Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Jurisprudence LG 327 Topic 5 John Rawls: Justice, Liberalism and the Social Contract John Rawls; 1921-2002 Author of A Theory of Justice (1971) - “many think [this] the most important work in political philosophy since the writings of John Stuart Mill” (Samuel Freeman) Themes • The idea of justice • The relationship between law and justice • Justice and the social contract: an alternative to natural law • The independence of moral and political theory in political liberalism • Rawls’ resurrection of the idea of the social contract: a “device of representation” • Justice as fairness and the “original position” • The meaning of the “veil of ignorance” • Justice as “political not metaphysical” • Critics of Rawls: communitarianism and the “situated self” • Is Rawls’ theory of justice based on an “abstracted” or “atomised” conception of the self? • Author of: - A Theory of Justice (1971;1999) - Political Liberalism (1993) - Justice as Fairness: a Restatement (2002) - The Law of Peoples (1999) • Introduction: the idea of justice The relationship of justice to law? The difference/relationship between ‘justice’ and ‘morality’? Why is justice relevant to jurisprudence (indeed to law)? What is the subject of justice? How does this make it different from morality? • Rawls’ preoccupation is: - What are the “fair terms of social cooperation” on the basis of which we might determine the justice and legitimacy of our law and institutions? Where are these principles of justice to be found are how may they be justified? - For Rawls, the answer lies not in natural law or even in ‘philosophy’ properly speaking, but rather in the idea of a social contract, constructed on terms that reflect the status of citizens as free and equal moral persons • The ‘principles of justice’ are those principles that rational persons would agree upon if they were deliberating from a hypothetically impartial standpoint, ignorant of certain morally-arbitrary factors such as wealth, gender, race, power, religion, etc. • However, justice pertains to the “basic structure” of society only – it has no “regulative role for all of life” – so the subject of justice is very different from the subject of morality and we could not base the “terms of social cooperation” on a “comprehensive” worldview, a moral or a religious doctrine. “…some have claimed that [the principles of justice] are specified … by an authority distinct from the persons cooperating … say God’s law, or with reference to natural law, or a moral order of values.” … instead, “the fair terms of social cooperation” are derived from an“agreement reached by free and equal citizens” [Justice as Fairness: a Restatement] • Because this agreement is to bound persons conceived as free and equal, the terms of this agreement must be “fair” and not defined with reference to any “comprehensive” philosophy or worldview: “in justice as fairness a democratic political society has no shared values and ends apart from those falling under or connected with the political conception of justice itself.” • In basing justice on the idea of contract, Rawls attempts to “generalize and carry to a higher order of abstraction the traditional theory of the social contract as represented by Locke, Rousseau and Kant” • However, this contract is meant as a hypothesis, a “thought experiment” in which we exclude certain reasons from deliberation on the scope of justice • This is the sense in which justice is “political not metaphysical”. It regulates the institutions of a society characterised by “reasonable pluralism”, therefore cannot be based on any “comprehensive” doctrine • This arises because justice is a sub-set of morality • Justice is “the cardinal virtue of institutions, as truth is of systems of thought.” • Justice is defined by fairness in the terms of social cooperation, rather than by any broader objective ‘truth’ • Political philosophy, specifically, cannot provide the answer to all dilemmas • Why is justice different from ethical theory? • Justice applies to the State rather than to private individuals and private relationships; Aristotle wrote “when men are friends they have no need of justice”. • What is important about Rawls’s work is how he frames justice as independent from other forms of morality, in the way that he roots in the idea of social contract rather than any conception of ‘natural law’ • Justice, as it applies to a whole society of persons, cannot be based on any “zeal for the complete truth” • For Rawls, the role of political philosophy to see whether “some underlying basis of philosophical and moral agreement can be uncovered”, or at least that a basis of social cooperation on a “footing of mutual respect among citizens may be maintained”. • The preoccupation of political philosophy therefore cannot be truth as such Rawls’s critique of utilitarianism: Utilitarianism says that just institutions should maximise the overall welfare or happiness of society: it is the view that “the institutions of the basic structure are to be arranged so as to maximise the average welfare of the members of society.” Bentham rejected natural rights as “nonsense on stilts” (in its rejection of natural law, utilitarianism is often associated with legal positivism. This was quite a radical idea in the 19th century but Rawls rejected it as inadequate – it failed to take the “separateness” of persons seriously enough Instead, Rawls wished to define what was “right” as “prior” to individuals’ private conceptions of “good” This would better account for ideas of equality and reciprocity Utilitarianism might require that certain persons’ rights would be compromised in order to facilitate a greater benefit for the society as a whole: “justice denies that a loss of freedom for some is made good by a greater good shared by others”. “There is no reason in principle … why the violation of the liberty of a few might not be made right by the greater good shared by many.” • He adds that not all interests are “commensurable”: – “in the history of democratic thought two contrasting ideas of society have a prominent place: one is the idea of society as a fair system of social cooperation between citizens regarded as free and equal; the other is the idea of society as a social systems organised so as to produce the most good summed over all its members” – From Justice as Fairness: a Restatement • Utilitarians, he says, overlook the special type of moral justification required for the state, as a coercive political authority: ‘in the light of what reasons and values … what kind of a conception of justice – can citizens legitimately exercise that kind of coercive power over one another?’ [ibid] • Thus, looking to the overall welfare of society, aggregated across its members, overlooks the value of consent as the moral basis for the legitimation of public authority: • ‘political power is legitimate only when it is exercised in accordance with a constitution … the essential of which all citizens, as reasonable and rationale, can endorse in light of their common human reason … this is the liberal principle of legitimacy’ [ibid] • “the fundamental status in political society is equal citizenship, a status all have as free and equal persons” • Thus, society is conceived as a fair framework for social cooperation which enables persons to pursue their own selfinterest – but on terms that all persons can be expected to endorse as equals Citizens are thus conceived as “free and equal”, living in a social framework which they may reasonably endorse. They are conceived as having two “moral powers”: “(i) One such power is the capacity for a sense of justice: it is the capacity to understand, to apply, and to act from (and not merely in accordance with) the principles of political justice that specify the fair terms of social cooperation. (ii) The other moral power is a capacity for a conception of the good: it is the capacity to have, to revise, and rationally to pursue a conception of the good. Such a conception is an ordered family of final ends and aims which specifies a person’s conception of what is of value in human life or, alternatively, of what is regarded as a fully worthwhile life. The elements of such a conception are normally set within, and interpreted by, certain comprehensive religious, philosophical, or moral doctrines in the light of which the various ends and aims are ordered and understood.” • These “moral powers” play a role in the original position: “since the veil of ignorance prevents the parties from knowing the comprehensive doctrines and conception of the good of the persons they represent, they must have some other grounds for deciding which principles to select in the original position” • Citizens are free and equal both in the sense that the power legitimately exercised over them is based on principles they may endorse in light of their “common reason”, and also in the sense that they reserve to themselves their choice of private or “comprehensive” identity: • “[they] claim the right to view their persons as independent from and not identified with any particular conceptions of the good, or scheme of final ends. ” • “given their moral power to form, to revise, an rationally to pursue a conception of the good, their public or legal identity as free persons is not affected by changes over times in their determinate conception of the good” • They ‘regard themselves as self-authenticating sources of valid claims’ • the conception of persons as free and equal is a ‘normative conception’, ‘given by political and moral philosophy’ • In this way, persons are not regarded as “passive carriers of desires” as under utilitarianism. They are considered to have an intrinsic interest in, and capacity for social cooperation. • Therefore, the social contract is not justified in view of citizens’ rational self-interest: they are “reasonable” as well as “rational” • In light of this, the “original position” models two things: • The “fair conditions under which …. citizens … are to agree to the fair terms of cooperation whereby the basic structure is to be regulated” • it models “what we regard … as acceptable restrictions on the reasons on the basis of which the parties, situated in fair conditions, may properly put forwards certain principles of political justice and reject others” • Rather than maximising overall utility, the parties in the original position, having a “higher-order” interest in the moral powers, seek a fair share of the “primary goods”: • “these are various social conditions and all-purpose means that are generally necessary to enable citizens to adequately develop and fully exercise their two moral powers, and to pursue their determinate conceptions of the good” • To derive these primary goods “we look to the normal circumstances of human life in a democratic society” – what do we need in order to exercise our “powers of moral personality”? • These are “things needed and required by persons in light of the political conception of persons … not merely as human beings apart from any normative conception … not things it is simply rational to want or desire … we use the political conception, and not a comprehensive moral doctrine, in specifying those needs and requirements” • “rational plans of life … depend on certain primary goods for their formation, revision, and successful execution” • Principles of justice are defined from the standpoint of a hypothetical ‘original position’ in which people know nothing about their position in society • What knowledge is available in the ‘original position’ – and why? “the fact that we occupy a particular social position, say, is not a good reason for us to accept, or to expect others to accept, a conception of justice that favors those in that position. If we are wealthy, or poor, we do not expect everyone else to accept a basic structure favouring the wealthy, or the poor, simply for that reason. To model this and other similar convictions, we do not let the parties know the social position of the persons they represent. The same idea is extended to other features of persons by the veil of ignorance” • This amounts to a “veil of ignorance” which constrains the knowledge available to the parties in the original position. The point of these “modelled constraints” is to reflect individuals’ equal moral status • The principles adopted will be just, says Rawls, because they are adopted and agreed upon from a standpoint of fairness • The agreement ‘must not be distorted by the particular features or circumstances of the existing basic structure’ • The original position eliminates the ‘bargaining advantages’ which may arise in a given society - ‘the bargaining advantages that inevitably arise over time within any society as a result of cumulative social and historical tendencies’ • This means that our institutions must be justified independently of the status quo • This will ground an argument for distributive justice (see ahead) • However, why should we set aside our talents and “native endowments” in arguing about matters of justice? • Note that in the original position, persons are denied knowledge not only of their bargaining advantages, but also, of their religious or philosophical beliefs • Why? To ensure that the principles of justice decided upon are appropriate to a society characterised by “reasonable pluralism” • Is this inherently problematic? • Note also that those in the original position are not denied all knowledge: they are modelled as “free and equal” • Note that for Rawls, the “reasonable” takes precedence over the “rational”. What do these ideas mean? • Reasonable persons are ‘ready to propose, or to acknowledge when proposed by others, the principles needed to specify what can be seem by all as fair terms of cooperation’ • But it is ‘rational’ for those who ‘have a superior political power or are placed in more fortunate circumstances … to take advantage of their situation’ • The two “principles of justice” arising from the original position • The parties in the OP would reject the ‘utility’ principle given the constraints on their deliberation within the ‘veil of ignorance’. Why? • They do not know their position in society – they would be unaware how the “calculus of social interests’ would affect them. Since they are accorded a ‘higher-order capacity’ to have and pursue a conception of the good, they would be concerned less with ensuring that the overall happiness or welfare of society were maximised in an aggregate sense, than in ensuring that they enjoyed the social and institutional conditions which enabled them to form and pursue a rational plan of life and revise this if necessary. • The parties would not accept utilitarian principles because it would render the exercise of their choice of worldview “subject to the calculus of social interests” on the basis of “a greater net balance of satisfaction.” • Instead they demand a roughly equal share of the “primary goods”. These are: 1 ‘The basic rights and liberties: freedom of thought and liberty of conscience, and the rest. These rights and liberties are essential institutional conditions required for the adequate development and full and informed exercise of the two moral powers’ 2 freedom of movement and free choice of occupation 3 powers and prerogatives of offices and positions of authority, responsibility 4 Income and wealth 5 ‘The social bases of self-respect, understood as those aspects of basic institutions normally essential if citizens are to have a lively sense of their worth as persons and to be able to advance their ends with self-confidence’ Instead of the utility principle, or natural law, the parties in the OP would settle on the following principles of justice: 1. equal liberty ‘each person has the same indefeasible claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties, which scheme is compatible with the same scheme of liberties for all’ 2. Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that a) they are to be of the greatest benefit to the leastadvantaged members of society (the difference principle). b) offices and positions must be open to everyone under conditions of fair equality of opportunity • The selection of the difference principle is obtained through the use of the maximin rule: ‘identify the worse outcome of each available alternative and then to adopt the alternative whose worst outcome is better than the worst outcomes of all the other alternatives’ • The parties in the OP must focus on the “best worst outcome” under each scenario considered in the OP • It is rational for the parties ‘not to be much concerned for what might be gained above what can be guaranteed by adopting the alternative whose worst outcome is better than the worst outcomes of all the other alternatives’ • The rejection of the utility principle assumes that ‘there are realistic social circumstances, even with reasonably favourable conditions, under which the principle of utility would require, or allow, that the basic rights and liberties of some be in various ways restricted, or even denied altogether, for the sake of greater benefits to others or for society as a whole.” • Since the principles of justice ‘secure the basic rights and liberties equally for all … and if the principle of utility may sometimes permit or else require the restriction or suppression of the rights and liberties of some for the sake of a greater aggregate of social well-being, then the parties must agree to the two principles of justice’ … “given the conception of the person in justice as fairness, citizens have, among other interests, certain religious, philosophical and moral interests and that the fulfilment of these interests must, if possible, be guaranteed. There are some things we cannot give up; they are not negotiable.” • The first principle of justice is given priority over the second given its “fundamental nature”: this rules out “trade-offs” between the basic rights and liberties and “social and economic advantages.” • … “the priority of liberty … means that a basic liberty can be limited or denied only for the sake of one or more other basic liberties, and never for a greater public good understood as a net sum of social and economic advantages for society as a whole.” • He claims the free market must be set within framework that prevents the trend of long term economic forces to concentrate property and wealth, which lead to inequality of opportunity as well as political domination • “if we ignore the inequalities in people’s prospects in life arising from these contingencies and let these inequalities work themselves out while failing to institute the regulations necessary to preserve background justice, we would not be taking seriously the idea of society as a fair systems of cooperation between citizens as free and equal” • Another assumption underpinning Rawls’ theory is that wealth can only be created and sustained through the framework of a coercive state which divides property and transmits it between generations, therefore people could only be expected to endorse and consent to the state if they were given a stake in the benefits of social cooperation, in the resources whose production was enabled by the coercive framework of the law: • ‘native endowments of various kinds … are not fixed natural assets with a constant capacity …. they are merely potential and cannot come to fruition apart from social conditions’ • The “priority of liberty” • Given the priority of the basic liberties, ‘we should count among them only truly essential liberties’ • ‘these liberties are bound to conflict with one another; hence the institutional rules specifying them must be adjusted so that each liberty fits into a coherent scheme of liberties.’ • ‘a liberty is more or less significant depending on whether it is more or less essentially involved in, or is a more or less necessary institutional means to protect, the full and informed exercise of the moral powers’ • In drawing up list of liberties, consider ‘what liberties provide the political and social conditions essential for the adequate development and full exercise of the full moral powers of free and equal persons’ • …‘liberty of conscience and freedom of association enable citizens to develop and exercise their moral powers in forming and revising and in rationally pursuing … their conceptions of the good’ • They ‘protect and secure the scope required for the exercise of the two moral powers … judging the justice of basic institutions, and pursuing our conception of the good … essential to us as free and equal citizens’ • This assumes that “our fundamental interests connected with the exercise of citizens’ two moral powers take priority over other interests”. • Liberty of conscience reflects the ‘often intractable nature of religious, philosophical and moral conflicts in the absence of a secure public basis of mutual trust.’ • The alternative idea represented by utilitarianism is that ‘all human interests are commensurable … that for any two interests, given the extent to which they are satisfied, there is always some rate of exchange at which a rational person is willing to accept a lesser fulfilment of the one in return for a greater fulfilment of the other’ • justice as fairness puts basic liberties “beyond the calculus of social interests” • These are “taken … off the political agenda” … • “by contrast, to regard the calculus of social interests as always relevant in specifying basic rights and liberties, as the principle of utility does, leaves the status and content of those freedoms still unsettled. It subjects them to the shifting circumstances of time and place.” - Thus the advantage of justice as fairness is to define justice independently of the demands of a dominant, majority social or cultural norm • Justice as fairness: “political not metaphysical” • This means justice is not based on any theoretical conception of objective, natural truth. It is rather an exercise in “practical reason” that can uncover a “fair basis for social cooperation” in a society of persons regarded as possessing the moral powers • The question being asked is less what is true/what is good? – than what are the fair terms of justice for the basic structure of a society of persons regarded as themselves having the capacity to themselves decide questions of ultimate truth or good? • This encapsulates the “political” nature of Rawls’s social contract – it does not regulate “all of life” – and illustrates the difference with natural law • This separating out of “political” and “comprehensive” issues is related to the “liberal principle of legitimacy”: • ‘political power is legitimate only when it is exercised in accordance with a constitution … the essential of which all citizens, as reasonable and rationale, can endorse in light of their common human reason … this is the liberal principle of legitimacy’ • This is a more complex way of saying that the legitimacy of government is derived from the consent of the governed – here, consent is given on terms that do not presuppose acceptance of any “comprehensive” worldview • Rawls says a democratic society cannot be a community – in the sense of a body of persons united in sharing the same comprehensive doctrine – therefore the “terms of social cooperation” in a just society cannot be based on a shared comprehensive worldview that everybody is expected to endorse • There is because a “permanent condition” of democratic societies is the “reasonable pluralism” of worldviews within it. Consensus on the “good life” could only be achieved through the “oppressive use of state power” • The fact that justice cannot be based on a comprehensive worldview is linked with the claim that citizens must be able to determine their own ends and beliefs: they “claim the right to view their persons as independent from and not identified with any particular conceptions of the good, or scheme of final ends.” • Therefore, ‘in justice as fairness a democratic political society has no such shared values and ends apart from those falling under or connected with the political conception of justice itself’ • Basic institutions should be ‘justifiable to all citizens’, and not just those who accept a particular private worldview. Grounds must be ‘accessible to citizens’ common reason’ – ie they do not presuppose acceptance of any idea of the good, or the final ends or purpose of their life. A political doctrine would be one which citizens can endorse whatever their private worldview. For example, freedom of conscience and religion – this is something that can be accepted by reasonable persons independently of what private worldviews they hold themselves • So “liberalism” in Rawls’s theory is not based on the idea of Enlightenment, autonomy or individuality – or even the idea that persons’ worldviews should be rational and based on autonomous deliberation – but rather on the idea that the State must regard them as having ownership or sovereignty over their “final ends”, whatever these might be. He says that justice as fairness is “not an Enlightenment project”. • In this way he hopes his theory can form the basis of an “overlapping consensus” between different (reasonable) worldviews • Thus, arguably, a state committed to “free thought” or “Enlightenment” ideology cannot respect equal liberty in the Rawlsian sense. It must account for ‘the burdens of judgment’. • This does not imply philosophical scepticism per se (ie that there is no ultimate truth) – it merely implies that this if for persons themselves to resolve: • ‘… it does not follow that there is no true comprehensive doctrine … it only says that we cannot expect to reach a workable political agreement on what it is’ • ‘… deep religious and moral conflicts characterise the subjective circumstances of justice’ • Moreover he notes: • “ it is a longstanding objection to liberalism that it is hostile to certain ways of life and biased in favour of others; or that it favors the values of autonomy and individualist and opposes those of community and associational allegiance. In reply, observe first that the principles of any reasonable political conception must impose restrictions on permissible comprehensive views, and the basic institutions these principles require inevitably encourage some ways of life and discourage others, or even exclude them altogether.” • Therefore, although political liberalism is derived independently of any comprehensive worldview, it cannot be strictly “neutral” between these … ‘does this by itself imply that its political conception of justice fails to be neutral between [comprehensive doctrines]? Given the connotations of ‘neutral’, perhaps it does fail, and this is a difficulty with that term. But the important question surely is whether the political conception is arbitrarily biased against these views, or better, whether it is just or unjust to the persons whose conceptions they are … it would not appear to be unjust to them, for social influences favoring some doctrines over others cannot be avoided on any view of political justice. No society can include within itself all ways of life. We may indeed lament the limited space … of social worlds.’ • He says that the politically-liberal state should not impose any worldview on children but it should educate them to the idea of political justice itself – they must gain a conception of themselves as “free and equal” …… • “… various religious sects oppose the culture of the modern world and wish to lead their common life apart from its foreign influences. A problem now arises from their children’s education and the requirements the state can impose … The liberalisms of Kant and Mill may lead to requirements designed to foster the values of autonomy and individuality as ideals to govern much if not all of life. But political liberalism has a different aim and requires far less. It will ask that children’s education include such things as knowledge of their constitutional and civil rights, so … that they know that liberty of conscience exists … and that apostasy is not a legal crime … their education should also prepare them to be fully cooperating members of society, it should also encourage the political virtues so that they want to honor the fair terms of social cooperation” • [From Justice as Fairness: a Restatement] • To re-cap … • “political power, as the power of free and equal citizens, is to be exercised in ways that all citizens as reasonable and rational might endorse in the light of their common human reason” - ie the peculiar character of state power requires a particular type of justification for its exercise Social unity is therefore rested not on a single accepted truth but rather a shared basis of social agreement that all persons can be ‘expected to endorse’ • The fact of reasonable pluralism precludes comprehensive doctrines ‘as a basis for a workable political agreement on a conception of justice’ • ‘It is a permanent feature of the public culture of democracy’ • ‘Just institutions … would serve no purpose – would have no point - unless those institutions … not only permitted but also sustained conceptions of the good … that citizens can affirm as worthy of their full allegiance. A conception of political justice must contain within itself sufficient space … for ways of life than can gain devoted support.’ • ‘an essential feature of a well-ordered society is that its public conception of political justice establishes a shared basis for citizens to justify to one another their political judgments; each cooperates, politically and socially, with the rest on terms all can endorse as just’ • What he calls “public justification” … must “proceed from some consensus” – which is the basis of the social contract • Therefore citizens must ‘be able to present to one another publicly acceptable reasons for their political views … our reasons should fall under the political values expressed by a political conception of justice … we must justify our use of corporate and coercive political power … in the light of public reason.’ • ‘public reason is the form of reasoning appropriate to equal citizens who as a corporate body impose rules on one another backed by sanctions of state power … shared guidelines for inquiry and methods of reasoning make that reason public, while freedom of speech and thought in a constitutional regime make that reason free’ • Complete agreement in society is not possible, it is only necessary to have agreement on the constitutional essentials • … ‘the aim of public justification is to preserve the conditions of effective and democratic social cooperation on a footing of mutual respect between citizens regarded as free and equal’ • ‘… so far as possible, political liberalism neither accepts nor rejects any particular comprehensive doctrine, moral or religious… justice as fairness hopes to put aside longstanding religious and philosophical controversies and to avoid relying on any particular comprehensive view’ • ‘… if this is achieved, we have an overlapping consensus of reasonable doctrines’ • The defence of constitutional democracy is arranged so as to win wide support but ‘we do not look to the comprehensive doctrines that in fact exist and then frame a political conception that strikes a balance between them expressly designed to gain their allegiance’. This would make justice as fairness ‘political in the wrong way’ • Citizens ‘affirm the political conception [of justice] from within different and opposing comprehensive doctrines’ • Justice as fairness takes account of the coercive nature of state power. How can this be justified? (Answer – by ensuring it is exercised by the light of principles which can be justified independently of any worldview • In light of the above, how is Rawls’s theory of justice different to the natural law theory? • Criticisms of Rawls’s Theory 1. The priority of liberty: why should liberty take precedence over everything else? Hart argues that Rawls’s “preference for liberty over other goods which every self-interested person who is rational would have” rests on “the ideal … of a public-spirited citizen who prizes political activity.” -“Rawls on Liberty and its Priority” (1973) 40 The University of Chicago Law Review 534, p. 534. • 2. The original position represents persons in an unrealistic way, as detached from their ends and commitments. • This is sometimes called the ‘communitarian’ critique of liberalism. It refuses to consider justice from the standpoint of abstracted individuals choosing the terms of social cooperation independently of their own attachments and worldviews • They disagree with the attempt to derive universal principles of justice “from an idealised standpoint”,independently of cultural, religious and other particularities. The state should not recognise the individual in the abstract but also the community within which he operates • See generally M. Walzer, Spheres of Justice (Oxford: Blackwell, 1983); M. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Oxford, 1989) • Communitarians focus instead on “socially and historically situated subjects … understood as members of communities and as bearers of particular identities” (Pettit and Kukathas on Rawls) • They question whether “the principles of justice that govern the basic structure of society can be neutral with respect to the competing moral and religious convictions its citizens espouse.” (Sandel) • Rawls is accused of “producing a deracinated sense of self,” or an “implausible” self “barren of constituent traits” (Sandel) • He constructs persons as “somehow existing above and acting independently of their social and historical contexts and bodily matrices” (Markell) • Communitarianism “values particular ways of life and subcommunities,” as well as “communities which shape self-identity and endow it with values and attachments” (Stolzenberg) • It denies that “[we can] detach ourselves in order to identify the principles by which to order our association”, and rejects the value of “agreement by pre-social individuals”, as we do not have the “capacity to construct a morality without self-knowledge.” • It “insists on the equal, even prior, importance of communal belonging”, and often “looks for a state that will be grafted closely onto a community’s way of life.” (Pettit) • The liberal conception of justice is alleged to portray the individual in a way that misrepresents “real life”. Walzer says that for Rawls, the individual is “constituted only by his wilfulness, liberated from all connection, without common values, binding ties, customs or traditions.” • Rawls’ defence of this is to say that we must accept principles of justice that can we endorsed by all independently of any particular worldview and this is the reason for representing persons independently of their identities in the original position. The purpose of the “veil of ignorance” is not to suggest that actual people should regard themselves as “detached” from their ends and identities • The original position is merely meant as a “device of representation” • 3. Justice as fairness suggests a universal conception of justice which takes no account of the different histories and characteristics of different societies • This is related to the communitarian critique. Just as individualist liberalism fails to account for the differences between individuals and their identities, it also fails to account for the differences between societies. • On this view, while the original position masquerades as universalist, it is really “parochial in construction”, reflecting Rawls’s preoccupation with American society • Sen observes that Rawls “seems to accept that there are incurable problems in getting a unanimous agreement on one set of principles of justice in the original position, which cannot but have devastating implications for his theory of ‘justice as fairness’” • Why should the social contract not take account of the different histories and characteristics of different peoples? Must the principles of justice be the same everywhere? • Communitarians suggest that “to know what rules or laws are appropriate for us we need to look more closely at our own community and moral tradition to discover what our values are – and what is necessary to protect them” [Pettit and Kukathas] • … “the idea of looking to uncover abstract principles of morality by which to evaluate or redesign existing societies is an implausible one.” • 4. Rawls’s political liberalism is not really ‘neutral’ between different worldviews or conceptions of the good • It is sometimes objected that it is effectively impossible to formulate principles of justice without entering into “comprehensive” questions of what is the purpose or end of human life – questions Rawls claims to avoid entirely • “A liberal must take his stand on the proposition that some ways of life, some types of character, are more admirable than others … Liberalism rests on a vision of life: a Faustian vision. It exalts self-expression, self-mastery and control over the environment, natural and social; the active pursuit of knowledge and the clash of ideas.” - Brian Barry - The point here is that liberalism is not merely committed to neutrality between worldviews but is itself committed to a particular worldview • Nagel states: “the original position seems to presuppose not just a neutral theory of the good, but a liberal, individualistic conception according to which the best that can be wished for someone is the unimpeded pursuit of his own path, provided it does not interfere with the rights of others.” • Similarly, Taylor attributes the “political” basis of Rawls’s theory to an “ethics of inarticulacy”, suggesting that the principles of justice rest upon an unstated moral basis: “we recognise that these are acceptable principles of justice because they fit with out intuitions. If we were to articulate what underlies those intuitions we would start spelling out a very ‘thick’ theory of the good.” C. Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), p. 89 • But Rawls never claims that his theory is intended to be “neutral” between “comprehensive doctrines” in the sense of neither favouring nor disfavouring any of them. Rather, it must be justifiable from a standpoint that does not pre-suppose acceptance of any of these • “No society can include within itself all ways of life. We may indeed lament the limited space … of social worlds” – the limits of liberal toleration? 5. By focusing on the principles of justice that apply to the State and the public sphere alone, Rawls’s theory overlooks the injustice and inequality that occurs within the private sphere and the family in particular This is often the criticism of feminists in particular (eg Susan Okin) who believe that Rawls, in limiting the “principles of justice” to the “basic structure” of public institutions, overlooks the injustice perpetuated within the family • Recall – why did Rawls limit the principles of justice to the “political association” of the state as opposed to associations and communities? • Okin argues that Rawls ends up ignoring the ways the internal dynamics of the family place subordinate women - which in turn leads him to overlook how this restricts the ability of women to be free and equal citizens within the political sphere • Rawls assumes “the family, in some form, is just”. In his later work he brings the family within the remit of the “basic structure”. Why? … ‘at some point society has to trust to the natural affection and goodwill of parents’ …However, ‘the principles of justice also impose constraints on the family on behalf of children who are society’s future citizens and have claims as such.’ • … ‘political liberalism distinguishes between political justice that applies to the basic structure and other conceptions of justice that apply to the various associations within that structure’ but ‘it does not regard the political and the nonpolitical domains as two separate, disconnected spaces, as it were, each governed solely by its own distinct principles’ • … ‘the principles defining the equal basic liberties … always hold in and through all so-called domains.’ • ‘if the so-called private sphere is a space alleged to be exempt from justice, there is no such thing’ • Sample questions on John Rawls: 1. What does it mean to say that Rawls’s theory of justice is a social contract theory? How does this make it different from natural law and utilitarianism in particular? 2. In what sense is Rawls’s theory of justice “political not metaphysical”? 3. What are the main criticisms of Rawls’s theory of justice?