where aesthetic experience is seen as a defining characteristic art), Shusterman recommends austerity. Thus, one reason why aesthetic experience should be dropped 68 as a criterion of essentialism is that âif aesthetic experience is to do the job of demarcating the entire realm of art, then its essentially evaluative content must be abandonedâ (Shusterman, 1997, p. 35). Too much focus on theoretical boundaries will likely deflate the usefulness of the concept in discussions of individual works of art. The concept may be most useful when it is deployed in philosophical discourse only indirectly. Maxine Greeneâs idea of âattendingâ in an aesthetic experience refers to the language we use to describe art, ask questions, imagine possibilities, and âsee new realities.â She claims that aesthetic education demands âsuch reflection and such talkâ (Greene, 2001, p. 25). Attending, on this view, is related to perception. Greene says, âI simply want to suggest the dependence of the qualitative aspect of things on a certain sort of noticingâ (p. 15). Educative aesthetic experiences, it is important to note, depend on this rapt and directed attention. She says, as a teacher, about the interaction between a teacher and students, âall I can do, as a teacher-critic, is to find a language that may help them attendâ (p. 26). The strong objection to a phenomenological account goes along with a turn away from a holistic view of aesthetic experience. âViewed as a univocal concept, aesthetic experience seems too confused to be redeemed as useful; so the first task is to articulate its contrasting conceptionsâ (Shusterman, 1997, p. 32). Shustermanâs positive account of aesthetic experience goes beyond phenomenology and includes four dimensions of experienceâan evaluative, phenomenological, semantic, and demarcation-definitional dimension. He defines these dimensions as follows: 69 First, aesthetic experience is essentially valuable and enjoyable; call this its evaluative dimension. Second, it is something vividly felt and subjectively savored, affectivity absorbing us and focusing our attention on its immediate presence and thus standing out from the ordinary flow of routine experience; call this its phenomenological dimension. Third, it is meaningful experience, not mere sensation; call this its semantic dimension. (Its affective power and meaning together explain how aesthetic experience can be so transfigurative.) Fourth, it is a distinctive experience closely identified with the distinction of fine art and representing artâs essential aim; call this the demarcation-definitional dimension. (p. 30) There are several worrisome aspects of this definition of aesthetic experience, and several helpful contributions to a philosophy of art as inquiry. Shusterman makes aesthetic experience sound too much like a fun trip to the theater rather than a sensuous dimension of everyday experience, and for this reason his definition is probably close to a common sense definition. This would be problematic if he stopped after naming the first two dimensions. But the association he draws to specific social activities such as the fine arts, as well as the caveat that aesthetic experience be meaningful, supports his definition with a stronger philosophical foundation. Together, these four aspects tease apart personal experience from a socio-historical dimension of experience, as each dimension involves the individual and the greater social landscape to different degrees. In these ways, aesthetic experience shows itself to be at least as complex as the theories that attempt to explain it. Aesthetics is continuous with moral theory in the sense that both discourses are interested in human experience, and when knowledge of the quality of a personâs inner experience is sought, evidence of another sort is usually gathered. In the case of the moral saint, for example, his behavior toward others tells 70 us what we need to know. In the case of the artistic genius, artworks serve as evidence. What one can extract from an encounter with art is not immediately apparent, however, and art may not be the only evidence that should count. 3.3 John Deweyâs Philosophy of Education A critique of the concept of genius coincides with the cultivation of at least two values necessary to my identification as an artist: a commitment to both art and truth. My belief in art and truth also grew alongside my inquiry into how MacIntyreâs remarks about subordination elaborated his conception of moral life. With his understanding of education and educational principles, Dewey articulated a view of art that sets the stage for a moral critique of genius despite a backdrop of diverse and conflicting theoretical views of art. This same view of art is wedded to an equally important concept of truth. Thus, Deweyâs philosophy of art is a grounding assumption of such a critique. Furthermore, if a dimension of genius has implications for art education, Deweyâs view of experience should be seen as part of a philosophical foundation for art education. Since Dewey links aesthetics with education, his manner of developing a notion of art involves approaching art in the context of education. âBy rethinking art in terms of aesthetic experience, Dewey hoped we could radically enlarge and democratize the domain of art, integrating it more fully into the real world which would be greatly improved by the pursuit of such manifold arts of livingâ (Shusterman, 1997, p. 33). 71 Dewey (1934/1980) turns to the themes of civilization and community when he says, âit is a matter of communication and participation in values of life by means of the imagination, and works of art are the most intimate and energetic means of aiding individuals to share in the arts of livingâ (p. 336). In this way, his vision of art and aesthetics is deeply committed to democracy, laying the foundation for understanding art as a shared, educational project. Dewey challenges us to perceive our environment as continuous with ourselves, to experience education as imaginative play, and to understand art as a byproduct of play. Dewey (1934/1980) gives an account of art as the material âartifactsâ of educational experience, and an exploration of human interaction with artifacts of human civilization in general. Deweyâs concept of a âlive creatureâ captures his conception of experience as a comprehensive foundation for his philosophical views. He builds up, systematically, a language for talking about living as a process of growth, where humans are situated and social beings that turn âexperience upon [themselves] to deepen and intensify [their] own qualitiesâ (Dewey, 1934/1980, p. 34). He introduces a vocabulary for investigating the esthetic (sic) qualities of experience that includes such ideas as form (p. 14), rhythm (p. 16), sense (p. 22), continuity (p. 28), unity (p. 37), and perception (p. 53). These terms depict various aspects of art and art making as âa quality of doing and of what is doneâ (p. 214). Artists themselves have subsequently explored many of the philosophical concerns Dewey raises (e.g., expressionism, technical production, and viewership). But Dewey resists classifying art objects into broad categories (p. 217); experience, he tells 72 us, always begins with the individualâaesthetic experience is a personal experience. Attempts to explain first person experience from the inside outâphenomenologyâ often rely on âthickâ stories about the nature of art and, by extension, reality. But Dewey goes beyond a strictly phenomenological account. âCommunication is the process of creating participation, of making common what had been isolated and singular . . . . Art breaks through barriers that divide human beingsâ (p. 244). The art object, he says, has a strange life beyond each personâs experience; it has the potential to change the way humans interact. With this effect in mind, he argues that the function of criticism âis the re-education of perception of works of artâ (p. 324). As one of many kinds of art education, Deweyâs interest in the perception of art follows his interest in inquiry. 3.4 Art for Oneâs Self Dewey posits a permanent incompleteness of education. In the first chapter of Democracy and Education he says, âlife is a self-renewing process through action upon the environmentâ (Dewey, 1916/1966, p. 2). Our environment is defined by our relationship to the natural world (i.e., the âworld itselfâ) and social forces (i.e., family, language, culture), and I will say more about this below. Dewey makes the inevitability of our interaction with this âsocial worldâ quite clear. He says, âthe continuity of any experience, through renewing of the social group, is a literal fact. Education, in its broadest sense, is the means of this social continuityâ (p. 2). Experience and education 73 are intertwinedâeducation is the sustenance and substance of human society. âSociety not only continues to exist by transmission, by communication, but it may fairly be said to exist in transmission, in communicationâ (p. 4). Here I will attempt to make some sense of this enigmatic claim. Deweyâs conception of education locates art making as this kind of transmission and communication. First, he revitalizes our vocabulary by asserting that education is an end in itself. It is important (so important!) that we do not gloss over this claim as a mere truism. So often is education understood as a means to an end outside of education, we must take Deweyâs talk of âendsâ and âaimsâ as decisive to his philosophy, âfor it is assumed that the aim of education is to enable individuals to continue their educationâor that the object and reward of learning is continued capacity for growthâ (Dewey, 1916/1966, p. 100). Upon further examination, this principle is not so general as it first appears to be. Dewey is decidedly not making the claim that education is hermetically sealed off or unbounded by competing claims on the âgoodâ or the âright.â On the contrary, he argues from the premise that the attempt to discern the end of human life is itself a value-laden process. With ends in mind, he says, âit is nonsense to talk about the aim of educationâ or any other undertakingâwhere conditions do not permit of foresight of results, and do not stimulate a person to look ahead to see what the outcome of a given activity is to beâ (p. 102). On this view, education is inherently a moral undertaking. An uncharitable critic might bring on a charge of circularity here: we adopt the principle of education as an end in itself because the principle demands that we adopt itâwe are 74 educated ad infinitum and there is no moral shape to this kind of life. To resist this nihilistic charge of moral âflatnessâ we need only accept Deweyâs minimalist accounts of anthropology and psychology: that humans are born into a social world which we may slowly come to know with increasing accuracy. Through the process, we shape our own life and the social world. But Dewey demands that we understand this observation to be somewhat false: the distinction between âselfâ and ânot-selfâ is an unfortunate consequence of language that can obstruct the process of living. Deweyâs concept of environment expands his notion of living as a âselfâ in the world. Deweyâs notion of self challenges us to perceive our environment as an extension of ourselves.22 He makes several distinctions to generate his special definition of environment. He says, âthe words âenvironment,â âmediumâ denote something more that surroundings which encompass an individual. They denote the specific continuity of the surroundings with his own active tendenciesâ (Dewey, 1916/1966, p. 11). At first glance, the idea that we are âcontinuousâ with our environment is too abstract. To add another layer of specificity to this claim, Dewey says, âthe things with which a man varies are his genuine environment,â so itâs possible that oneâs environment is made up of âthings that are remote in space and timeâ (p. 11). For humans, the environment is also social because our âactivities are associated with [other people]â (p. 12). 22 Richard Eldridge reads Deweyâs concern with self as a concern with âpersonhood.â For an extended discussion of what personhood entail, see Eldridge (1989). 75 This conception of the environment informs our thinking about art making. If art making is an activity in which we experience continuity with our environment by actively varying things which constitute it, then art making will be a process in which learning about oneâs self can take place. For Dewey, art education is not only learning how to make art, but also learning about our environment. Furthermore, to perceive art as Dewey perceives it we have to understand art making as necessarily educativeâa reflective process that dwells on continuity between the artistâs self and his environment. Continuity, however, must be understood according to Dewey as dependent on a personâs active interest in his interaction with the world. The difference between a âspectatorâ and an âagentâ (or âparticipantâ) is that âthe latter is bound up with what is going on; its outcome makes a difference to himâ (Dewey, 1916/1966, p. 124). Dewey elaborates on this distinction by invoking the concept of interest: There are words which denote (the agentâs) attitude: concern, interest. These words suggest that a person is bound up with the possibilities inhering in objects; that he is accordingly on the lookout for what they are likely to do to him; and that, on the basis of his expectation or foresight, he is eager to act so as to give things one turn rather than another. (p. 125) Dewey construes interest as foresight about our environment, and he appeals to the normative usage of the word. âThe word interest, in its ordinary usage, expresses (i) the whole state of active development, (ii) the objective results that are foreseen and wanted, and (iii) the personal emotional inclinationâ (p. 126). That is, interest is central to the understanding of art as educationalâthe special meaning of interest highlights the significance of humans âto be interested is to be absorbed in, wrapped up in, carried 76 away by, some object. To take an interest is to be on the alert, to care about, to be attentiveâ (p. 126). In this way, Deweyâs conception of interest further develops his view of the connectedness between human agents and the environment: how we undergo a process of development that we experience as a âsituatedâ being, giving us a more capacious framework for appreciating the natural world. With this theoretical foundation, we can now tentatively argue that art should be an instrument for negotiating the relationship between a person and the world. Presumably we already negotiate our relationship to the world in a variety of ways (e.g., by maintaining relationships with other people, cultivating a personal style, pursuing a career of one sort or another, and so on), but Dewey calls into question the breadth and depth of our actions as a process of self-renewal. His concept of agency implies not only participation, but reflective participation: if we need to be able to choose between different outcomes that will make a difference to us, then we need to be able to measure the difference. Here, the value of education as a process of reflecting on conduct is apparent, and art is obviously one instrument among many. Thus, we confront the skeptical question: why art education? Adults could conceivably reflect on their conduct in a great many ways. Why not promote science education, language education, religious education, political education, environmental education, or any other education that enhances our understanding of our relationship to the world? Dewey appreciates the diversity of our modes of reflection and carves out a special place for art. Art answers to the need for a particular outcome of education as he sees itânamely, that education should shape the time we devote to work and 77 leisure.23 The comprehensiveness of Deweyâs philosophy of education becomes quite apparent hereâthere seems to be no place in our lives that is immune to the transformative process of education. Is this really possible or desirable? Indeed, Dewey (1916/1966) believes that democracy is beholden to the ideal of education as play: The realization of a form of social life in which interests are mutually interpenetrating, and where progress, or readjustment, is an important consideration, makes a democratic community more interested than other communities have cause to be in deliberate and systematic education. (p. 87) This statement can be seen at once promoting institutions of education as well as cultures of education. The artworld, understood as a cultural force, is responsible for making leisure more thoughtful and work more playful. Dewey directs our thinking about the psychological aspects of art making. He says, âonly a personal response involving the imagination can possibly procure realization even of pure âfactsââ (p. 236). Art making must be imaginative to be educative just as it must be educative to have a positive effect upon the social environment. For Dewey, imagination is cerebral and emotional, and he believes that âthe imagination is as much a normal and integral part of human activity as is muscular movementâ (p. 237). Thus, for Dewey, artâs role in democratic life is the integration of the individual and the environment, and a playful manifestation of imagination in a social space. 23 For an extended discussion of Deweyâs notion of play, see Huizinga (1950). 78 4. Conclusion In art, work and leisure combine as serious, imaginative play. The greatest obstacle to this will be a sense of alienationâa perceived lack of continuity between oneâs self and the world. To overcome this, Dewey recommends a respect for the dignity and uniqueness of human experience, and argues that the object and reward of learning is continued capacity for growth. The doubt we feel as artists is often intense and corporeal, but there is no royal road for learning in Deweyâs ideal conception of education. Understanding art making as an educative experience enables usâeven compels usâinto action as artists. What exactly it means to âact as an artistâ is beyond the scope of my dissertation, but we have retrieved at least one perspective: as a result of the peculiar tradition and institutions of the artworld, art will likely convey not only information, but also, as Dewey anticipates, ideas about being a âselfâ in the world. On Deweyâs view, artistic activity carries inquiry further than mere pontification.24 Works of art are shown to modify the world in a useful way. And because art demands a particular exactness in our thinking, it is unlikely that would be otherwise knowledgeable about the things we investigate through art. This Deweyan perspective does not, however, currently permeate institutions of art education, and though it is a vital contribution to philosophy of art education, I do not attempt here to 24 Sullivan (2005) puts forward the view that art practice can be a kind of research, but I am more interested in art making as inquiry. Inquiry implies a personal set of desires, interests, and values 79 articulate how it intersects with natural science. Philip Kitcher gave a lecture series on what he calls the ânaturalistic impulseâ at Columbia University in 2004, and much of what interests me about the intersection between naturalism and the human sciences can be traced back to his work on Deweyâs Pragmatism.25 With this definitional ground in mind, we can now turn to a critique of genius from the perspective of art education, and its implications for the achievement of subordination as one part of growth. This is a âsecond chanceâ for geniusâthe conceptâs rich history and various meanings make it intelligible to contemporary artists and art educators, but also subject it to uneducative understandings. In Chapter III, I discuss the problem of genius and outline a methodology for reclaiming its educational value. Though my critique will ultimately be a philosophical one (and not historical per se) the philosophical task arises from the historical milieu. that research does not. Yet inquiry is partially defined by philosophy and partially defined by practice, and therefore, thoroughly grounded in social life. 25 For a contemporary scientific view of naturalism, see Kitcher (1992). 80 IIIâCONCEPTUAL FRAMEWORK 1. The Problem of Artistic Genius 1.1 A Brief Genealogy In ancient and medieval times, a genius was thought to be a spirit who gave good or bad advice. This understanding of genius is traceable in philosophical work as far back as Plato, who observed that poets âwork in a kind of frenzy they cannot account forâ (Barzun, 1989, p. 344). By the beginning of modernity (c. 1500), âgenius came to mean a knack of doing a particular thingâa gifted person was said to âhave a geniusââ (p. 342). Great artists in particular are thought to be geniuses, perhaps owing to the origin of the term. But âwhat we mean by genius derives rather from the Latin ingenium, meaning both natural disposition and innate abilityâ (Eysenck, 1995, p. 13). Recent academic debate about genius is related to its evolving ordinary meaning. This debate includes Romantic expansions and elaborations on an Enlightenment 81 conception of genius that deepened and complicated the concept, both as a matter of artistic productivity and intellectual ability. From the late eighteenth century to the present, the term genius has come to be used to describe people who are seen as innovatorsâa notion which was fostered in relation to and by other tenets of modernity. The modern notion of originality gathers its meaning in Romanticism, wherein philosophers (and thinkers of all kinds, especially poets) viewed persons as geniuses if they were understood to be able to create âoriginalâ and âexemplaryâ works of art. For example, Wangâs (2000) discussion of Romanticism explores genius as a theoretical construct with respect to literature. Arguing that Romanticism is a trope on the value of history, Wang claims, âa consideration of artistic beauty invariably leads to the matter of its creationâ (p. 22). Genius cannot be easily dismissed, he argues, as it addresses the âjudging subjectâsâ relation to nature, which he associates with Romanticism as a literary critic (p. 16). The âcatachresis of genius,â so named, becomes an aporia in literary interpretation. In the twentieth century, art critics frequently used genius to describe great artists, often calling attention to different character traits as different contexts require.26 Rosalind Kraussâ interest in the nature of originality in the age of mechanical reproduction leads her to the matter of tradition (Krauss, 1981). Her thesis that the avant-garde can be understood as a result of a discourse about originality informs my 26 For a representative example of how critics characterize genius, see Hartmann (1991), p. 276. 82 interest in genius. 27 She claims that some artists have been on a quest to create original art, while others are aware of the absurdity of this quest. Today, genius is commonly understood as an individual trait or set of distinct abilities. For example, Armstrong (1998) defines genius as a set of qualities including curiosity, playfulness, imagination, creativity, wonder, wisdom, inventiveness, vitality, sensitivity, flexibility, humor, and joy. This view comes out of psychological literature that has self-consciously attempted to demystify genius. Psychologists have largely focused on creativity as an essential aspect of genius. 28 Gruber recommends against adopting a view of genius, and adopting instead a process-oriented view of creativity deduced from case studies of exemplary historical figures. His theory of creativity follows from the ordinary meaning of genius as an innate quality or disposition that facilitates the achievement of excellence (Duddy, 1999; Barzun, 1989; Bromwich, 1985; Nahm, 1950). Social theory presents us with a model whereby communities of like-minded practitioners grants recognition to exceptional practitioners (Alicke, 1997; Wheeler & Miyake, 1992; Wood, 1989).29 As with disciplinary knowledge, this identification 27 For more on her conception of originality as a discourse, see Kraussâ (1981) essay The Originality of the Avant-Garde. She discusses the meaning of Modernist art that can be understood, from her critical perspective, as the result of inquiry into the meaning and nature of originality. 28 See Ward, T. B., Finke, R. A., & Smith, S. M. (1995) as an example of how research on creativity overlaps research on genius. 29 For more about the nature of hierarchical social labeling, there is a cottage industry of psychological work on âsocial comparisonâ to reference. See, e.g., Alicke, et al. (1997), Festinger (1954), Morse & Gergen (1970), Wheeler & Miyake (1992), and Wood (1989). This literature also provides an explanation for why there are self-proclaimed geniuses, and shows how the nature of 83 appears to be objective (universalizing) in its intent. The theoretical assumption that cognitive processes contribute to greater creativity is often reified by the psychological and cognitive study of creativity. Testing is often used to assess creativity with such tests as the Torrance Tests of Creative Thinking, Wallach and Kogan Tests, Remote Associates Test, and Thinking Creatively with Sounds and Words (as cited in Scope, 1998). Recent literature on creativity follows from the American Psychological Association highlighting the importance of the study of creativity in 1950 (Scope, 1998).30 Exceptional products of the visual arts are recognized as creative (Weisberg, 1988), and also that theoretical models and inventions that result from work in the natural sciences are seen as creative (Gardner, 1988; Weisberg, 1988). Although one is tempted to associate creativity with extremely high levels of achievement based on these examples, Milgram (1990) argues that creativity is not limited to exemplarity in personal and vocational spheres (as cited in Scope, 1998, p. 2). Scope notes that creativity is a complex construct, and follows other researchers in identifying four major branches of research: creative products, creativity as a psychological trait, cognitive processes and creativity, and environmental factors and creativity. Sternberg and Lubart (1996) conclude that creative people often exhibit psychological traits that include independence of judgment, self-confidence, attraction this claim reinforces the folk psychology notion that recognition by a community is an essential aspect of genius. 30 I am indebted to Ellis Scope for his doctoral work, A Meta-Analysis of Research on Creativity: The Effects of Instructional Variables (1998). My awareness of recent psychological research on creativity (Gardner, 1988; Milgram, 1990; Runco, 1994; Sternberg & Lubart, 1996; Weisberg, 1988) is informed by his analysis. 84 to complexity, aesthetic orientation, and risk-taking (as cited in Scope, 1998, p. 5). According to a cognition perspective, the cognitive processes necessary for the manifestation of creativity are problem identification, generation of solutions and ideas, and evaluation and modification of ideas and solutions. Runco (1994) finds that these processes need not occur in any particular order. Thus, creativity is commonly treated synonymously with creative processes, which are, in turn, often identified under the more specific rubric of creative problem solving. Scope (1998) suggests metacognitive skills influence creative problem solving, when these skills are understood to be knowledge about general cognitive strategies and procedural knowledge about monitoring, evaluating, and regulating these strategies (p. 7). Alongside the problem of defining genius is the problem of identifying young geniuses. Hulbert (2005, November 20) explores current and past trends in this area. Recently, for example, the effort to give young geniuses a superior education has been widely adopted in American schools, while private efforts have also been implemented on a wide scale (Hulbert, 2005, November 20, p. 68). Psychological research has been at the heart of much of these efforts, though its meaning for education is less than clear. The driving force of such social change has been, in many ways, the hope for greater and more significant social changeâthe proponents of identifying genius at an early age are seemingly driven by the image of past geniuses as change agents, individuals whose achievements bring a cascade of new ideas, technologies, and possibilities to civilization. 85 The uneasy status of the not-yet-eminent genius has brought about a new vocabulary for talking about the cause, meaning, and nature of what is sometimes only known as genius after the effect of a personâs achievements are widely understood. Finding the mark of creativity in adolescenceâeven preadolescenceâoften means comparing individualsâ achievements against othersâ on a battery of tests. It means quantifying outcomes that are not easily quantified, especially in the case of artistic ability. There is little evidence to believe researchers bent on identifying the greatest geniuses are on the right track since most children who once achieved the highest scores on these tests settle into comfortable lives as merely above-average practitioners in the arts and sciences (Hulbert, 2005, November 20, p. 78). The history of the concept of genius seems to reflect the diverse ways artistsâ work is valued. On closer inspection, however, this rich interweaving of ideas by aestheticians, ethicists, Romantics, and post-Romantics alike, fails would-be artists in subtle ways. By failing to take responsibility for the educational value of the discourse surrounding genius, the concept is turned inside out and understood and discussed from the perspective of the audienceâthe consumers of art. This has the insidious effect of passively influencing art pedagogy that, in turn, trains students to appreciate art that is made by someone whose phenomenological experience is safely and conveniently inaccessible for the purpose of critique.31 Thus, the forces of arbitrariness 31 The art historian may object here, noting that art history is the careful and deliberate study of such phenomena. The separation of Art History and Studio Art as disciplines, however, artificially restricts the possibilities of a fruitful exchange of ideas. For more on this circumstance, see Efland (1990), especially Chapter Eight: Art Education from World War II to the Present. 86 and contingency gathered by social practices that may be external to the practice of art making influence the reception of the concept of genius. In this way, genius may overwhelm an ideal of excellence with the idea of luck. To be recognized in any positive way by a community creates the possibility of a new hierarchy of relationships, but the notion of genius often distorts the value of recognition. That is, if genius is believed to be an accident of birth, 32 how can a community nurture a sense that art making is something to which one is âcalled,â and therefore a worthwhile, lifelong project one cultivates for oneâs self and others?33 What if a community has too many geniuses or not enough? In a community that values genius, might an artist become too reliant on those judgments or make unwarranted judgments about his talents? The world is a complex milieu of ideas and actions, and the concept of genius cannot and should not be divorced from the manifold aspects of human experience out of which it rose, in which it trades, and into which it can again be cast. The purpose of this study, outlined in detail in the following section, is to confront the concept at the edge of history and on the brink of the future of art education. 32 Even sophisticated debate about developmental determinism, and a high-minded attitude about the balance between ânatureâ and ânurture,â does not banish the persistent and reasonable worry that underlying biological structures have an effect on intelligence, broadly conceived. See, e.g., Eysenck (1995), especially Chapter 2 on genius and intelligence. 33 See Hansen (1995) for his rich description of teaching as a calling. 87 1.2 Research Questions MacIntyreâs concept of subordination locates the force of genius at one moment in a social landscape demarcated by practicesâas a currency of practitionersâ relationships with other practitioners. This allows us to imagine a âmoral frameworkâ for understanding genius, and I explored that framework in Chapter IâGauguin made paintings that explored the moral status of his professional decisions and activities. On considering Gauguinâs example, I argue that his achievements in art are moral achievements, even though they may give rise to undesireable consequences. In Chapter II, I elaborated the problems a moral theory based on this framework could aim to resolve. These were shown to be educational problems. As I outlined in Chapter II, MacIntyreâs story of how people enter into practices is incomplete. Perhaps he avoids telling a story he is not qualified to tellâwarning, as he does, that âthe uninitiatedâ cannot fully understand excellence in a practiceâ practice-specific stories that require insider knowledge. Perhaps he prefers not to discuss practitionersâ perspective, or sees it as having little consequence for moral theory. Either way, I believe it to be a significant problem, both for moral theory and practitioners with an eye to education. Genius, understood as an extreme example of excellence, will be shown to define the educative nature of MacIntyreâs concept of subordination. Some individuals achieve profoundly individual yet resonant outcomes in their art practices. Putting the concept of genius front and centerâa concept that gathers 88 meaning historically in association with the artsâis a strategy for better understanding the impact of subordination on excellence. In addition, a critique of genius is potentially significant for arts practitioners, who cope with genius as one aspect of art practice. The matter of what constitutes a practice-specific account of artistic genius therefore emerges as a central question. Other questions follow. How does the concept of artistic genius relate to moral excellence? How does the concept of artistic genius relate to art practice? How do art educators currently understand artistic genius? How does subordination lead to artistic excellence? How is art understood as original and exemplary? These questions are directed at conceptualizing a particular answer. I am not just asking, âWhat is genius?â without a context. Because my critique emerges from my experience as a student of art, I am asking what role genius plays in art education.34 34 Verhesschenâs (1991) work on narrative research as educational research is significant for my study. He makes a comparison between narrative research and philosophy after surveying narrative studies and finds that they lead to revelations for the researcher and a subsequent transformation. By posing narrative research as a way to answer research questions when meaning for a practitioner is at stake, Verhesschen argues that this is a legitimate end for scientific research. 89 2. Methodology 2.1 My Approach to the Problem The concept of genius began as an explanation of artistic expression and has become associated with intelligence. This shift in perspective speaks to geniusâ usefulness as a concept. Social practices such as the arts seem to cohere well if some practitioners are seen as geniuses, even if the concept is somewhat antagonistic to some practitioners. In a social landscape besieged by economics, politics, sports, and other spheres of influence, geniuses may increase the autonomy of art practice. If this is seen as a beneficial outcome, and I believe it should be, then the concept warrants further investigation and consideration. Theories of genius are fragmented and incomplete, yet there is the need to tell as comprehensive a story as possibleâif not for the sake of philosophy, then for the sake of those practitioners who are negatively influenced by the concept. This is a quality that philosophy rightly aspires to: a quality that makes a theory potentially more useful, as well as potentially wrong. With this positive project in mind, I treat the notion of âartistic geniusâ as partaking of a more universal concept of genius. The specificity to the arts both reflects the conceptâs historical relation to arts practices and gestures toward the broader concept of genius. The practice-specific concept suggests a 90 special meaning of excellence in art, and leaves open the possibly of whether there are other kinds of genius. Genius is often linked to creativity, which is often result-orientedâa conception of genius that has been strengthened by work in the sciences (Ghiselin, 1952). But there is also the possibility that genius is related to creativity, and there is an additional distinction made in psychological literature between act-oriented and process-oriented conceptions of creativity.35 When conceived of as an act or a process, genius seems less like an enduring characteristic. Gardner (1993) recommends avoiding the question âWhat is creativity?â and asks instead, âWhere is creativity?â This question points to an interpretive structure as the key to understanding creativity. But there are many available structures: MacIntyreâs theory of moral life, Gardnerâs own theory of multiple intelligences, Freudâs theory of the unconscious, Dantoâs theory of the end of art history, and so on. To some extent, almost any theoretical structure will do. Contrary to Gardnerâs intuition, therefore, I believe there is more at stake in the former question. By choosing MacIntyreâs philosophy as a philosophical framework, and Deweyâs philosophy as a guiding principle, I have answered this question only provisionally. There is much left to be defined, and it is important in a different way than anticipated by Gardner. It is important for art. 35 In an unpublished paper on creativity, Anthony Cocciolo distinguishes between art-oriented and process-oriented conceptions of creativity (personal communication, December 15, 2005). He helpfully draws a contrast between Koestlerâs (1964) act-oriented conception, and Gruberâs (1989) process-oriented conception. 91 Like MacIntyre (1984), I prefer the notion of a âpracticeâ when specifying what is similarly captured by the concepts of âdomainâ or âdiscipline.â In MacIntyreâs lexicon, the term âpracticeâ evocatively captures and emphasizes relations between social activities and individualsâ lives. He partly defines practices as complex social activities (p. 189), and many of the arts meet his terms (which I will discuss at length in Chapter V). Practices need not be strictly defined, and nowhere do I discuss exactly how art making qualifies as a practice other than to emphasize art as inquiry in Chapter II. Like other aspects of the natural world, and perhaps perplexingly so, there is no permanent ânatureâ of many human activities. Any endeavor to better capture the past, present, and future qualities of practices, therefore, begins on unsteady ground. 2.2 My Analysis of the Problem A theme of my studyâthe achievement of subordinationârequires that I critique MacIntyreâs systematic moral philosophy to use it as a guide for philosophizing about genius as one aspect of art practice. I speak in MacIntyreâs language because my project partly overlaps his project, and it locates my argument in a wider discourse. The same can be said for my use of Kant and Gadamerâs philosophies, as I encounter these 92 philosopherâs insights with respect to the conceptual window I establish with my interest in a particular kind of excellence in art practice.36 It is difficult to ascertain the impact of my critique of genius on MacIntyreâs theory of virtue, Kantâs theory of judgment, or Gadamerâs theory of understanding. Although such a critique potentially speaks back to all these philosophies, I am deploying them here as theoretical frameworksâhistorically significant lenses through which a critique of genius can gain traction on a messy, complex ground of experience. My experience of art practice, shaped and colored by culture, context, and circumstance, only partially guides my philosophical approach; my previous work in philosophy is also influential with respect to the overall form of my critique. I began my critique with an exegesis of Deweyâs view of education to put forward a positive view of the conjunction of art and education, but it is not the purpose of my critique to argue against alternative views of art. Genius is studied to better understand both artistic excellence and artistic influence. Moral philosophy, epistemology, hermeneuticsâphilosophies of these types (and many others) can be (and should be) deployed to improve art education, but this is a slow and multifaceted process. My critique of genius is partly a critique of the third person perspective embodied in psychological literature, and how such an understanding is born out by 36 I will use the term arts practice to refer to the notion of a community of individual artists sharing a common set of tools, values, and discourses. This is always a vague matter, as communities are unlikely to be in perfect agreement about what constitutes a practice. In certain cases, I use the plural âart practicesâ to gesture toward diversity among artists and avoid confusion about my assumption regarding tradition. 93 the first person perspective in practice. This perspective, I will argue, insufficiently captures characteristics of artistic genius from the perspective of art education. The study will take the form of a philosophical analysis of one âlocus of significationâ I identify as critical in my education as an artist.37 As a method of inquiry, I deploy philosophy in a way that best suits the subject of my experience. As a departure from a strictly defined body of literature, this study assumes that a scholarly analysis of concepts can (and should) proceed from a âcritical autobiography,â and this can successfully be styled as analytic philosophy.38 But this work also has the intent of making objective claims about the world.39 With the art classroom in mind, I am interested in the predictive power that could come from understanding how artists learn from other artists. I believe this relation partakes of more than mere âsubjectiveâ interests; I do not accept that art making is so deeply autobiographical that there is nothing to guide the work of teaching. Although I share the view that teaching cannot be reduced to âteaching methodsâ or strategies (Hansen, 2001), I am interested in normative truths about art practice that can inform teaching. I assume that my experience in a collegiate studio art program is common, even if my response of seeking a finely tuned, philosophical rationale for continuing to make art after graduation is not. 37 I use the term âlocus of significationâ to highlight philosophyâs variable function and purpose across different academic domains. To call it an âentity,â âconcept,â âvalue,â or so forth would oversignify and do an injustice to the genre of writing I am attempting to sustain. 38 For an elegant summary on what is meant by âanalytic,â see Leiter (2002) on the difference between analytic and continental styles of philosophy. 94 2.3 My Argument for Artists Moral truths, although non-relativistic, are usually framed by enculturation (Haste, 1996), and this means everything that can be a truth about how we live is framed by our cultureâlanguage, habits, customs, activities, and norms. Since this is so, the problems of moral philosophy can be rendered as matters of education. Educational philosophy is a discipline that theorizes about the educational aspects of human actions, attitudes, and values. Moral philosophy, however, does not recede entirely from view. It concerns historical inquiry about the matter of goodness. Moral philosophy thus becomes a perspective from which to pose educational questions that investigate truths about language, habits, customs, and so forth. Likewise, philosophical anthropology offers resources for this inquiry, albeit as a âmetaâ discourse (i.e., âthis is how X community viewed the matter of Yâ), and such a higherorder discussion could evaluate rival premises and worldviews. The MacIntyrian perspective I build upon, for example, could be brought under a critical lens in a way that I will not attempt here. I approach meta-ethical discourse as a comparative analysis of the correspondence between humans and their worldviews, and not about rightness or wrongness according to a restricted, philosophical domain that promises to âdetermine 39 For a helpful philosophical discussion of objectivity as an ideal, see Nagel (1999). 95 a correct course of actionâ for each situation put to it.40 Virtue ethics, a second-order project with a strong revival in the second half of the twentieth century, regards the achievement of an orientation toward the good as the primary telos of human experience.41 Epistemologically, subordination implies a belief in knowledge that bears on a âpracticalâ situation, and a concurrent belief that someone else has such knowledge. A skeptical objection that there is no such knowledgeâand therefore no reasonable desire for such knowledgeâmust be suspended for my inquiry to continue. This objection would be too strong, for it appears that people do rely on other peopleâs judgments all the time. The act of deferring oneâs judgment involves an act of trustâa belief that there is an end of education at which point a person is qualified to make a right judgment. We do not have to believe that such judgments will be right for all time, but it makes sense to think of a student as committed to this image of subordination. Thus, I am happy to admit that subordination, perceptions of excellence, and even the concept of genius may be wholly human, and therefore contingent, matters. 40 The domain of ethics may be best described in this way with respect to education. For example, Chris Higgins has emphatically pursued this distinction in his work on the âethics of teachingâ as a matter of teachersâ eudaemonia. For more on this, see Higgins (2003), especially where he refers to Williamsâ (1985) and othersâ remarks on this polemic. 41 An obvious counterexample to the claim that virtue ethics is a second-order project would be the case where philosophy itself is considered as a practice, and a philosopherâs first order of business was to study virtue. Indeed, we must entertain the possibility that some practices overlap with other practices. In Chapter V, it will be shown that the practices of teaching and learning are an example of this overlap, and being too strict about the autonomy of practices comes at too high a cost. When MacInytre claimed that teaching was not a practice, his critics and allies were quick to reject his view. They argue that teaching has become a fully-fledged practice in light of its aims, institutions, rituals, and so on. To see how they responded, see the special issue of The Journal of 96 There is a mode of philosophy that sets its goal as doing foundational legwork for once and all, and philosophical writing in this vein sets the stage for readers to commence such a task. My ambition is to write for this effect, but not without acknowledging that for truth to emerge, everyone must do the work for him or herself, even if this means closely recapitulating the philosophical thinking of othersâ. The critique of genius that follows is my own, and its consequences for artists are not yet clear. The philosophical perspective that emerges from this critique, however, is potentially useful to artists, educators, and philosophers alike, albeit in different ways. In the final chapter, therefore, I will discuss the emergent view of genius and its implications for art education. 2.4 My Aim as a Philosopher of Art Education This study identifies subordination as an aspect of education in general that should serve as a point of reference for future pedagogical recommendations. It assumes that a complex web of values influences every person, and that education is jointly a process of individual growth and social engagement (Dewey, 1916; Gutmann, 1987). With respect to Deweyâs (1934/1980) view of art and Gadamerâs (1960/2002) view of tradition, art is posited as an event-object in a relationship-rich world of things. MacIntyreâs account of morality provides a context for both examining the educative Philosophy and Education, 37(2). I give my own response to MacIntyreâs view below in Chapter V, 97 crosscurrents of art making, and therefore, understanding subordination as one part of the humanistic project of the human sciences. Flanagan (1991) puts it plainly: âknowledge in the human sciencesâknowledge of ourselves as fallible beings with all manner of quirksâgives us a certain amount of control over the nature, structure, and quality of our livesâ (p. 314). Throughout the critique, what are abstract concepts will become better defined as my critique of genius proceeds from multiple perspectives and develops a narrative structure. As research, this study interrogates issues surrounding my personal experiences as an art student. To some, my perspective may seem highly idiosyncratic, but I suspect it will be familiar to many participants of liberal education. After all, it was the initial educational outcome of failing to become an artist that motivated my further philosophical inquiry. As a result of my subsequent introspection, my study situates itself as a kind of rationale for practicing the arts.42 While my interest in philosophical inquiry may be exaggerated compared to many âprofessionalâ artists, it is an idealistic articulation of an underlying structure of art practices. In brief, I aim to make contributions to both moral philosophy and educational philosophy by telling a story about a kind of activity that is manifest in art. This study further develops moral theory within the field of art education. Moral theory is understood to have particular relevance for art practitioners as Section 3. 42 By acknowledging a Humean skepticism about the limitations of any rationale, I have attempted to attend to only a part of my own rationale for practicing the arts. 98 reflective agents in institutions of liberal education, and those institutions as arenas of democratic life. In emphasizing the historical dimension of art practices, I expect to show how a certain configuration of a practitionerâs life can help sustain the ongoing work of a practice in spite of idiosyncratic perceptions held by student practitioners and others. A study of subordination is an exploration of the intersection of tradition and personal narrative in practices. The contingent nature of tradition will be explored as an overcoming of resistance to historical thinking, and the event of âstanding under traditionâ will be considered as an essential aspect of art. This philosophical dialogue will possibly persuade others to come to an agreement about values as a community and sustain further dialogue. Artists, critics, and historians who are interested in âartistic influenceâ can read MacIntyreâs account of subordination in practices as an opportunity to systematically locate the idea of influence in a dialogue oriented toward excellence. Posed as an extreme example of excellence in art practices, the concept of genius may clarify the nature of artistic influence. One kind of interpersonal relationship among artists will be described in greater detail, and this will clarify some of the persistent notions of artfulness that threaten to close off the domain of art making from students like myself. Teachers may also benefit from this dialogue. Because teachers are emissaries of educational institutions, teachers help each student cultivate a balanced response to his or her self, a practice, and the world. A study of the historically bound concept âartistic geniusâ may be a useful evaluative tool for art teachers of all kinds for considering how they are perceived by students in relation to a practice. This pertains 99 especially to teachers in higher education where students confront a clash of artistic and vocational drives. One reason art teachers need a deep understanding of genius is that they must be proactive proponents of excellence.43 No antidote for skepticism about oneâs self is readily available in art education. Passing off anxiety about genius as a âpersonalâ problem underplays the conceptâs rich history and relationship to the artsâa conversation that could be brought into art classrooms where students struggle. Artistic creation is connected to at least as many features of the world as there are human in it, and the significance of this diversity should not be diminished. The tradeoffâhaving no pretension of crafting a strictly universal theory of geniusâis made for the sake of crafting a useful theory. My aim in conceptualizing genius from the perspective of art education is, therefore, for art educators and their students. Part II begins this conceptualization by arguing that genius should be seen as a more intimate recognition of an artistâs relation to a tradition of practice. 3. Limitations Without a concern for moral philosophy, my argument would go as follows: I argue for a provisional definition of genius as an ideal relationship between an 43 It would be interesting (as well as difficult) to measure this viewâs impact on education. The philosophical legwork I am undertaking here is merely propaedeutic to this sort of fully-fledged naturalistic inquiry. 100 individual and tradition. Hermeneutics helps define the ideal as a balance between presentism and historicism during the work of âunderstanding.â I support this argument with several points, making my case for the provisional definition to be the preferred definition. I show that 1) the notion of genius is historically associated with the arts; 2) activities like art making are best understood as âpractices;â 3) practices are considered a source of âmorality;â 4) we prefer the products of artists who stand under tradition; and 5) genius is wrongly thought to be a matter of originality without due consideration of the role of tradition. In the actual arrangement, I have tried to capture the implications of this definition for moral philosophy. Although I had hoped the resulting argument (about both morality and moral philosophy) would make the argument for reconceptualizing genius stronger, and vice versa, I am not sure it has this effect. What counts as evidence, and for what argument, is too easily confused, and it is left to the charitable reader to both follow the logic and arrive at meaningful conclusions from the shifting terrain of âeducational theory.â While my experience of art education (especially in the college classroom) ultimately frames one view of art making at a nexus of critical, moral, and educational philosophy, there are implications for philosophy. Gadamerâs hermeneutic theory of tradition and MacIntyreâs tripartite theory of moral life are frameworks for seeing the significance of genius within a horizon that includes Kant and his conceptual legacy.44 I 44 Gadamer (2002) describes the subjectivization of aesthetics largely through his depiction of the concept of genius in opposition to the methodological structure of the natural sciences. While I find this argument constructive from a hermeneutic point of view, I am reminded by Gadamerâs own theory of understanding that the resulting instrumental portrayal of genius need not obscure 101 provide, however, no foundational argument for this philosophical perspective. The process of making meaningâwhere autobiographical continuity is expectedâtrumps the objection that a tautology underlies this interpretation of a concept. From the perspective of current work in meta-ethics, therefore, it is defanged as a work of criticism. From the perspective of art education, it is propaedeutic to criticism. From an autobiographical perspective, its critical function is scholarship. Read in this way, I hope a charitable reader will reconsider theorizing as research. For my part, I will engage a wide community of thinkers to avoid the perils of philosophical solipsismâ although this is never reassuring as it should be. Robbie McClintockâs (2004) essay on the academic study of education highlights this studyâs potential in three distinct modes: scholarship, research, and criticism. Concept formations of the kind I am undertaking could potentially be carried out within an academic discipline as a âdisinterestedâ study of educationâwhich he describes as contributing no direct professional recommendationsâbut this community is underrepresented and not well supported in modern universities (McClintock, 2004). My study will not be so disinterested. As I have hinted at above, it will be applied to the âfieldâ of studio art. Unfortunately, I am writing for a discipline area that suffers from an over-professionalized and under-theorized existence. artistsâ work. For artists whose work can be construed as an expression of human science, the matter of genius is very much alive and not to be ignored simply because it has been understood differently in contrast to objectivity in the natural sciences. 102 3.1 Moralities and Languages As one approaches the concept of morality, one must keep the milieu of human experience in view. Philosophers seeking applications for finely tuned moral theories (or those finely-tuning moral theories for application) are likely to forget these complexities. Philosophy need not be inapplicable, but practitioners of philosophy (of all kinds and abilities) should heed the importance of nuance. This is a troubling proposition for many philosophers and scientists who regard truth as a matter of subjecting succinct and isolable events to highly objective processes of verification. Yet as difficult as it is to secure truth by the methods I have chosen, those under sway of a perversely technological notion of progress should not inconsiderately brush alternative (and similarly sophisticated) methods aside. Although my subject matter is not atoms, molecules, chemical structures, or the stars, but the human event of genius, I am similarly interested in truth. A limitation of the study, therefore, is my ability to summon the methodological resources of my own choosing to serve two masters: they must be sufficiently rigorous in order to tell the truth, and they must be sufficiently âopenâ to serve as an invitation for my colleagues, wherever and whomever they may be, to âverifyâ my findings. A current tendency is to assume that âgeniusâ refers to a kind of person, but this was not always the case. And it is not agreed upon, even today, in what way a person qualifies a genius. Furthermore, a common appeal in the artworld is to equate a consistent output of a certain kind of product with a permanent (or durable) 103 characteristic of the creator of those products (Stern, 1971). A key distinction that is called for is whether or not âartistic geniusâ is understood as a character trait, a sum total of a personâs traits, or something else. There are merits to all these ways of talking about genius. When I use the term as I do in the dissertation title, I simply mean to regard artists who are ordinarily recognized as âgeniusesâ and make a universalizing statement. The universal concept cannot be shown to hold in all cases, and it is not meant to. It is, however, argued by me to make sense of most cases, and to the exclusion of cases where I argue that it was misattributed in the first place. If it were shown to be the case that, in fact, most cases are not well-described by the term âgenius,â then it will have been proven wrong to call it such. This would indicate deeper problems for my argument, such as whether or not I can rightly criticize MacIntyre for misunderstanding the role of subordination in moral life, whether Kant is wrong for depicting genius as a matter of originality, or whether genius can rightly said to have a moral nature at all. Concepts influence behavior, and should be understood to be âthings in the worldâ about which there can be an objective truth (Kitcher, 1992; Garver, 1986; Eames, 1977).45 Truth may emerge from different cultures and languages, but it is not 45 Values are constituted by and constitutive of many unseen things (customs, culture, beliefs, rational thoughts, and so on). It is a tenet of value theoryâa mode of moral philosophyâthat principled actions are made possible by values. Though I recognize the need for more clarification about the concept of values, I will instead offer clarification about the notion of practice in Chapter V, Section 1. 104 relativistic.46 It is objective in the sense that it aspires to be universal. Philosophy, it can thus be said, is usually written in a âthinâ language, without the full burden of the minute details of experience. The hope is that readers will be persuaded to do the work of translating abstractions back into the âthickâ languages of experience. 3.2 Disciplinary Boundaries There are a number of lenses for understanding genius that I will not entertain here, such as the matters of luck and âtalent.â These are, admittedly, powerful frameworks for understanding geniusâand I will attend to them when they loom especially largeâbut I will not pretend to treat them at all comprehensively. Theorizing a moral conception of genius means leaving these lenses behind, even if they helpfully fill out a broader conception of genius. I study genius at the intersection of moral philosophy and art education, and a major theme of this interdisciplinary area is internal motivation for engaging the act of artistic creation. Hence, I want to dispose straightaway with external motivations, internal motivations for engaging other tasks, and non-motivational matters. 46 Relativism often follows on the heels of âsubjectivity,â but naturalism eschews it. My view of subjectivity as a natural part of the world is not novel, but perhaps it is not often put so succinctly. What exactly constitutes nature has been debated from the nineteenth century onwards (and all the way back to ancient Greece, if one allows for post-Enlightenment prejudices). I see Gadamerâs (2002) discussion of language as partially redressing this matter. For more on âsituatedness,â which is another name for the belief that culture âgoes all the way down,â see Greene (1995), especially her description of the âshapes of childhoodâ (p. 73-86). 105 For some, my work will suffer the comparison to previous explorations of genius as creativity. But I intend my work as another matter. For example, Gruberâs work on creativityâhis evolving systems approach and the case studies he and his students developâis concerned with a sufficiently different matter than artistic genius. First of all, he studies all kinds of eminent individuals. Secondly, his case study method does not have a principled method for defining eminence as genius after Romanticismâits foundation is commensurate with a normative conception of creativity. It is the articulation of just such a principled view of genius that my critique aims to generate. Where Gruber detects methods in artistsâ creative processes, his work should be understood as recommending examples of art practice. The concept of genius has a much more expansive history than can be gathered by a few examples, or even a single philosophical perspective. As such, my critique is self-consciously related to art education as a strategy for bounding the concept in a productive way. I hope to summon an audience that does not readily exist by calling attention to what this project offers. My colleagues are art educators who value the emphasis liberal education places on inquiry. While I have culled my scholarship primarily from literatures surrounding the problem of artistic geniusâinterpreting this as a framework for educational matters in the studio art classroomâthis is also a study in moral philosophy. As philosophy, my study will be seen as risking an approach to too small a problem from too parochial a perspective. This is a necessary limitation, and philosophy has much potential with this scope and on this scaleâdespite any such projectâs narrow appeal. My project is not an exercise in aesthetic philosophy (nor, if 106 there is indeed a difference, philosophy of art). It does not sustain a focus that would appeal to art historians. It is not general enough to interest moral philosophers with a broad interest in virtue ethics (MacIntyre scholars will likely find it too technical, or worse, torturously long-winded). And it is too far a field for mainstream educational philosophers. Lacking a ready-made audience, I undertake ethical and educational projects simultaneously, and write with art educators in mind. A weakness of philosophical argumentation with multiple theoretical premises is that it will be unwieldy to disprove it. What is to be done? Theories are often thought to need to be âsurroundedâ by empirical evidence, but they can also simply become âusefulâ (in a Pragmatic sense). I hope for both these outcomes to be possible, but I have aimed more at the latter and have delved into several topical discourses to renew interest in the meaning of artistic genius from an educational perspective. After proposing a hermeneutic theory of subordination in Part II, which I argue shapes artistsâ perceptions of other artists and their work, I turn to Kantâs philosophy in Part III to test the outcome of this critique. 107 PART IIâHOW WE THINK ABOUT ARTISTS The audience as understander, attempting an exact reconstruction in its own mind of the artist's imaginative experience, is engaged on an endless quest. It can carry out this reconstruction only in part. This looks as if the artist were a kind of transcendent genius whose meaning is always too profound for his audience of humbler mortals to grasp in a more than fragmentary way. And an artist inclined to give himself airs will no doubt interpret the situation like that. But another interpretation is possible. The artist may take his audience's limitations into account when composing his work; in which case they will appear to him not as limitations on the extent to which his work will prove comprehensible, but as conditions determining the subject-matter or meaning of the work itself⌠We have inherited a long tradition, beginning in the late eighteenth century with the cult of 'genius', and lasting all through the nineteenth, which is inimical to this. R. G. Collingwood, 1938/1958, pp. 311. 108 IVâSOCIAL DIMENSIONS OF MORALITY 1. Lessons From Psychology The matter of saintliness affords us a glimpse of genius through a moral lens, but I want to continue to resist a narrow moral perspective. Psychological literature has multiple avenues for framing the concept of genius, so the difficulty will be in applying existing research to the task of securing a relation between genius and artistsâ practices. In his book Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism, Owen Flanagan (1991) calls for a psychologically realistic ethical theory, and this will serve as a contribution to a hermeneutic view of genius. Starting from ethical and psychological discourses, Flanagan depicts a spectrum of personality types, and he shows how those types hang together as a rich variety of human lives. In contrast to virtue ethicists who Flanagan sees as trying to link good action and good character, and instead of an act-based psychological account that supposes a minimal set of moral principles from which good action flows, he argues that there can be no single theory of morally good character (Flanagan, 1991, pp. 331- 109 332). Understanding this characteristic of moral theory, which is often posed as an inadequacy, is the purpose of this chapter. Posing genius as a personality trait establishes the scope of an exploration of the moral nature of genius by setting parameters for moral theory. To this effect, psychologists make an important distinction between an intrapersonal and interpersonal dimension of personality that contributes to standards such as moral goodness (Flanagan, 1991). Precisely because this distinction is so difficult to maintain in actual evaluations of persons, psychologists remain skeptical about the boundaries of moral theory. Here, I explore the limits of philosophy, especially in regard to the interpersonal side of moral philosophy. This may prove to be useful elsewhere for experimentally testing the incidence of the concept of genius I go on to describe in Chapter V and Chapter VI. 2. Attribution Theory According to Flanagan (1991), âthe links between internal psychological features and actions are exceedingly complex and multiply trackedâ (p. 331). For the purpose of better representing reality with theory, he says, âwe need a better moral psychology, one that does not naturally fit either of the main traditions available to usâ (p. 12). By this, he means that philosophy has not yet adequately rendered the human mind in a 110 comprehensible and systematic way. He views philosophy in a similar way, though not quite as disparagingly, as Eysenck (1995) who says: [In philosophy] words like âimagination,â âinsightâ and so forth are sprayed about without definition, without possibility of measurement, without forming a testable theory, or even usually a comprehensive one⌠Philosophers seldom take kindly to such [criticism], and point to the obvious imperfections of scientific measure, particularly in its early stages. They look with amusement at our attempts to measure creativity, or intuition. (p. 4) The rival traditions of moral theory Flanagan seeks to go beyond represent two models of goodness and, therefore, two ideals of moral excellence. I will place these traditions in a greater historical context in the following section, but even a cursory description suggests the greater contours of the often-contested ground of moral philosophy. Flanagan (1991) describes these traditions as follows: One is the model of the principled reasoner who applies some supreme generalpurpose algorithm to all moral problems. The other is the model of the morally excellent person as the fully virtuous person. (p. 11) In other words, he finds both deontological and virtue-based approaches to ethics unsatisfying. Starting from these perspectives, Flanagan is able to prioritize his interest in ethics from the bottom upâfrom personalities to social evaluation. This is an enviable position from the perspective of moral philosophers who do not distinguish between absolute and contingent aspects of morality. Psychologists who start by assessing connections between thought and action are able to secure a foundation for morality that will suggest the proper use of the theory later on. This is important for a reconceptualization of genius because it may suggest a particular way to view supererogation, thereby revealing how such a moral ideal may be achieved. 111 2.1 Epistemic Foundations of Morality âEthicsâ is a broad domain of philosophizing about a wide range of ideas and problems. Not all work in ethics is about the same thing, and traditions have formed around various threads of inquiry. Thus, there is a âdeontologicalâ tradition grounded in Kantâs inquiry, a âutilitarianâ tradition grounded in Bentham and Millâs inquiry, and a âvirtue ethicsâ tradition grounded in Aristotleâs inquiry. There are other traditions, including offshoots and schematically similar (but differently described) traditions, but these are arguably the âBig Threeââand they are rival traditions. 47 That they are rivals means, partly, that they do not agree on what counts as ethics even though they use much of the same language, and partly that they agree on what counts and disagree about its meaning or importance. All three theories differ as to what âknowledge of moralityâ should and does refer. I am committed to invoking the tradition of virtue ethics in the case of genius, but I agree with Flanagan that it is not yet a complete theory. It may be currently useful only within philosophyâto help secure a framework for discussing philosophical problems. As such, it can be useful in the way it was useful for me as an art student groping for a rationale, but remain at the margins of wider discussions of moral excellence. Many philosophers remain unconvinced of its truth, and this would not be a problem were it not for the fact that they are convinced that other traditions better 47 For more on these rival traditions, see MacIntyre (1988). 112 describe (and resolve) the problems virtue ethics seeks to describe and resolve.48 More agreement among philosophers on the best organization of the domain of ethics is neededâconcessions should be made on both sides to allow for moral knowledge that intersects with other domains of knowledge and human activity. Since moral knowledge is widely thought to affect work in politics, science, religion, and other spheres, its refinement will be an important philosophical contribution.49 Flanagan believes a psychological perspective can help sharpen the debate surrounding the issue of moral excellence, and specifically, help define virtue. Adding to the difficulty of improving moral theory, virtue is a key term in the discussion of morality across traditionary boundaries. According to the deontological tradition, for example, an excellent person is someone who can be said to have some kind of intellectual virtue. Virtue ethics generally entails something more like a âunityâ of virtuesâa unity that often includes intellectual virtues, but necessarily encompasses many others. Both traditions beg the question of what constitutes virtue (or a virtue), and this question looms large over those philosophical projects. Indeed, such a question returns ethical and moral theorizing to its roots; but such foundational 48 For example, according to Scanlonâs (1998) âcontractualistâ view, I can rightly ground my rationale for making art on a justification that others cannot reasonably reject. According to this view, however, cases of supererogation must be evaluated on a case-by-case basis. Part of the value of virtue ethics, therefore, is the central role of supererogation. 49 My side interests in politics and religion does not do justice to where I fall along the timeworn polemic of philosophy between the two poles of âhuman mattersâ and the âhard factsâ of nature. With a deep interest in the work of science, I believe that virtue ethics can be seen as a bridge between the human sciences and the natural sciences. For more on this compatibility of these paradigms of knowledge, see Crease (1997), Skinner (1990), Polkinghorne (1983), and Gadamer (1960/2002). 113 concerns are, for Flanagan, out of place in the present. He puts forward the view that a differentiated notion of excellence is essential to ethics. For example, he says that if we start by conceiving of the ideal of excellence as constituted by principles, then we have already restricted the domain of morality too muchâprecluding ethics from identifying and categorizing diverse ways of life that are already commonly understood as excellent. This is reminiscent of Wolfâs concern for ânonmoralâ excellences, recast as a matter of personality. For psychologists, personality refers to individualsâ deep-seated psychological processes as well as differences between individuals. Many theories of thought and behavior fall under this branch of psychology, and a view of genius could be construed in many ways as a matter of personality. For the purposes of the present study, a few key insights about personality theories in general may serve as a useful corrective for moral theory. Some psychological research recommends choosing an explanatory âlevelâ for thinking about artists, and this points to attribution theory as a helpful framework. How we make attributions about personality has consequences for attributions about supererogation. But excellence, according to Flanagan, should be only partly understood as a result of personalityâthis is an outcome of his psychological portrayal of âminimal personsââand this sets the stage for looking at education in practices from a social perspective. 114 2.2 Minimal Persons For psychologists, the broad topic of morality evokes numerous theoretical lenses. Theorizing may take into account behavior, situations, dispositions, and traits as well as broader concepts such as identity, desire, cognition, and so on. But broad frameworks need not be cast as unifying frameworks, and a lack of unity may even be preferable from the perspective of theory. Flanagan (1991) puts this soberly enough: The usefulness of distinguishing among different explanatory levels designed to capture phenomena and regularities occurring and emerging at different planes is widely accepted as methodologically sound in the philosophy of mind, in psychology, and in cognitive science. (p. 136) To set the stage for explanatory divergence, Flanagan outlines and defends a theory of personalityâa theory of âminimal personsââthat cogently accommodates a wide range of theories of personality while limiting the impact of the first person view of a concept such as genius from the outset. That is, third person views may involve first person views, and an evaluative framework may be compromised by tendencies such as self-defense or self-aggrandizement. From a psychological perspective, an argument for distinctiveness among persons is needed to guard against the theoretical mistake of collapsing the idea of âpersonalityâ with a disembodied social norm. This protects against a self-sealed view of geniuses. The matter at hand, then, is why moral theory must have a psychological account of personhood, and I will continue this discussion below and again in Chapter V. 115 The theory of minimal persons supports the view that persons are separate and have distinctive points of viewâa matter that partly undermines moral theoryâs impulse to support a social agenda. Without an adequate account of supererogation, virtue ethics may appear to have this impulse. If it did, it would attest to the fact that individualsâ autonomy to choose a way of life is diminished against the rush to achieve excellence of any kind (or a specific kind). We do not need to go as far as virtue theorists, however, to imagine an intellectual virtue of some kind that settles and orders individualsâ social orientationsâwe can explain the diversity of human lives and ends along with a different explanation of how those ends are achieved. Flanaganâs (1991) portrait of minimal persons emerges from several premises: 1) âminimal persons consciously bear the information about themselves that they are conscious subjects of experienceâ (p. 63); 2) minimal persons are âintentional systemsâ (p. 63); and 3) minimal persons care about âthe satisfaction of their desires over timeâ (p. 64). In effect, it is just this kind of account that MacIntyre calls âthe narrative order of a single human life,â though for MacIntyre this picture of the individual occupies a different theoretical space. I will not attempt to elaborate (or untangle) his particular vision here, even as it may adequately serve the same purpose as a theory of minimal persons, it is burdened by a developmental picture of virtue Flanaganâs theory eschews. For Flanagan, the three-pronged theory of personality is self-evident and sufficient as a framework for considering behaviors that are believed to have a moral valence. Drawing a conclusion from the principle of minimal psychological realism, Flanagan (1991) invites philosophers to consider diverse ends of moral evaluation: 116 Good lives cannot be envisaged, nor can they be created and sustained, without paying attention to what goes on outside the agentâto the multifarious interactive relations between individual psychology and the natural and social environments. (p. 312) A minimal person viewed apart from a larger context is a barren place for morality to reside. Though persons need not be minimal in any finite sense, Flanaganâs conveyance of the potential of persons offers a sensible approach to the problem of genius. The identification of genius can be taken up at the intersection of the âintrapersonalâ (whether this is expressed as desire, intention, or simply awareness) and the âextrapersonalââon an interpersonal ground. The theory of minimal persons helps locate interpersonal aspects of personality, and recommends a third person perspective for conceptualizing moral ideals. It seems uncontroversial that good lives cannot be envisaged without attending to the world beyond the individual, but then this statement also implies that some sort of attentiveness is essential to the bringing about of good lives. The extent that such knowledge is enviable or necessary was left underdetermined by the theory of minimal persons. Here, the strong claim is not as interesting as the weak one. The weak claim seems to be that living well requires introspection and observation of the external world. Following the discussion of traits as useful and flexible dispositional âpackages,â this claim begs the question of who or what can and cannot pass as good based on patterns of behavior and assumptions about personality. This is evocative of other questions Flanagan seeks to answer, such as, âWhat kind of introspection and observation is passable as the bedrock of morality?â and, âMust we be moralityâminded 117 to partake of the good life?â If answered in the affirmative, the latter question cuts too harshly against Wolfâs intuition that a saint need not actively conceptualize a moral framework for his actions to be counted as good. The importance of the third person perspective suggests that morality is likely to be swayed by interpersonal matters. Traitology, the psychological study of personality as constituted by deep-seated and persistent dispositions, thus emerges as one potentially powerful foundational pillar of moral philosophy. 2.3 Attribution Biases Attribution theory gives a âmore general and unified account of how we in fact think about personsâin both first person and third person situationsâ (Flanagan, 1991, p. 311). It tempers to what degree genius can be considered objectively real at an intersection of behavior and social values. It is also particularly relevant when popular opinion about persons is taken seriously and at face value. Psychology literature explores attribution theory from many angles, and Flanagan highlights three biases in attributing traits as most applicable to moral theory: 1) overestimation of dispositional factors in general, 2) overestimation of dispositional factors from the third person point of view, and 3) a self-serving bias. In this section the significance of these biases in the way people characterize the behavior of others is elaborated for the purpose of anticipating how genius might be attributed. 118 Hypotheses about both dispositional and situation factors contribute to observations about personality. Dispositional factors are the result of existing patterns of behavior or habits, whereas situational factors are the result of an external, changing environment. An important observation from the perspective of psychological research is about the âfolk psychologyâ tendency to âoverestimate the impact of dispositional factors and to underestimate situational onesâ (Flanagan, 1991, p. 306) when judging moral personality.50 It seems one reason to be skeptical or eliminativist about traits is that people in general are likely to overlook the importance of situations on behavior and rush to judgment about the presence of a trait. It is therefore likely that genius is too often attributed to a person as a fundamental disposition, and recognitions of excellence may be wrongly associated with matters of disposition in general. For psychologists who acknowledge the force and utility of the concept of traits, the mistake to be avoided here is wrongly attributing traits by relying on an unrepresentative sample of behavior. Thus, observations of excellence over time serves as a better indication of genius as a trait.51 Another aspect of attribution that is manifest in experimental research is an individualâs tendency to more often describe the behavior of othersâ as the result of dispositions than oneâs own behavior (Jones & Nisbett, 1971), as cited in Flanagan 50 For more on this characteristic of attribution, see Rossâ (1977) work on Fundamental Attribution Tendency (cited in Flanagan, 1991, pp. 305-311). 51 I treat ârecognitionâ and âattributionâ as the same, though there is a shift of emphasis about an agentâs judgment. This is technical point, but an important distinction in psychoanalytic literature rests on the two-way relationship implied by recognition. 119 (1991, p. 309). When pushed for an explanation, it seems we rely less on traitology when it comes to our own behavior because of the following asymmetry: In many cases we have much more information, and thus better predictive data, about ourselves than about third parties and thus can dispense more easily with the summarizing trait apparatus in our own cases. (p. 310) Flanagan sees this bias as a corollary of the tendency to overestimate dispositional factors, and it highlights a purpose of traits as a way to summarize a view of a person. It stands to reason that one may attribute genius as a trait to a third party as the result of a lack of information similar to the information one has about oneâs self. For example, if a person has very little experience in the arts, even mediocre artistic achievements may elicit veneration. Another intriguing psychological phenomenonâespecially intriguing in a discussion of exceptional moral personalitiesâis the bias we have identifying behaviors as representative of traits when this serves our own interests (Schoeman, 1987). While this is shown to manifest itself in situations where we can impute positive traits to ourselves, it may be that we also act out of self-interest when attributing traits to others. For example, Gauguinâs exodus to Tahiti may earn him increased recognition as an artistic genius (beyond his ability to paint with secondary colors) because it distanced him from social norms. That is, it may serve the interest of non-artists to distance themselves from the work of artistsâessentially relinquishing them from the task of painting (Alicke, et al., 1997). Though this is not a clear-cut example, it speaks to the difficulty of parsing trait biases when the complex matter of identity is involved. The codification of genius as a trait (or certain traits as genius) may regulate a normative 120 conception of excellence, thereby decreasing expectations for oneâs self and recasting behavior in an acceptable way (relative to other non-geniuses). Both the self-serving bias and the fact that we are not as likely to ascribe our own behaviors to traits raise skepticism about supererogation. We need not dismiss popular opinion so much as qualify it in the aforementioned ways. Due to these biases, the historical turn from the view of genius as a feature of artistic experience to that of genius as a âglobalâ character trait of certain persons cannot be seen as entirely rational.52 Furthermore, because traitology exists at the level of folk psychology, a philosophical discussion of genius as a trait may simply contribute to an understanding of competing conceptions of genius. To delve into the implications of traitology for artists, we need to consider how conceptions of excellence are influenced at the level of folk psychology. 3. The Third Person Perspective There are several important implications for genius as a trait observed from the third person perspective. Because of errors in the way traits are recognized, it is possible that genius is wrongly attributed to persons. Even if the trait of genius was 52 The shifting emphasis on genius as a trait coincides with the rise of individualism in western cultures and the concurrent development of art making as a practice. I will not discuss the meaning of this historical circumstance here, but for a detailed analysis of the rise of individualism, see Taylor (1989), especially Part II: Inwardness. 121 shown to exist in some meaningful sense, the tendency to undervalue situational factors makes attributions that are not checked for error doubtful. One personâs opinion is not going to help us determine if a trait is present, so consensus may be a useful tool for identifying genius. But problems may persist especially if, for example, different conceptualizations of a trait hinder attribution. Likewise, observing situational behavior is not in itself indicative of traits, but a baseline along which traits may be said to occur. If genius is shown to be manifest in the works of art a person produces, then we should look for repetition of artistic outputâa single instance of production is not good evidence for the presence of a trait. These situations point to the need for a well-articulated view of genius from the third person perspective, and the resulting assurance will come at the cost of placing less value on the meaning of art practice for the artist. That traits are manifest over time plays to the hand of the saint, who, for one reason or another, is narrowly focused on a particular behavior. As Wolf shows us, a person may naturally exhibit a behavior that is demonstrable of saintliness, and this may be more or less a matter of luck. It could also be a matter of actively choosing to behave a certain way, but this internal difference is lost when viewed from the third person perspective. There are, therefore, several places to look for traits, such as in a personâs actions or in the product of their actions. Looking between the person and the products is possible: a trait or traits both make certain products visible (valued) and also make certain (but minimal) actions appear related to those products. Consensus building via corroboration is further brought into question by the phenomenon of âin- 122 group thinkingâ (Flanagan, 1991, p, 311). Observations of in-group thinking tells us that if it is somehow useful to artists that some artists are considered geniuses, then consensuses on particular cases may be biased in favor of identifying that trait. If third person experience is accepted as a reasonable vantage from which to identify genius, then there need be additional checks against in-group bias.53 About the matter of the third person perspective in general, there is a significant tension that arises between social psychological literature and MacIntyreâs theory of virtue in practices. Since MacIntyre claims individuals external to a practice cannot judge the goods internal to a practice (discussed below in Chapter V, Section 2.2), and since genius may arise in a way that is only practice-specific, his theory is resistant to the checks and balances that broad consensus about genius requires. This matter does not affect all aspects of the conceptualization of genius equally, and since I am not set on measuring the frequency of genius in the general population, it is not a great concern here. It may also be that a third person perspective within a practice is deemed sufficient despite of in-group bias. This it does call for skepticism about traits in general, and I will return to this matter in Chapter V. 53 Hugo Ortega-Lopez brought my attention to how Modiglianiâs relationship with Picasso is a telling example here (personal communication, February 15, 2006). Modigliani persisted making paintings despite widely held doubt (but not his own) that his genius was inferior to Picassoâs. We cannot know exactly why he persisted to produce art in spite of the lack of support from the art community, but his artwork is testament to his own conviction of the importance of his work. We should not be surprised then, if, just as Modigliani had surmised, Picassoâs last spoken word was âModigliani.â To achieve the recognition that he was indeed the greater artist, did Modigliani simply have to be immune to external recognition? Could Picasso not doubt such a strong conviction? Perhaps he felt the abundance of external recognition he received somewhat disqualified his own status as a genius compared to Modiglianiâs less recognized but similarly productive behavior. This is only 123 Psychologists push back skepticism about traits by appealing to the utility of observations, and they talk about traits in everyday life. Thus, the tentative and pragmatic nature of traitology allows for theorizing about traits. Even if a persistent, shared, and identifiable aspect of personality eventually showed itself to be temporary or situational, attribution theory helps us understand the changing nature of traits. But the matter of biases and the discussion of strategies for rightly identifying traits only offers indirect clues as to whether genius is or is not a trait or set of traits. Insights from psychological research have been merely propaedeutic to a reconceptualization of genius, steering philosophy through some of the difficulties of morality. 3.1 Genius as a Trait If genius were a trait, repeat observations and corroboration about those observations would be a reasonable basis for judgment, but a vicious circle should still be avoided. It is all too easy to follow folk psychology into an endless cycle of observation and definition, without controlling for the attribution biases described above. A sensible conclusion is to trust third person observations of genius, but to withhold judgment about whether the trait is recurrent, and therefore a persistent aspect of personality. We do not also want to suppose a direct correlation between the frequency of oneâs artistic production and genius, or suggest that repetition is essential speculation. But it does suggest the power of recognition is not unappreciated by artists, and also 124 to genius. 54 On the other hand, the matter of unrealized traits potentially defies traitology, for psychologists have no choice but to be silent about the status of unobservable phenomena. One purpose of the reconceptualization of genius within a morla framework is to agree on what counts as the deep-seated nature of genius. Two main premises of this study are thus: 1) there exist measures of human aptitude in art practice such that certain individuals excel when others do not, and 2) folk psychology contributes to the recognition of certain artists as exceptional and, potentially (though not always uncontroversially), as geniuses. Traitology and its implications set us on course to better explain genius on many levels. And while there are numerous ways to approach (and analyze) excellence in art practices (as well as analyze the meaning of artistic excellence in light of other practices and social structures), the adoption of the framework suggested aboveâa third person perspective moderated by a weak view of intrapersonal attributionânarrows the focus of moral philosophy. Indeed, it may be that once the biases of attribution are controlled for, there is nothing left to explainâgenius may simply not be a substantive aspect of that the fate (and horror) of genius being overlooked (by a community) is real. 54 See Albert (1983), especially Chapter 1, for an overview of how psychologists are (or have been) committed to the project of measuring genius alongside eminence with quantitative instruments. Since there is a strong identification of geniuses as people who have been widely perceived as geniuses, the sample for determining the IQs of geniuses and eminent individuals is both warranted and suspect. I believe the correlation between âcreative productivityâ and high IQs is better understood only as eminence. I worry that considering genius as such would treat tradition as too âthin.â Tradition is more complex, and this may lead to philosophical confusion about the role of either coming to an agreement or the traditionary events as overarching aims of ethics. In fact, these are only two goals among many, and they are not the only goals in service of inquiry. I will discuss tradition at length in Chapter VI, Section 2. 125 personality. Chapter V turns to the matter of education in practices in general with this possibility in view. Considering the drawbacks of a study about focusing on the importance of a misunderstood or misleading concept, perhaps it is best to remain skeptical about genius as a trait. At some point, a student of art chooses whether to take art seriously as a vocation, to make art âon the side,â or not at all. It is possible, however, to appreciate the nuances of artistsâ lives without understanding what choosing art making as a way of life involves, and, on this view, the point of conceptualizing genius as a trait is to better understand this part of our social landscape. As an undergraduate, it was not the case that I wanted to be an artistic genius. I wanted foresight about whether to make art practice a greater or lesser part of my life. There is philosophic work left to be done to explain how a trait such as genius relates to art practice, such as 1) looking closely at traits as a source of excellence, and 2) looking at excellence anew from the perspective of art education. To relocate the concept away from its roots in folk psychology, the first step will be locating a salient aspect of art practice with the historical concept of genius in mind. To that end, Chapters V and VI focus on subordination as a particular and narrow aspect of art practice that, while not the only important aspect, concieves of artistic production from a hermeneutic point of view. 126 4. Conclusion Traitology has several implications for a critique of genius. It offers a way to a parse third person views of genius from first person experience; it reveals how perceptions of morality may change dependant upon oneâs perspective; and it shows that genius may be theorized as one aspect of personality because of a predisposition to summarize othersâ behaviors. Accordingly, there is no reason to think that genius, like other traits, is any less ârealâ than other features of the human world. This suggests a way ahead. We could restrict considerations about genius to recurrent cognitive phenomena that are likely to lead to attributions from the third person perspective. This is, in effect, what psychologists do (Eysenck, 1995). Adopting this perspective means that our interest in first person experience will be minimalâbut related to specific aspects of art practice. Turning to first person experience, however, allows us to remaining skeptical about traitology while privileging the perspective of artists. In effect, psychology sharpens conjecture about the relation between personality and typology, while the issue of luck still looms large. Insofar as we want to understand underlying patterns of behavior that lead to the recognition of genius, we have to theorize much more slowly. As I suggested in Chapter II, MacIntyreâs theory discloses an aspect of practice that plays a central role in the achievement of excellence in practices: subordination. In the next chapter, I argue that subordination is a key 127 concept in moral theory cum educational theory, and as such, it lends itself to a powerful explanation of genius. 128 VâACHIEVEMENT OF SUBORDINATION 1. Excellence in Practices If genius is seen as a trait, the social world is a more complex space for artists to navigate. Philosophers, artists, and everyone else who enters into dialogues about art are confronted with summarizing descriptions of artists that inform encounters with art and artists. As a result, psychologists are more likely to take seriously claims about genius that arise in this socially-negotiated manner than, for example, claims by artists about themselves. But discussion about genius is likely to bear out speculation about development and growth, and here the artist may be at an advantage, for it is she who may be most familiar with the complexities of art practice. And though we may be suspicious of an artistâs view of herself (due to the biases of the first person perspective), artistsâ views of each other may deserve a special status when compared to âoutsidersââ observations. An artistâs perspective differs somewhat from an outsiderâs perspective. A notable feature of the artistâs perspective is that it cannot be said to exist prior to a practice of art makingâit is coextensive with it. While third person perspectives could 129 be understood as locating and describing artistic experience, views of artistic excellence that arise from observation alone, and not âhands-onâ experience, are likely to vary according to a particular point of view. A political theorist or activist, for example, might be inclined to judge artistic excellence according to the political value of an artwork. Artists, we may conclude, are a more reliable source for determining artistic excellence because their judgment is grounded in artistic experience. Yet this begs the question of what should be understood as a valid rubric for excellenceâmany interests can be understood as competing for justification. How justification is thought to proceed may hinge upon whether excellence may be understood to reside in artists, or it may be understood to reside in works of art. In the first case, an artist could be rightfully called a genius were she to be known to have good intentions. The latter case could go as follows: if the public reception of a work of art were to be said to matter for the determination of how âgoodâ it is, and the recognition of genius is dependant upon art being deemed good, then the excellence of an artist is essentially contingent upon the reception of her work. Art criticism oscillates between these two poles, and debates in aesthetics often hinge on where critics fall along this spectrum. Essentially, this is an interminable debate from a theoretical point of view. To say that we are interested in genius from a âmoral perspectiveâ means we come down on the side that privileges the experience of artists, if only provisionallyâ provisional because a relation to artworks plays an important role in oneâs identification as an artist, but there is a point beyond which it no longer makes sense to demand this correlation. That is, there exists a class of objects that count as artworks, and we 130 rightfully refer to it when we identify artists, but what counts as art is not always clear. Since individual cases are determined dialogically, and disputes are expected, it should not worry us if this class can be defined only vaguely. This is a reasonable determining ground for a socially constructed identity, and discussions about artistic excellence can commence. We should not be surprised, however, that the problem of choosing a rubric for excellence persists. It is a problem that will not be fully resolved here, as excellence may come in as many forms as there are differences of opinion about the purpose or meaning of art. But this does not mean moral theorizingâor morality itselfâhas run aground. Artistic excellence, seen from a moral perspective, is about an artistâs whole lifeâmeaning not that everything is equally important, but that how and in what way oneâs life coheres as an artist is in view. Here, the primacy of art practice is apparent, and philosophy can be seen as providing a framework for comparing more or less excellent artists. Unfortunately for philosophy, the notion of âpracticeâ arrives on the scene with no ready-made boundary between an artistâs work and other aspects of her life. The quality and reception of oneâs artworks are only one part of an artistâs practiceâdepending on his or her goals, an artist may achieve different kinds of success. Artists may choose to 1) create more or less art, 2) make their art more or less public, 3) work with other artists, and so on. Artists may also strive to become better. This is the special case of âimprovementâ that intersects with the matter of educationâ indeed it is the matter of art education. Yet, perhaps my experience of art education (see Chapter II) is indicative of the theoretical difficulty surrounding the matter of what 131 counts as improvement. Art practices are multifaceted, and this leads to irreducible complexity for the matter of education. Answers in the form of, âX counts as improvementâ are always unsatisfying in two ways. Because a dialogue about X needs to occur within a practice in order for it to be true of the practice (this is implied by the discussion above about what âcountsâ as art), a claim will always be contingent upon the perspective of artists who deem X to be important in the first place. And even if there is such a dialogue, it cannot be considered to be settled once and for all, so the significance of choosing X is diminished. This problemâthat the meaning of excellence is socially determinedâis a problem for moral philosophy, and this comes as no surprise. Moral philosophies attempt to render human action according to a conception of goodnessâwhether that good is Aristotleâs telos or Millâs utilitarianism, an argument is put forth (or an assumption is made) that there is an underlying structure or order according to which human action is intelligible as more or less excellent. MacIntyreâs philosophy unfolds along these lines. His conception of moral life as three âregistersâ of experienceâ practices, narrative quests, and moral traditionsâis one solution to the problem of excellence in art as socially determined. It is almost enough. The story of virtue emerging âon the groundâ in practices makes room for diverse kinds of excellence that constitute morality, and is even unshaken by charges of relativism (âWhy these practices? Why this good?). Even MacIntyre is ultimately confounded by the problem. Perhaps ironically (since he sets his own philosophy apart from othersâ on this point), 132 the ascendance of virtue toward final âhistoricalâ ends loom in the background of his philosophy. He says, for example: Why begin from practices? Other moral philosophers after all have begun from a consideration of passions or desires or from the elucidation of some conception of duty or goodness. In either case the discussion is all too apt to be governed from then on by some version of the means-end distinction according to which all human activities are either conducted as means to already given or decided ends or are simply worthwhile in themselves or perhaps both. What this framework omits from view are those ongoing modes of human activity within which ends have to be discovered and rediscovered, and means devised to pursue them. (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 273) That even MacIntyreâs philosophy refers incessantly to âendsâ should give us pause. Is there such a thing as moral philosophy without an end or ends? Our answer depends upon our needs. Conceptions of genius that overdetermine artistic excellence are analogous to conceptions of moral philosophy that overdetermine human action. Underdetermination may be preferable, but neither will it suffice when overdetermination is âin the airââe.g., when art students peruse the art library. The knee-jerk reaction may be to leap to counter overdetermination with still more overdetermination, and with all his talk about rationality and rival traditions, MacIntyreâs philosophy must be seen as taking this route. The opposite may be unthinkable: quietism. This also fails to be a true response, for in philosophy a response should (and needs to) take the form of an argument. A measured version of underdetermination of excellence can be such a response, as it may convey an argument while steering clear of known fallacies and mere conjecture. In other words, we need to philosophize even more, and aim at understanding education in art practice. 133 Moral philosophers, whether they like it or not, may not be equipped to understand the different meanings of human action and its so-called ends. 1.1 Philosophy of Education The best alternative to moral philosophyâor perhaps the likeliest heir of the inheritance of moral philosophyâis philosophy of education (or âeducational theoryâ). I will not discuss its breadth or history here, but in short, the concerns once addressed by the abstract notions of ought are, in educational theory, superceded by studies of cognition, relationships, identity, and so on. Instead of being reduced to emotivismâ the doctrine that moral judgments are expressions of preferenceâphilosophers of education seek to explain some of the underlying structures that make expressions of preference (among other capacities) possible.55 Insofar as other philosophers and scientists also explain these structures, they too could be understood as philosophers of education, especially when they address âgrowthâ in the sense Dewey articulates (see Chapter II). Thus, MacIntyreâs theory of virtue can be partly read in this way. Subordination, theorized by MacIntyre (1984) as an essential experience for entering into a practice, causes judgments about excellence to arise in a systematic way 55 Emotivism is not interested in the intersection of an individualâs preferences and the surrounding social world. It is too atomistic in its conceptualization of morality, and too sympathetic to the charge of relativism that follows on the heels of the claim that the meaning of excellence is socially determined. For more on emotivism, see Stevenson (1945/1960). For more on why it fails, see MacIntyre (1984), especially Chapter 2. 134 (p. 188). Expanding his account of subordination, therefore, is one way to read MacIntyre as a philosopher of education. Because of my interest in art, I will depart from MacIntyre by eschewing the vocabulary of âvirtue.â In addition to a theory of a âunity of the virtuesâ (a concept I will return to in Chapter VII), moral philosophers such as MacIntyre want to strengthen the perception that lives characterized by deep involvement in social practices are recognizably excellent. Virtue theory positions âvirtueâ as partially synonymous with âexcellence,â but renders it systematically according to a broader framework of âgoodness.â56 This larger story of ethics, however accurate it may or may not be, is supported by observations of social interactions. Like any adept interlocutor in ethics, or philosophy in general, MacIntyreâs views are viable even as critiques are leveled at his work. For this reason alone, the history of the concept notwithstanding, the idea of virtue still resonates. It is just this matter of unity, however, that Chapter IV recommends against. For while unity may be a reasonable aim from a personal perspective, it is an unwieldy theoretical notion, especially from a psychological perspective. Though the comparison between saints and geniuses commenced in Chapter I hinted at the importance of traits as summarizing apparatuses, and Part I outlines an examination of genius within a moral framework, traitology can be seen as a necessary side-constraint on moral theory. 56 The notion of a systematic framework arises in the form of a telosâan ultimate end or goal of existence. The sense of an âultimateâ end points to an ordering of goods, but it is not obvious how this may work out in a real context. Though the goal of âhappinessâ is often held up as an example of an ultimate end, application of this theory has proven difficult. In contrast to this top-down model, some virtue ethicists try to define our telos from the bottom-up. See, for example, Taylor (1989) for his theory of âhypergoodsâ as goods that trump other goods. 135 Attribution theory, discussed in Chapter IV, supports the hypothesis that genius is a trait or set of traits, but not a unity of virtues. The mistake will be to collapse the distinction between a âsetâ of traits and a âunityâ of virtues, but such a unity is just the kind of higher-order trait that attribution theory recommends against (by calling for a situation-sensitive lens on persons and personality).57 The mistake of imputing behavior to traits because details about a person are lacking should increase standards for behavioral evidence. Just as we dispense with summarizing trait apparatuses in first person reflection, so we should dispense with them from the third person when possible. Sets should give way to single traits as evidence is refined. Since the present inquiry into genius seeks a practice-specific and theoretically narrower understanding of genius, it should not be surprising that we suspend the possibility of genius as a set of traits. Genius may elsewhere be defined as a set of traits, but this is effectively what my inquiry sets out to avoid within the given theoretical and autobiographical framework. Therefore, if a future theory of genius requires one or more additional traits be added to my specification, then it can be understood as competing with a hermeneutic theory of genius in two ways. 1) It would mean that genius is not a single trait, and 2) it muddies the identification of the greatest single predictor of artistic excellence. My philosophical interest in education is therefore an additional side-constraint on my analysis of genius, as it means I am seeking a behavior 57 Ethicists will recognize the similarity between âsituational understandingâ and the Aristotelian notion of âpractical wisdom.â It is an Aristotelian emphasis on wisdom, however, that traitology warns against. 136 that explains the emergence of artistic excellence. I am positing a normative ethics in an inquiry restricted by my interest in art educationâespecially its formative and social aspects as described by Dewey. I am not rejecting other normative ethics so much as privileging the perspective of art education (e.g., understanding Gauguinâs development as an artist is more interesting than understanding his development as a husband or father). Traitology helps to frame genius alongside education and development, but psychology, social psychology, cognitive psychology, and other experiment-based research do not offer a comprehensive framework from which to displace educational philosophy and other philosophical discourses. (I am not primarily interested, for example, in genius as a pattern of firing neurons or a hegemony of practitioners. I am interested in genius as a way of life.) Thus, we have to philosophize for art education in a new vernacularâone that both deploys and challenges existing moral philosophy. The remaining chapters arrive at a view of artistic genius as excellence in art practice. To describe the moral landscape of art education, and differently than it is elsewhere and otherwise represented by ethics (and aesthetics), I argue that moral excellence in art practice is contingent upon subordination. 137 2. The Value of Educational Goods 2.1 MacIntyreâs View of Subordination If the first person account of genius is evinced by the claim âI am a genius,â and the third person account is captured by the claim âhe is a genius,â then the claim âyou are a geniusâ represents a different perspectiveâthat of the âsecond person.â This perspective shows up in situations where one artist trusts the judgment of another artist. Such convictions have been historically understood as a constitutive aspect of education, apprenticeship, subordination, and so on. Here, I use the term âsubordinationâ to invoke MacIntyreâs concept of a practice. The assertion that such behavior also implies domination, oppression, servitude, slavery, and the like should be suspended on the grounds that, in some sense, nothing worthy of the name of trust is ever really granted. 58 Subordination emerges from MacIntyreâs (1984) story of virtue (p. 188). Virtue is not only valued in practices, he argues, but it is at least partially cultivated in practices as well. For MacIntyre, practices are essentially good, and as I briefly discussed in Chapter II, this valuation must be understood as a weaker kind of good than can be 58 With the term subordination, I read MacIntyre as being concerned with trust in interpersonal relationships, and not power per se. The dialectic of power potentially adds an interesting layer of interpretation, but not one I will pursue here. 138 sought elsewhere (Porter, 2003, p. 41), as he imagines a âlogical development of virtueâ that builds on the experience of excellence in practices. He points to subordination and âexposureâ as two features of behavior that coincide with the âachievementâ of the intrinsic good of practices (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 188). I take him to mean that exposure and subordination help to explain the development of excellence in practices. For example, he links subordination to practices in the following way: [The practiceâs] goods can only be achieved by subordinating ourselves within the practice in our relationship to other practitioners. We have to learn to recognize what is due to whom; we have to be prepared to take whatever selfendangering risks are demanded along the way; and we have to listen carefully to what we are told about our own inadequacies and to reply with the same carefulness for the facts. (p. 191) This is an instrumental depiction of subordination toward the end of achieving âgoods.â To better understand the process of striving for virtue entailed by this, we have to consider MacIntyreâs step-by-step account of virtue that begins with the achievement of goods in practices. I will turn to this account in the following section. I will also show that MacIntyre does not fully articulate the process by which a person becomes a more excellent practitioner. Exposure and subordination remain only tantalizing clues that may serve as a MacIntyrian philosophy of education. Thus, though only clarifying MacIntyreâs account of the âearlyâ manifestation of virtue, a closer look at exposure and subordination may help us reconsider genius as a matter of moral excellence. 139 2.2 The Development of Excellence In MacIntyreâs estimation, the discussion of the development of excellence begins with the notion of exposure. Increasing oneâs exposure to a practice, he argues, is the most basic strategy for becoming a practitioner. The basic formula here is something like this: the more one is exposed to a practice, the more likely one will be able to recognize the excellence of products as measured against historical standards (e.g., becoming a fan of baseball may lead to deeper involvement in the game). Exposure establishes necessary foundational experiences for achieving excellence, but common sense tells us it is an insufficient condition for becoming an excellent practitioner. Practitioners must be more than observers. MacIntyreâs intuition that âevery practice requires a certain kind of relationship between those who participate in itâ (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 191), leads to his claim that subordination is a necessary step in the process of entering into a practice. Explaining the role of subordination, MacIntyre says, A practice involves standards of excellence and obedience to rules as well as the achievement of goods. To enter into a practice is to accept the authority of those standards and the inadequacy of my own performance as judged by them. It is to subject my own attitudes, choices, preferences, and tastes to the standards which currently and partially define the practice. (p. 190) Essential to this definition is the fact that one cannot become expert in a practice if one does not engage it as a shared, social project. This nominally means a practitioner must have qualities essential to any cooperative activity (Porter, 2003, p. 41), and MacIntyre suggests that the virtues of justice, courage, and honesty are necessary components of 140 practices (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 191). The discussion of goods that follows somewhat obscures the matters of exposure and subordination. MacIntyre claims a practiceâs internal goods âcan only be achieved by subordinating ourselves within the practice in our relationship to other practitionersâ (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 191). I understand him to equate âthe achievementâ of these goods with their attainment or appreciation of these same goods. But this has already been shown to be a somewhat unsatisfactory description. It seems, for example, that there are multiple kinds of internal goods, some of which may be easier and harder to appreciate, attain, or achieve. Confusion arises when one takes seriously MacIntyreâs claim that someone who lacks necessary virtuous qualities cannot experience the âinternal goodsâ of a practice (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 191). What are these virtuous qualities? How does one âacquireâ them when these goods are necessary to the allotment of value (of a practice) in the first place? MacIntyre appears to beg the question of how excellence in practices is only partially constituent of virtue. For Aristotle, whose philosophical insights guide MacIntyre in this area, reflection on virtues is held together by a core conception of virtue (Porter, 2003, p. 40). It is unclear to what extent Aristotleâs âvirtueâ is synonymous with a modern conception of excellence, and MacIntyre makes the matter somewhat more difficult when he rejects some of Aristotleâs metaphysics with his adoption of Thomism. Nevertheless, he pursues this âfirst stepâ of the definition of virtue by developing a notion of excellence in practices. 141 To make sense of excellence, MacIntyre quickly moves from a discussion of what defines a practice to a discussion of âgoodsâ that are internal to practicesâwhat he calls âinternal goods.â 59 This minimal treatment of human development is not surprising given the breadth of the After Virtue project. Indeed, he seems to go down this path to make better sense of individualsâ varying understanding of practices. Positing a plurality of goods pays respect to local experience and individualsâ differences, but also diverse practices. The specificity of these goods is highly dependent on their articulation, and they can only be specified in terms of a particular practice. For example, MacIntyre says of chess playing that internal goods may be âthe achievement of a certain highly particular kind of skill, strategic imagination, and competitive intensityâ (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 188). But in what sense is there a plurality of goods? How did we ever get from the good to the goods? The example is given of a young chess player who is lured into the practice with external goodsârewards that are independent of the game, as âtheir achievement is never to be had only by engaging in some particular kind of practiceâ (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 188)[emphasis in the original]. The difference between internal and external goods has been contested somewhat in literature surrounding MacIntyreâs theory of practices (notably in literature pertaining to education), and the outcome is that we cannot rule out some overlap. I will return to this matter below. Presently, it is enough to 59 MacIntyre has elaborated somewhat on the definition of a practice, but remains content with a definition that is vague and suits his particular ideological whims. For more on this matter, see the special issue of The Journal of Philosophy and Education, 37(2) on MacIntyreâs contributions to educational theory. 142 recognize that a conception of goods qua good is the most expansive description of how excellence is recognizable in practices. Partly due to their instrumental value in practices, goods stand out as special aspects of experience. But it is not always clear what may be counted as a good. Goods are thought to provide a practitioner with a conception of the good that is intrinsic and not merely instrumental to the experience of virtue (Porter, 2003, p. 41), but their instrumental value cannot be overlooked if we are to appreciate the social nature of practices. How fine-grained can we be about the difference between instrumental goods and intrinsic goods? This discussion of goods quickly becomes confusing. 2.3 Two Kinds of Goods On MacIntyreâs account, there are two kinds (varieties) of internal goods, neither of which is described as particularly instrumental to the achievement of excellence. The first kind of good is the âexcellence of the products,â including (for example) practitionersâ performances, and this excellence âhas to be understood historicallyâ (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 189). The discussion of the achievement of the second internal goodââthe pursuit of excellenceâ (p. 190)âas the good of a certain way of life is more problematic. To be sure, living a greater or lesser part of life as a painter (for example) seems to be a good according to a narrative quest, and this involves the development of virtue outside of practices alone. This kind of good, 143 therefore, seems to be a shortcut that anticipates the difficulty of characterizing individualsâ diverse experiences of practices. The second kind of good presents additional difficulties. Even more than the obvious problems of trying to measure or account for how particular variables influence excellence (which is already disputed in a broad body of educational research), it is not clear what âexcellenceâ should be taken to mean. Even for scholars who are thoroughly immersed in the Aristotelian tradition that MacIntyre represents, the work of judging an individual case of excellence presents challenges to the whole enterprise of valuing excellence.60 The depth and quality of oneâs involvement in a practice seems to be the result of a confluence of circumstances and opinions. Thus, MacIntyreâs theory, as a theory of education, seems to trade on the assumption that a personâs experience of excellence (the first person experience) will âfitâ well with a common understanding of excellence (a view held by a community). Lacking a more elegant name for this assumption, I will call it an internal-external correlation. For example, if I am a good fisherman by most standardsâI can tie my line up nicely, navigate marine topography well, and cast smoothlyâyet I catch no fish, it can 60 Aristotle (2000), with his view of phronesis, claims that a cases warrant examination in light of particular contexts, but what exactly is constitutive of a context is an open question. For example, we may want to acknowledge a studentâs drawing as excellent, but until we know him or her well, we will have a hard time discerning whether or not any single work is really worthy of merit. It is then a slippery slope to the point where we want to know each studentâs entire life story, which may indeed be important for arriving at sound judgments. Similarly, we can understand the problem of context with respect to multiple and overlapping spheres of life. A technically bad drawing may be a great psychological achievement. 144 rightfully be called a matter of luck.61 When I do catch fish, their strength and size will be a âjustâ measure of my ability, and other fishermen will rightfully see the truth in both cases. This internal-external correlation can be said to work well in cases where the excellence of a practice is judged by simple standards, or notions of excellence are tied to easily identifiable external goods. But standards are not always so obvious or similarly agreed-upon. In the case of an art practice, about which tastes can change, judgments about the value of internal goods can be made more âsubjectively,â and where the would-be external goods have historically been subject to sharply limited production, the internal-external correlation can break down. A result of this complexity may be that the matter of âbadâ luck can be exacerbated. This may not be an important problem in cases where the individual is indifferent to outsiderâs perceptions. But in cases where an evaluative community is desirable, and it is fragmented or simply does not pass judgment, MacIntyreâs theory is not yet sophisticated enough to explain how a good practitioner becomes better. Thus, arriving at some clarity about educational goods leads back to MacIntyreâs convincing but elusive practice-community equation. This âethicsâ needed to be better articulated, for no other reason than in the defense of artists whose livelihoods depend on fair or consistent judgments. This is not a trivial matter, and not only a matter that only pertains to practicing artists. For example, how artists are perceived is a perennial footnote in the 61 Fishing is one of MacIntyreâs favorite examples. I deploy it in his honor, but also to maintain a 145 national debate over mandated curriculums and public school funding. Art is treated as a non-essential, extracurricular, and, tragically, often unnecessary part of schooling. As students of this system grow older, a âtrickle-upâ effect changes the way colleges and universities support the arts (and there is certainly a top-down effect in place too). âToo much talkâ about art may indeed be a bad thing for the artworld, but for the purpose of social change, artists need to secure autonomy as a community and deliver a confident opinion on the experiential, developmental, and intellectual importance of art making. On whether or not society is so constituted so as to make spending resources on art education in public schools defensible against arguments from the âbottom line,â one can only remain hopeful. 3. Education Without Virtue 3.1 Teachers and Students If excellence is contingent upon both the quality of oneâs exposure to a practice and the quality of oneâs subordination to other practitioners, then these are essentially an additional kind of good. They are not either of the two kinds of goods MacIntyre modicum of continuity with his perspective. 146 proposes exist in practices, and it is difficult to see how they would count as goods according to the intuition that a good is phenomenologically goodâthat the experience of the good feels like âhuman flourishing.â That is, goods need to be ends in themselves, and neither exposure nor subordination meets this qualification in practices such as arts, sports, or sciences. There is, however, another possibility. Education itself could be understood as a practice with its own conception of ends and moral phenomenology. MacIntyre has been resistant to such a claim even though many of his critics decry his conviction.62 The most common objection to his denial that education is a practice is based on the fact that there are institutions whose primary purpose is education. The notion that education is about specialized habits of mind is not new, and educational research about âcritical thinkingâ points to habits that are dissociated from specific practices. There are also the facts that teaching is a specialized profession and the title of âstudentâ is bestowed without regard to a specific practice. But perhaps these are shallow objections. MacIntyre has something more in mindâthat his denial of the practice of education is staunchly theoretical, or even ideological. As a theoretical claim, it could be motivated by the intuition that, as a practice, education is missing something important. It could also be motivated by the thought that education is essential, in 62 See, for example, the special issue of The Journal of Philosophy of Education (Vol. 37, No. 2, 2003) on MacIntyre and education. See also, Ibid. ( Vol. 35, No. 1, 2002) for Joseph Dunneâs interview with MacIntyre (pp. v-19). 147 some form or other, to all practices. This would bestow on education the status of being something like a meta-practice, and MacIntyre seems unwilling (at the moment) to entertain such possibilities. There is also the possibility that MacIntyre does not wish to grant education status as a practice because he believes it is a mistake to do so. This would put it in a group with other practices, such as evil ones, that MacIntyre does not discuss. This would be a much harder argument to make, as it most certainly relies on judgments that are external to practices in themselvesâit requires an already broader vision of good. Confusion arises in the debate about whether or not teaching is a practice when the practical routines of schooling are not carefully considered apart from the broader âmoral association in which all human agents are engaged by virtue of social membershipâ (Carr, 2003, p. 266). We need a better distinction between two senses of teaching. Carr agrees with MacIntyre that teaching is not a practice according to this view of teaching and education as fundamentally moral activities. In this way, he very clearly argues that what makes someone a good teacher is not the âspecialized professional trainingâ that serve the specific social, economic, and bureaucratic ends of schooling, but the very same qualities that make the teacher a good person. I am partly sympathetic to MacIntyreâs view that anything so fundamental to social life cannot be a constituent to the definition of a practice, but I am not convinced the counter-argument could not be more deeply respectful of the complexities of schooling. The move to parse the differences between the work of schooling and educative behavior does not hold up against the simple fact of the widespread 148 recognition of teaching in schools as a practice. Here, we follow MacIntyre who, despite his controversial remarks to the contrary, simply does not lay the groundwork anywhere to disregard commonplace social agreement on such an issue. Carr, or MacIntyre himself, may disagree with the effectiveness of schooling, so instituted, but in my mind that cannot be grounds for disproving the claim that teaching is a practice. Playing baseball may not make me a better fisherman, but it may be worthwhile for its own sake. Carr agrees, as he is particularly interested in the value of teaching for âthe promotion of a love of knowledge, truth and virtue for its own sakeâ [his emphasis] (Carr, 2003, p. 264). Perhaps he has just drawn the net too close, for while teaching may include these goods, it may include others as well. What makes Carrâs argument appear tight is his insistence upon a conveniently simplistic notion of the âmoral self-transformationâ he proposes as a definition of education (Carr, 2003, p. 265). Here again I have to defer to MacIntyreâs insight into the role of practices in moral life to contradict his own claim that teaching is not a practice. It is true that teaching is, in some sense, necessary to all practices, but this kind of teaching is not to be confused with a systematic institutional project of exposing children to a set of practices. MacIntyre acknowledges the importance of exposure in the event of becoming a practitioner, and this suffices as a deepening of Carrâs abstract notions of knowledge, truth and virtue so as to be a virtue-ethicistâs rebuttal. Maybe this is where Carr splits his differences with MacIntyre and maintains his hope that there may be universally recognizable knowledge, truth, and virtue. From such a perspective schooling could indeed be seen as a peculiar task where the managerial skills of 149 classroom teaching can be seen as wholly separate from the quality of a teacherâs character that really motivates education. This view contrasts with MacIntyreâs emphasis on practices as the origin of morality. It is a teacherâs ability to perform in the whole capacity of a purveyor of a practice (even an activity that is rumored to be part of a practice) that can be said to be the essential characteristic of the practice of teaching, regardless of other applications of these criteria. Carrâs poorly articulated challenge to teachersâthat just because a task is not theoretical or technical does not necessarily make it easyâmisses the point. Teaching is technical and theoretical when construed in this quite different way than only âmoral relations in which positive self-transformation is presupposed to improvement of othersâ (Carr, 2003, p. 266). We should acknowledge that exposure and subordination do not qualify as goods within a practice to which they grant a practitioner access. But they do make the achievement of other goods possible, so they share some definitional ground with virtue that is thought to coincide with the intrinsic good of practices. It invites additional confusion, however, to call this âvirtueâ (as MacIntyre does). It is something more like what Dewey called a âhabit of mindââa disposition that readies one for experience. Sadly, this begs the question of what counts as virtue. In a sense, a more robust definition is suspended until the matters of the narrative order of a single human life and moral traditions have been explored. This may or may not lead to a different understanding of virtue. 150 3.2 The Practice of Education One solution is to grant education the status of a practice regardless of the paradox that follows. For it would appear that one must be a practitioner in educationâ a studentâbefore one has access to other practices. Indeed, problems arise. For example, this conflicts with the fact that sometimes poor students are excellent practitioners, and vice versa. But I propose understanding oneâs excellence as a student as leading to a different (and specific) kind of success in other practicesâthe ability to enter into practices with ease (but not necessarily access that directly and automatically leads to excellence). It amounts to having certain habits of mind.63 It is not only the ability to enter into a practice, but the process of sustaining a relationship to a practice that teaching makes possible. Analogous to MacIntyreâs concept of internal goods in practices, I will therefore call exposure and subordination âeducational goods.â It is not yet clear, however, to what degree these goods lead to the possibility of excellence in other practices. One possible outcome is that while they lead to the achievement of other goods, they do not contribute to the achievement of excellence. On this outcome, MacIntyreâs worry about teaching being understood as a practice seems right. For what good, we might ask, does it do us to be excellent at the practice of education without ever 63 The observation that certain habits of mind coincide with flourishing was made by Aristotle, who conceived of âintellectual virtuesâ such as practical wisdom and judgment (Aristotle, 2000, pp. 103115). 151 achieving excellence in any other practice? On the other hand, recognizing education as a practice has several consequences. 1) The moral philosopher can give a better explanation of how internal goods are recognized. 2) Some virtues, like patience, will seem more like internal goods. 3) The notion of a unity of virtues (especially intellectual ones) is not needed to explain the achievement of internal goods. 4) The matter of a narrative order of a single human life (a narrative quest) can be understood in relation to the practice of education. 5) âMoralityâ can be understood along the lines of access to practices. And 6), âTraditionâ can be understood apart from morality. Each of these outcomes will now be considered in more detail. (1) MacIntyreâs argument that excellence leads to the perception of internal goods, and vice versa, begs the question of what is meant by âexcellence.â A more elegant explanation of excellence in practices may be given by considering the prolonged experience of internal goods as well as educational goods. The fact that internal goods are as individualistic as practitionerâs experiences should not deter moral philosophers from recognizing that hierarchies of excellence in practices are similar across practices. While this observation that may lead to the notion that virtues exists above (or between) practices, a simpler claim is that these so-called virtues are internal goods of education. MacIntyre (1984) tentatively agrees: A virtue is an acquired human quality the possession and exercise of which tends to enable us to achieve those goods which are internal to practices and the lack of which effectively prevents us from achieving any such goods. (p. 191) MacIntyre says this is only a tentative and partial definition of virtue, which leaves open the matter of how else virtue may be understood. This is a sign of an overburdened 152 concept. Does the lack of patience, for example, really mean a practitioner cannot achieve âany such goodsâ? A theory of education will be better off accounting for essential human qualities that allow for achievement. (2) That qualities often described as virtues are better understood alongside educational goods does not contradict the sense that they may otherwise be practicespecific. Courage in wartime is not the same as courage in public speaking, but there is a sense that both require a similar commitment to a practice. Once we acknowledge that these commitments follow from exposure and subordination, the notion that courage is part of a moral phenomenology of war is sensible enough. If what we mean when we refer to virtues are habits of mind, there may be no need to contrive a logical development of virtue apart from prolonged educational experience. That is, it should not be surprising that the combination of increased exposure and subordination over time leads to experience that other practitioners privilege when they seek out guidance and fellowship. (3) It follows from Flanaganâs (1991) critique of a âunity of virtuesâ from a psychological perspective that instead of making a positive (essentialist) argument about the achievement of excellence, we should prefer a minimal psychological account. The notion of exposure and subordination as educational goods is this kind of minimal account of the achievement of internal goods. According to this account, one simply does or does not have sufficient experience to become an excellent practitioner. Part of this experience is becoming a practitioner to which other practitioners choose to become subordinated. I will say more about this important point in the following 153 chapter, but for now it is enough to recognize that this will be where excellence gathers meaning. In other words, in this practice-based definition of excellence, the notion of unity gives way to the notion of community. (4) It is unclear why MacIntyre conceptualizes narrative quests as âlogically followingâ the development of virtue in practices. Perhaps he is addressing the âordering of goodsâ in a similar way as Taylor (1989) accomplishes with his concept of âhypergoods.â This defies psychological minimalism. As Flanagan (1991) shows, there is too much diversity in moral life to make hypotheses about overarching patterns of identity. But this does not preclude us from making hypotheses about underlying structures of identity formation. When MacIntyre argues for the importance of the narrative order of single human lives, he does so to suggest that virtue cannot be defined apart from the distinctiveness of human identities. To take this seriously means having to be skeptical about the notion of moral tradition, for it is too difficult to generalize across practices (not to mention the difficulty of generalizing across identities). A preferable alternative is to say that moralities develop alongside the experience of educational goods which are by and of involvement in practices with traditions. This is akin to Flanaganâs claim that there are moral personalities. (5) While the concept of morality may be superfluous within practices, it is still helpful as a term for the difficulties surrounding entering into practices. It captures the experience of education. Choosing between practices becomes a substantive dimension of morality, and determining ârightâ or âwrongâ action (that favored discourse of analytic philosophy) can be understood as a complex matter pertaining to 154 individuals and communities with ongoing commitments in multiple practices. To say that someone is morally excellent is to make a claim that he or she is well positioned and/or capable of achieving excellence in a practice. It is the same as claiming he or she is an excellent student or teacher. Precisely because of the overlapping nature of education (with other practices), it is often helpful to say both things. (6) MacIntyre includes the case of forward-thinking practitioners into the definition of a practice. He alludes to the âresult that human powers to achieve excellence, and human conceptions of the ends and goods involved, are systematically extendedâ (p. 187)[my emphasis]. Without the sense that human powers and conceptions are systematically extended, it would not be difficult to imagine that MacIntyre is referring to individualsâ growth. But the reference to a system brings about the image of practitioners carrying practices forward togetherâthis is also implied by his notion of a moral tradition. MacIntyre is often thought to be a Communitarian because of this emphasis on community as a foundation of moral principles, though he distances himself from this movement on the grounds that nation states should not be understood as communities (Murphy, 2003, p. 159). His emphasis is on practices. The nature of the systematic extension he has in mind is clear in the following claim: To enter into a practice is to enter into a relationship not only with its contemporary practitioners, but also with those who have preceded us in the practice to its present point. It is thus the achievement, and a fortiori the authority, of a tradition which I then confront and from which I have to learn. (p. 194) 155 The problem with this idea of forwardness, besides its speculative nature, is its sheer complexity. Who is capable of judging what counts as the forward direction? MacIntyre does not mean that forward-thinking practitioners merely extend tradition in time, but intentionally transform it according to their particular beliefs, values, desires, and so on. The notion of a distinctive moral tradition, therefore, is ambiguous given the diverse possibilities for morality. Disambiguating our understanding of morality will mean giving up the moral claim embedded in forwardness. We should claim, contrary to MacIntyre, that practices are systematically extended in the wake of the achievement of subordinationâthe development of âhuman powers to achieve excellenceâ and âhuman conceptions of the ends and goods involvedâ are the causes and the effects of this activity. Together, these six outcomes amount to a major reconceptualization of what is meant by âmoral nature.â To refer to moral nature is to adopt a philosophical perspective that allows us to compare the capacity of practitioners to experience internal goods, and therefore be rightfully judged as more or less excellent practitioners within a community. It may refer ultimately to a universal principle (or set of principles) that can be said to govern human behavior, but the complexity of such a claim would be immense. The term âvirtueâ is deemed problematic because it refers to just this kind of overarching good. In its place, we find a dialectic of education that generates its meaning in a practice where students and teachers strive to systematically extend the tradition of other practices. I have argued that there is nothing paradoxical about thisâthe world is replete with overlapping practices in 156 which practitioners stake their identities on vague and varied grounds. With an eye to this greater landscape of practices, MacIntyre makes the following observation: Commitment to sustaining the kind of community in which the virtues can flourish may be incompatible with the devotion which a particular practiceâof the arts, for exampleârequires. So there may be tensions between the claims of family life and those of the artsâthe problem that Gauguin solved or failed to solve by fleeing to Polynesia. (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 200) This strange notion of virtues flourishing (and not humans flourishing) is symptomatic of MacIntyreâs commitment to a vantage of social criticism. Like anyone, he has a particular notion of the goodâindeed, the good society. Strange though it may seem, this may fall outside the scope of ethics. The tension he describes is simply a fact of life. Since none of us can truly stand outside of tradition, we may have to settle for entering into debates about the good with only our diverse commitments at which we have arrived through our experience of practices. 4. Conclusion What makes some practitioners stand out as morally excellent is a specific kind of relationship they negotiate with other practitionersâthe achievement of subordination. Understanding subordination as central to education, and therefore central to moral life, is a major step toward adopting a provisional account of artistic genius as moral excellence. This chapter defines parameters by which achievement in a practice can be understood as moral excellence. Tradition is theorized as a set of 157 ongoing relations between practitioners, and subordination is shown to be the strategy by which practitioners maintain, uphold, and carry forward a shared understanding of excellence. There is, however, much left unsaid about the nature of subordination, and Chapter VI aims to better define subordination as an educational good. I turn to Gadamer to elaborate the artist as understander, and argue that a certain mode of subordination is an essential feature of artistic genius. 158 VIâHERMENEUTIC EXCELLENCE 1. Gadamerâs Philosophical Hermeneutics Attribution theory left us with a picture of the human inclination to make assertions about âpersonality,â understood as a bundle of habits, or traits. Summarizing behavior from a third person perspective was seen to have practical outcomes. For the present inquiry, it is notable that genius may indeed be a persistent (or âdeepâ) aspect of personality, but its social value is dependent upon its outward appearance. In determining what genius can be said to best refer, at least with regard to (and in the terms of) practices, I turned to MacIntyreâs view of excellence in practices. A framework was adopted for understanding excellence as a student as a key component of the achievement of excellence in practices. This kind of excellence is seen as a good contender for defining moral excellence, but it is also made up of constituent parts that require further definition. Exposure and subordination have been identified as important achievements (MacIntyreâs âgoodsâ) internal to the practice of education. To better understand excellence in education, these two goods may be further elaborated, and other internal goods may need to be identified (reflection, âcritical 159 thinking,â and other names for rigorous intellectual activity come to mind). By this I mean that, if we take exposure as the more basic of the two goods, then MacIntyreâs picture of subordination is lacking in some respects. Like other practices, there will be standards for excellence in education, and it is helpful to understand the causal relationship between a good and excellence. Although I have already argued that subordination partly describes what we ordinarily mean when we describe the excellence of students, this needs further elaboration. The concept of subordination draws our attention to moments of practice where one practitioner enters into a trusting relationship with another practitioner, but I want to draw out the most important features of this relationship to consider its meaning and implications for the concept of genius. Gadamerâs theory of understanding will be shown to further define subordination as an educational good, and vice versa. Truth and Method (Gadamer, 1960/2002), is a seminal work of hermeneutics in which Gadamer develops the philosophical study of interpretation and understandingâphilosophical hermeneuticsâas a universal theory that builds on other early twentieth-century insights in philosophy and science (such as psychology). This chapter seeks to use philosophical hermeneutics as an interpretive lens to describe an activity that most reliably leads to innovative (and, therefore, excellent) artistic products. Philosophical hermeneutics frames this activity as a process of understanding, interpreting, and experiencing traditionary events. 160 1.1 Artworks as Examples A recent art exhibition, War Images (Hughes, 2005), helps put forward the significance of Gadamerâs view of understanding by exploring the experience of traditionary events. Hung as a solo exhibition at the Macy Art Gallery at Teachers College, this show (my own) was partly intended an exploration of philosophical hermeneutics. I attempted to better understand how Picasso constructed the portrayal of emotion in his series of Weeping Women created during (and ostensibly about) the 1937 Spanish Civil War (see Figures 5-7 for a only a few examples from his larger body of work). I responded to his images, as well as my experience of viewing them, by creating a series of digital artworks that were printed on paper. I created a total of twelve pieces, several of which were multi-panel works. 161 Figure 5. Pablo Picasso, Weeping Woman, 1937. Figure 6. Pablo Picasso, Weeping Woman, 1937. 162 In War Images, seven framed works were digital âsketchesâ that represented Picassoâs original portraits with better accuracy than the other works in the show (Figure 8). I cropped these images in close approximation to the originals, and I manipulated them only slightly.64 The remaining larger works (paper sheets hung from clips in five arrangements) were the âexperimentalâ part of the show that represented the movement of my thoughts and interests in Picassoâs art, war, and so on. But to say these artworks represented my thoughts and interests is only partly true, and Gadamerâs philosophy helped me reconsider the complex process that took shape as I created and displayed these artworks. 64 Sometimes small âmovementsâ in Photoshop render a formerly iconic image unrecognizable. I will discuss the use of Photoshop further below in this section. 163 Figure 7. Pablo Picasso, Weeping Woman, 1937. Figure 8. Brian Hughes, Untitled (5 of 7), 2005. 164 Though working with digital files in Photoshop is relatively easy, the creation of images is complex. I set out to make the body of work that constituted the exhibition by downloading thumbnail-sized images of many of Picassoâs Weeping Women from Google Image Search. I played with the thumbnail imagesâdissected them, distorted them, and cropped them. I made several dozen copies of each image and developed a method that produced satisfying results with a few Photoshop tools and filters. One of Picassoâs more abstract and emotionally powerful pieces in this series, a monochrome drawing, was my first subject. The 21 images that came from this âoriginalâ constituted the largest mural-sized piece in the show, and are also the preparatory âdrawingsâ of this body of work. The sheer size of this piece, however, suggests it is the culmination of War Images. I hung them by clips in an overlapping row to create doubt about whether or not this piece was meant to be so understood (Figure 9).65 The secondlargest piece, another monochrome mural (Figure 10), was the second piece I made, and it was similarly hung. 65 This hanging method was the best way to fit these pieces on the wall from top to bottom, and aesthetically it worked to eliminate many of the clips from view while increasing the unevenness of the surface 165 Figure 9. Photograph from War Images (Hughes, 2005). Artwork: Brian Hughes, Untitled (21 Images), 2005. 166 Figure 10. Photograph from War Images (Hughes, 2005). Artworks: Brian Hughes, Untitled (9 Images), 2005 [left]. Brian Hughes, Untitled (6 of 7), 2005 [right]. These pieces contrasted with the more refined presentation and installation of three pieces created from color reproductions of Picassoâs paintings: one diptych and two polyptychs (each one composed of four panels). I made the polyptychs after the initial monochrome murals. I made the diptych next, and only after all of these large images found their place as the focus of my exhibition, did I turn my attention to the smaller Picasso-like images that I imagined serving as âkeysâ to the larger works by clearly referencing the âoriginalâ Picassoâa need which arose only after I saw how abstract the large pieces had become. For each larger, multi-panel piece, I created a 167 single 11â by 17â image. These smaller pieces turned out to be the most interesting part of the exhibition, and artists and critics who saw the exhibition noted this. 66 While I first made these pieces with the intention of preserving the reference to the specific Picasso work that was being manipulated for the larger piece, several of the smaller pieces became the intellectual culmination of my process (Figures 11-12). These pieces represent my interpretation and understanding of Picassoâs work, as well as my intention to communicate about the emotional experience of war. 66 One critic, Dan Kramarsky, found the smaller pieces to be the most serious âdrawingsâ (personal communication, February 5, 2005). Danâs wife, Janet Cohen, is an artist who specializes in conceptual drawing and his father is a serious collector of post-expressionist, minimalist drawings. Right away he gravitated to a few of the small pieces in the show that are very abstract. He enjoyed these because he could see my âhandâ in them better, and I knew what he meant even though my hand was mediated by layers of technology. His favorite piece was actually the culmination of this body of workâthe last piece I created (Figure 12). 168 Figure 11. Brian Hughes, Untitled (6 of 7), 2005. Figure 12. Brian Hughes, Untitled (7 of 7), 2005. 169 Gadamer offers a novel picture of how humans experience tradition as an event, and the artworks in War Images are partly meant to convey the manifold possibilities of such experiences. As I interpreted Picassoâs originals, I considered the meaning of the weeping woman whose portrait was depicted in a particular way by Picasso. I considered how she looks and what that means for how she feels; I considered the construction of the image; and I considered the effect of altering the image. In the following sections, I use the experience of working with Picassoâs Weeping Woman paintings as an example of the process of understanding. 2. The Nature of Understanding The study of interpretation and understanding is historically related to the study of biblical and legal texts. In the nineteenth century, scholars with an interest in historical understanding such as Schleiermacher and Dilthey in the German tradition expanded the discourse of hermeneutics to include general problems of interpretation and understanding in the work of historiography.67 The problem was: How do we know what really happened in the past if the only tools we have are historical documents and our modern conceptions of the world (and conclusions drawn from applications of 67 See Gadamer (2002) for the long version of this story. For more on the current status of the human sciences, see McDonald (1996). 170 these tools are found to be inconsistent)? The discipline of hermeneutics recommends methods for understanding historical eventsârecommendations that have since been applied to ânegotiating traditionâ in general. In the twentieth century, the problems of historiography were articulated even more abstractly. Philosophers such as Paul Ricouer, Hans-Georg Gadamer, and Jürgen Habermas connected these problems of historiography to philosophical thinking about epistemology. They asked questions such as: âHow does language limit our understanding of anything?â âAre there specifically human ways of understanding?â With the worries of hermeneutics, these philosophers complicated the age-old philosophical question, âWhat does it mean to know?â In Gadamerâs portrayal of âphilosophical hermeneutics,â art objects come alive as âtraditionary materialâ with a relationship to a practice, a life, and a language. Before we return to the matter of subordination, it will be worthwhile to explicate Gadamerâs view of understanding. A sustained philosophical look at the work of understanding privileges, if only for a moment, some aspects of art practice. Though texts are often the subjects of interpretation, for Gadamer the idea of a âtextâ is more loosely defined as a Heideggerian âthingâ (a familiar association for postmodernists), and works of art can be such things. Understanding, Gadamer will be shown to say, is a dialogue about a thing in a worldly context. His critique of the âradical subjectivizationâ of aesthetics is largely about the relationship between a thing and its context, as well as the philosophical misunderstanding of the nature (and significance) of dialogue. Turning to artworks as texts means dialogues inspired by and surrounding art should be treated 171 as nontrivial. Following Chapter V on MacIntyreâs view of subordination, this means we are particularly interested in what these dialogues mean for artists and art practice. Understanding, however, must be distinguished from other kinds of communication. It is not a special task, for example, if people are already in agreement with each other (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 180). Understanding means coming to an agreement about a thingâand this as a matter of truth. While it is plain enough that a certain amount of agreement is important to communities that engage in practices, the process of understanding is multifaceted and complexâit is quite another matter to see how agreement is essential to practices, and this is how the theory of subordination as an educational good will contribute to a hermeneutical model of education. 2.1 Subordination as Coming to an Agreement The notions of âexperiencing tradition as an eventâ and âthe process of understandingâ are intertwined. To complicate matters, both notions must be understood in terms of an agreement about a thing, as Gadamer emphasizes the âdialogical process where two positions or points of view find their way to agreement on one and the same particular reality or subject matterâ (Bubner, 1994, p. 69). To consider tradition or understanding as matters of agreement is to consider them from a relational perspectiveâa perspective which relates back to education. This is the first of three perspectives in this chapter which allow us to distinguish between more and less pronounced cases of subordination. 172 The matter of agreement is important because it emphasizes the social nature of practices. Artists, for example, are not likely to always (or immediately) agree about the truth of an artwork. The same can be said of artists and their audience. That is, the âfacts of lifeâ are often muddled in artistic representation. The work of coming to an agreement about a subject matter involves an âIâ and a âThouâ who reconcile different substantive experiences. This was the case, for example, when I appropriated Picassoâs imagery to make meaningful art about war and emotion that related to his work. Prior to interpretation, according to Gadamer, neither his artworks nor mine represent these subjects truthfully. It is only in and through artistic processes and the interpretation of artistic processes that Picasso and I arrive at an agreement. Understanding is bounded by a context. To understand a particular work of art, for example, one is ultimately limited by the horizon of oneâs experience and the horizon of the work of art. We look at art through living eyesâeyes which have seen the world in a particular way. A work of art, made by another person with different worldly experiences than our own, represents a different way of looking. It would not, however, be correct to say that the true meaning of the painting is wholly inaccessible to an audience by virtue of these differences. There are also many things that an artist and his or her audience have in common, and other knowledge of life that it would be difficult to classify other than to simple assert that it is part of human experience. It would be equally wrong-headed to assert, without qualification, that one understands the painting, for with a welcome serious-mindedness about art we would not want to reduce the painting to the mere sum total of the viewerâs previous 173 experience. âA work has the character of an event, which goes beyond the subjectivity both of the creator and the spectator or listenerâ (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 118). That is, there is a real chance, in front of the Weeping Woman, for a person to expand his understanding to include something of the world as it was in 1937 amidst the atrocities of the Spanish Civil War. Or, likewise, there is a chance, in front of Untitled (7 of 7), for a person to expand his understanding to include something of the world as it was in 2005 during the American invasion of Iraq. Balancing the immediate force of the âlanguagesâ one currently speaks (as a viewer) with the strangeness and visual presence of the painting (made by another artist) should be the goal for an observer interested in the meaning of Picassoâs work (i.e., with an interest in historical truth). In the process of coming to an agreement with Picasso about certain features of the world there is the possibility of both Picasso and his audience undergoing a transformation. That Picasso himself is no longer alive, and the notion of him changing lacks sense, there is nevertheless a sense in which his identity, along with a painting, undergoes a change after having been encountered by others. An art historian interested in the meaning of this painting, for example, would have to have some account of people like us taking an interest in it. 2.2 Subordination as a Path of Understanding The scenario of viewing an artwork is a relatively straightforward case of coming to an agreement when compared to educational scenariosâscenarios when 174 both the I and Thou are participants in a shared practice. To respond to the question I asked in Chapter IIââIn what way could exposure to my professorsâ practices have enhanced my education?ââwe have to turn to more complex cases. Educational scenarios involve the matter of how artists undergo processes of understanding while also creating works of art. When understanding is sustained over time, as it often is during the production of art, it is more difficult to describe as a Gadamerian hermeneuticist. Art making is a messy processânot only often materially, but often conceptually so. Indeed, many philosophical investigations in the twentieth century show the process of understanding to be varied and replete with idiosyncrasies and possibilities (Haste, 1996; Greene, 1995; Mink, 1987). In this section, the process of coming to an agreement will be subsumed under the matter of an artistâs experience of a âpath of understanding.â The basic argument remains: there is a kind of art making that involves coming to agreements with others. But the twists and turns made by artists change the content of such agreements. According to Gadamer, understanding takes the shape of a dialogue. The dialogue leads the interpreter onto a path of understanding which is defined as an ongoing movement between understanding âthe partsâ and âthe wholeâ of a thing. In so describing understanding with the metaphor of a path, Gadamerâs concern is for the possibility of truth in the human sciences after the âsubjectivization of aestheticsââhis name for the undesirable view of subjectivity that sees individualsâ aesthetic experiences 175 as totally isolated, and therefore, as yielding knowledge with no claim to truth.68 Aesthetic experience, on this view, is highly personal, and aesthetic knowledge is really no knowledge at all. To accept this view of human experience is tantamount to believing, in an epistemological sense, that everyone only experiences the landscape of his or her own island: I can tell my friend about the path through the woods and the vegetation on the far shore, but she can only imagine these details in comparison to the Martian topography of her own island. Human experience is imagined to be radically individualistic. In contrast to this unworldly aesthetics, Gadamer argues that we inhabit the same landscape. Our experience is our own only in the sense that we have a âbodiedâ perspective, but by traversing the same paths, encountering the same horizons, and anchoring our language to shared experience, we are able to map out the shared world. With a view to this alleged case, Dewey saw both the very essence of science and the possibility of educational relationships. He says, âthe map orders individual experiences, connecting them with one another irrespective of the local and temporal circumstances and accidents of their original discoveryâ (Dewey, 1990, p. 198), and that the map âputs the net product of past experience in the form which makes it most available for the futureâ (p. 199). Dewey strongly urges us to remember that it is the explorerâs notes from his or her daring, exploratory journey that makes map-making possible. 68 Gadamerâs concern if for universal truth, otherwise known as âtruth with a capital âT,ââ and not merely subjective and contingent truths. The difference between these two notions of truth is a persistent worry of contemporary philosophy. Nagel (1999) offers a sober view of the difficulty, but also the possibility, of universal truth through his work on objectivity. 176 Gadamerâs concept of the path of understanding renews the spirit of this metaphor. Philosophical hermeneutics shows us how we both use the map and live the life of the explorer at the same time. As the I, an artist may encounter the Weeping Woman as a depiction of a subject such as a certain kind of suffering. He is able to recognize this experience because it is a specific case of a broader, widespread human experience. As the Thou, the painting represents the suffering known to Picasso. A dialogue begins when the I and Thou are not in agreement about this subject. One aspect of Gadamerâs view is that there would be a common view of this particular kind of suffering were it not obscured by that which makes it present: language, or more specifically in this particular case, the tradition of painting. Tradition is the historical condition that is coextensive with the practice. Tradition allows us to expand our knowledge by âclosing a distanceâ (in this case, the distance of time and place between Picasso and myself) at the cost of possible misunderstandings. The occasion for entering into a dialogue about suffering is an event supervened upon by a tradition in which an I and Thou may eventually agree. This is what is meant when Gadamer says, â[subject matter] is the path and goal of mutual understandingâ (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 180). Insofar as tradition is receptive to the dialogue, a shared view of suffering becomes (to a greater or lesser degree) part of the true meaning of the painting. This only begins to describe, however, the scenario of the artist as viewer. Even as a viewer, the artist enters into a significant dialogue with another artist. This much is conveyed by the example of someone coming to an agreement with 177 Picasso about suffering. But the path of understanding, as a second perspective from which we can judge subordination, can be more circuitous than a single case of agreement. In this process of coming to an agreement, the subject of suffering will elicit questions about traditionâquestions which will not be equally interesting, or intelligible, to everyone. And not all questions will be equally important to understanding. The most interesting questions, from the perspective of art education, are often those that dwell on the relationship between the meaning of a subject (such as suffering) and a tradition of the arts (such as portrait painting). For the philosophical hermeneuticist, questioning is a behavior that tells us more about this relationship for an artist as a student of painting. The significance of questioning for Gadamer is related to his theory of the hermeneutic circle as the form of the process of understanding in âhistorical consciousness.â69 The circle is a metaphor that âdescribes understanding as the interplay of the movement of tradition and the movement of the interpreterâ (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 293). It is an idea that captures the dialogical relation between the parts and the whole as opposite poles on a spectrum of conceptualization. In the example of suffering, it is the difference between what suffering can mean and what a particular case adds to understanding. Neither a general concept nor the meaning of a particular case is independent of one another, and the circle reminds us of their 69 The notion of historical consciousness is central to hermeneutics. For more on historical consciousness as an explanatory framework for knowledge, see Gadamerâs (1960/2002) critique of Diltheyâs analysis of knowledge, especially pp. 231-242. 178 interrelationship during the process of understanding. It is not, however, a metaphor that makes sense of agreement (i.e., a shared experience); our circle is our own. Questioning is shaped this way because students arrive on the scene with a relationship to a tradition. Indeed, we have a relationship to many practices, and as artists, these relationships take the form of prejudices. â[An] initial meaning emerges only because he is reading the text with particular expectations in regard to a certain meaningâ (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 267). The concept of prejudice is precisely that which makes us expectant of and receptive to meaning. For Gadamer, a prejudice is a positive valence of personality. âThe meaning of âbelongingââi.e., the element of tradition in our historical-hermeneutical activityâis fulfilled in the commonality of fundamental, enabling prejudicesâ (p. 295). In this way, prejudices can both make one receptive to a thing and make oneâs reception of a thing unique. Gadamer shows that this is not a radically subjective uniqueness because each person has, in their own peculiar way, inherited their prejudices from tradition. Thus, when a thing addresses us, and we wish to understand tradition, we need to foreground our prejudices (p. 269). If a student is not conscious of his or her biases, he or she will not learn what a practice has to offer. The student will not share the experience of living as an artist within a community of practitioners. The act of posing questions is related to the suspension of oneâs prejudices. As Gadamer says âall suspension of judgments and hence, a fortiori, of prejudices, has the logical structure of a questionâ (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 299). In this way, the foregrounding of prejudices can lead to the suspension of judgment. To suspend oneâs 179 judgment opens a space for questioning. Whereas prejudices normally foreclose the process of understanding, questions embrace dialogue. Questions allow us to look more closely: âWhy does she look terrified?â âWhy is she painted in primary colors?â âIs that a tissue or veil of tears?â We look at the painting for questions, not answers. This enables a student to relate to an artist in the way that subordination requiresâhe or she can âget insideâ the mind of the artist and ask the questions that the artist may have asked. It is a first step toward meeting MacIntyreâs requirement that subordination involve a practitionerâs acceptance of the authority of standards of excellence within a practice. To apprehend a painting as a answer to a question is an essential condition for trusting that another artist has achieved excellence in painting. This will become clearer as the relationship between two artists is described as the substance of tradition in the following section. For now it is enough to see that subordination is made possible by questioning. Gadamer (1960/2002) says, âthe text must be understood as an answer to a real questionâ (p. 374), and by this he means that I discover something in the painting that makes a difference to me. This echoes Deweyâs Pragmatism as discussed as âart for oneâs selfâ in Chapter II. The example of War Images (Hughes, 2005) makes clear how questioning can lead an artist to a subject such as suffering a painting represents to him. Picassoâs suffering became the subject of my inquiry, and the generative source of the exhibition. For Gadamer, âthe most important thing is the question that the text puts to usâ (p. 373). This may be a question such as, âWhat does this painting of a weeping woman portray?â I confronted Picassoâs artworks and the ideas of sadness, 180 hysteria, grief, and suffering came to my mindâresponses that reflect how oneâs response is complicated by the form of painting (the tradition of which does not have only one weeping woman). The painting âspeaks to us from the pastâ (p. 374), poses this question to the viewer, and in response to the question the viewer can âattempt to reconstruct the question to which the traditionary text is the answerâ (p. 374). The viewer will remember weeping women he or she has seen, remember what it feels like to weep, and so on. These experiences are not Picassoâs, but his experience, his understanding, and his artistry inform them. In this way, we comprehend and develop a common question with Picasso. The potential of art as inquiry is circumscribed by this path of understanding in, around, and through works of art. A painting may contain many questions, however, and some are not recognizably our ownâunderstanding involves these questions too, and âthe fusion of horizonsâ is Gadamerâs name for the convergence of âhistoricalâ questions and our own. That is, a question allows us to ask, alongside a text, questions posed by a wider community. The question to which Weeping Woman is an answer for us encompasses Picassoâs experience as well as ours, and is a question for which artists seek the truth. âThe historical movement of human life consists in the fact that it is never absolutely bound to any one standpoint, and hence can never have a truly closed horizonâ (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 304). A viewerâa visitor to a museum, a researcher on the internet, or an artist in his studioâwill not have circumscribed tradition once and for all and achieved an âobjectiveâ understanding of suffering through this process of questioning, but the painting creates a shared 181 experience that is made possible by standards of inquiry and obedience to rules. 70 Subordination affords viewers access to this experience and allows artists to speak, in this way, on behalf of tradition. 2.3 Subordination as a Traditionary Event The concept of a traditionary event is yet a third perspective of philosophical hermeneutics that describes the matter of subordination in light of education. It is clear by now that one may engage understanding to a greater or lesser degreeâthat there are better and worse ways to seek the truth. Sometimes we have the patience to look closely at a painting, sometimes we are interested in questions a painting does not speak to, and sometimes we have no interest in a dialogue at all. When we do enter into dialogue, and we are lucky enough to have the tools we need to bring our selves to the process of understanding, we are still faced with a difficult cognitive task. This is the task of negotiating the process of understanding as a traditionary event. To this end, Gadamer discusses the ideal balance for dialogue as a passage between presentism and historicism. These two terms represent poles on a spectrum of our familiarity with a 70 Artists, on this account, have a very difficult road ahead. The more fragmented artistic practices and traditions become, the more difficult it will be to make art for an audience. Strategy will prevail. Artists who develop oeuvres with pedestrian imagery may increase the likelihood that an audience will be able to understand their work. Galleries and museums that specialize in specific âmomentsâ or âstylesâ of art may be a bigger draw for field trips. Art that is marketed in a specific region as âlocalâ art may gain a local following. And historians and critics who act as intermediaries between the âartworldâ and a wider audience and âmake senseâ of art may increase their readership over that of their academic peers. All these occurrences can be understood as a response to the difficulty in understanding what artists do and why they do it. 182 thing, and bear out the optimal orientation for a person seeking to understand a part of the world. To draw out the moral significance of understanding, I will call the successful balance between presentism and historicism âhermeneutic excellence,â and turn to the matter of hermeneutic excellence below. But first the meaning of âfamiliarityâ is discussed as a quality pertaining to things as âtraditionary materialâ and their role in traditionary events. By the end of this section, the definition of a traditionary event should be clear. The value of art is often judged according to its ability to evoke a fruitful dialogue among experts (and not only living experts) about a subject that is preserved âamid the ruins of timeâ (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 289). Yet even experts may not always be interested in the same subject. They may be content with studying Picassoâs technique of applying paint to the canvas, the composition of a painting, or some other aspect of the piece. Indeed, when anyone enters into a dialogue with a work of art, they are able to form questions about what they do not already know because of tradition. Tradition is what addresses usâwhat commands our attention and speaks to usâwhen we enter into a dialogue with a thing. This personification of tradition follows MacIntyreâs claim that a practice is not only a living community: To enter into a practice is to enter into a relationship not only with its contemporary practitioners, but also with those who have preceded us in the practice, particularly those whose achievements extended the reach of the practice to its present point. (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 194) 183 On this account, all individuals who share in the process of inquiry participate in a MacIntyrian practice, and the notion of tradition refers to such a practice as a community of inquiry. The depiction of the historical nature of practices tends to go along with a notion of tradition as an unbroken chain of practitioners in service of a practice. Alas, this is a clumsy philosophical portrayal of the complex situation tradition describes. Because the difference between a community and a tradition is not always well defined, it is important to articulate how these terms will be distinguished here. Henceforth, I follow Gadamer in personifying tradition because it is meant as an overarching description of a community that takes on board the shared experience of that community. But personification evokes the analogy to individual identity, and begs the question of how individuals within a community are different from one another, and may struggle to extend a practice in different ways. An important limit of this definition of tradition, therefore, is to allow that it does not encompass all aspects of identity, but is instead the imagined sum total of a communityâs shared identity. It is not understating the case to say that imagination, so employed, will only vaguely grasp such matters. Yet the notion of tradition is too important to cast aside. The confusion about the boundary and nature of a tradition is less important than the way that it modifies the notion of community. To talk about a community of artists, for example, refers to a group that shares values, ideas about art, phone numbers, and so on. To say that a group of artists share a tradition is to invoke MacIntyreâs special concept of a practice 184 which, in turn, implies that the group shares a conception of excellence that emerges from the work of a practiceâit involves morality. Thus, the concept of tradition references timeless features of a practice in a way community does not. If âcommunityâ names the individuals who participate in a practice, then âtraditionâ names the ways in which they participate. A traditionary event is an intersection of individual experience and the life of a community. It is a moment when an artist confronts the reality of his workâhow art can be made, how it will be interpreted, what it means, and what difference it will make. The matter of understanding is necessary for capturing (philosophically) what is involved in this confrontation precisely because: Hermeneutical consciousness is aware that its bond to this subject matter does not consist in some self-evident, unquestioned unanimity, as in the case with the unbroken stream of tradition. Hermeneutic work is based on a polarity of familiarity and strangeness (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 295). In giving us this concise statement about hermeneutic work, Gadamer expects that we comprehend this richness of it. There is a strong relationship, for example, between the content of both sentences. Gadamer is equating âfamiliarityâ with traditionâs âunbrokenness,â except he will later go on to say it is the individual who actually experiences familiarity. In contrast to this quality, he equates âstrangenessâ with an individualâs awareness of the âbrokennessâ of his historical consciousness. These two terms also describe, in a more direct way, two extremes of a traditionary event for an I and a Thouâpresentism and historicismâto which I will turn below. First, two other aspects of this passage warrant further discussion: 1) the hypothesis about the artist (âhermeneutical consciousnessâ) being aware of the contingencies of 185 nature, and 2) the evocative description of a cognitive task as a foundational pillar of hermeneutic work. The nature of these observations is in view as Gadamer addresses the problem of familiarity and strangeness as a relationship to tradition. He says: Hermeneutics must start from the position that a person seeking to understand something has a bond to the subject matter that comes into language through the traditionary text and has, or acquires, a connection with the tradition from which the text speaks. (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 295) The struggle to understand a tradition is played out through attempts to understand traditionary texts (traditionary material). To understand the purpose or meaning of painting, one must first understand paintings, and the quality of oneâs understanding is predicated on oneâs understandings. The experience of familiarity and strangeness are implicated in both aspects of this process, and both âlevelsâ of understanding implicate the movement of understanding between familiarity and strangenessâhistorical consciousness on its âcircularâ path. Gadamer helpfully distinguishes between these two levels by pushing back the problem of how we arrive at more general (or âuniversalâ) modes of understanding, which he discusses under the rubric of âhorizons.â This leaves the matter of how we understand a practice such as painting as the subject of understanding, âproperlyâ understood. From this perspective, tradition is indeed a âself-evident, unquestioned unanimity,â because an individualâs historical consciousness cannot overcome his or her situated perspective even though he or she may be aware of its limitations. Indeed, it is this situation that historical consciousness hopes to overcome by understanding history (i.e., the subject of understanding, âphilosophicallyâ understood), for the ability to paint for a community 186 is partly discovered in and through encounters with historical horizons. When this hope of historical consciousness supervenes on a practitionerâs work, this work is rightly understood as a traditionary event. For the sake of philosophy, Gadamer says, âeverything contained in historical consciousness is in fact embraced by a single historical horizonâ (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 304). While his words elicit a strange picture of the artist (any artist) as potentially in full agreement with the world, he means this to be true. But this is a claim MacIntyreâs concept of a practice, and the definition of internal goods it entails, serves to refute. At least, the concept of practice helps to tease apart a strong version of Gadamerâs claim from a weak one, and the theory of subordination as an educational good shows why we should prefer the weak claim over skepticism about the strong one. Whereas the strong claim takes Gadamerâs claim seriously, the weak claim amends it with the caveat that it is too general to ever be disproved. If it were not for the philosophical purpose Gadamer intends, such a theory may as well be thrown out. That purpose is, instead, part of his defense of the human sciences. While such an intent may or may not be in service of my work here to give a more general account of subordination as an educational good, it should be set aside but not thrown out. Preserving the weak claim means we can dodge the outright rejection of the possibility of a unifying horizon, and by association, objectivity. It still aspires to Gadamerâs defense of the human sciences, but it is more modest. A weak version of his claim could go as follows: âMost things in 187 historical consciousness may be embraced by a single historical horizon of a practice.â71 This does, after all, appear to be the ambition of tradition, whose appearance as an unbroken stream is an effect of the nature of understanding, and a result of the embodied human experience of horizons. The concept of the âhorizonâ animates Gadamerâs discussion of historical consciousness because he is concerned with âthe superior breadth of vision that the person who is trying to understand must haveâ (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 305). Perhaps what is startling about Gadamerâs view is that this âsuperior breadth of visionâ is so often associated with philosophical understanding. The introduction of a weak view of tradition may temper his claim yet again. In this case, our understanding of the âperson who is trying to understandâ is modified by our awareness of practices as a site of understanding. Understanding may be quite different from one practice to another, and oneâs attempt to understand the arts, for example, must necessarily be different that oneâs attempt to understand sports. Portrait painting requires a person to engage different processes than fishingâit hardly warrants comparison, except from the perspective of philosophy, and this is Gadamerâs (and partly my own) practice-based point of view. The special case that some practices aspire to have horizons that span the 71 It is worth noting here, if only as an aside, that the popularity of sports may be a result of this quality of historical consciousness. Most sports meet MacIntyreâs definition of practices. But they are, additionally, surprisingly engaging from a spectatorâs point of view. Perhaps due to the clear (and visceral) nature of excellence in sports, as well as the clearly stated rules of engagement, it is easy to comprehend a fairly comprehensive historical horizon. That is, sports wear tradition on their sleeve, and often literally so. In light of this example, Gadamerâs notion of an embrace makes more sense, for we see how being privy to a single historical horizon makes us feel goodâwe enjoy understanding what is going on, and knowing why one outcome is better than another. 188 âknowledgeâ of other practices emerges from history, and it is a nonobvious and nontrivial point that this is ever more than an aspiration. While both MacIntyre and Gadamer explore the possibility and consequences of these cases, I will not explore them further here. It is enough to grant that the world is replete with diverse practices and more and less comprehensive horizons of understanding that emerge from them. This will only be seen as too weak a statement from both Gadamerian and MacIntyrian points of view. The point of defending a weak view is to envisage a stronger theory. Here, this will come at the cost of admitting to some doubt about the precision of applications of moral philosophy. A stronger theory is imagined here as more closely wedded to educational philosophy (and psychology) rather than normative philosophy. Hence, Gadamerâs interest in traditionary events as encounters with historical horizons takes on less significance as it pertains to philosophical understanding, and more significance as it relates to the work of carrying a practice forwardâMacIntyreâs term for the intersection of practices and moral traditions (by which he means shared visions of virtue and the good life). By emphasizing the role of subordination in education generally, I am attempting to shift the burden of proof for moral philosophy to practice-specific cases of achievement. That is, I am interested in committing moral philosophers to a project whereby moral excellence is defined in an ongoing manner by educational excellence, which is further defined as the achievement of subordination in a practice, understood as the culmination of a traditionary event. Moral excellence still names what educational excellence cannot: that one cannot attain the vision that a 189 single historical horizon affords by standing outside of tradition. We stand within it, and from this position it is all too easy to think that they we are already in agreement with one another. In the following section, this argument culminates in the synthesis of moral philosophy and hermeneutics as an articulation of the process of understanding as an educational ideal. 2.4 Subordination as Hermeneutic Excellence Everyone who engages tradition negotiates experiences of the present and the past so as to move into the horizon that âembraces the historical depths of our selfconsciousnessâ (Gadamer, 1960/2002, p. 304). To achieve hermeneutic excellence, therefore, we must avoid both âpresentismâ and âhistoricismââtoo much reliance on the present or the past, respectively, that distorts understanding. Gadamer describes presentism as the perspective that overemphasizes our language. Simplistic though it may seem, this could be, for example, to think that the Weeping Woman is about wearing unstylish clothing. Gadamer (1960/2002) says, We are always affected, in hope and fear, by what is nearest to us, and hence we approach the testimony of the past under its influence. Thus it is constantly necessary to guard against overhasty assimilating the past to our own expectations of meaning. Only then can we listen to tradition in a way that permits it to make its own meaning heard. (p. 305) To avoid presentism, we must bracket out our prejudices to the best of our ability and âlistenâ to tradition. Presentism is a common mistake of understanding, for it is easy to assimilate a question with what we already know. Whereas what we know 190 from one practice may first appear to be perfectly analogous to another practice, this is seldom the case. As MacIntyre (1984) tells us, the patience of a fisherman is different from the patience of a chess player because of the technical skills involved and the different ends toward which those skills are directed (p. 193). When a student enters into a practice, it may be difficult to grasp the particular ends involved, and an experienced practitioner may continue to feel this way as his or her exposure to a practice increases over time. Avoiding presentism means trusting that a practice has a tradition into which it is worth entering. And so, avoiding presentism means actively suspending oneâs judgment. The matter of presentism brings attention to a similarity between different degrees of the experience. A student might have a limited exposure to a practice while a teacher might have many years of experience participating in, or learning about, a practice. This is an important difference, yet the model of subordination is the same: there is a tradition to which a practitioner subordinates himself or herself. Confusion about this matter may arise for several reasons. 1) Students often subordinate themselves to other people (who are often âteachersâ), whereas mature practitioners subordinate themselves to a more invisible network of people, both alive and dead. 2) Students are often more concerned with increasing their exposure to a practice, whereas mature practitioners are often concerned with deepening their understanding of one aspect of a practice. 3) Students may be noncommittal in their relationship to a practice, whereas mature practitioners have often made vocational decisions related to their ongoing commitments to a practice. And 4) Students may literally have to 191 suspend their incredulity about the significance of another practitionerâs achievement, whereas mature practitioners, with a more comprehensive understanding of a tradition, are willing to accommodate diversity. These are only a few of the differences between practitioners with different degrees of experience within a practice, yet they suggest a divergence in two degrees of subordination: the subordination of the mature practitioner to tradition, and the subordination of the student practitioner to other individuals. While these are two modes of the same process of understanding, it is now clear why MacIntyre eschews the notion of education, teaching, or learning as a practiceâthese are all part of the regular operations of other practices. As I argued in Chapter V, however, this duality should not deter us from so recognizing these activities as practices in their own right. This recognition potentially brings attention to the special task of hermeneutic excellence, as well as the distinctiveness of diverse practices as ways of life.72 Subordination, as the âlook and feelâ of hermeneutic excellence, is a feature of traditionary events. Surprisingly perhaps, this means it is necessary for the work of coming to an agreement. An I and Thou do not subordinate themselves to one another per se, but to the tradition of a shared practice. Presentism is the complex mistake of not upholding the process of understanding in good faith at any point during oneâs work within a practice, and avoiding it is only one part of what subordination entails. 72 Higgins (2003a) aptly calls this distinctiveness a âmoral phenomenology.â 192 To achieve hermeneutic excellence, we must also avoid âhistoricism,â which Gadamer (1960/2002) defines as follows: We think we understand when we see the past from a historical standpointâ i.e., transpose ourselves into the historical situation and try to reconstruct the historical horizon. In fact, however, we have given up the claim to find in the past any truth that is valid and intelligible for ourselves. (p. 303) Historicism, seen as a mistake of historical consciousness, is the opposite of presentism. It is a loss of self in the process of understanding, an obstruction to inquiry. It is a loss of bearing on why tradition matters for us. Historicism disrupts the connection between the process of understanding and the good life that is achieved through a practice. It is the impulse to make art for artâs sake while we stand idly by and watch a war ravage a nation. Art as inquiry desires more than mere continuationâit is the culmination of a tradition in the present. Art as inquiry is a Pragmatic project that makes a difference in our world. The criterion of excellence that emerges from between these two extremes of hermeneutic consciousness is the ability to speak with tradition and animate traditionary material as an answer to a common question. It is coming to an agreement about the meaning of a work of art with the intention of making it more powerful. In this way, an exemplary work of art orients us in our time. This does not contradict Gadamerâs idea that tradition is embraced by a single horizon. Tradition, Gadamer says, is that which gives us traction to change the world: In fact the important thing is to recognize temporal distance as a positive and productive condition enabling understanding. It is not a yawning abyss but is filled with the continuity of custom and tradition, in the light of which everything handed down presents itself to us. (p. 297) 193 Hermeneutic excellence is excellence in education alongside excellence in other practices. It describes an activity that goes hand in hand with subordination, and it is central to the concept of morality that I have argued for thus far. It is a quality of a personâs process of understanding that connects oneâs self to other selvesâit is an excellence of community building. Subordination does not only consist in hermeneutic excellence, but can follow from it. Subordination, for example, is an attitude an art student may adopt, after he has understood the Weeping Woman for the first time, to suspend his prejudices and engage a community of artists as a maker of art. A so-called âgenius practitionerâ experiences tradition in the same way as we have seen above, but her experience, unlike just any practitionerâs, is attended by a kind of hermeneutic excellence that constitutes the quality of her genius. In Gadamerâs language, we can describe both the depth and clarity of her historical consciousness on paths of understanding, and her path between presentism and historicism that makes possible a fusion of horizons. As I have endeavored to show in this chapter, these are two interdependent features of her âhistorical being.â With this process of understanding in view, we can now describe subordination from the perspective of a student with two additional caveats. 1) It is what occurs throughout a traditionary event when the person who is subordinated to, the teacher, has a prior relationship to traditionary material that a student is confronting. And 2) it is a name for when a student acknowledges that his teacherâs experience is more nuanced than his own. 194 3. Verticality in Practices Subordination sustains tension between the activity of making art and the process of understanding art. Historically, this tension is familiar to arts practitioners as the gap between creation and viewership and, as such, is an aporia of aesthetic philosophy. Looking at a work of art, the modern viewer asks, âWhat does it mean to me?â or âWhat is the artist saying?ââthese are not meant as two sides of the same question, though we are now able to see this compartmentalization of tradition as a mischaracterization of the process of understanding. Recognizing this problem is especially important when the viewer is an arts practitioner, no matter how novice or expert. The subjectivization of aesthetics, for example, can be understood as a deep misconception about artistsâ ability to oscillate between art making and viewershipâbetween presentism and historicism. For Gadamer, this tension is positive. It is the open space for the student-artistâs educational questions to emerge. According to MacIntyre, this emergence is the essence of the vitality of practices in general, without which (to paraphrase MacIntyre) human powers to achieve excellence, and the human conceptions of the ends and goods involved cannot be extended. For Pragmatists such as Dewey, this is the ability of a self to transform the world. The picture of practitionersâ education reveals a unity within tradition. The experience of tradition in the artsâpractices in which there are tangible products that 195 are often overtly symbolic of untimely connections between past, present, and future human actionsâadds to artistsâ self-understanding as a community with a shared orientation towards moral life. Genius can now be rightly valued as a concept that restores verticality to the experience of interpersonal relationships in practices, and, in educational terms, makes the good of subordination more intelligible in the multipractice community educators call âthe social world.â It is just another case where the potential for achievement comes at the cost of a philosophical tension. 4. Conclusion Hermeneutic excellence implies two directions for art (for art practice): art for tradition and art for students. It describes an ideal process of engaging tradition, and it is equally applicable for the point of view of the novice practitioner and the mature practitioner. Hermeneutic consciousness is an orientation toward practice that postulates a tradition. According to MacIntyreâs definition, it is definitive of practice because it creates a sense of verticality in a practice for all practitioners. It is now evident how subordination proceeds as a relation between two individuals in a practice, and we can describe subordination with additional caveats. Hermeneutic excellence describes a practitionerâs cognitive process of solving the problems of a practice. It is only possible to work within a practice in this way once an 196 awareness of excellence is achieved, and the appearance of art objects as âoriginalâ and the art practitioner as âexemplaryâ are potential by-products of this mode of creation. Subordination, understood as one part of hermeneutic excellence, is a compelling account of genius. Genius is a confluence of many things, but it also has a moral meaning that obtains within a community of artists. For artists, it is important that genius is not only a matter of being the âright person at the right time,â but instead (or in addition to) it is the achievement of subordination over the course of a lifetime. The embodiment of this achievement as a work of art, or a whole oeuvre, is not only what qualifies one as an excellent artist, but it is also a hallmark of a practice as a moral oneâa practice with a âliveâ (as Dewey might say) tradition. Further development of these themes will show us how artists can avoid the idealization of embodied traditionary authority in the arts, while locating its value as an educational good. In Part III, I discuss how Kantâs observations about genius intersect with the theory of hermeneutic excellence as moral excellence. 197 PART IIIâCRITIQUE OF GENIUS [C]ome close to Nature. Then, as if no one had ever tried before, try to say what you see and feel and love and lose. Donât write love poems; avoid those forms that are too facile and ordinary: they are the hardest to work with, and it takes a great, fully ripened power to create something individual where good, even glorious, traditions exist in abundance. So rescue yourself from these general themes and write about what your everyday life offers you; describe your sorrows and desires, the thoughts that pass through your mind and your belief in some kind of beautyâdescribe all these with heartfelt, silent, humble sincerity and, when you express yourself, use the Things around you, the images from your dreams, and the objects that you remember. If your everyday life seems poor, donât blame it; blame yourself; admit to yourself that you are not enough of a poet to call forth its richesâŚâ And if out of this turning-within, out of this immersion in your own world, poems come, then you will not think of asking anyone whether they are any good or not⌠A work of art is good if it has arisen out of necessity. That is the only way one can judge it. Rainer Maria Rilke, 1903-1908/1986, pp. 6-9. 198 VIIâMORALITY AS SUCH 1. The Metaphysical Tradition Part III of my study of artistic genius begins by returning to a vital philosophical contribution to the study of art. In Chapters IVâVI, it was shown that the way we think about artists has implications for the way we think about genius. The same will be true for how we think about aesthetics in general. Kantâs Critique of the Power of Judgment (1793/2000) served as a touchstone for generations of aesthetic philosophers, so I will now turn to his writing on art and genius to bring his views to bear on the matter of hermeneutic excellence. Understanding how he conceptualized the relation between artists and art will contribute to the theory of the educational role of subordination in moral life, and entering into a dialogue with Kant is also a rite of passage for any theory that aspires to be taken seriously as philosophy. Henrich (1992) summarizes the significance of Kantâs critique for aesthetics in the following way: It combines and reconstructs the analyses of aesthetic predicates and the aesthetic attitude that emerged in Leibnizâs and Lockeâs schools, as they have been formulated by philosophers like Alexander Baumgarten and Johann Georg Sulzer on the one hand and like Hume and Burke on the other. But it also elevated the aesthetic theory to a new level by integrating it into the framework of a new epistemology that Kant had worked out in the Critique of Pure Reason 199 based on the view that what we call âreasonâ consists in a complex interaction of various epistemic operations. (p. 29) The conceptual connection between art and knowledge Kant charts out plays a pivotal role in our understanding of art as inquiry, and it is essential to the moral view of genius. Though this is perhaps not the result Kant had in mind, I believe it adequately captures an outcome of his metaphysics.73 Thus, the âscientificâ devaluation of art practices along with other human sciences can be seen as a direct consequence of the belief that reason is so constituted by epistemological complexity. This is exactly how I do not wish Chapter VI to be read. Though in a text such as this one (my dissertation) there may be an abundance of references to âdialogue,â discussion,â and discourse,â these terms should not be taken literally. Practices may differ as to the mode of discourseâpainters paint to each other, musicians play for each other, and chemists look through microscopes togetherâand this should not be passed off as a trivial matter. While they often also speak in an âordinaryâ language, this should not be mistaken as a âprimaryâ mode of communication when we are referring to a practice. Aesthetic philosophy after Kant, however, was overwhelmed by the project of reconciling the many languages of practices with the emerging model of the mind. Living in the aftermath of this debacle, we will benefit from a return to the watershed moment in aesthetics that Kantâs theory represents. 73 For a helpful biographical story of Kantâs interest in aesthetics, see Henrich (1992), especially Chapter 2. Certain facts bring to light how Kant was able to strategically commingle discourses in aesthetics and epistemology. 200 The purpose of this chapter will be to once again return to the moment when we first encounter art practice, and remember what excellence looks like. This is a moment before we understood what philosophical hermeneutics has to offer, so the discussion of the awareness of aesthetic excellence that follows must have several parts. First, we must agree on what counts as âaesthetic,â and do so in a way that leaves open some of the most difficult questions about the moral nature of human experience. It is this work that I began in Chapter IV. Secondly, there must be a qualification of excellence, and this will here take the form of a discussion of beauty that, in turn, will be shown to ground the discussion of exemplarity that it precedes. Third, the outcome of the awareness of aesthetic excellence should be given, and here it will be shown to give rise to questions about artistsâ experiences as makers of art. This is an exegesis of Kantâs philosophy that should extend and deepen the depiction of art practice begun in Chapters I and II. 2. The Way Kant Saw Nature in the Subject Kantâs reflection on art has been influential in the widespread conceptualization of art and its value, and the richness of the philosophical dialogue surrounding his writing demonstrates its lasting influence.74 His corpus serves as a dense confluence of 74 Today, scholars who work in the domain of natural science (âscientistsâ) are rarely interested in the transcendental foundations of their work. Although some are, they tend to gravitate toward philosophy. From a humanistic vantage, this is lamentable, as dialogues that would otherwise 201 concepts that affect how art is received, how art is made, and how art is taught. Though significantly incongruous with contemporary dialogues about education, Kantâs thinking lends itself to my critique.75 His view of genius is a direct precursor to the Romantic view that impacted the artworld in the nineteenth century, changing forever the lives of artists like Gauguin who became superstars and icons of the Western canon. For Kant, the concept of genius, with its roots in the arts, plays an important role in securing a definition of judgment that he found lacking in the Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1998) and the Critique of Practical Reason (1788/1996). As he worked on his Critiques over time, he came to believe that âjudgmentâ is the name for a necessary bridge between human reason and nature (Guyer, 1979). His writing on art informs my moral conception of genius and bears on the matter of subordination, as he relates genius to judgment via beauty. According to Kant, beauty is a phenomenal quality of âtrueâ works of art. Kantâs theory of judgment, educate (i.e., enlighten) the public about the interests, standards, and powers of scientific work is, at best, sustained by outsiders, or at worst, nonexistent. As a consequence of this state of affairs, philosophers have been made to become expert metaphysicians about work they never get to do. This is part of Kantâs legacy. The enduring promise of the Enlightenment is the promise that humans can know the world and transform it. I imagine the critique of genius as part of the project of building a scientific method from the ground up. The danger of this foundation, however, is the possibility of not getting very far or failing to undertake a transformative project at all. But the opposite is also possible. As I hope to show, to begin from within the domain of aesthetics and once again enter into the Enlightenment project has the potential to engage the imagination of a living community in a shared quest for truth, beauty, and goodness. 75 The irony will not be lost on some that I am reading a translation of Kant. This is not a great worry to me, as this Kantâthe translated Kantâis quite remarkable in his own right. As hermeneutics shows us, the problem of translation is hardly specific to translation between languages. Translations of his writing have no doubt compounded the interminable disagreement over how Kant should be read, but the problem of translation is only a symptom of the difficulty of reading Kant in the first place. For a discussion of the problems of translation, see (Gram, 1982), especially Chapter 1. 202 therefore, puts forward a conception of beauty that is pivotal for art practice. A close reading of his aesthetics (sic) reveals the relation of genius to the overarching project of his three major Critiques. Before turning to this relation, I should provide at least the barest description of my interpretation of his philosophical projects: I understand Kantâs transcendental philosophy to be a set of critiques that, when considered as a whole, create a world (by describing its boundaries) within which a theory of reason, and therefore a vision of the good life, is defensible. In this way, Kantâs philosophy frames the project of the Enlightenment as an agreement on a ârationalâ discourse that can mobilize moral action and serve as a foundation of a good and just community (Hills, 2004). In this way, Kant is commonly regarded as leading modern philosophyâs preoccupation with epistemology. And although the âproblem of knowledgeâ is foregrounded in the Critiques, I would like to advocate a reappraisal of this topic as only one way to understand Kantâs concerns. The notion of genius arises in Kantâs discussion of fine art at the end of the Analytic of the Sublime, but I read these passages (§30 â §54) as a continuation of the Analytic of the Beautiful.76 Though Kantâs concept of the sublime articulates a relationship between the human mind and nature that better positions his acceptance of artworks as specific instances of beauty, I will not say much about it here. In 76 The phrase âaesthetic judgment,â however, is misleading. It conjures up an image of a judgment that is wholly aesthetic, or about something that is thought to be aesthetic. By contrast, the overarching title of this part of the critique is âCritique of the Aesthetic Power of Judgment,â and so it seems as if âthe aestheticâ is only one aspect of judgment. I read Kant as intending this later meaning, as the problem of judgment arises from his earlier critiques that are concerned with 203 contrast to beauty, he theorizes the sublime as a magnitude of nature that the mind does not acquiesce a priori or through phenomenal experience (Kant, 1793/2000, pp. 131-134). Beauty, he seems to say, is something we innately understand, something âin which the subject feels itself as it is affected by the representationâ (p. 89). I cannot help but feel some unease at this premise, but it resonates with my experience as a young artist in the presence of great art. For this reason, I entertain the possibility that his view is representative of a nascent experience of art as representation. It is difficult, however, to reconcile this view with MacIntyreâs theory of internal goods, as one should not innately understand what one does not experience as a practitioner. Kantâs theory falls into place when we equate representation with exposureâKantâs view of innate understanding is closely wedded to the experience of seeing. Along these lines, Kant describes the relationship between beauty and nature, where nature is beautiful without form (i.e., sublime), and art âcan only be called beautiful if we are aware that it is art and yet it looks to us like natureâ (p. 185). Both beauty and nature, it seems, are known to us through art. Genius, proposed as the source of beautiful art (p. 186), would seem to be a vehicle for understanding everything beautiful and natural, but this will prove not to be the case. The shifting role of nature in Kantâs description of genius allows for a more ordinary faculty to play the role of comprehending beauty in nature: imagination. reason, practical reason, imagination, understanding, and an so on. Kant himself may intentionally equivocate at times, and my intent here is only to bring attention to this matter. 204 2.1 What Counts as Nature Genius is not a key concept of Kantâs positive theory of judgment. For example, Crawford (2003) says Kant unambiguously claims that artists (in general) create aesthetic ideas. On a reading the Dialectic of the Aesthetic Power of Judgment, Crawford draws out the conclusion of Kantâs claim that âgenius manifests itself in the creation and presentation of aesthetic ideas, which result from the exercise of the productive imaginationâ (p. 161). Crawford argues, âfor Kant, talent, spirit, and genius do not represent distinct faculties; rather they comprise ways of setting in motion oneâs other ordinary faculties, especially imaginationâ (p. 160). Serving merely as a prompt for artists to apply the powers of reason to art making, genius appears more like the poetic inspiration it referred to in ancient times. This is genius depicted as a wayside attraction for a society on its way from the gallery of fine objects to the sitting room of smoke and pleasant critiqueâfrom beauty to goodness. Kant partially elucidates his conception of nature when he says, âgenius is the talent (natural gift) that gives the rule to artâ [his clarification](Kant, 1793/2000, p. 186). The âruleâ must at least be understood as that which makes beautiful art âa kind of representation that is purposive in itself and, though without end, nevertheless promotes the cultivation of the mental powers for sociable communicationâ (Kant, 1793/2000, p. 185). Kant clarifies the role of the ârule of natureâ further by noting that since the âinborn faculty of the artistâ is itself a part of nature, âgenius is the inborn predisposition of the mind⌠through which nature gives the rule to artâ [translatorâs 205 emphasis](Kant, 1793/2000, p. 186). Thus, the âgivingâ is a natural phenomenon of which beauty is an outward manifestation. Offering a different perspective of the matter of beauty, Kant says, âtaste as it were makes possible the transition from sensible charm to the habitual moral interestâ (Kant, 1793/2000, p. 228). His philosophical followers have made various and sordid attempts to read him consistently on these matters. Crawford (2003) tentatively puts forward the argument that for Kant âthe ultimate significance of beauty in art and the explanation for the experience of it being inherently and universally pleasurable for us lies in its being a symbol of moralityâ (p. 165). Guyer (1979) cites R. K. Elliottâs sympathy with the view that âif it were not for the moral analogy there could be no judgments of taste, but only private preferences and judgments of objective perfectionâ (cited in Guyer, p. 352). Guyer therefore asserts that Elliott commits himself to Crawfordâs view âthat perception or sensitivity to beauty may be demanded of everyone because beauty is a symbol of the morally good, and sensitivity to such a symbol may be demanded as part of the demand of morality itselfâ (Guyer, 1979, p. 353). But Guyer suggests neither that the connection between beauty and morality in Kantâs theory is clear, nor that it would have the outcome of universality claimed by Crawford and Elliott if it were shown to be the case. This retreat from the analogy between beauty and morality may somewhat redeem genius in the eyes of moral philosophers interested in geniusâ relationship to nature. Guyer offers a lengthy reading of Kant to show why the additional matter of morality is unhelpful. He turns to Kantâs passages on communicability and sociability 206 and reads Kant as claiming âthe inclination to society creates an interest in the means to society, among which is a regard to universal communicability; so such a regard is demanded of othersâ (Guyer, 1979, p. 364). That beautiful objects can be valued because they offer us the ability to communicate helps make sense of Kantâs claim that taste is a basis for detecting the rule of artâand therefore genius. But, as Guyer argues, this does not helpfully complete the deduction of aesthetic judgment. It does not show how we come to have the faculty of taste. As a way out of this lack of explanation for taste, Crawford deflates Kantâs view of genius. He says, âto take on a form that allows it to be communicated and stand the test of judgment, genius must be combined with tasteâ (Crawford, 2003, p. 160). Taste is crucial, he says, for the enterprise of art to be successful. But this only begs the question, Why genius? Why not another characteristic of the mind such as quickness or memory? Taste can go a long way as a basis for art, and this was no doubt Kantâs worry when he distinguished fine art from all other kinds or mechanical production and imitation. But, for a theory of nature as the vector of beauty, a better description of how we come to have either taste or genius is needed. Kant does not focus on the process whereby geniuses become productive artists. Instead, he offers a view of genius that points to imagination and understanding as key aspects of aesthetic judgment. He claims harmony between imagination and understanding is the basis of aesthetic response, and beauty is the quality of an object that elicits such a response. About this lack of attention to the formative aspect of appreciation for art, Guyer (1979) suggests the jig is up: 207 Having denied that a standard for either the estimation or the production of beauty can be found in the realm of determinate concepts and intentions, he concludes that this standard must be found âin what is mere nature in the subject, but which cannot be comprehended under rules or concepts, that is to say, the supersensible substratum of all [the subjectâs] faculties (which no concept of understanding can attain), and consequently in that in relation to which all of our cognitive faculties are to be made harmonious, this being the ultimate end given by the intelligible [basis] of our nature.â (p. 341) [the authorâs translation] By pushing back the question this far, there seems to be no way for Kant to talk about the nature of genius other than to say it is ânatureâ itself. This is disappointing, but even more, it leaves us with a sense of Kantâs exasperation about the matter of universality when it comes to human affairs. Guyer shows Kant to be eliding his own rules of engagement by invoking the noumenal realm, and furthermore, that it is not clear that it advances his deduction of judgment. Kantâs view of genius is muddled. While he has been previously understood to have made clear and determinate arguments about artists and art practice, his ideas fall flat in light of a stricter definition of practice. His overt concern with conceptualizing a model of the mind (i.e., epistemology) trumps his interest in understanding the meaning of ânatureâ as a locus of beauty. Engaging him in this dialogue, however, has allowed us to see what aesthetics looks like with only a thin concept of tradition. When aesthetic excellence is reduced to the surface of things, beauty is indeed a mysterious and elusive qualityâand the concept of genius is one part of a quick philosophical fix. In Section 3.3, the matters of sociability and communicability of artâoutlined here as artâs universal qualitiesâwill be explored and linked to the idea of tradition. This will secure subordinationâs role at two moments in art practice: 1) as a good that allows 208 novice practitioners to experience the distinctive qualities of a practice, and 2) as a special kind of ongoing relationship among artists. 2.2 Two Kinds of Beauty Kant says that there are two kinds of beauty: free beauty and adherent beauty. âThe first supposes no concept of what the object ought to be; the second does presuppose such a concept and the perfection of the object in accordance with itâ (Kant, 1793/2000, p. 114). This is reminiscent of his description of the difference between beauty in nature and beauty in art, and draws out the matter of artistic excellence as aesthetic perfection. Lyotard (1994) furthers our understanding of Kantâs move away from the first kind of beauty as, âsublime feeling can be thought of as an extreme case of the beautifulâ (p. 75). Engaging other eighteenth-century philosophies of art, Kant strategically attends to the matter of tasteâthe discernment of beauty. To better define his theory of the faculty of taste in relation to his theory of judgment, Kant discusses various fine arts and their relative worth. The perception that art is potentially universally appealing frames his characterization about artistic genius from the outset. He says, âone could even define taste as the faculty for [knowing] that which makes our feeling in a given representation universally communicableâ (Kant, 1793/2000, p. 175). Nowhere, however, does he distinguish between educated or knowledgeable viewers of art, nor more or less formal viewings, so I will take him to be evoking a sense of the possibility of universality. 209 Kant acknowledges that every art âpresupposes rules.â He says, âbeautiful art cannot itself think up the rule in accordance with which it is to bring its product into beingâ (p. 186). This is a misleading description, however, as the awkward phrase that âart cannot itself think up the ruleâ follows from his broader hypothesis that aesthetic judgment is not dependant on concepts. Art cannot be considered beautiful simply because it is judged as following rulesâan argument that reinforces his theory that judging is not synonymous with reasoning. While beauty is perceived innately, reason requires concepts for its determining ground.77 This is essentially how he concludes that ânature in the subjectâ (p. 186) gives rule to art. Nature partly defines genius for Kant, and this points to a durable (not only momentary or fleeting) characteristic of artists who make beautiful art. This says more about the logical structure of art as an artifact of experience than the actual appearance of beautiful art. Perhaps it is optimistic to think that Kantâs view of art and beauty does not narrow the field of art too much (to the exclusion of âuglyâ art), but Kant was not settling differences of taste. He was interested in taste as a faculty that provided clues to the problem of a priori knowledge. By implying that beauty is a quality by which we discern what counts as art, I take Kant as highlighting, if indirectly, the importance of the appearance of art as evidence of an artistâs reason. Whether or not an artist will be said to be a genius will ultimately depend on the 77 See Kant (1781/1998) for a discussion of the relation between concepts and understanding, especially the On the Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding, pp. 219-244. He concludes that understanding is a name for the mental faculty that provides cognition with rules. 210 characteristics of his art. Besides being self-evidently a new rule of nature, however, the excellence of beautiful art is not yet clear. In the next section, I turn to Kantâs description of the art of genius as original and exemplary. These will be shown to be key characteristics of beautiful art. 3. Boundaries of the Concept of Genius Further consideration of Kantâs observations about genius informs our historical reception of the concept. As I show in Chapter III and IV, psychologists, educators, and philosophers often do not treat the meaning of genius in a principled wayâit is deployed as a highly specific term to denote achievement on a test or as a catchall term for a set of desirable qualities or characteristics. Avoiding this conceptual mess, Kant defines genius in relation to beautyâan effort that culminates in a twopronged theory of genius. We can guard against the capricious winds of popular sentiment by following Kant, but also by showing how one part of his definition is stronger than the other. This also suggests a strategy for defining the concept of genius in general, and not only in relation to art practice. 211 3.1 Two Kinds of Excellence Beauty is at the center of the philosophical question about the relation between the human mind and nature. As we saw above in Section 2.1, Kant discusses the relation between beautiful art and genius in the section titled âBeautiful art is art of geniusâ (§46) wherein the matter of nature begs the question of how beauty is defined. Asking what sort of rule it is that genius gives to art, Kant struggles to define it. With the case of a âjudgment about the beautifulâ (Kant, 1793/2000, p. 188), he appears to discuss judgment with respect to his concern for the rules of art: namely, the act of identifying beautiful art.78 The matter of identification, however, is vague and intertwined with a conception of goodness. A short digression on this matter is called for before turning to Kantâs two-pronged view of genius. Beauty and goodness are both complex, and somewhat cumbersome, philosophical concepts. Maria Eaton (1997) shows that beauty and goodness are commonly either understood to be ontologically equivalent, or beauty is understood as historically and conceptually dependent on a conception of goodness. She somewhat prefers the former, but believes theory goes especially wrong (and our insight into both art and morality is diminished) when Kantian formalism asserts a discrete separation between the aesthetic and the ethicalâa distinction that is to one end of the spectrum 78 Kant focuses on this matter of identification, without looking at the evidence of how artists use the work of genius as a model. This is an important turn, and I will return to it below in a discussion of exemplarity in Section 3.3. 212 that helps us categorize different moments of experience, which we only really do in retrospect anyway. This has led to an extended discourse of the relationship between beauty and goodness, and because the meaning of goodness is no more settled that beautyâindeed, it is perhaps infinitely more contestedâthis has become an interminable discussion for aesthetic philosophers. Agreement about beauty, it seems, requires a corresponding agreement ethics. As I have suggested in Chapter VI, and as MacIntyre (1988) elsewhere shows, a mutual understanding is not tenable outside of a particular tradition. At best, there will be moral traditions to which aestheticians may belong, but it is unlikely those traditions will map neatly onto discursive communities in aesthetic philosophy. It should therefore be no surprise that philosophical difficulties abound when beauty and goodness are treated as ontologically equivalent concepts. In the review of recent literature in aesthetics, Eaton finds both a conception of a âformalistic priorityâ that describes a way of making a moral decision by choosing style first and content second, and a âpsychological priorityâ that asserts a causal connection between a personâs aesthetic activity and the quality of his or her moral reflection (Eaton, 1997). She explains what it would mean for the âaestheticâ to be prior to the âethicalâ by showing how theories that claim to privilege the aesthetic often presuppose a concept of moral goodness. So, she says, when Jefferson claims that certain kinds of cities make for better citizens, he is really saying that inhabitants of those cities demonstrate goodnessâaesthetics is incidental to his vision (Eaton, 1997, p. 357). 213 Eaton turns to Charles Peirceâs tripartite explanation of human experience as an example of a theory that does succeed at giving priority to aesthetics, but at too high a cost. In looking for an ultimate origin of human values, Peirce attributes aesthetic theory to âfirstnessâ which, according to Eaton, is âthe quality of the felt worldâthe world as inner, subjective experienceâ (Eaton, 1997, p. 357). And Eaton shows how Peirceâs argument situates feelings beyond language, and therefore completely separate from the ethical, which she argues is a legacy of Kantâs reasoning. She also cites Foucaultâs âgeneral theory of the way in which human practices and institutions define us as individuals, as communities, and as individuals-in-communitiesâ as a view that pays a great deal of attention to aesthetics (p. 358).79 Eaton finds all these views lacking a more comprehensive vision of ethics, even if it seems to always loom in the background. She criticizes an untenable distinction between aesthetic and ethical activity and argues for the âconceptual interdependence viewâ of the relationship between aesthetics and ethics (Eaton, 1997). Of conceptual interdependence, she says, âin order to understand morality and thus become a mature moral person, oneâs action must have both appropriate style and content, and this requires aesthetic skillsâ (p. 361). In describing the process of developing those skills, she says âaesthetics can become as important as ethics not because making an ethical decision is like choosing wallpaper, but because it is like choosing one story over 79 Eaton (1997) claims Foucaultâs work is representative of many postmodernistsâ views of the role of art practice, p. 359. 214 anotherâ (p. 362). Aesthetics, in other words, is a lot like ethics when understood apart from art and art practices. According to her theory, art can be good in two ways. 1) Art can be understood as beautiful because it is seen as good. This may lead an audience to ascribe excellence to the artist, and then 2) the artistâs art can be understood as good. This is not the same âexcellenceâ that I call hermeneutic excellence. Whereas for Eaton, beauty denotes a representation of goodness in the mind of a viewer of art, artistic excellence is quite independent of the appearance of art. It is possible that an artist may achieve excellence in the more abstract sense of being a good scholar of art, and there may or may not be sufficient evidence of this activity in the artistâs work. Indeed, there are more reasons than not for this additional translationâthe audienceâs understandingâto fall short. Kantâs concern with originality, as a first kind of excellence, should be understood as an elaboration on Eatonâs first kind of excellenceâthe infusion of moral deliberation in art. As such, it makes sense that aesthetic philosophers have dismantled the metaphysics of originality and returned the discussion to the aporia of the beautygoodness discourse (I discuss this below in Section 3.2). The notion of beauty as a natural quality of objects (both in nature and man-made) impacts the identification of artists as excellent in an important way. Judgment about excellence is disconnected from judgment about art. Art may be considered exemplaryâa second kind of excellenceâwhether or not its artist is purposefully engaging tradition. Where Kant implied an automatic connection between exemplary art and genius, we can see it as problematic. To show that the recognition of artists as geniuses rests on a further 215 qualification does not imply that Kant was wrong, but shows his discussion of judgment to be lacking nuances that virtue theory and hermeneutics bring to light. In the following sections on originality and exemplarity, I conclude the development of my critique of genius with a Kantian picture of the achievement of genius. 3.2 Originality As if he had art education in mind, Kant says, âgenius is a talent for producing that for which no determinate rule can be given, not a predisposition of skill for that which can be learned in accordance with some ruleâ (Kant, 1793/2000, p. 186). Originality, according to Kant, is one characteristic of art created by a genius. Adding the qualification that the products of genius are exemplary, serving others as models for imitation, Kant describes art as being âa standard or a rule for judgingâ (p. 187). What counts as originality has been much discussed in aesthetics, and these discussions have been both antagonistic and beneficial to art practice. From a postRomantic perspective, art practice cannot be unhinged from tradition. Already in the early twentieth century, in his comparison of the arts to languages in The Principles of Art, Collingwood (1938/1958) articulated a view of the artistâs role in making art meaningful. His description of the relationship between artists and audiences (quoted at the beginning of Part II of my dissertation) succinctly captures the difficulty of attributing the meaningfulness of beauty to the intention of the artist. It explains the frequent misattribution of the term âoriginal,â and suggests a route to properly 216 understanding meaning-makingâa route was that was taken by artists themselves under the banner of âModernity.â Rosalind Krauss, for example, theorized a critical discourse on originality in the following way: Modernism and the avant-garde are functions of what we could call the discourse of originality, and that that discourse serves much wider interestsâ and is thus fueled by more diverse institutionsâthan the restricted circle of professional art-making. (Krauss, 1981, p. 58) Krauss argues that artists have actively grappled with notions of origins, original art, and originality and that this largely defines Modernism as a style of art making. This is a reasonable outcome of Kantâs description of genius as producing art with no determinant rules, including precedents in art. Indeed, the process of imitating other art is seen as inimical to genius. Krauss discusses the pervasiveness of the concept as follows: The theme of originality, encompassing as it does the notions of authenticity, originals, and origins, is the shared discursive practice of the museum, the historian, and the maker of art. And throughout the nineteenth century all of these institutions were concerted, together, to find the mark, the warrant, the certification of the original. (Krauss, 1981, p. 58) Kraussâ description of the artworldâs attempt to seek out originality is quixotic but unsettling. Kantâs hollow explanation about some artistsâ ability to create original art, not only did not deter artists from seeking recognition as geniuses, but it apparently exacerbated their desire for it. Yet Kant looks at originality in art largely from an non-artistsâ perspective, and he does not overcome the limitations of this perspective to better define artistic processes. In retrospect, the problems of attribution discussed in Chapter IV provide an ample explanation for Kantâs view of originality. 217 And MacIntyreâs theory of internal goods also points to Kantâs lack of detailed analysis of artists or artworks as a symptom of his ascription of metaphysical properties to some artists. The mistake of highlighting the appearance of originality as excellence, however, does not mean Kantâs theory of judgment is irreparable. With his observations of exemplarity, Kant locates beauty and genius in relation to subordination and anticipates educational problems. The model of historical consciousness developed in Chapter VI makes clearer the matter of originality in the arts. According to this model, to understand a work of art as an original, one foregrounds it against something that already exists. If the claim of originality is to have teeth, then it is implied that it is foregrounded against a sufficient set of things. This need not be a comprehensive claim about all aspects of the work of art, but merely an attribute we value. This weak claim of originality is still tenable. If, for example, artists consider Picasso to be a genius, and they give evidence for this claim by pointing to his depiction of suffering, then they are saying, in effect, that the Weeping Woman makes a kind of suffering available to us that was not previously portrayed in art. The boldness of this claim, and ultimately its truthfulness, rests on our understanding of tradition; it is strengthened by our relative expertise on both suffering and artful depictions of suffering. 218 3.3 Exemplarity On Kantâs account, geniuses create original and exemplary works of art, yet these qualities are only partly intelligible against his conception of beauty. The analysis of originality partly sharpens our understanding of geniusâKantâs thinking on the matter is convoluted, and others have draw out its significance. Exemplarity is entirely another matter. More questions arise than are settled by Kantâs conception of aesthetics, but his discussion of the role of exemplarity in art practice offers yet more clues about his understanding of genius. In this section I show how exemplarity can be decoupled from the myth of originality, and how this modifies Kantâs theory of taste in a useful way. To make clear how beautiful art differs from mere mechanical art (art that one can learn to make), Kant notes that there is indeed a mechanical element to all art of genius, and that it is an essential condition (Kant, 1793/2000, p. 188). The mechanical element serves as an end for genius, without which a work of genius would be âa mere product of chanceâ (p. 189). This appearance of âacademic correctnessâ is combined with âthe originality of his talentâ in âthe character of geniusâ and his work (p. 189). Kant warns against the presumption that originality alone is proof of genius, and slights young artists who blow off academic training. âGenius can only provide rich material for products of art; its elaboration and form require a talent that has been academically trained, in order to make a use of it that can stand up to the power of 219 judgmentâ (p. 189). This emphasis on elaboration, details, and form follows from his discussion of imitation. Kant determines that beautiful art serves âas a model not for copying, but for imitationâ (Kant, 1793/2000, p. 188)âa distinction which seems to gesture to the ephemeral process of art making, and not merely the result. He continues, âthe ideas of the artist arouse similar ideas in his apprentice if nature has equipped him with a similar proportion of mental powersâ (p. 188). This shows the process of manifesting genius in art to be much more complex than seems possible by his earlier definition that entailed a view of nature. He also describes the models of art as âthe only means for transmitting [rules of nature] posterityâ (p. 188). Though the end of imitation is not yet clear, it appears to be a strange and important affair. Interestingly, Kant also says genius âcannot itself describe or indicate scientifically how it brings its product into beingâ (p. 187). The author of beautiful art, he says, cannot know how the âideas for itâ came into being, and cannot communicate to others how to produce similar objects (p. 187). Given this claim, did Kant envision artists speculating about the origins of their art and being wildly wrong?80 And what effect might this have on students learning to make art? 80 The intellectual provenance of a product of genius should be of great interest to art educators. With everything that can go into an artwork, it would seem there is still plenty to talk about, but the extent to which nature imparts beauty in art without corresponding knowledge in the artist will have consequences for the expected outcomes of art education. 220 Since artworks attributed to genius are often executed with great skill, the argument goes, genius is therefore often equated with skill.81 Kant maintains, however, that genius cannot be taught. He does not say art making cannot be learned, but rather that the quality of fineness is not directly a product of education. This makes sense if we consider the kind of attention to detail one student might possess relative to another. When skill accompanies such attentiveness, it is often the case that students are lauded as future artists, but Kantâs qualification that genius should not be equated with skill challenges this conception of excellence. This disjunction, along with the emphasis on originality, should thus be understood as a clarification about the matter of development. Kant is claiming that artists possess a power that is necessary for the production of beautiful art prior to education. Hence, the appearance of beauty is only an outward clue of an artistâs so-called âinnate talent.â Kant argues that the âfacility for learningâ does not count as genius (Kant, 1793/2000, p. 187). Since he qualifies this remark by stating that âlearning is nothing but imitation,â I take him to be referring to a procedural kind of learning such as rote memorization. He makes a further claim that a person who âinventsâ in art and science, and who is considered a âgreat mindâ may still not be a genius âsince just this sort of thing could also have been learned, and thus still lies on the natural path of inquiry and 81 I am hard-pressed to come up with counterexamples. To those who would object to this point by invoking the work of some modern and postmodern artists, I would point to artists such as Cy Twombly who are understood as possessing great skill by art critics. As with so many areas of artistic specialty, the uneducated viewer is often at a disadvantage to recognize meticulous or thoughtful production techniques. Even the âblank canvasesâ of minimalism are more complicated than they first appear. 221 reflectionâ (p. 187). This distinction raises problems for recognizing genius, and maybe Kant does not intend for such identifications to take place. He may only be proposing the theory to serve as an explanation for certain kinds of art. Education cannot, on this view, transform someone into a genius who was not already so disposed to be transformed. The importance of education, however, remains an open question. The matters of skill and communication lead to additional insights about exemplarity. Kant describes a âweakâ kind of art education in the following way: [S]uch a skill cannot be communicated, but is apportioned to each immediately from the hand of nature, and thus dies with him, until nature one day similarly endows another, who needs nothing more than an example in order to let the talent of which he is aware operate in a similar way. (Kant, 1793/2000, p. 188)82 Two new aspects of art making are proposed by this passage: 1) every artist is unique, and 2), the genius needs at least one example to activate his genius. What kind of example does this need to be? This passageâs proximity to the discussion of the work of genius as exemplary suggests understanding this work as such a model. If this is the case, then Kant is offering a glimpse of a world where genius effectively passes from person to another. At the risk of suggesting exemplarity is merely a result of judgment, a question should be put to Kant: If the products of genius serve as models, whom exactly do they serve and to what end? Both questions, the for whom and the for what, are important. 82 The personification of nature hereâthe hand of nature bestowing talent on a newborn artistâis telling of Kantâs aversion to an explanation that directly invokes God. Even though he turns to theology in his critique of the teleological power of judgment, he pushes back the problem here and consistently refers to nature as the source of genius. 222 There are multiple ways in which art can be a modelânot just as a model for other art, for example, but as a religious totem or a political touchstone. Cases where art serves as a model for the creation of other art just happen to be a central concern for art educators. Kant may be proposing that there are some artists who are geniuses and some who are not, but then this begs an educational question: why are non-geniuses striving to make âmerelyâ decorative art? Kant may otherwise be proposing that while imitating art cannot be educational for genius, imitation can serve some other end for the artist-genius. That is, he grants that there are features of the world that supervene on the production of art. To grant that art may not always be a contemplation of morality reflects diverse traditions in the artworld since Kantâs time (or, if they are actually ânew,â then they should be seen as elaborations and expansions of traditional possibilities or tendencies in art). Modern art pushed the boundaries of the traditional artworldâits practitioners and its institutionsâin ways that defied âconservativeâ expectations. Ugly art, for example, became a real possibility as the meaning of beauty was brought under further scrutiny in the twentieth century. In wider artworld discourses, this shift underscores the meaning of the term âModernismâ and makes sense of much twentieth century art and art practices. Kant has not yet heard this news. Originality and exemplarity imply a strange kind of audience. Originality implies the audience is cut off from tradition. Exemplarity, a less ephemeral quality than originality, suffers a similar fate in Kantâs work, but resonates as a nascent recognition of the importance of tradition in art practices. Kant 223 does not explain why a work of art is more often understood as exemplary than the artist who made it, but artists today should strive to know more than Kant so art does not serve as a superficial basis of judgment. One outcome of the critique of genius is, therefore, an imperative for artists to take responsibility for the reception of their work. As Collingwood (1938/1958) observed, âwe have inherited a long tradition, beginning in the late eighteenth century with the cult of 'genius', and lasting all through the nineteenth, which is inimical to thisâ (p. 312). The critique of genius has the potential to release the artistâs moral impulse to assume that responsibility. 3.4 Summary Taken together and in order, developments in philosophy reflectâindeed, help bring aboutâmoral qualities of art. Kantâs and Gadamerâs contributions further problematize the achievement of subordination, though I argue their philosophies position us to better understand the features of such relationshipsârelationships MacIntyre implicates in the ongoing livelihood and development of practices. The implications for education will be explored further in Chapter VIII. Art, it seems, can be an intermediary through which one genius may serve as a model for another genius. Thus, the work of art is not strictly the modelâthe beauty of artistic products serves to strengthen the perception of the artist as a model. For the moral nature of artistic genius to come alive, the qualities of a work of art essentially must be mapped onto the artistâfor then exemplarity is intelligible as a characteristic 224 of genius. Does it make sense to call genius more or less than this? The circumstances that lead up to and shape the creation of a work of art, however, are often a barrier to intelligibility. Defining excellence with art practice in mind is a matter of adopting a framework for understanding art making, which, if it is done well, will expand and amplify the view of morality I have articulated above. We need more philosophies of art. We need more moral philosophies. But each of us should strive to construct one philosophy we can live by. I have here sought to critique the concept of genius in such a way as to make it compatible with a paradigm for my art practiceâmy paradigm by virtue that it both incorporates and propels my philosophizing, and a shared paradigm so far as it enables participation among a greater community. While these communities are inconstant (and judgments about art are often arbitrary and capricious), genius can be rightly understood as an achievable ideal. 4. The Moral Wilderness To adopt the view of morality I articulated in Chapters IVâVII is to somewhat reverse directions from MacIntyreâs hope that morality can âemerge from the wildernessâ (MacIntyre, 1958). The diversity of traditions within tradition means practices are likely to be fertile ground for educational experiences, but not at all as elegantly ordered as MacIntyre imagines. I suspect MacIntyre denies teaching is a practice because something like a âunity of the virtuesâ is less important in a world 225 where teachers attend to the needs of individual, motivated learners. Having scrutinized the kind of experience students must have to achieve excellence, it is clear that the matter of trust is more important than unity. Genius, as a philosophical model of excellence, may be most useful where trust is lacking. Moral philosophers who imagine a top-down model of moral personality propose a theory of unity where philosophy, as a higher-order virtue, engenders rational and principled action. The critique of genius challenges this picture of morality. The theory of hermeneutic excellence (qua subordination) as an educational good is not meant to replace the theory of unity, but displace it. The quality of a personâs relationship to tradition is meant to be open to interpretation, and theoretically up-for-grabs. Whereas moral philosophers have, in the past, positioned philosophical thinkingâreflectionâas central to the good life, I am proposing we adopt a decentralized, distributed (across practices) view of moral excellenceâmoral excellence as the achievement of subordination. Though I do not settle this dispute here, it is now possible to pose several related questions. First, since genius is a helpful rubric for excellence for art practice, I wonder if we can postulate an ethics where practices are seen as ends in themselves, where no explanation of âhypergoodsâ is necessary. This would be tantamount to a vision of moral life where individuals are understood as ordering and balancing the pull of multiple practices in no particular wayâa very different view than one where we are always guided by a shared telos such as democracy, freedom, etc. 226 Second, if there are such shared visions of the good, is genius a more prevalent and relevant telos in the contemporary world than other conceptions? This would go along with the argument that individualism is a key self-conception of our age. If this were a more fruitful way to predict behavior and intervene in social systems, then it should displace âvirtueâ as an overarching model of ethics. For this to be a meaningful change, it would have to be shown what the key distinctions between virtue and genius are, in short, the difference between a genealogy of the good and a genealogy of tradition. Such a change may sidestep some frequent mistakes of ethical discourse. The question is not whether or not such a change is right, but whether it is right for us. Given the far reach of formal education in the world today, I believe the discourse of genius is not only more accessible, but more likely to culminate in diverse and fruitful lives. The discourses of virtue, ethics, and especially morality are too easily shortcircuited by the question of âright and wrong.â Another question that it is now possible to ask points in a different direction. If hermeneutic excellence is extremely difficult to achieve (and only partly because of our prejudices about excellence), why not leave it to chance? That is, why should educators stake their livelihood on a project with such a low probability of success? This handsoff approach would not be so different from the current state of affairs in the artworld (in and beyond educational institutions) where we simply let persons who are ânaturallyâ inclined to make art do what they prefer to do, and do not actively encourage 227 everyone else to participate in art practices.83 Presumably, there would be enough artists working on diverse enough projects to fulfill the current demand for aesthetic objectsâespecially given the increasingly powerful scope of broadcasting and networking technologies. While this may indeed âsuffice,â an initial objection could be that it fails on account of other values we have and will likely continue to have. It abdicates our responsibility as educators, which is (on a so-called âliberalâ or âhumanisticâ account) to give every person an extended opportunity to explore his or her interest in diverse practices. Art educators are especially likely to bristle at the option of leaving art to chance, knowing firsthand the kind of experiences hands-on participation in the arts make possible. This underscores the premise that we value such experience in the first place, but this might not always be the case. Rejecting âgeniusâ and embracing âluckâ as a substitute for exemplarity cuts against the value we currently place on achievement, but could potentially inspire the sameâor even betterâdevelopmental outcomes educators deem valuable. This speculation reminds us that conceptualizing a moral nature of genius remains problematic for theory even when it increases our understanding of art, artists, and art practice. But theory always challenges practiceâcritique is at once a resolution to this tension, and a symptom of it. And understanding, philosophers 83 There are many amazing exceptions to this charge, and I do not mean to diminish them. Good schools, good museums, and good artists all contribute to the promotion of the arts. Still, is it not possible to go further? 228 remind us, is valuable in its own right. In the next and final Chapter, I turn to practical outcomes for pedagogy that follow from the kind of relationships that an awareness of genius, as a disposition for inheriting and solving the problems of a practice, has been shown to make possible. 229 VIIIâWHY EDUCATION MATTERS 1. Where We Are Now Where the moral nature of genius is eclipsed by a modern preoccupation with âintelligence,â the hermeneutic power of genius is foreclosed. Thoughtful and productive artists are met with saccharine appreciation instead of commitments to engage in a shared process of understanding. The conceptual rehabilitation of genius offers artists a strategy to recapture the imagination that overly hegemonic and sterile institutions threaten to command and sell back to society in piecemeal. Likewise, an awareness of artistsâ historical task has the potential to strengthen artistsâ public image as conveyors of important human truths. There is much confusion in communities of art education, on a philosophical level, about what constitutes success in art practices and the arts in general. The concept of genius sheds light on the matter. Its rehabilitation has implications for all artists, and especially those artists who act as frontline ambassadors of the artworld: art educators. Reclaiming this instrumental concept is part of the project of getting 230 subordination right. This will not, however, be the end of the struggle for educators. Just as genius may be misinterpreted as unrelated to hermeneutic excellence, artistic inquiry will continue to tread a thin line between Kantâs ârationalisticâ science and postmodernismâs âmoral relativism.â The first mistake will be to equate inquiry about genius with artistic inquiry, and teachers will be responsible for helping students understand the special nature of art making as inquiry. Genius is an historically and theoretically bounded framework for evaluating artists and their practices. It captures the force of artistsâ ambitions as they aspire to investigate and innovateânot dwell in delusion and dissatisfactionâand uphold art practice as a thoroughgoing educational activity. The interpersonal dynamic of hermeneutic excellence makes this possible, of which the achievement and development of subordination in educational settings is only an initial outcome. 2. Awareness of Genius There are a few ways in which genius can âmatterâ for education. One theme of my study is to highlight the importance of the appearance of verticality in art practice for subordinationâthis is the sense that geniuses support the education of other artists as makers art. The other way to put this is that the concept of genius draws artists further into art practice. My critique of genius is at once a premise and an outcome of this view. That is, I employ a hermeneutic tactic to make the critiqueâmy 231 primary argumentâstronger: I argue that verticality is important because it leads to important recognition on behalf of students, and at the same time I claim subordination (a potential result of that recognition) can strengthen a communityâs agreement about which practitioners are eminent. This agreement, in turn, makes verticality possible. Additionally, I argue (in Chapter VI) that this outcome can make the eminent practitioner more excellent (including, but not limited to, more hermeneutically excellent). Thus, I show that hermeneutic excellence is at least partially constitutive of genius, and argue that in conjunction with the production of communicative art, it should be understood as the essence of the concept. There is a need to tailor the concept of genius to fit this view, which I argue is possible alongside a rehabilitation of the historical concept vis-à-vis Kantâs view of nature. If one rejects the idea that the concept can be so rehabilitated, then a weaker version of my primary argument still holds: excellent artists will be shown to do the work of sustaining and extending a tradition of inquiry by orienting their art practice within a community in the special way disclosed by philosophical hermeneutics. Admittedly, this is a less innovative theory, as it does not depart too far from MacIntyreâs view of practice and Gadamerâs view of tradition. It does, however, show the special concept of tradition to be deepened by the special concept of practice, and visa versa. A synthesis between this theory and the problem of genius, however, captures the meaning of moral excellence in a more powerful way. There are many possible objections to this philosophical undertaking. One can object to 1) my positioning of ethics as a meaningful discourse for art, 2) my 232 modifications to MacIntyreâs ethics, 3) the subsuming of hermeneutics under ethics, 4) my interpretation of Kantâs metaphysics and its significance for morality, and 5) my regard for the role of philosophy in art practice. I have tried to address all these objections in the previous chapters, but often only implicitly. An explicit defense of all these grounds will not be made here, as I believe they are already made elsewhere, and more often than not, more deftly than I can manage. For example, I do not intend to âproveâ that subordination occurs, nor respond to critics who dislike the term. The underlying assumption that subordination is important may be brought under greater scrutiny. For the defense of this view, I must defer to MacIntyreâs ethics. This is just one tactic to defer a conversation on âfinal ends,â for whether or not subordination is understood as important within practices, or whether or not skepticism bears on the role, definition, or even the existence of practices, this requires another inquiry with a different foundation than the present one. Psychology may provide even better conceptual tools for analysis of the matter of subordination, but it will still lack the ideological grounding MacIntyreâs theory provides. Indeed, there will be as many objections as there are threads of other philosophical arguments supporting my critique. For my part, I will parse the implications of my critique in a few more important ways. Genius can also âmatterâ for education in the sense that the concept supports the ethical framework I articulated in Chapters I, II, and V. This is a significant recentering of the discourse of morality in relation to the arts, and achieves the goal of further developing virtue ethics with art practice in mind. This offers artists a way to 233 think about ethics in relation to art practice, and therefore strengthens the interdisciplinary relationship between art and philosophy. I call attention to an âawareness of geniusâ and not âawareness of the concept of geniusâ because it is only the former that is constitutive of the phenomenon my critique seeks to explain. The latter is a distinctly philosophical experience that is not necessarily achieved (to a matter of degree) alongside the former. It is the awareness of geniuses that arises from the awareness of tradition that forms the foundation of the experience of subordination. From MacIntyreâs account of the three registers of moral life, we have extracted a narrower and more descriptive theory of artistic genius. Not only is genius an intersection of practice, narrative, and tradition, but now the concept signifies the way artists relate to one another, learn from each other, and develop as members of community. Coinciding with this ethical framework is a new space for art teachers to discuss the meaning of art, and these discussions are helpfully bounded by rich historical and theoretical material. Teachers may welcome such a perspective, especially those teachers who also work as âprofessionalâ artists. They may benefit intellectually, as well as professionally in two senses: as professional artists and as professional teachers. They may see their own work as an artist in a new light, and reconsider their role as teachers as well. I will discuss the implications for pedagogy in the following section. There are even more compelling conclusions to draw from the critique of genius. That is, there are educational implicationsâways that education matters for the cultivation and manifestation of genius. The knowledge that a genius is (and has 234 been) supported by his or her educational surroundings allows us to see art education in a new way. Entertaining these implications means we have come a long way from the Romantic view of genius as an innate gift or talent. And Kantâs metaphysics will never be the same again. But neither will the view that âeveryone is a geniusâ (or even potentially a genius) be tenable. The details of subordination and hermeneutic excellence make clear that there is a long road ahead for artists who will one day be rightfully understood as geniuses. Geniuses, however, still have the potential to cause real harm in practices, especially practices that are delicate enterprises like art making. One might ask, âif X can do Y so much better, why should I do Y at all?â While such doubt is unlikely to change our moral orientation, it could easily derail endeavors that are complex, frustrating at times, and not easily evaluated. The sense that the recognition of genius is a matter of luck remains. But to the extent that we are complicit in that recognition, we can be conscious of the kind of activity that accompanies the creation of works of art that merit that recognition. As far as I can tell, there is no need to be decisive about what kind of commitment to the arts or a community that such recognition need entail. A person may produce one piece of meaningful art in his lifetime, or he may produce thousandsâeither way, he may become a model for other artists. But this far from automatic. Those who care about art practices must account for the success of individuals who are recognized as geniuses, including the geniuses themselves, if not only for the sake of oneâs own clear-minded orientation in a practice, then for the vitality of the educational institutions that support the ongoing life of the practice. 235 Formal education is influential here for two reasons: 1) it consists of institutions that support the work of artists, and 2) those institutions can make available the moral tradition that includes the critique of genius. Though these two aims intersect with one another, they are slightly different. The former aim can be understood as a broad aim in terms of praxisâthere are many ways for artists to become more excellent, and as many ways for institutions to attend to that development. The latter aim, however, refers more directly to an artistâs intellectual and emotional sense of himself or herself. The critique of genius serves critical functions when it is situated within institutions of education. The several ways philosophy can make a difference for art practice are as follows: 1) The art community, and therefore art practice, is disjoined from its tradition by excessive historicism. 2) Arguments for creativity and aesthetic experience further isolate the arts from existing paradigms of inquiry, and have been rather unhelpful from a philosophical perspective. Given modern preoccupations with identity, the critique of genius is well suited for art educators. 1) It respects the dialogical limitations of the classroom by acknowledging the private life of students and teachers. 2) A critique of genius empowers educators to modify their teaching practice, without losing their autonomy. 3) Students take advice from educators seriously (e.g., because of the educational context or the teacherâs work as an artist). 4) A teacher can use his or her judgment to guide a student to look at a particular work of art in its context. 236 Why does other exposure to the artworld not suffice? 1) One does not know how to look for the salient parts of other artistsâ practices (one does not see the âmessy bitsâ). 2) One does not automatically get a sense of the purpose of art practice that is related to the purpose of inquiry. Art is often reduced to glossy pictures of finished pieces (although it need not be, it all too easily is). Artworks in galleries and museums are not presented as âworksâ of a living project, but âpiecesâ of the representational (i.e. modernist) world. At best, art becomes a theory. At worst, it is only a commodity. There are also disadvantages to the framework of hermeneutic excellence. Art educators might ignore hermeneutic excellence and remain silent about paradigms that support art education. This is understandable, as the subjectivization of aesthetics has rendered art impotent in relation to other disciplines in institutions of education. Remaining silent about the relation between knowledge about art and knowledge in general essentially insulates art educators from both internal and external criticism. That is, it is just too easy for artists and art teachers to be misunderstood. This quietism likely has the undesirable effect of changing the environment of art education. Instead of widespread and common discussion leading to shared inquiry, inquiry, and therefore knowledge, is intensely local and parochial. This fragmentation brings about a breakdown of (or circumvents a development of) the social structures that engender and support trust within the art community. Subordination that is not systematically supported may develop haphazardly and not be adequately sustained. Or it may not occur at all. 237 3. Implications for Pedagogy Can a certain kind of âopennessâ on the part of the teacher invite subordination? Several pedagogical options come to mind. 1) Teachers can point out similarities between studentsâ art and well-known artists (but this is not very compelling). 2) They can demonstrate their intellectual depth with insightful comments/remarks (this too seems uninspired). 3) They can model a relationship to a tradition or community of inquiry. Since the classroom can be a site of ongoing dialogue, educators have an advantage over their professional peers in conveying their knowledge of art practice, and I will discuss these strategies in this section. Small differences in how artists relate to each other may affect artistic processes and outcomes. There are many ways hermeneutic excellence is currently highlighted in the studio classroom. Consider the following scenarios. Professors often have students study the practices of other artists. They might point a particular student to a particular artist. Professors make observations about studentsâ work. They might make specific comments about one aspect of a process, effect, or habit. They might relate this one thing to something another artist is known to do. From the perspective of hermeneutics, they make connectionsâbetween students and professional artists; between students and other people or ideas; from one student to another; from one artist to another; and so on. These are some aspects of life in the studio classroom, and they are, we imagine, essential components of art education. 238 But does the possibility of subordination arise? Or as Maxine Greene might ask, when does a studentâs future open up to new possibilities? Any one of these possible connections might be a sufficient experience on a given day. But in my own experience, nothing came quite as close as those experiences wherein I felt increasingly connected to a community. Activities where I was asked to work with another student made the work of art come alive. (e.g., swapping drawings, a mural where everyone participates, even group critique.) But there was one persistent problem: none of my classmates were professional artists (although it was exciting to work with those few who were more interested, versatile, etc.). Why did the most advanced artist in the room never fully bring her self into the conversation or classroom activity? Why was a practice of art making not being modeled in the liveliest way possible? The professor is a unique representative of the artworld: a living, practicing, experienced person with connections to a wider community of artists. There are, however, numerous other reasons a professor might choose to not share her art practice with her students: habit, doubt, shyness, an educational philosophy, time constraints, a lack of a method for doing so, etc. Does the concept of hermeneutic excellence provide a compelling story that trumps these reasons? I argue that it does, and I believe there is more to say elsewhere about how it does according to a picture of art as a mode of naturalistic inquiry. It is only important to consider how this sharing is bounded by how hermeneutic excellence is recognizable in the first place. Were a professor to make available certain aspects of his own art practice to his students, he would be inviting students to enter into an already messy domain of 239 understanding, interpretation, and meaning making. How would he present his practice in an open but accurate way when it is probably the case that he is an artist for the very reason that he would rather âshowâ than âtellâ? Indeed, in this case of a professor communicating anything, the articulation itself is a traditionary event for his students. So, should we be optimistic that he could portray his hermeneutic excellence visually? For that matter, can any artist who takes on a project other than one that explicitly draws attention to the subject of hermeneutics? I have my doubts. How can one prompt an audience to attend to what is essentially the methodological component of art practice? Such precision would seem to come at too high a price, and this worry may be similarly applied to any orchestrated discussion of a âpractice.â Perhaps to successfully negotiate such a process of understanding (the kind imagined above) between a professor and her students, everyone involved would have to be aware of the âeducational languagesâ they speak, and enter into the dialogue with a sense of what is at stakeâwhy, for example, a decision to deploy a cubist strategy for depicting space created the right emotional atmosphere that the painting needed to convey a sense of sadness to a certain audience; and how this decision arose from an offhanded remark by a cantankerous friend about a George Braque painting. This seems a bit ambitious for the undergraduate studio. Young artists are likely to experience skepticism about art practiceâperhaps a symptom of a perceived lack of talent. They may also find themselves confronting the problem of relativism without proper philosophical tools (i.e., âwhy should I choose to make art rather than to do X?â). Not surprisingly, art teachers have a variety of 240 classroom strategies to help students resist and overcome this existential crisis (e.g., by acting as role models, giving students positive feedback, leading them through helpful exercises, and so on). But art education is not always so structured, and art teachers may not always deliver the psychological goods, so to speak. More likely, it seems a student must be particularly ready to appreciate (or, to interpret) a moment of hermeneutic excellence. And perhaps less sweeping recommendations for curricular structures can produce more dramatic results. How? Consider the case where a professor divulges too much information. Unrealistic expectations about the kinds of lives artists are supposed to lead are set in motion in culture at large. Professors, who are not usually on the short list of artists likely to be reviewed in the âArtsâ section of The New York Times and whose work will likely not be studied by art historians, are caught in a bind. Should they not direct studentsâ attention towards âmodelâ (and therefore archetypal) artists? And they do. And one can imagine the line of thought going: âWould it not be presumptuous to inject my own art and artistic process into the educational dialogue at this point?â What about those moments when reaching for the art history book is too much? What about a moment when a student who has been deeply engaged in a physical process of scratching a charcoal still life onto paper âcomes up for airâ? A professor, who has been informally circulating around the studio, takes notice and arrives at the studentâs side to be a co-observer of the artwork-in-process. Instead of offering a response that is meant to make connections between this work and the studentâs earlier work, or between this work and a renowned artistâs work, the 241 professor offers up a personal anecdote. âOne time IâŚâ Or, âWhen I was recently trying toâŚâ This is my modest philosophical recommendation. Art educators have a wealth of first-hand experience of negotiating traditionary events. They may not be geniuses in the broadest sense of the concept, but they are granted special access to moments when human life is already open to new possibility. The orientation of practitioners towards excellence of all kinds is only one reason such utterances could make a significant impression on students. Humans are social creatures and communities are ethereal structures we desire to create and inhabit. Books, videos, and the Internet are media that cannot produce the possible richness of exchanges between teachers and students. Dialogues between individuals that emerge and take shape over time have the greatest educational possibility in the studio. Provoking, guiding, and shaping dialogue is the responsibility of educators interested in nourishing studentsâ attachment to the intellectual and emotional work of art making. How every student learns to cultivate his or her own hermeneutic excellence depends on how thoughtfully welcoming each ambassador of the larger community of working artists chooses to be. 4. The Future of Art Education The integration of art making and higher education is troubling for both art and education. Current trends in education are a result of different conceptions of art, 242 artists, and art making which have supported different and often conflicting strategies to fit artists into educational institutions (Efland, 1990; Singerman, 1999). Art educators should better define art as inquiry, and then justify the claim that studio artists can and should learn how to do it. As I demonstrated above, what I refer to as inquiry begins where moral and educational philosophies converge around questions about aesthetic, moral, and psychological aspects of art making. There are many histories of art and artists. We are saddled with the history, for example, of an elite group of artists treated as âgiftedâ or âspiritualâ geniuses in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. There is also the history of artwork that aspires to transform its viewers, and yet another that speaks to the formalistic content in artwork, and how this content reflects changes in the material and economic life of the artist. And so on. If some art educators have been proponents of the notion that âonly the few persons destined to achieve greatness as artists,â then at least they were not alone. On confronting history, we may find that art educators have been influenced by the work of aestheticians, historians, and critics, but the complexity of tracing back the influence of the concept of genius on art education should by now be clear. While I one could argue that throughout history people have connected the creation/invention of âgood artâ to genius, it is just as likely that this is false. It is difficult to imagine, beyond the horizon of our own culture, what it means for a person to be a genius. Of the many modern concepts bound up in the concept of genius, perhaps the most troublesome for us is that of individuality. And for cultures that differ from our own (e.g.: England in the eighteenth century, the Renaissance in Italy, 243 or Platoâs Athens), it is difficult what to make of selfhoodâand how individuals defined themselves in terms of activities like art making. The concept of genius is on unsteady historical ground because different systems of apprenticeship, different sources of inspiration, and different social landscapes lead to a very different artistic identity. Even the notion of âartistâ can mislead us, suggesting as it does a Romantic vision of creation rather than subordination. Due to these historical tensions, art educators must turn inwards, as well as to tradition, to define art education. If, for example, the undergraduate studio classroom exists firstly for the purpose of making art, and there are many supposedly valid conceptions of what art is, then what seems to be an ideal state of affairs for the artworld is bad for students in institutions of liberal education: there is no ready-made educational paradigm (i.e., âcurriculumâ) to help students become forward-thinking art practitioners. This concern is reflected in current educational research. While postmodernism widen studentsâ conceptions of art and promote diversity (Stinespring, 2001), this is not itself a curriculum that supports inquiry as a goal for art education. Without such a shared foundation, can teachers locate their educative practice on an institutional map? How can they justify their work as practitioners in liberal education without articulating their relationship to a productive and fruitful tradition of art? Presently, teachers cope with this lack of orientation at the classroom level, but make very few systematic or sustained efforts to reconcile art making with inquiry or liberal learning. Consequently, art students are not initiated into a community that is in step with knowledge-centered traditions of higher education, and studio programs 244 are undervalued as sites of rigorous study. In contrast to this state of affairs, art teachers should be able to articulate the relationship between art making and liberal education and art students (i.e., students in the studio classroom) should contribute practice-specific knowledge to the academic community. There are strong traditions of inquiry in the visual arts, and practitioners in higher education should embrace them as the pillars of an educational paradigm that is able to guide students who will inevitably work within diverse traditions of art. Studio education should no longer concern only the technical aspects of art makingâin addition to a modicum of art history, art theory, and art criticism, art students should pose philosophical questions in the studio to understand the knowledge that is embodied in art. Art and philosophy can be moral in this broad sense: they are sites for questions such as âWhy make art?â and âWhy choose the life of an artist?â which are variations of Socratesâ question, âHow should one live?â The current dearth of moral philosophy, so construed, in the context of art making in higher education means that this important aspect of art proceeds only haphazardly, if at allâeach student in the studio classroom exists in relation to a milieu of popular (and unpopular) conceptions of art by himself or herself. Understanding art making as a context for inquiry should change our expectations for art education within the culture of higher education. In this way, art practitioners will be able to add their voices to conversations about the intersection of art and the world by making art, and also by reading, thinking, and entering a dialogue about ideas, values, and beliefs that are conceived and analyzed in wider discourse. 245 Art practitioners need a theory that responds to the discord between art making and education at the institutional level. My dissertation may affirm the role of certain side-constraints on teachers, students, and curriculums, but it also demonstrates that art programs supported by an educational philosophy have the potential to support, sustain, and carry forward the vital work of art making. By addressing art making in this way, my philosophical argument contributes to the scholarship it advocates by both reclaiming art inquiry as one essential component of liberal education and locating its place among other disciplines. A moral theory that identifies how studio education is fit for the culture of inquiry of higher education should have clear consequences for pedagogy and offer practical guidance when we confront educational problems. The critique of genius, carefully construed, is a vital part of such a theory. 246 REFERENCES Albert, R. S. (Ed.). (1983). Genius and Eminence: The Social Psychology of Creativity and Exceptional Achievement. New York: Pergamon Press. Alicke, M. D., LoSchiavo, F. M., Zerbst J., & Zhang S. (1997). The Person Who Outperforms Me is a Genius: Maintaining Perceived Competence in Upward Social Comparison. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73(4), 781789. Argall, T. G. (2006). The Night We Killed the Lobster. Retrieved on March 27, 2006, from http://www3.sympatico.ca/tg_argall/Lobster.htm Aristotle (2000). Nichomachean Ethics. Oxford: Cambridge University Press. Armstrong, T. (1998). Awakening Genius in the Classroom. Retrieved February 20, 2003, from http://www.netlibrary.com/ebook_info.asp?product_id=42219 Barzun, J. (1989). The Paradoxes of Creativity. The American Scholar, 58(3), 337-351. Bekkala, E. (2001). The Development of Artists at Rhode Island School of Design. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Teachers College, Columbia University, New York. Bernstein, J. M. (1992). The Fate of Art. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press. ______. (1995). Recovering Ethical Life: Jürgen Habermas and the Future of Critical Theory. New York: Routledge. Blacker, D. (1999). Complex Equality and Democratic Education: The Challenge of Walzerâs Spherical Pluralism. Educational Theory, 49(2), 181-206. 247 Bromwich, D. (1985). Reflections on the Word Genius. New Literary History, 17(1), 141-164. Bubner, R. (1994). On the Ground of Understanding (B. Wachterhauser, Trans.). In Wachterhauser, B. (Ed.) Hermeneutics and Truth. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. Carr, D. (2003). Rival Conceptions of Practice in Education and Teaching. Journal of Philosophy and Education, 37(2), 253-266. Carr, D. & Steutel, J. (Eds.). (1999). Virtue Ethics and Moral Education. London: Routledge. Choi, H. (2001). Harry Broudyâs Theory of Aesthetic Education as General Education. Unpublished doctoral thesis, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Colby, M. (1995). Narrativity and Ethical Relativism. European Journal of Philosophy, 3, 132-156. Collingwood, R. G. (1938/1958). The Principles of Art. New York: Oxford University Press. Coltman, R. (1998). The Language of Hermeneutics: Gadamer and Heidegger in Dialogue. New York: State University of New York Press. Coraor, J. E. (1985). The Performative Aspects of Viewing Art: An Existential Grounding of Art in Foundational Education. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, The Pennsylvania State University. Costantino, T. (2002). Problem-Based Learning: A Concrete Approach to Teaching Aesthetics. Studies in Art Education, 43(3), 219-231. Crawford, D. (2003). Kant's Theory of Creative Imagination. In Guyer, P. (Ed.), Kantâs Critique of the Power of Judgment: Critical Essays. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. Crease, R. P. (1997). Hermeneutics and the Natural Sciences. Man and World, 30(3), 259-270. Cyr, L.-P. (2000). A Conversation Between Sculptor and Stone. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Teachers College, Columbia University, New York. 248 Daloz, L. A. (1986). Effective Teaching and Mentoring. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Danto, A. C. (1984). The End of Art. In Lang, B. (Ed.), The Death of Art. New York: Haven Publishing. _____. (1992). Beyond the Brillo Box: The Visual Arts in Post-Historical Perspective. New York: The Noonday Press. Davis, J. (2000). Metacognition and Multiplicity: The Arts as Models and Agents. Educational Psychology Review, 12(3), 339-359. Devettere, R. J. (2002). Introduction to Virtue Ethics: Insights of the Ancient Greeks. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press. Dewey, J. (1909/1975). Moral Principles in Education. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press. _____. (1916/1966). Democracy and Education. New York: The Free Press. _____. (1934/1980). Art as Experience. New York: Pedigee Books. Dickie, G. (1996). The Century of Taste: The Philosophical Odyssey of Taste in the Eighteenth Century. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Duddy, T. (1999). Teaching the Unteachable: Art and the Ideology of Genius. CIRCA 89 Art Education Supplement. Retrieved October 4, 2004, from http://www.recirca.com/backissues/c89/supp_duddy.shtml Duffus, R. L. (1928). The American Renaissance. New York: Alfred Knopf. Eames, S. M. (1977). Pragmatic Naturalism: An Introduction. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press. Eaton, M. M. (1997). Aesthetics: The Mother of Ethics? The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 55(4), 355-364. Eaton, M. M. & Moore, R. (2002). Aesthetic Experience: Its Revival and Its Relevance to Aesthetic Education. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 36(2), 9-23. Efland, A. (1990). A History of Art Education: Intellectual and Social Currents in Teaching the Visual Arts. New York: Teachers College Press. 249 Eisner, E. & Peshking, A. (Eds.). (1990). Qualitative Inquiry in Education: The Continuing Debate. New York: Teachers College Press. Eldridge, R. (1989). On Moral Personhood: Philosophy, Literature, Criticism, and SelfUnderstanding. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. ______. (1997). Leading a Human Life: Wittgenstein, Intentionality, and Romanticism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. ______. (2001). The Persistence of Romanticism. New York: Cambridge University Press. Eliot, T. S. (1922). Tradition and the Individual Talent. Retrieved November 7, 2004, from http://www.bartleby.com/200/sw5.html Eysenck, H. J. (1995). Genius: The Natural History of Creativity. New York: Cambridge University Press. Festinger, L. (1954). A Theory of Social Comparisons Processes. Human Relations, 1, 117-140. Findlay, J. N. (1981). Kant and the Transcendental Object: A Hermeneutic Study. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Flanagan, O. (1991). Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Foot, P. (1978). Virtues and Vices. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Fowler, C. (1996). Strong Arts, Strong Schools. New York: Oxford University Press. Funk, C. B. (1990). The Development of Professional Studio Art Training in American Higher Education, 1860-1960. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Teachers College, Columbia University, New York. Gadamer, H.-G. (1960/2002). Truth and Method. New York: The Continuum Publishing Company. ______. (1985). Philosophical Apprenticeships (R. R. Sullivan, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ______. (1986). The Relevance of the Beautiful and Other Essays (R. Bernasconi, Ed., N. Walker, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 250 ______. (1992). Hans-Georg Gadamer on Education, Poetry and History: Applied Hermeneutics (D. Misgeld & G. Nicholson, Eds., L. Schmidt & M. Ruess, Trans.). Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Gardner, H. (1993). Creating Minds: An anatomy of creativity seen through the lives of Freud, Einstein, Picasso, Stravinsky, Eliot, Graham, and Gandhi. New York: Basic Books. Garver, N. & Hare, P. H. (Eds.). (1986). Naturalism and Rationality. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books. Geiger, R. L. (Ed.). (2000). The American College in the Nineteenth Century. Vanderbilt Issues in Higher Education. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press. Gilmore, J. C. (1986). Picturing the World. Albany: State University of New York Press. Ghiselin, B. (1952). The Creative Process. Berkeley: U. C. Press. Good, D. (1988). Individuals, Interpersonal Relations, Trust. In D. Gambetta (Ed.), Trust: Making and Breaking Cooperative Relations (pp. 31-48). Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Graham, G. (2003). MacIntyre on History and Philosophy. In M. C. Murphy (Ed.), Alasdair MacIntyre. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gram, M. S. (Ed.). (1982). Interpreting Kant. Iowa City: University of Iowa Press. Greenberg, R. (2001). Kant's Theory of A Priori Knowledge. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press. Greene, M. (1995). Releasing the Imagination. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass Publishers. ______. (2001). Variations on a Blue Guitar. New York: Teachers College Press. Grondin, J. (2003). The Philosophy of Gadamer. Bucks: Acumen Publishing Limited. Gruber, H. E. (1974). Darwin on Man: A Psychological Study of Scientific Creativity. New York: E. P. Dutton. 251 ______. (1989). The Evolving Systems Approach to Creative Work. In Wallace, D. B. & Gruber, H. E. (Eds.), Creative People at Work. New York: Oxford University Press. Guérin, D. (1978). The Writings of a Savage. New York: The Viking Press. Gutmann, A. (1987). Democratic Education. New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Guyer, P. (1979). Kant and the Claims of Taste. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ______. (1994). Kant's Conception of Fine Art. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 52(3), 275-285. Gyorgy, P. (1999). Between and After Essentialism and Institutionalism. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 57(4), 421-437. Hamilton, E. & Cairns, H. (Eds.). (1999). Plato: The Collected Dialogues. Bollingen Series LXXI. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Hansen, D. T. (1995). The Call to Teach. New York: Teachers College Press. ______. (2001). Exploring the Moral Heart of Teaching: Toward a Teacher's Creed. New York: Teachers College Press. Hartmann, S. (1991). Critical Modernist (J. C. Weaver, Ed.). Berkeley: The University of California Press. Haste, H. (1996). Communitarianism and the Social Construction of Morality. Journal of Moral Education 25(1), 47-55. Henrich, D. (1992). Aesthetic Judgment and the Moral Image of the World. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Hicks, J. (1999). It's Catch-up Time for Aesthetics. Art Education, 52 (4), 42-46. Higgins, C. (1998). Practical Wisdom: Educational Philosophy as Liberal Teacher Education. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Teachers College, Columbia University, New York. ______. (2002). Das Glück des Lehrers (The Flourishing of the Teacher). Zeitschrift für Pädagogik, 48(4), 495-513. 252 ______. (2003a). MacIntyre's Moral Theory and the Possibility of an Aretaic Ethics of Teaching. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 37(2), 279-292. ______. (2003b). Teaching and the Good Life: A Critique of the Ascetic Ideal in Education. Educational Theory, 53(2). Hills, A. (2004). Kantian Trust. Retrieved November 7, 2004, from http://www.open2.net/trust/downloads/downloads.htm Horton, J. & Mendus, S. (Eds.). (1994). After MacIntyre: Critical Perspectives on the Work of Alasdair MacIntyre. Cambridge: Polity Press. Hostetler, K. (2003). Solidarity and Moral Community. Retrieved June 15, 2003, from http://www.ed.uiuc.edu/EPS/PES-Yearbook/92_docs/Hostetler.HTM Hughes, B. (2002). What Students Do: MacIntyre's Moral Theory of Education. Unpublished masters thesis, Teachers College, Columbia University, New York. ______. (2005). War Images. New York: The Macy Gallery. Hulbert, A. (2005, November 20). The Prodigy Puzzle. The New York Times Magazine, Section 6. Huizinga, J. (1950). Homo Ludens: A Study of the Play-element in Culture. Boston: Beacon Press. Jaeger, R. M. (Ed.). (1997). Complementary Methods for Research in Education. Washington, D.C.: American Educational Research Association. Johnson, P. A. (2000). On Gadamer. Belmont: Wadsworth. Jones, E. E., & Nisbett, R. E. (1971). The Actor and the Observer: Divergent Perceptions of the Causes of Behavior. New York: General Learning Press. Kant, I. (1781/1998). Critique of Pure Reason. New York: Cambridge University Press. ______. (1785/1996). Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals. In M. J. Gregor (Ed.), Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy (pp. 37-108). New York: Cambridge University Press. ______. (1788/1996). Critique of Practical Reason. In M. J. Gregor (Ed.), Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy (pp. 133-272). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 253 ______. (1793/2000). Critique of the Power of Judgment. New York: Cambridge University Press. Kent, L. A. (2001). The Case of Lucio Pozzi: An Artist/Teacher's Studio Critique Method. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Teachers College, Columbia University, New York. Kindler, A. (2000). Art Education Outside the Search for Deep Meaning: Sometimes What Matters is on the Surface. Art Education, 53(1), 39-43. Kitcher, P. (1992). The Naturalists Return. The Philosophical Review, 101(1), 53-114. Koselleck, R. (2002). On the Anthropological and Semantic Structure of Bildung. In R. Koselleck (Ed.)The Practice of Conceptual History (pp. 170-207). Stanford: Stanford University Press. Kostler, A. (1964). The Act of Creation. New York: Macmillan. Krauss, R. E. (1981). The Originality of the Avant-Garde: A Postmodernist Repetition. October, 18, 47-66. ______. (1986). The Originality of the Avant-Garde and Other Modernist Myths. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Kuspit, D. (1988). The Student Artist and Humanistic Education. Art & Academe, 1(1), 12-20. Leiter, B. (2002). Analytic and Continental Philosophy. Retrieved November 7, 2002, from http://www.philosophicalgourmet.com/analytic.html Longuenesse, B. (1998). Kant and the Capacity to Judge. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Lowenfeld, V. (1952). Creative and Mental Growth. New York: Macmillan. Lucas, C. J. (1994). American Higher Education: A History. New York: St. Martin's Griffin. Luków, P. (2003). Maxims, Moral Responsiveness, and Judgment. Kant-Studien, 94, 405-425. 254 Lyotard, J.-F. (1994). Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime (E. Rottenberg, Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. MacIntyre, A. (1958). Notes from the Moral Wilderness I. The New Reasoner, 7 (Winter), 90-100. ______. (1984). After Virtue (2nd ed.). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. ______. (1988). Whose Justice? Which Rationality? Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. ______. (1991). An Interview with Alasdair MacIntyre. Cogito, 5, 67-73. Marshall, E. (1995). Theoretical Neutrality and Pedagogical Purpose: What Do Our Students Really Learn from an Aesthetic Theory? Art & Academe, 7(2), 41-51. McClintock, R. (2004). Homeless in the House of Intellect: Formative Justice and Education as an Academic Study. New York: Laboratory for Liberal Learning. McDonald, T. J. (Ed.). (1996). The Historic Turn in the Human Sciences. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. McGann, J. J. (1983). A Critique of Modern Textual Criticism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Melnick, A. (1973). Kant's Analogies of Experience. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Milgram, R. M. (1990). Creativity: An Idea Whose Time has Come and Gone? In M. A. Runco & R. S. Albert (Eds.), Theories of Creativity (pp. 215-233). Newbury Park: CA: Sage Publications. Milner, M. B. (1979). On Not Being Able to Paint. New York: International Universities Press. Mink, L. O. (1987). Historical Understanding. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Mittelstädt, K. (1968). Paul Gauguin: Self-portraits. Germany: Bruno Cassirer. Morse, S. & Gergen, K. J. (1970). Social Comparison, Self-consistency, and the Concept of the Self. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 16, 148-156. Murdoch, I. (1971). The Sovereignty of Good. New York: Routledge. 255 Murphy, M. C. (2003). MacIntyre's Political Philosophy. In M. C. Murphy (Ed.), Alasdair MacIntyre. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nagel, T. (1999). The View from Nowhere. In K. DeRose and T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader (pp. 272-291). New York: Oxford University Press. Nahm, M. C. (1950). Genius and the Aesthetic Relation of the Arts. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 9(1), 1-12. Niklas, U. (1994). On the Philosophy of Teaching Philosophy of Art. Art & Academe, 6(2), 1-12. Norton, C. E. (1913). Letters of Charles Eliot Norton. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Nussbaum, M. (2002). Humanities and Human Development. The Journal of Aesthetic Education, 36(3), 39-49. Palmer, R. E. (Ed.). (2001). Gadamer in Conversation. Yale Studies in Hermeneutics. New Haven: Yale University Press. Parsons, M. (2002). Aesthetic Experience and the Construction of Meanings. Journal of Aesthetic Education, 36(2), 24-37. Perruchot, H. (1963). Gauguin. Cleveland: The World Publishing Company. Polkinghorne, D. (1983). Methodology for the Human Sciences: Systems of Inquiry. New York: State University of New York Press. Porter, J. (2003). Tradition in the Recent Work of Alasdair MacIntyre. In M. C. Murphy (Ed.), Alasdair MacIntyre. New York: Cambridge University Press. Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, Belknap. Rilke, R. M. (1903-1908/1986). Letters to a Young Poet (S. Mitchell, Trans.). New York: Vintage Books. Rorty, R. (1982). Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. 256 Ross, L. (1977). The Intuitive Psychologist and His Shortcomings: Distortions in the Attribution Process. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psycology. New York: Academic Press. Runco, M. A. (1994). Conclusions Concerning Problem Finding, Problem Solving, and Creativity. In M. A. Runco (Ed.), Problem Finding, Problem Solving, and Creativity (pp. 271-290). Norwood, NJ: Ablex Publishing Corporation. Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge: The Belknap Press. Schiller, F. (1967). On the Aesthetic Education of Man. New York: Oxford University Press. Schjeldahl, P. (2002, July 29). French Postcards. The New Yorker, 82-84. Schoeman, F. (1987). Statistical Norms and Moral Attributions. In F. Schoeman (Ed.), Responsibility, Characters, and the Emotions: New Essays in Moral Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Scope, E. (1998). A Meta-Analysis of Research on Creativity: The Effects of Instructional Variables. Unpublished doctoral dissertation. Fordham University, New York. Shusterman, R. (1997). The End of Aesthetic Experience. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 55(1), 29-41. Simonton, D. K. (1999). Origins of genius : Darwinian perspectives on creativity. New York: Oxford University Press. Singerman, H. (1999). Art Subjects: Making Artists in the American University. Los Angeles: University of California Press. Skinner, Q. (Ed.). (1990). The Return of Grand Theory in the Human Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Slote, M. (1992). From Morality to Virtue. New York: Oxford University Press. Smith, F. (1998). The Book of Learning and Forgetting. New York: Teachers College Press. Smith, R. (1987). Excellence in Art Education: Ideas and Initiatives. Reston: National Art Education Association. 257 Stinespring, J. (2001). Preventing Art Education from Becoming "A Handmaiden to the Social Studies.â Arts Education Policy Review, 102(4), 11-18. Stern, A. (1971). The Making of a Genius. Miami: Hurricane House Publishers, Inc. Sternberg, R. J. & Lubart, T. I. (1996). Investing in Creativity. American Psychologist, 51(7), 677-688. Stevenson, C. L. (1945/1960). Ethics and Language. New Haven: Yale University Press. Stillinger, J. (1991). Multiple Authorship and the Myth of Solitary Genius. U.S.A.: Oxford University Press. Sullivan, G. (2005). Art Practice as Research. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Tate, J. W. (1998). The Hermeneutic Circle vs. the Enlightenment. Telos, 110, 9-38. Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the Self. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Thomson, B. (Ed.). (1993). Gauguin by Himself. New York: Little, Brown, and Company. Verhesschen P. (2001). Revelation and Transformation: Narrativity as a Paradigm for Educational Research. Retrieved November 3, 2004, from http://www.psy.kuleuven.ac.be/cobv/Engels/doctorats/2001e-Piet.PDF Wain, K. (2003). MacIntyre: Teaching, Politics and Practice. Journal of Philosophy and Education, 37(2), 225-239. Wallace, D. B. & Gruber, H. E. (Eds.). (1989). Creative People at Work: Twelve Cognitive Case Studies. New York: Oxford University Press. Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. U.S.A.: Basic Books. Wang, O. N. (2000). Kant's Strange Light: Romanticism, Periodicity, and the Catachresis of Genius. diacritics, 30(4), 15-37. Ward, T. B., Finke, R. A., & Smith, S. M. (1995). Creativity and the Mind: Discovering the Genius Within. New York: Plenum Press. Weinsheimer, J. C. (1985). Gadamer's Hermeneutics: A Reading of Truth and Method. New Haven: Yale University Press. 258 Weisberg, R. W. (1988). Problem Solving and Creativity. In R. J. Sternberg (Ed.), The Nature of Creativity (pp. 148-176). New York: Cambridge University Press. Wheeler, L. & Miyake, K. (1992). Social Comparison in Everyday Life. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62, 760-773. White, H. (1981). The Value of Narrativity in the Representation of Reality. In W. J. T. Mitchell (Ed.), On Narrative (pp. 1-23). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Williams, B. (1985). Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ______. (1988). Formal Structures and Social Reality. In D. Gambetta (Ed.), Trust: making and breaking cooperative relations (pp. 3-13). Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Wilson, J. (1998). Art-making Behavior: Why and How Arts Education is Central to Learning. Arts Education Policy Review, 99(6), 26-33. Wolf, S. (1982). Moral Saints. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 79(8), 419-439. Wood, J. V. (1989). Theory and Research Concerning Social Comparisons of Personal Attributes. Psychological Bulletin, 106, 231-248. Woodmansee, M. (1984). The Genius and the Copyright: Economic and Legal Conditions of the Emergence of the "Author." Eighteenth-Century Studies, 17(4), 425-448. Zangwill, N. (1999). Art and Audience. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 57(3), 315-332. Zwirn, S. G. (2002). To Be or Not To Be: The Teacher-Artist Conundrum. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Teachers College, Columbia University, New York.