Download Mackie and Rowe

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

List of unsolved problems in philosophy wikipedia , lookup

Problem of evil wikipedia , lookup

Irenaean theodicy wikipedia , lookup

Theodicy wikipedia , lookup

Augustinian theodicy wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
THE PROBLEM OF EVIL
Edited by
MARILYN McCORD ADAMS
and
ROBERT MERRIHEW ADAMS
OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS
Oxford University Press, Walton Street, Oxford ox2
Oxford New York Toronto
Delhi Bombay Calcutta Madras Karachi
Petaling Jaya Singapore Hong Kong Tokyo
Nairobi Dar es Salaam Cape Town
Melbourne Auckland
and associated companies in
Berlin Ibadan
6DP
Oxford is a trade mark ofOxford University Press
Published in the United States
by Oxford University Press, New York
Except where othenvise stated © Oxford University Press, 1990
First published 1990
Paperback reprinted 1992
All rights reserved. No part ofthis publication may be reproduced,
stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means,
electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without
the prior permission of Oxford University Press
This book is sold subject to the condition that it shall not, by way
oftrade or otherwise, be lent, re-sold, hired out or othenvise circulated
without the publisher's prior consent in any form of binding or ,cover
other than that in which it is published and without a similar condition
including this condition being imposed on the subsequent purchaser
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
The problem of evil.-(O),ford readings in philosophy).
I. Evil
1. Adams, Marilyn McCord II. Adams, Robert Merrihew
II 1.84
ISBN 0--19-824867-9
ISBN 0-19-824866-0 (Pbk)
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
The Problem of evil/edited by Marilyn McCord Adams and Robert
Merrihew Adams.
p. cm.-(Oxford readings in philosophy)
Includes bibliographical references.
I. Good and evil. 2. Theodicy. I. Adams, Marilyn McCord.
lI. Adams, Robert Merrihew. IlI. Series.
BJ/401.P76 1990 2I6-dc20 90-34004
ISBN 0-19-824867-9
ISBN 0-19-824866-0 (Pbk.)
Printed and bound in
Great Britain by Bookcraft (Bath) Ltd,
Midsomer Norton, Avon
I
EVIL AND OMNIPOTENCE
J. L. MACKIE
traditional arguments for the existence of God have been fairly
thC)rouglhlycriticised by philosophers. But the theologian can, if he wishes,
this criticism. He can admit that no rational proof of God's existence
oo:ssltJle. And he can still retain all that is essential to his position, by
that God's existence is known in some other, non-rational way. I
however, that a more telling criticism can be made by way of the
tra,diti:onal problem of evil. Here it can be shown, not that religious beliefs
rational support, but that they are positively irrational, that the several
of the essential theological doctrine are inconsistent with one another,
the theologian can maintain his position as a whole only by a much
extreme rejection of reason than in the former case. He must now be
prep31red to believe, not merely what cannot be proved, but what can be
dis(Jrcwed from other beliefs that he also holds.
problem of evil, in the sense in which I shall be using the-phrase, is a
prc)bll~m only for someone who believes that there is a God who is both
OI11nir)otl~nt and wholly good. And it is a logical problem, the problem of
clarif:ying and reconciling a number of beliefs: it is not a scientific problem
might be solved by further observations, or a practical problem that
be solved by a decision or an action. These points are obvious; I
mention them only because they are sometimes ignored by theologians,
sometimes parry a statement of the problem with such remarks as
can you solve the problem yourself?' or 'This is a mystery which may
revealed to us later' or 'Evil is something to be faced and overcome, not
be merely discussed'.
In its simplest form the problem is this: God is omnipotent; God is wholly
and yet evil exists. There seems to be some contradiction between
three propositions, so that if any two of them were true the third
be false. But at the same time all three are essential parts of most
the:olc)gical positions: the theologian, it seems, at once must adhere and
consistently adhere to all three. (The problem does not arise only for
L. Mackie, 'Evil and Omnipotence', first published in Mind, 64 (1955), pp. 200-12. Reprinted
by permission of Oxford University Press.
26
27
J. L. MACKIE
EVIL AND OMNIPOTENCE
theists, but I shall discuss it in the form in which it presents itself
ordinary theism.)
However, the contradiction does not arise immediately; to show it
need some additional premises, or perhaps some quasi-logical rules connecting the terms 'good', 'evil', and 'omnipotent'. These additional principles
are that good is opposed to evil, in such a way that a good thing alway
eliminates evil as far as it can, and that there are no limits to what a
omnipotent thing can do. From these it follows that a good omnipoten
thing eliminates evil completely, and then the propositions that a goo
omnipotent thing exists, and that evil exists, are incompatible.
.ga~;onably be suspected of thinking, in other contexts, that his power is
A. ADEQUATE SOLUTIONS
Now once the problem is fully stated it is clear that it can be solved, in
sense that the problem will not arise if one gives up at least one of
propositions that constitute it. If you are prepared to say that God is
wholly good; or not quite omnipotent, or that evil does not exist, or
good is not opposed to the kind of evil that exists, or that there are limits to
what an omnipotent thing can do, then the problem of evil will not arise for
you.
There are, then, quite a number of adequate solutions of the problem of
evil, and some of these have been adopted, or almost adopted, by various
thinkers. For example, a few have been prepared to deny God'somnipotence,
and rather more have been prepared to keep the term 'omnipotence' but
severely to restrict its meaning, recording quite a number of things that an
omnipotent being cannot do. Some have said that evil is an illusion,
perhaps because they held that the whole world of temporal, changing
things is an illusion, and that what we call evil belongs only to this world,
or perhaps because they held that although temporal things are much as
we see them, those that we call evil are not really evil. Some have said that
what we call evil is merely the privation of good, that evil in a positive
sense, evil that would really be opposed to good, does not exist. Many
have agreed with Pope that disorder is harmony not understood, and that
partial evil is universal good. Whether any of these views is true is, of
course, another question. But each of them gives an adequate solution of
the problem of evil in the sense that if you accept it this problem does not
arise for you, though you may, of course, have other problems to face.
But often enough these adequate solutions are only almost adopted. The
thinkers who restrict God's power, but keep the term 'omnipotence', may
unlimited. Those who say that evil is an illusion may also be thinking,
that this illusion is itself an evil. Those who say that 'evil' is
privation of good may also b.e thi~king, inconsistently, that, privatio.n ~f
is an evil. (The fallacy here IS akm to some forms of the naturalIstIc
in ethics, where some think, for example, that 'good' is just what
"Arltributes to evolutionary progress, and that evolutionary progress is
good.) If Pope meant what he said in the first line of his couplet, that
'di:sorder' is only harmony not understood, the 'partial evil' of the second
must, for consistency, mean 'that which, taken in isolation, falsely
to be evil', but it would more naturally mean 'that which, in
is61lati 1on, really is evil'. The second line, in fact, hesitates between two
that 'partial evil' isn't really evil, since only the universal quality is
and that 'partial evil' is really an evil, but only a little one.
addition, therefore, to adequate solutions, we must recognise unsatisfclct<)ry inconsistent solutions, in which there is only a half-hearted or
tenlPC,raI~Y rejection of one of the propositions which together constitute
problem. In these, one of the constituent propositio~s is explicitly
tej,ect,ed, but it is covertly re-asserted or assumed elsewhere m the system.
B. FALLACIOUS SOLUTIONS
these half-hearted solutions, which explicitly reject but implicitly
one of the constituent propositions, there are definitely fallacious
sol111ti<ms which explicitly maintain all the constituent propositions, but
imlPli<jtly reject at least one of them in the course of the argument that
expllaills away the problem of evil.
There are, in fact, many so-called solutions which purport to remove the
C011tr:adiction without abandoning any of its constituent propositions.
must be fallacious, as we can see from the very statement of the
pro1ble:m, but it is not so easy to see in each case precisely where the fallacy
I suggest that in all cases the fallacy has the general form suggested
above: in order to solve the problem one (or perhaps more) of its constituent
propositions is given up, but in such a way that it appears to have been
and can therefore be asserted without qualification in other
COI'lte)(ts. Sometimes there is a further complication: the supposed solution
to and fro between, say, two of the constituent propositions, at one
asserting the first of these but covertly abandoning the second, at
point asserting the second but covertly abandoning the first. These