Download HTTP://SLATE

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

The Evolution of Cooperation wikipedia , lookup

Steven Pinker wikipedia , lookup

Before the Dawn (book) wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
H T T P :/ / S L AT E . M S N . C O M / I D /2 1 24 5 03 /
M E D I C AL E X AM I N E R : H E A L TH A N D ME D I C I N E E XP L A I N E D .
Cave ThinkersHOW EVOLUTIONARY
PSYCHOLOGY GETS EVOLUTION WRONG.
By Amanda Schaffer
Posted Tuesday, Aug. 16, 2005, at 7:16 AM ET
This spring, New York Times columnist John Tierney
asserted that men must be innately more competitive than women since they monopolize
the trophies in—hold onto your vowels—world Scrabble competitions. To bolster his case,
Tierney turned to evolutionary psychology. In the distant past, he argued, a no-holdsbarred desire to win would have been an adaptive advantage for many men, allowing
them to get more girls, have more kids, and pass on their competitive genes to today's
word-memorizing, vowel-hoarding Scrabble champs.
Tierney's peculiar, pseudo-scientific claim—not the first from him—reflects the extent to
which evolutionary psychology has metastasized throughout public discourse. EP-ers'
basic claim is that human behavior stems from psychological mechanisms that are the
products of natural selection during the Stone Age. Researchers often focus on how
evolution produced mental differences between men and women. One of EP's academic
stars, David Buss, argues in his salacious new book The Murderer Next Door that men are
wired to kill unfaithful wives because this response would have benefited their distant
forefathers. Larry Summers took some cover from EP this winter after his remarks about
women's lesser capacity to become top scientists. And adaptive explanations of old sexist
hobbyhorses—men like young women with perky breasts and can't stop themselves from
philandering because these urges aided ancestral reproduction—are commonly marshaled
in defense of ever-more-ridiculous playboys.
Evolutionary psychologists have long taken heat from critics for overplaying innate
characteristics—nature at the expense of nurture—and for reinforcing gender
stereotypes. But they've dismissed many detractors, fairly or no, as softheaded feminists
and sociologists who refuse to acknowledge the true power of natural selection.
Increasingly, however, attacks on EP come from academics well-versed in the hard-nosed
details of evolutionary biology. A case in point is the new book Adapting Minds by
philosopher David Buller, which was supported by a research grant from the National
Science Foundation and published by MIT Press and has been getting glowing reviews like
this one (paid link) from biologists. Buller persuasively argues that while evolutionary
forces likely did play a role in shaping our minds, the assumptions and methods that have
dominated EP are weak. Much of the work of pioneers like Buss, Steven Pinker, John
Tooby, Leda Cosmides, Martin Daly, and Margo Wilson turns out to be vulnerable on
evolutionary grounds.
EP claims that our minds contain hundreds or thousands of "mental organs" or
"modules," which come with innate information on how to solve particular problems—how
to interpret nuanced facial expressions, how to tell when someone's lying or cheating.
These problem-solving modules evolved between 1.8 million and 10,000 years ago,
during the Pleistocene epoch. And there the selection story ends. There has not been
enough time in the intervening millenia, EP-ers say, for natural selection to have further
resculpted our psyches. "Our modern skulls house a Stone Age mind," as Cosmides' and
Tooby's primer on evolutionary psychology puts it. The way forward for research is to
generate hypotheses about the urges that would have been helpful to Stone Age babymaking and then try to test whether these tendencies are widespread today.
What's wrong with this approach? To begin with, we know very little about the specific
adaptive problems faced by our distant forebears. As Buller points out, "We don't even
know the number of species in the genus Homo"—our direct ancestors—"let alone details
about the lifestyles led by those species." This makes it hard to generate good
hypotheses. Some EP-ers have suggested looking to modern-day hunter-gatherers as
proxies, studying them for clues about our ancestors. But this doesn't get them far. For
instance, in some contemporary African groups, men gather the bulk of the food; in other
groups, women do. Which groups are representative of our ancestors? Surely there's a
whole lot of guesswork involved when evolutionary psychologists hypothesize about the
human brain's supposedly formative years.
In addition, we are probably not psychological fossils. New research suggests that
evolutionary change can occur much faster than was previously believed. Natural
selection is thought to effect rapid change especially when a species' environment is in
flux—precisely the situation in the last 10,000 years as humans learned to farm,
domesticate animals, and live in larger communal groups. Crucially, Buller notes, in order
for significant change to have occurred in the human mind in the last 10 millennia,
evolution need not have built complex brain structures from scratch but simply modified
existing ones.
Finally, the central, underlying assumption of EP—that humans have hundreds or
thousands of mental problem-solving organs produced by natural selection—is
questionable. Many cognitive scientists believe that such modules exist for processing
sensory information and for acquiring language. It does not follow, however, that there
are a plethora of other ones specifically designed for tasks like detecting cheaters. In
fact, considering how much dramatic change our forebears faced, it makes more sense
that their problem-solving faculties would have evolved to be flexible in response to their
immediate surroundings. (A well-argued book from philosopher Kim Sterelny fleshes out
this claim.) Indeed, our mental flexibility, or cortical plasticity, may be evolution's
greatest gift.
So, if evolutionary psychology has so many cracks in its foundations, why is it so
stubbornly influential? It helps that EP-ers like Buss and Pinker are lively, media-friendly
writers who present topics like sex, love, and fear in simple terms. More to the point for
scientists, EP's conclusions can be quite difficult to falsify. Even if its methods of
generating hypotheses are suspect, there is always the possibility that on any given
topic, an EP-er will turn out to be partly right. That forces critics to delve into the details
of particular empirical claims. Buller does this in the latter part of his book and
successfully dismantles several major EP findings.
For instance, EP-ers have asserted that stepparents are more likely to abuse their
stepchildren than their own sons and daughters because in the Stone Age, the parents
who selectively devoted love and resources to their own progeny would have had a leg up
in passing on their own genes. The proof is data that purport to show a higher rate of
modern-day abuse by stepparents than by parents. When Buller dissects the data,
however, this conclusion begins to fall apart. To begin with, most of the relevant studies
on abuse do not say whether the abuser was a parent or stepparent. The EP assumption
that the abuser is always the stepparent creates an artificial and entirely absurd
confirmation of the field's hypothesis. In addition, research has shown that when a
stepfather is present, a child's bruises are more likely attributed to abuse rather than to
accidents, whereas when a biological father is present, the opposite tendency exists.
Buller has to wade in deep to unravel this, but the effort pays off.
Ultimately, the biggest problem with EP may be that it underestimates the power of
evolutionary forces—both to tinker continually with the human brain, and to have created
ingenious and flexible problem-solving structures in the first place. There's a nice irony
here, since for years EP-ers have ridiculed opponents for not appreciating evolutionary
theory's core tenets. Buller goes so far as to note an eerie resemblance between EP and
intelligent design, which also treats human nature as fixed and complete. The more
persuasive claim is that there is no single human nature, and that we're works in
progress.