Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Book Reviews Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction Thomas Nagel Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialistic Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly Wrong Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012, 130 pp. ISBN 978 0 19 991975 8 Reviewed by Eva Jablonka1 and Simona Ginsburg2 The Major Teleological Transitions in Evolution: Why the Materialistic Evolutionary Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly Right In his recent book, Thomas Nagel argues that our ideas about the entities that constitute the world, and our notions of the evolution of biological entities, are inadequate. Nagel regards himself as a diagnostician, not a healer: he diagnoses what he regards as the deep problems of the current scientific world-view and leaves the healing — the solutions — to future scientists. This position allows him to be very vague about what the future solutions may entail. Nevertheless, if his analysis is valid, it can still be an important contribution to our scientific world-view. In this review-essay we argue that although Nagel points to great challenges that evolutionary biologists must (and do) address, his diagnosis is faulty and the validity of his conclusions is therefore doubtful. Before we present our critique, a short summary of Nagel’s principal arguments is necessary. Nagel starts from the constitutive problem, the nature of reality. He argues that ample phenomena point to an explanatory gap between the mental and the physical. Since the reduction of the mental to the physical is, he argues, impossible, and since the stuff of which brains are [1] Tel Aviv University, Israel. [2] The Open University, Israel. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20, No. 9–10, 2013, pp. 177–205 Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 178 BOOK REVIEWS made is no different from other cosmic stuff, we must change our notion of ultimate reality and adopt neutral monism. In Nagel’s version, neutral monism means ‘…a form of understanding that enables us to see ourselves and other conscious organisms as specific expressions simultaneously of the physical and the mental character of the universe’ (Nagel, 2012, p. 69). Nagel rejects emergence from the physical as an option that may explain life, phenomenal experiencing, logical reasoning, and moral evaluations, favouring instead the greater theoretical elegance of reductive neutral monism. The second big problem for Nagel is that evolutionary theory as he understands it cannot explain the emergence of life, consciousness, logic, and human values, and is also inadequate with regard to the evolution of complex adaptations such as the genetic code and translation. Even if we accept the existence of inherently proto-mental basic stuff, the riddle of evolution, Nagel claims, is not solved, because it is still a mystery how life, consciousness, reason, and values evolved from the proto-mental precursors which were not living, not conscious, not reasoning, and not value-laden. Not only does Nagel find the above features of the cosmos inadequately explained by a naturalistic evolutionary theory based on selection, but he also believes that they can never be adequately explained by such materialistic theories. Hence he suggests that some teleological value-driven law of nature is at work in the cosmos. We focus on this second line of argumentation, which, as it turns out, has repercussions on the first, constitutive problem. We highlight two problematic issues: Nagel’s general view of modern evolutionary theory, and his difficulties in understanding those major transitions in the history of life that have led to the emergence of new teleological systems. His presentation of both issues, we argue, is simplistic and impoverished and leads him to unwarranted conclusions. The Evolution of the Educated Guess Nagel’s complaint about evolutionary theory is that he just cannot imagine how random mutation and natural selection could lead to the wonderful complex adaptations we see, such as the genetic code, phenomenal consciousness, reasoning, and moral values. An early representative quotation reads: ‘…with regard to evolution, the process of natural selection cannot account for the actual history without an adequate supply of viable mutations, and I believe it remains an open question whether this could have been provided in geological time merely as a result of chemical accident, without the operation of some Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction BOOK REVIEWS 179 other factors determining and restricting the forms of genetic variation’ (Nagel, 2012, p. 9). Somewhat apologetically Nagel explains two pages earlier that he is just a well-read layman, and acknowledges, in a footnote to the above quotation, some biological and cybernetic considerations that complicate the simple picture expounded in Dawkins’ The Blind Watchmaker (1986), which, together with some books on Intelligent Design (ID), seem to be his major sources of knowledge of evolutionary biology. This is a strange attitude from someone who purports to diagnose the problems of modern evolutionary science. The present version of naturalistic and materialistic evolutionary theory is not to be found in Dawkins’ popular writings a quarter of a century ago, and ID books are not the best source for learning about twenty-first-century evolutionary biology. The huge progress in molecular and developmental biology has led to new insights that impinge on evolutionary theory without introducing new laws of nature. For example, every twenty-first-century evolutionary biologist acknowledges that aspects of development, such as modular organization, have led to increased evolvability, and that the systems generating hereditary variations have themselves evolved, becoming increasingly sophisticated, thereby increasing evolvability. One of the greatest sources of variation in sexually reproducing organisms is meiotic recombination. A large body of data shows that the site and rate of meiotic recombination can be altered in response to environmental conditions, and that these properties were most probably moulded by natural selection. Moreover, it has been shown that mutational changes in DNA base sequence can span a spectrum from totally blind, to spatially targeted, to directed and adaptive; mutation rates are under environmental and developmental control with specific and evolved internal genetic engineering systems carrying out genomic changes in response to challenges. James Shapiro’s book Evolution: A View from the 21st Century marshals a lot of old and new evidence pertaining to these issues. The evidence leads Shapiro to argue that the genome should be regarded not as a ‘read only memory (ROM) system’, subject only to accidental changes, but as a ‘read–write (RW) memory organelle’, a system that dynamically modifies existing information both during individual development and during evolution (Shapiro, 2011). It should be stressed that even if we were not aware of the supporting data that Shapiro and others present, Darwinian evolutionary logic would compel us to assume that such variational systems should have appeared during evolutionary history. There is nothing magical about variation-generating systems that shield them from being Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 180 BOOK REVIEWS shaped by natural selection. There are adaptive mutational hot spots, genomic regions that are sensitive to specific stresses, and adaptive biases in the mutation rate, and the sites of integration of transposed or externally acquired DNA sequences (Jablonka and Lamb, 2005/2014; Shapiro, 2011). As the geneticist Lynn Caporale wrote, ‘Chance favors the prepared genome’ (Caporale, 1999). The ability to be so prepared is moulded by natural selection. In addition to the responsiveness of the genomic system, additional information-transmitting systems, which play a role both in the regulation of development and in the transmission of information within and between generations, have evolved during the history of life. Such evolved systems enable the transmission of targeted and induced developmental variation. In other words, they enable ‘soft inheritance’, the inheritance of environmentally directed and developmentally filtered variations. These include: the epigenetic inheritance systems (EISs), which allow gene expression patterns to be transmitted both within and between generations; the behavioural inheritance systems that enable the transmission of non-symbolic, socially learned information within and between generations; and the symbolic systems (such as language, art, and music) that are specific to humans. All these enable the transmission of developmentally acquired — induced and learned — information. Moreover, these inheritance systems interact and can influence the direction and rate of evolution of the genetic system (Jablonka and Lamb, 2005/2014). Although there is always a stochastic element in the generation of variation, the variation that is eventually transmitted is in no sense the result of purely random accidents: dedicated evolved systems ensure that hereditary variations — evolutionary guesses — are educated and informed, rather than blind shots in the dark. These evolved systems are intrinsic teleological systems, presenting no special mystery for evolutionary biologists. They are the outcomes of selection rather than being the consequence of a special, additional, law of nature as Nagel proposes. Nagel’s portrayal of modern evolutionary theory as one based on ‘random mutation and natural selection’ is crude, dated, and misleading. The existence of sophisticated information-generating and transmitting systems means that the blind watchmaker has evolved some residual vision (Avital and Jablonka, 2000). The rules of evolution have been themselves evolving. BOOK REVIEWS 181 Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction The Major Teleological Evolutionary Transitions in Evolution: Some Lessons from the Origin of Life Research Nagel’s focus on life and living, on consciousness or phenomenal experiencing, and on human abstract reasoning and moral evaluation — all phenomena and processes that presuppose values and goals — has deep roots in western philosophy: Aristotle carved the living world at these very same teleological joints in On the Soul. From an evolutionary point of view, the understanding of the evolutionary transitions that led to these Aristotelian goal-directed systems is, indeed, the greatest challenge of twenty-first-century evolutionary biology. The first challenge is the transition to the first living system/s, to Aristotle’s nutritive soul, a very difficult and intensely researched topic, which most scientists would agree does not present a conceptual mystery. The second is the understanding of the transition to consciousness, the evolutionary origin of Aristotle’s sensitive soul, where we are still largely in the dark (not for long, we believe), and the third is the transition to rationalizing-symbolizing animals, to Aristotle’s rational (human) soul, one of the hottest topics in present-day evolutionary-cognitive biology, going all the way back to Darwin (1871). Although all these goal-directed systems are the products of chemical and biological evolution, how they evolved are major questions for evolutionary biologists and for philosophers, because with all these teleological transitions a new way of being emerged. Since Nagel regards the origin of life as a process that cannot be explained by current naturalistic approaches, we briefly outline the approaches that led to breakthroughs in the study of the origin of life and transformed it from a metaphysical mystery to a tough scientific problem. We suggest that similar approaches can lead to progress in understanding the transition to consciousness, and that these are already employed in studying the transition to human rationality and values. Before matter was viewed as inherently active, before Darwin’s evolutionary theory, and before the appreciation of biochemical cycles in the early twentieth century, the dynamic goal-directed organization that is the hallmark of living organisms could not be comprehended. The phenomenon of life was seen, quite rightly, as a deep mystery by biologically well-informed philosophers and naturalists. In the first third of the twentieth century, after these insights were gained, Alexander Oparin in the Soviet Union and J.B.S. Haldane in the United Kingdom suggested scenarios for the origin of life. Their suggestions were anchored in two related convictions and three empirical insights. The two convictions, which were shared by all Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 182 BOOK REVIEWS evolutionary biologists since the beginning of the nineteenth century when Lamarck first proposed them, were that life is to be understood as a certain type of dynamic organization, and that no life-specific vitalist principles and assumptions were needed: the dynamical organization we call life is constituted by coupled chemical reactions the components of which can be identified in as yet non-living complex chemical systems. The three empirical insights were an understanding of cell metabolism in biochemical terms, an understanding of heredity in terms of replication, and an understanding of the kind of geochemical settings that may have prevailed on the ancient earth that could have generated the first living entities. The scenarios and the attempts to simulate them formally, in the lab, and later in silico, made the nature of life a hugely difficult scientific question. As Iris Fry’s detailed analysis shows, decisive experimental support for alternative ‘paradigms’ of the emergence of life are still lacking, but the problem is, in principle, answerable through scientific research (Fry, 2000; 2011). Although different scientists and philosophers emphasize different characteristics of life, most researchers agree about a list of features that are jointly sufficient for a system to be characterized as living: self-organization, closure/individuality, metabolism and development, responsiveness/plasticity, reproduction/multiplication, heredity and hereditary variation, and evolution by natural selection (which implies that hereditary variations affect the chances of reproduction). The simplest organizational dynamics that instantiate these properties are then sought. The ambition is not just to simulate a self-reproducing system such as a self-replicating RNA molecule, but to simulate the minimal living systems which instantiate all the above properties. In the early 1970s, Maturana and Varela suggested that a living system must have an organization that allows closure and dynamic selfconstruction and outlined the general organizational principles of such systems, which they called autopoietic systems (summarized in Maturan and Varela, 1987). At the same time, Tibor Gánti developed a more concrete theoretical-chemical model of minimal life, the chemoton, consisting of a membrane, an autocatalytic metabolic cycle, and an informational molecule regulating the rate of reproduction. The chemoton’s dynamics exhibited the basic life-characteristics mentioned above, and the chemical, cyclical-stoichiometric perspective has been useful as a guide for further theoretical and empirical approaches to the origin of life (Gánti, 1971/1987; 2003). One contemporary approach, starting from the attempt to synthesize a protocell in the laboratory, has been analysed by Mark Bedau, who explores Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction BOOK REVIEWS 183 chemoton-like CMP models. The C in CMP stands for ‘Container’ that keeps the system together, M for ‘Metabolism’ that extracts usable resources and energy from the environment, and P for ‘Program’, which controls the protocell’s process and carries replicable and inheritable combinatorial information (Bedau, 2012). As in Gánti’s chemoton, the three component systems are coupled, so that each is supporting the operation of the other components. Bedau analyses different representations of such a system which makes it possible to envisage different evolutionary routes leading to a cohesive and fully-coupled CMP, a protocell. Although the contributions of Bedau and his predecessors are conceptual, and a full-blown chemoton or CMP system has not yet been synthesized in the lab, there are intense and imaginative efforts to simulate different geochemical conditions conducive to the formation of the simplest living entities that may have existed on Earth 3.8 billion years ago. As J.D. Bernal suggested over half a century ago, once the geochemical conditions on ancient Earth are simulated, the next three stages are: (i) the emergence of biological monomers (e.g. amino acids and pyrimidines); (ii) the emergence from those monomers of more complex and more stable biological polymers and systems of interactions; (iii) the emergence from these latter systems of the first bona fide biological organisms (Bernal, 1949). Today, as many different possible geochemical conditions are simulated in labs all over the world, the first two stages have successfully been achieved. There is little doubt in the origin of life community that in spite of the great complexities involved, the generation of a bona fide protocell by the end of the twenty-first century is highly feasible. Nagel’s assertion that the origin of life is a scientific mystery requiring the aid of a new teleological law of nature that goes beyond the intrinsic teleology of self-reproducing evolving entities is not shared by the scientists working on the problem. We wish to highlight three issues related to the life-transition, which are also relevant to the other teleological evolutionary transitions. The first is that rather than a single, and inevitably highly contentious, line between life and non-life (or consciousness/nonconsciousness), a transition is likely to be gradual. A grey zone, a spectrum rather than a single transition point, marks the road to the mature new system. Nevertheless, a complexity threshold marking a state of a mature new system can be and should be suggested, for it is the recognition of this complexity threshold that enables us to reconstruct the transition and the grey area. Maynard Smith and Szathmáry (1995) suggested that with the transition to life, the threshold is Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 184 BOOK REVIEWS marked by the system manifesting unlimited heredity. Systems that can have only very few hereditary variants are limited heredity systems, and are not fully living; they reside in the grey area between the living and non-living phases. They are on the evolutionary route to life if they evolve further and the number of their hereditary variations becomes practically unlimited. According to Maynard Smith and Szathmáry, the transition to open-ended evolution marks the complexity threshold for living. As we see it, such heredity systems had to be part of something like an autopoietic chemoton system to carry out the complex processes that enable unlimited heredity and open-ended evolution. We suggest that similar criteria can be employed when identifying the other teleological transitions: the transition to consciousness is marked by unlimited associative learning (Ginsburg and Jablonka, 2010), and the transition to rationality and human values by unlimited symbolic representation. The second issue is closely related to the previous one, and addresses one of the concerns Nagel voiced, the supposed statistical implausibility of the emergence of life from ‘mere’ chemistry, especially since rare events cannot be amplified by natural selection. However, some reactions (e.g. cyclical reaction on two-dimensional surfaces) can be more stable than others, and these reactions can scaffold further reactions which are even more stable, and so on (see, for example, the scenario suggested by Wächtershäuser, 2006). Evolution by differential stabilization rather than by conventional natural selection can be the result. Moreover, as the origin of life research has shown, there is nothing out of the ordinary about the chemical reactions leading to the first stages in the process, although it did take a lot of ingenuity to simulate Bernal’s first two stages. The third stage, the generation of a protocell by combining several complex chemical cycles, is very demanding and as yet difficult for scientists to simulate; however, in a planet rich in complex organic molecules and chemical cycles, and with a variety of conditions, the chances that in several hundred million years selective stabilization processes will lead to the emergence of protocells seems plausible if not inevitable; hence — in the words of one scientist — life would be a ‘cosmic imperative’ (de Duve, 1995). De Duve offered a detailed scenario that may serve as an example of the type of physical and chemical constraints that would drive the formation and stabilization of organic molecules such as different amino acids and the resulting multimers. He argued that the chemical constraints ensured that the proto-metabolic reactions were reproduced as long as environmental conditions did not change, and enabled the later effectiveness and selective Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction BOOK REVIEWS 185 advantage of the first metabolic enzymes and ribozymes. He concluded that ‘life arose through the succession of an enormous number of small steps, almost each of which, given the condition at the time, had a very high probability of happening’ (de Duve, 1991, p. 112). A third issue is the unaided emergence of novel entities with new goals. Nagel regards such emergence as unsatisfactory: he feels that life, consciousness, reason, moral values cannot be just ‘spandrels’, or by-products of lower level processes. In a sense he is right: although like any genuine novelty when it first originates the above processes are not products of selection for that novelty, their nature is not exhausted by this assertion and by saying that new functions are enabled when they appear. Once teleological transitions occur they present a new way of being. The emergent entity requires new categories for describing it. With the emergence of life, mere chemical processes and mechanisms became organized into systems to which a goal can be ascribed (the goal is self-maintenance), and it is with this transition that the parts and processes of such systems could be said to have functions. Function is not a new high-level chemical process or trait: in Aristotelian terms, it is a facet of the teleological cause, ‘that for the sake of which’; it is something that only parts or processes in goal-directed systems can have. Biological function (also known among philosophers as teleo-function) is defined as the role that a part, a process, or a mechanism plays within an encompassing system, a role that contributes to the goal-directed behaviour of that system. As we have already noted, the most basic goal-directed behaviour of living organisms is self-maintenance (survival), and in the long-term, reproduction. Functional information is any difference that makes a difference to the goal-directed behaviour of a system, and in the case of simple living forms, to the system’s self-sustaining dynamics. Preliving chemical processes do not have functional information, since they are not part of a self-maintaining complex system. Functions and functional information define the way of being of living organisms, and are therefore irreducible to descriptions in terms of simple chemistry. And once functions can be ascribed to parts and processes within a system and there are hereditary variations that affect functionality, the system can evolve by natural or artificial selection. In this context, the views of another philosopher, David Chalmers, should be mentioned: like Nagel, Chalmers thinks that consciousness poses an insurmountable problem to present-day science (‘the hard problem’); but, unlike Nagel, he regards the issue of the origin of life as merely that of understanding complex and adaptive mechanisms (that are, of course teleo-functions; Chalmers, 1997); from our perspective, this claim is Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 186 BOOK REVIEWS beside the point, because only with the emergence of life did the notion of function become meaningful in the first place. The result of the century-long experimenting, theorizing, and philosophizing about the origin of life is that the nature of life and the naturalistic origins of living entities lost their aura of metaphysical mystery for most scientists and biologically informed philosophers. We have acquired an improved understanding of the dynamic nature of matter, we have good ideas as to how certain types of autopoieticdynamics can instantiate it (chemoton dynamics is one example), we can describe aspects of such systems mathematically (see, for example, Bailly and Longo, 2011), and we can figure out how functions arise. We have yet to accomplish the third and most difficult stage in Bernal’s scheme, and this may take much time and much ingenuity, but we do not see the need for Nagel’s new teleological law of nature. Teleology is naturalistically intrinsic to life. The transition to consciousness is the greatest mystery in Nagel’s list of teleological transitions. How are we to approach it? The evolutionary transition to consciousness did not enjoy the intense and systematic exploration that we see with respect to the study of the transition to life, and this research direction is necessary if we are to get rid of the metaphysical fog surrounding the topic. In order to understand how first-person experiences arose during evolution, we suggest that a similar heuristic to that successfully used in the origin of life research is necessary: a list of broadly accepted characteristics of subjective experiencing must be compiled, and the dynamics that constitutes the enlisted characteristics must be sought. Identifying a complexity threshold can greatly help in discovering important aspects of this dynamics, and the exploration of evolutionary building blocks and scenarios can lead to new insights. Finally, just as functioning is not a new high-level chemical process or trait but rather a facet of the newly evolved reproductive telos, so consciousness should be seen as a facet of a new telos. Conscious states are emergent, dynamic, system-wide sensory categories (what we call felt-needs and motives), that had evolved as an aspect of complex associative learning and that had opened up a whole new functional realm (Ginsburg and Jablonka, 2010). Like every emergent property, the origin of such primary consciousness was not the result of selection for it, but calling it a spandrel rather than an emergent organizational property is in this case an unhelpful rephrasing of its emergent nature. The same evolutionary heuristic is applicable to the evolutionarily related issues of human reasoning and human values. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction BOOK REVIEWS 187 There are many additional issues that we did not address in this review, some of which were discussed in depth by other reviewers of Nagel’s book. The notions of reductionism and emergence that Nagel endorses are highly problematic, a point which was discussed by Dupré (2012). Another point we did not discuss here is Nagel’s notion of physical matter, which is far from being ‘inert’, but is seen by physicists as a complicated flux of dynamic elementary particles held dynamically by various forces. We did not discuss the problem of the evolution of the genetic code and translation, which is, indeed, one of the most difficult and as yet unresolved problems in evolutionary biology. There are three major theoretical approaches which when combined can — in principle — provide a solution to this problem, although there is no experimental research programme at present that can reconstruct the actual stages in the evolution of the code (Koonin and Novozhilov, 2009). Lastly, we barely touched the weakest arguments in Nagel’s complaint — the evolution of reason and human values, which are intimately related to the evolution of human linguistic representation and social communication, a central topic in the study of human evolution (Dunbar, 1996; Larson, Déprez and Yamakido, 2010), which is hardly mentioned by Nagel. In summary, we believe that Nagel is right in arguing that the teleological transitions posit special philosophical and evolutionary challenges. However, we believe that all these transitions are explicable within a sophisticated evolutionary framework, which once understood seeps down (or up?) and reframes the philosophical problems. We think that Nagel’s problem may be the well-recognized problem of the failure of evolutionary imagination. As Darwin confessed, the evolution of the eye made him shudder, but as he explained, this was the problem of a failure of his imagination rather than a failure of his evolutionary theory (Darwin, 1859/1872). Once the major teleological transitions are studied from an evolutionary-transition perspective, Nagel’s constitutive problem is likely to dissolve and with it his demand for a special and general teleological law of nature. New teloi do appear during the history of life and they do begin to drive the evolution of the lineages in which they emerge, but physical emergence and a sophisticated version of naturalistic evolutionary theory provide a sufficient explanation. Acknowledgment We thank Iris Fry for her helpful comments on this review-essay. 188 BOOK REVIEWS Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction References Avital, E. & Jablonka, E. (2000) Animal Traditions: Behavioural Inheritance in Evolution, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bailly, F. & Longo, G. (2011) Mathematics and the Natural Sciences: The Physical Singularity of Life, London: Imperial College Press. Bedau, M.A. (2012) A functional account of degrees of minimal chemical life, Synthese, 185 (1), pp. 73–88. Bernal, J.D. (1949) The physical basis of life, Proceedings of the Physical Society A, 62, pp. 537–538. Caporale, L.H. (1999) Chance favors the prepared genome, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 18 (870), pp. 1–21. Chalmers, D.J. (1997) Moving forward on the problem of consciousness, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4 (1), pp. 3–46. Darwin, C. (1859/1872) The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life, 6th ed., London: John Murray. Darwin, C. (1871) The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex, 1st ed., London: John Murray. Dawkins, R. (1986) The Blind Watchmaker, New York: W.W. Norton. de Duve, C. (1991) Blueprint for a Cell: The Nature and Origin of Life, Burlington, NC: Neil Patterson Publishers. de Duve, C. (1995) Vital Dust: Life as a Cosmic Imperative, New York: Harper Collins Publishers. Dunbar, R. (1996) Grooming, Gossip and the Evolution of Language, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Dupré, J. (2012) Book review of Thomas Nagel, Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly False, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, 29 October. Fry, I. (2000) The Emergence of Life on Earth — a Historical and Scientific Overview, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Fry, I. (2011) The role of natural selection in the origin of life, Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, 41 (1), pp. 3–16. Gánti, T. (1971, Eng. trans. 1987) The Principle of Life, Budapest: Omikk. Gánti, T. (2003) The Principles of Life, with a Commentary by James Griesemer and Eörs Szathmáry, New York: Oxford University Press. Ginsburg, S. & Jablonka, E. (2010) Experiencing: A Jamesian approach, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 17 (5–6), pp. 102–124. Jablonka, E. & Lamb, M.J. (2005/2014) Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Koonin, E. & Novozhilov, A.S. (2009) Origin and evolution of the genetic code: The universal enigma, Life, 61 (2), pp. 99–111. Larson, R.K., Déprez,V. & Yamakido, H. (2010) The Evolution of Human Language: Biolinguistic Perspectives, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Maturana, H.R. & Varela, F.J. (1987) The Tree of Knowledge: The Biological Roots of Human Understanding, Boston, MA: Shambhala Publication. Maynard Smith, J. & Szathmáry, E. (1995) The Major Transitions in Evolution, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nagel, T. (2012) Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialistic Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly Wrong, Oxford: Oxford university Press. Shapiro, J.A. (2011) Evolution: A View from the 21st Century, Upper Saddle River, NJ: FT Press Science. BOOK REVIEWS 189 Wächtershäuser, G. (2006) From volcanic origins of chemoautotrophic life to Bacteria, Archaea and Eukarya, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society London, B, 361, pp. 1787–1806. Giulio Tononi PHI F: A Voyage from the Brain to the Soul New York: Pantheon Books, 2012, 364 pp. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction Review by Richard A. Buck California Institute of Integral Studies Galileo awakes and finds his soul hovering above his sleeping body, and suddenly it is swept through his nostrils into his skull. His soul floats through his brain, and sees a universe within his skull. He thinks, ‘What is, is what can be perceived. Reality is only made of pure experience. The brain can hold the sky because it can beget the soul, and when a soul is born, a universe is delivered’(Tononi, 2012, p. 8). Thus begins Galileo’s journey in search of the nature of the soul, and his dialogues with great minds of the various centuries. Through the device of Galileo’s dialogues, Tononi in PHI F explains the current neurological research into consciousness for the general reader, culminating in a description of his own theory of consciousness. PHI F is a work of art. The sentences and paragraphs flow easily in a conversational tone; it is after all a dialogue between Galileo and other great minds. It reads like a detective story, uncovering the secrets of consciousness step by step, and Tononi succeeds in creating suspense about what Galileo is going to find next. It is organized into 33 short chapters. Most chapters begin with a one-sentence statement of what will be demonstrated in the chapter. Each chapter ends with notes, where Tononi explains some of the scientific history behind the dialogue in the chapter, and sometimes alerts us to slight inaccuracies in the dialogue from a scientific point of view. The notes also describe the art in the chapter. The text is richly illustrated, often with images of great works of art — almost one on every page. The only criticism I have of the pictures is that they are not captioned, and you have to consult the notes to view their pedigree. While captions might have detracted from the aesthetics of the pages, they would have improved the reading experience. Why does Tononi resurrect Galileo to be our tour guide to consciousness? Tononi wrote a book on Galileo, which has not yet been translated into English, so we can presume that he knows quite a bit about the man. Galileo is actually the perfect guide. With his keen scientific intellect, he asks the right questions, yet at the beginning Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 190 BOOK REVIEWS knows no more than us. Like Socrates, Galileo does not rest until he achieves a clear understanding of what he sees and hears. While Galileo is our main guide, he converses with a number of pseudonymous characters created by Tononi, but modelled after great philosophers and scientists in history. Among the models for his characters are: Francis Crick, Descartes, Alan Turing, Claude Shannon (father of information theory), Kant, William James, Thomas Nagel (philosopher), Spinoza, Leibniz, and Darwin. Galileo even has a talk with the devil. Giulio Tononi, a psychiatrist and neuroscientist, is the David P. White Professor of Sleep Medicine at the University of Wisconsin. He has developed a theory of consciousness, which he calls the integrated information theory of consciousness. While PHI F was written to explain his theory to non-scientists, readers can find a technical explanation of his theory in Tononi (2008). The underlying neurological processes of his theory are explained in A Universe of Consciousness: How Matter Becomes Imagination (Edelman and Tononi, 2000), written with Nobel prize winner Gerald M. Edelman. Tononi and Edelman classify their work as the ‘neural correlates of consciousnesses’ (ibid., p. 8), and they distance themselves from cognitive psychologists, who use metaphors from artificial intelligence and computer science to explain consciousness. While Tononi’s theory employs mathematics extensively (Tononi, 2008), PHI F stays clear of mathematics — except for one mathematical expression (in the notes on p. 145). Tononi’s hypothesis is that consciousness is integrated information and that the level of consciousness depends on how much information is integrated. He names this integration of information F (Phi). Here is Galileo’s summary of what he has learned about F: F may be low for individual neurons, each one too feeble to effect much change by itself, though they be multitudes. And giant crowds of neurons are far too rough to make the fine distinctions that consciousness requires. But small groups of neurons will speak together loudly, be better heard by other groups, and together form a large and varied complex of surpassing F. (Tononi, 2012, p. 344) In other words, integrated information is ‘the information generated by a system above its parts, where the parts are those that, taken independently, generated the most information’ (ibid., p. 164). There is no difference relative to F, in Tononi’s view, between a human or animal brain and another type of complex system, such as wires and integrated circuits. If we could build a system of integrated circuits Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction BOOK REVIEWS 191 complex enough, it could integrate information to the degree that it would be conscious. Having established consciousness as integrated information of a complex system, Tononi, through Galileo, unveils its implications. While consciousness does not reduce to matter, it relies on matter; if the brain is destroyed, the ‘soul too would collapse’ (ibid., p. 239). Animals have consciousness, just not as much as humans. Also, at some point, a fetus has consciousness. Yet, contemplates Galileo: ‘There is less soul in a slumbering human embryo than in a poor old donkey… Early on, an embryo’s consciousness — the value of its F — may be less than a fly’s’ (ibid., p. 281). The possibility of quantifying F raises some intriguing questions regarding the various states of consciousness discussed by Wilber, Combs, and others. For instance, the Wilber-Combs Lattice has developmental stages of consciousness on one axis and realms of conscious experience on the other (Combs, 2009, p. 101). If a person’s consciousness is at the intersection of non-dual on the realm of experience axis and rational on the developmental axis, what would we expect the quantity of F to be? Would F increase as one moved up the lattice from archaic to integral and across the lattice from gross to non-dual? Or perhaps F would not increase at all, but different areas of the brain would be activated in different states of consciousness. Tononi asserts that F would increase as brains become more complex and the activity of integration increases. Thus, we could confidently assert that a human would have a higher F than a fish. But, would I have less F than the Dalai Lama? PHI F does not enlighten us on these questions, but if Tononi’s work progresses to the point where F can be measured, many avenues for research would be opened. The F level of practising Buddhists and Hindus could be measured and correlated with their subjective states of consciousness, which of course would present additional problems of measurement. If we were able to do this, would it enhance our understanding of states of consciousness? We do not know, but even the Dalai Lama has said on many occasions that all knowledge, including advances in science, should be used to improve our understanding of ourselves and the universe. My supposition is that to actually compare the neural integration of information with the various ideas of states of consciousness that more than a single value of F would be needed. We would have to have a way of measuring which areas of the brain were most prominent in the integration. Tononi’s F theory has some critics in the neuroscience field. Christof Koch identifies challenging aspects of the theory (Koch, Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 192 BOOK REVIEWS 2009, p. 19). First, to calculate the value of F, even for an earthworm, would take all of Google’s more than 100,000 computers. Second, it does not answer why nature evolved creatures with a high F. Third, it does not explain why so much of our brain processing and behaviour is unconscious. Michael Cerullo praises Tononi’s theory for ‘being one of the first theories to link consciousness with empirically testable concepts of information’ (Cerullo, 2011, p. 46). Yet, Cerullo points out that the theory has flaws as an information theory. One of the flaws is that the theory does not have a way of assigning meaning to the integrated information. This thinking is in line with the point I make above that we probably need more than a single value of F to correlate with a state of consciousness. PHI F is a fun and informative read. It is a pleasurable way for the general reader to get up to speed on the neuroscience of consciousness. The book would be worth buying just for the pictures. For those of us who believe that there is something transcendent about consciousness, Tononi gives no support. Yet, it is hard to deny a neurological relationship with consciousness, whether you believe that the brain causes consciousness or not. Tononi finds no evidence of a transcendent consciousness, but he does not disprove its existence either. However, if the idea of F leads to a better understanding of the brain, it is a worthwhile endeavour. References Cerullo, M.A. (2011) Integrated information theory: A promising but ultimately incomplete theory of consciousness, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18 (11–12), pp. 45–58. Combs, A. (2009) Consciousness Explained Better: Towards an Integral Understanding of the Multifaceted Nature of Consciousness, St. Paul, MN: Paragon House. Edelman, G.M. & Tononi, G. (2000) A Universe of Consciousness: How Matter Becomes Imagination, New York: Basic Books. Koch, C. (2009) A theory of consciousness: Is complexity the secret of sentience, to a panpsychic view of consciousness?, Scientific American Mind, pp. 16–19. Tononi, G. (2008) Consciousness as integrated information: A provisional manifesto, The Biological Bulletin, 215, pp. 216–242. Tononi, G. (2012) PHI F: A Voyage from the Brain to the Soul, New York: Pantheon Books. BOOK REVIEWS 193 Derk Pereboom Consciousness and the Prospects of Physicalism Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011, 197 pp. ISBN: 978-0-19-976403-7 Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction Reviewed by Tom McClelland Lecturer, University of Glasgow Email: [email protected] In his latest book, Derk Pereboom explores the prospects of a physicalist metaphysics of consciousness. His overall position is that ‘…there are several physicalist options that are serious possibilities, and although we do not now know that any one of them is true, knowledge of this general sort is not ruled out’ (p. 8). He argues that any progress for physicalism will depend on questions about the nature of consciousness, the nature of the physical, or the nature of the metaphysical relation between them. Interestingly, Pereboom offers proposals in all three categories over the three sections of his book. Chapters 1–4 challenge our grasp of our own conscious states by developing the qualitative inaccuracy hypothesis. The idea is that ‘…introspection represents phenomenal properties as having certain characteristic qualitative natures, and it may be that these properties actually lack such features’ (p. 3). The possibility of this systematic misrepresentation of our own phenomenal properties is claimed to undermine the knowledge and conceivability arguments against physicalism. Chapters 5–6 focus on the physical side of the equation by exploring Russellian monism. This is ‘…any view that combines (1) categorical ignorance, the claim that physics, or at least current physics, leaves us ignorant of certain categorical bases of physical dispositional properties, with (2) consciousness- or experience-relevance, the proposal that these categorical properties have a significant role in explaining consciousness or experience’ (p. 89). Some versions of Russellian monism can be construed as physicalist. Chapters 7–8 present a non-reductive physicalism. Against reductionism, Pereboom argues that ‘[n]atural kinds in psychology are not identical to natural kinds in physics because psychological causal powers are not identical to microphysical causal powers’ (p. 5). To square this robust psychological realism with physicalism, he proposes that ‘[t]he deepest relation between the psychological and the microphysical is constitution, where this relation is not to be explicated by the notion of identity’ (p. 5). All mental properties are composed of physical properties, but not reducible to them. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 194 BOOK REVIEWS These three themes are unified, as Pereboom explains (p. 3), by a Kantian influence (it is no coincidence that the author is a scholar of Kant in his own right). Other figures in the history of philosophy also crop up in Pereboom’s arguments. Ideas from Descartes, Locke, and Leibniz are presented with great clarity and applied effortlessly to the contemporary debate on consciousness. This unusual attention to historical figures proves to be productive and illuminating on several occasions. The book’s three themes are also unified by their each being somewhat unconventional. Though they are all off-piste versions of physicalism, Pereboom consistently shows why they should be taken seriously. The take-home message of the book is that if physicalism turns out to be true, it will be in some non-standard form. Rather than attempting to salvage failed physicalist proposals, Pereboom carefully points the way to new and exciting alternatives. I have mentioned some threads that unify the book, but I should also mention its deeply disjunctive nature. We are presented with three quite distinct physicalist positions, and within the three corresponding sections we are often presented with a range of alternative options. As a reader, one should not look for ‘the Pereboom account of consciousness’. There is none. This makes critical evaluation tricky. Challenging his arguments is less like attacking the soft underbelly of a dragon, and more like battling a hydra: for every position you reject, two more seem to grow in its place! Those searching for definitive proposals will also be frustrated by the heavily qualified character of Pereboom’s conclusions. One important analysis of a thought experiment is merely deemed ‘not implausible’ (p. 23) and one position is only favoured ‘tentatively’ (p. 42). This tone is ubiquitous, and many claims are not asserted outright. The disjunctive and tentative nature of Pereboom’s proposals should by no means be regarded as weaknesses. They reflect his stated aim of identifying ‘serious possibilities’ for physicalism rather than advocating a definitive stance (p. 8). Where others are guilty of ignoring the shortcomings of their accounts, Pereboom is consistently sensitive to an idea’s limitations and to alternative possibilities. He is aware not just of philosophical considerations that could count against his proposals, but of the important role of empirical developments in deciding the issue of physicalism (p. 172). For instance, he states that the accuracy of his non-reductive account ‘…is a matter for empirical investigation, which is currently incomplete, and so confidence that this position is true would need to be moderated’ (p. 169). The last sentence of the book captures his humility: ‘…my arguments don’t come close to showing that these physicalist proposals are true, BOOK REVIEWS 195 but only that they are reasonable options in the ongoing debate’ (p. 172). This modest conclusion clearly reflects a deep appreciation for the subtleties of the question at hand, and does nothing to diminish the significance of the book’s many achievements. To give an idea of those achievements, it will be worth considering each of Pereboom’s three main proposals in turn. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction The Qualitative Inaccuracy Hypothesis This is, as far as I can tell, a genuinely original strategy for the defence of physicalism. It is the most intriguing proposal of the book and is worthy of particular attention. Conscious states have phenomenal properties, and our introspection of those properties represents them as having a certain qualitative nature. Despite the best efforts of existing physicalist proposals, it appears that a phenomenal property cannot at once have that qualitative nature and be physical. However, Pereboom suggests it is a possibility that phenomenal properties ‘…do not in fact have these qualitative natures, and that introspective representation is in this sense inaccurate’ (p. 14). This is not to say the phenomenal properties do not exist, but rather that we get the nature of those properties wrong. The real nature of phenomenal properties is physical, while the characteristics that preclude them from being physical are misattributed to them. More boldly, Pereboom suggests that the relevant misrepresentation could involve introspection presenting phenomenal properties as primitive when they are not (p. 17). Phenomenal properties appear to be metaphysically simple properties whose entire qualitative essence is revealed in introspection, but it is an open possibility that this does not reflect the true nature of those properties. Chapter 1 introduces the hypothesis in the context of the knowledge argument. The suggestion is that even though Mary ‘…does not represent phenomenal states in the characteristic introspective way…’, it could still be the case that ‘…the natures of these properties might accurately be represented by way of Mary’s physical knowledge’ (p. 24). On leaving her monochromatic room, Mary does acquire a new belief that the phenomenal property characteristic of seeing red has that mysterious qualitative nature ‘R’. However, ‘[o]n our open possibility, phenomenal redness has no such qualitative nature, so this belief will be false’ (p. 25). The true nature of phenomenal redness was already captured by her physical knowledge. Mary’s putative discovery is actually just a misrepresentation of a phenomenal property Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 196 BOOK REVIEWS with which she was already familiar. Since Mary does not learn any new truth about red perception, the threat to physicalism disappears. Chapter 3 explains the application of the qualitative inaccuracy hypothesis to the conceivability argument — specifically Chalmers’ zombie argument. We can indeed conceive of a ‘…scenario exactly like ours microphysically but without phenomenal properties whose qualitative natures are accurately represented introspectively…’ (p. 59). However, the hypothesis of misrepresentation suggests that phenomenal properties are not in fact accurately represented by introspection. As such, when we take ourselves to be imagining a zombie scenario, we are not imagining a scenario that lacks phenomenal properties as they really are. We can imagine microphysical duplicates of our world that are stripped of the phenomenal properties that appear to be instantiated in our world. However, the claim is that a world like ours microphysically but without the phenomenal properties that they really have is not ideally conceivable. As is well known, only ideal conceivability plausibly entails metaphysical possibility. If the inaccuracy hypothesis is true, an agent in ideal conditions would know that phenomenal properties do not have the nature that they introspectively appear to have: the nature that floats free of the physical facts. Genuine zombie scenarios would then be inconceivable to such an agent. Pereboom illuminates his proposal by way of an analogy with secondary properties. Our tactile sensation of warm air might accurately represent its temperature, but we misrepresent the air as having a quality that, as Locke would put it, ‘resembles’ our sensation of it (p. 16). The heat-sensation is a feature of how heat appears to us when it affects us, but not a feature of how it really is. The Kantian insight is that this kind of distinction also applies to our knowledge of mental states. Our awareness of mental states is causally mediated, so mental states may not appear as they really are (p. 9). Pereboom’s suggestion is that introspective representations of phenomenal states systematically misrepresent them as having a qualitative nature that does not correspond to their actual qualitative nature. This is a fascinating strategy, but is not without its problems. When science banished qualities such as redness from external objects, those qualities were rehoused in the perceptual experiences of observers to whom those objects appear. However, as science attempts to grapple with the nature of conscious experiences, there again seems to be no place for such qualities. Pereboom’s strategy is to rehouse those qualities once more. Conscious states do not really have that qualitative nature, but merely appear to from the perspective of introspective Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction BOOK REVIEWS 197 states. Put like this, it seems that Pereboom is merely shifting the problem to a new location. To his credit, he pre-empts this criticism and attempts to rebut it (pp. 26–8). He argues that there is no commitment to introspective states themselves having the problematic qualitative nature. They might appear to, but this would just be yet another level of misrepresentation (p. 27). For Pereboom, it is misrepresentation all the way up! However, for his analogy with secondary properties to hold, the buck must surely stop with something that really does have the qualitative nature in question. Pereboom goes to great lengths (especially in chapter 4) to map out how the hypothesis relates to existing physicalist positions, and how it avoids the objections raised against them. His perceptive and succinct summaries of the literature are greatly illuminating and helpfully locate his proposal within the debate. Pereboom’s project requires him to perform something of a tight-rope walk: on the one hand, he risks being too generous towards existing physicalist accounts, rendering his alternative view redundant. On the other, he risks conceding too much to the anti-physicalist critics of those accounts, and failing to evade their objections. Since the correct account of consciousness will surely be found between the extremes, this balancing act is well motivated, and for the most part it is performed successfully. For instance, Pereboom shows how his proposal maintains something of the spirit of the phenomenal concept strategy whilst avoiding its propensity to ‘…predict seeming possibilities where there are none’ (p. 83). That said, other explorations of pre-existing positions are less successful. An extended examination of Stoljar’s Epistemic Strategy paints the qualitative inaccuracy hypothesis as a much-needed supplement to Stoljar’s account (pp. 69–75). Stoljar proposes that the apparent irreducibility of conscious experiences is symptomatic of our limited conception of the non-experiential world. One plausible line of criticism suggests that ‘…Stoljar’s case would benefit from a partially specified hypothesis about the nonexperiential that could really be true’ (p. 74). Pereboom’s suggestion is that the fact of which we are ignorant is that introspection misrepresents the qualitative nature of phenomenal properties. This suggestion gets Stoljar’s strategy wrong in at least two ways. First, Stoljar is concerned with the possibility of our having an impoverished conception of the non-experiential: we are missing a concept required for the explanation of consciousness. Learning that the qualitative inaccuracy hypothesis is true does not involve acquiring a richer conception of the non-experiential, so is not the kind of possibility with which Stoljar is concerned. Second, the 198 BOOK REVIEWS real appeal of Stoljar’s proposal is that it leaves consciousness precisely as it is. Our experiences can be exactly as they appear to be, yet have a non-experiential explanation, even though that explanation is presently beyond our comprehension. Pereboom’s position, however, leaves our conception of the non-experiential as it is, and instead demands a radical shift in our understanding of consciousness. Ironically, the Russellian monism that Pereboom considers next is the kind of proposal countenanced by Stoljar’s strategy. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction Russellian Monism In chapters 5–6 Pereboom proposes Russellian monism as an alternative possibility for physicalists. Our current physical concepts refer to properties via their causal role, but do not characterize the categorical bases that explain them. Thus, ‘…we are at this point ignorant of the nature of these categorical properties. This ignorance creates epistemic space for speculative proposals about the nature of these categorical bases that might at the same time explain phenomenal consciousness’ (p. 89). If those unknown properties qualify as physical, then physicalism would be vindicated. With a conception of the physical that included those categorical properties, zombies would be rendered inconceivable. In this section, Pereboom is not developing a new physicalist proposal but rather expounding and assessing a pre-existing position. His examination of this perplexing strategy is outstanding. The current debate contains confusion about the nature of the properties of which we are thought to be ignorant. Pereboom cuts through this confusion in an exposition that synthesizes ideas from Leibniz and Kant to Stoljar and Blackburn and which navigates the tricky ‘dispositional/ categorical’, ‘extrinsic/intrinsic’, and ‘absolute/relative’ conceptual dichotomies. Issues surrounding the nature of our ignorance — whether it is a failure of deduction, acquaintance, or abduction — are also explored in a succinct and critical manner (pp. 103–9). The antiphysicalist ‘micropsychist’ proposal that the categorical properties are experiential receives a balanced evaluation (pp. 114–5), but Pereboom ultimately encourages the ‘protophenomenal’ view that those properties are non-experiential physical properties that ground both microphysical properties and phenomenal properties (pp. 115–6). There are some ideas in this section that may have benefited from further attention. For instance, a key issue is what it would take for categorical properties to qualify as physical. Pereboom states that BOOK REVIEWS 199 Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction ‘these properties might… be similar enough to those over which current physics quantifies to count as physical’ (p. 89). But it is not clear what standard of similarity is in place here, why that similarity would guarantee physicality, or whether it is plausible that categorical properties could resemble the dispositions characterized by physics. In Pereboom’s defence, the admirable efficiency of this section would perhaps have been compromised if every such issue was considered in detail. Overall, Pereboom’s examination of Russellian monism provides a valuable springboard for future discussion of this important strategy. Compositional Non-reductive Physicalism Chapters 7–8 offer a compelling picture of the metaphysical status of psychological states. Pereboom explains that ‘[t]o qualify as robust, a nonreductive physicalism must satisfy two requirements. First, neither types nor tokens of mental causal powers can be identical to types or tokens of causal powers at a more basic level. Second, the mental must be causally efficacious qua mental’ (p. 148). His motivation for the first condition concerns the multiple realizability of the mental, which he carefully argues is incompatible with mental states being identical to physical states. The motivation for the second condition is that if a psychological state is efficacious only in virtue of its physical properties, this would not be a genuine case of mental causation (pp. 157–8). Pereboom’s proposal is that mental properties are compositional, meaning that they are exhaustively constituted by physical properties. ‘The mental is physical… because each mental entity is constituted by — that is, made up of, materially coincident with, and necessitated by, but not identical with — some microphysical entity’ (p. 171). The proposed relation with the physical is tight enough to avoid Kim’s accusation that non-reductivism leads to overdetermination (pp. 141–4) and emergentism (pp. 144–7). Pereboom explains that his account offers a robust psychological realism. Interestingly, he shows how the functionalist model according to which mental states are causal structures implemented by a physical base is effectively anti-realist about mental causal powers (pp. 148–56). Pereboom’s defence of his compositional account is comprehensive and encompasses a wide range of issues and potential objections. As with his other key proposals, we are offered a sensible compromise between standard physicalist and dualist positions. 200 BOOK REVIEWS Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction Consciousness and the Prospects of Physicalism is a well-executed book that comes highly recommended. Ideas are explored with notable precision and efficiency and presented with great sensitivity to the contemporary and historical literature. A variety of original contributions are offered and, though many claims require further support, Pereboom successfully shows that the prospects for physicalism are hopeful. Shaun Gallagher Phenomenology Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012, 237 pp. ISBN 9780230272491 Reviewed by Magnus Englander Malmö University, Malmö, Sweden Saybrook University, San Francisco, CA, USA Email: [email protected] or [email protected] Husserl referred to most of his published works as introductions to phenomenology, modelling for his followers the importance of repeatedly returning to phenomenology’s point of departure and rearticulating its aims. For those writing introductions to phenomenology today, the task entails an added responsibility: serving as a point of access to a complex philosophical tradition. To accomplish this in a concise manner is an even greater challenge. A high degree of pedagogical skill is required in order for the material to be accessible for novice students without neglecting or oversimplifying essential philosophical ideas. In other words, the task of writing a good introduction is to-make-the-essential-accessible-to-the-beginner. Two recent and popular introductions to phenomenology are already available: one by Dermot Moran (2000), the other by Robert Sokolowski (2000), both entitled Introduction to Phenomenology. Moran takes the reader chronologically through some of the major contributors to the tradition, whereas Sokolowski tackles the main concepts of phenomenology more directly. Gallagher and Zahavi’s (2012) The Phenomenological Mind ought also to be mentioned: a long-anticipated text, it made phenomenology accessible at an introductory level while fostering dialogue with empirical cognitive science research. Gallagher’s (2012) Phenomenology parallels The Phenomenological Mind both in terms of its structure and its content. Nevertheless, there is also an important difference: Gallagher’s new book is Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction BOOK REVIEWS 201 broader in its scope, offering an introduction that is even more accessible to those who are encountering phenomenology for the first time. Having used the three earlier texts mentioned above in introductory phenomenology courses, I would say that Phenomenology (2012) is not a substitute for the other three but, rather, the first text I would propose students read. Gallagher grounds each chapter in classical phenomenological thought and then dialogues with contemporary phenomenology and empirical cognitive science research. Each chapter is in a sense ‘front-loaded’ with Husserl or Merleau-Ponty’s ideas, which are then explored in the contemporary context. Following the structure of Gallagher’s book, I will explore the text in three sections: Part 1 of Phenomenology discusses the nature of phenomenology and its methods, Part 2 concerns its basic concepts, and Part 3 addresses existential and interpersonal issues. Part 1 Merleau-Ponty’s (1962, p. vii) preface to the Phenomenology of Perception is his famous effort to answer to the question ‘What is Phenomenology?’. Thus it does not come as a surprise that Gallagher uses the same title for his first chapter. Gallagher reviews some of the definitions of phenomenology, including those of Sokolowski and Moran, and provides an historical account of the movement. This is a challenging task; however, Gallagher addresses it by focusing on the differences between Husserl and Heidegger, a helpful approach for students. A history of phenomenological philosophy makes up the main part of the chapter, including the ups and downs of the movement in the twentieth century and its revival in relation to the cognitive sciences in the 1990s. Gallagher does not discuss phenomenological philosophy’s impacts on clinical or research psychology (see, for example, Spiegelberg, 1972; Cloonan, 1995; Giorgi, 2009); as interesting as it would have been to the psychologist, addressing the phenomenological psychological movement in Europe or the United States is beyond the scope of this book. In introducing phenomenological philosophy it is customary to first distinguish it from naturalism and then proceed to describe Husserl’s philosophical method. Gallagher does just that in chapters 2 and 3. Chapter 2, ‘Naturalism, Transcendentalism and a New Naturalizing’, addresses the dispute regarding whether phenomenology can be naturalized or not. Gallagher introduces Husserl’s important argument against naturalism and his proposal of a phenomenological psycho- Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 202 BOOK REVIEWS logy. The chapter appropriately includes an introduction to the work of Marbach and of Varela, and finally of Gallagher’s own work with ‘front-loading’. Front-loaded phenomenology builds on the idea that phenomenological insights can be integrated into the process of experimental design, providing for a collaborative view (between the empirical scientist and the phenomenological philosopher) of how to naturalize phenomenology (pp. 37–9). Naturalization is still the first issue for phenomenology and Gallagher shows its relation to contemporary cognitive neuroscience. In chapter 3, ‘Phenomenological Methods and Some Retooling’, Gallagher introduces central methodological concepts such as the epoché, the phenomenological reduction, and eidetic variation. Having addressed these fundamentals Gallagher turns to the importance for philosophers of challenging purely philosophical findings through an exploration of the fruits of empirical psychological research. He writes, ‘Most real-world phenomena, and living bodies in particular, especially those with highly developed brains, are often too complex, unpredictable, non-linear, and so forth, for us to imaginatively vary them in an exhaustive and adequate manner’ (p. 51). After acknowledging the empirical sciences, Gallagher returns to a focus on Husserl with the cautionary note that ‘It is never certain that experimental controls introduced for good scientific reasons don’t change the phenomenon under observation. This is, once again, the problem of factual contingency, which Husserl tried to avoid by having recourse to pure imagination’ (p. 51). Gallagher then discusses how simulation methods (as employed in, for example, evolutionary robotics) might supplement the method of eidetic variation. He closes the chapter with an introduction to the first-person approach to knowledge (and how this is different from first-person as subject matter). By the end of chapter 3 the careful reader will have acquired a clear sense of the phenomenological position regarding naturalism as well as a sense of the phenomenological philosophical method. Part 2 Chapters 4, 5, and 6 address the classic topics in phenomenology such as intentionality, embodiment, and time. In the chapter on intentionality (chapter 4), Gallagher reviews Brentano’s work, and the wellknown passages in Husserl’s Logical Investigation, and summarizes the differences between the American West Coast and East Coast phenomenological camps regarding the meaning of the noema. Gallagher Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction BOOK REVIEWS 203 also offers an alternative interpretation of intentionality, drawing upon research into embodied cognition, and presents the enactive approach, anticipating the transition to chapter 5 on embodiment. In chapter 5, Gallagher takes on the meaning of hyletic data in Husserl and the contemporary rejection of qualia from functionalist and extended mind theorists. Gallagher describes the position of enactive theorists and the anti-representational view. He concludes, ‘What it is like for me, the embodied agent engaged in the world, to experience X — this is surely something that calls for further phenomenological investigation’ (p. 99, italics in original). In chapter 6, Gallagher highlights a favourite phenomenological topic, the concept of lived-time. Appropriately he front-loads Husserl’s analysis, including the irreplaceable example of listening to a melody. As in previous chapters, Gallagher relates the topic to an enactive approach. In one particular passage Gallagher makes a distinction in regard to action that could help a beginning student understand the difference between objective time (in terms of its relation to causality) and lived-time. Gallagher states, ‘If… we reframe the question in terms of the intrinsic temporality of action, it is not something in the past that causes or determines my action; it is some anticipated possibility of the future, some goal that draws me out of my past and present circumstances and allows me to transcend, and perhaps to change, all such determinations’ (p. 113). Part 3 The last part of Gallagher’s text is concerned with existential topics such as the self, narratives, the lifeworld, and intersubjectivity. In chapter 7 Gallagher examines persistent inconsistencies regarding of the notion of the Self in the phenomenological literature. Gallagher guides his reader through the complex disagreements between the movement’s founders, arriving finally at the phenomenon of the minimal self. As in his recent work with Zahavi (in The Phenomenologial Mind), the distinction between agency and ownership becomes the main focus of attention. The chapter ends with a discussion of the embodied self, including a contemporary discussion on robotics. This chapter effectively ties together themes introduced earlier in the book such as the first-person perspective and embodiment. Chapter 8 introduces the reader to the foundational concept of the lifeworld (that was briefly mentioned in the book’s opening passages). Gallagher provides a cogent introduction to the phenomenological conception of the lifeworld, drawing upon both Husserl and Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction 204 BOOK REVIEWS Heidegger: ‘The scientific world is a theory about the world — in the same way that metaphysics offers theories about the world. But before we try to explain the world in any kind of theoretical fashion, we are living in the world’ (p. 160). He returns to the exploration of selfagency but now in the context of action, all to set the stage for an introduction to the idea of the narrative self. In chapters 7 and 8 Gallagher is able to successfully integrate the book’s primary themes while saving the ‘big issue’ for last, the greatest a priori of all: intersubjectivity. Chapter 9 opens with a discussion of transcendental intersubjectivity in Husserl’s work. The question of the possibility of knowing the other merges with more fundamental question of how we are capable of knowing anything at all. By working through Husserl’s concepts of apperception and pairing, in the context of the phenomenology of empathy, Gallagher addresses the misconception that Husserlian phenomenology is guilty of solipsism. Although solipsism was already raised and negated in the introduction, in light of the eight preceding chapters, the reader will have arrived at a fuller, more integral grasp of this critical issue. Gallagher draws from Husserl, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Sartre in his discussion of intersubjectivity; however, he also integrates the important, contemporary work of Dan Zahavi. And of course, the chapter would not be complete without a section on social cognition and the arguments against theory-theorists and simulation theorists. Conclusion For those seeking an introductory text to phenomenological philosophy that reviews the major concepts in philosophy, includes the words of the phenomenological movement’s founders, and integrates research in cognitive science with contemporary phenomenological philosophy, Gallagher’s text is an excellent resource. For those seeking an historical review of the movement, Gallagher (see p. 205) recommends Moran’s introduction. Gallagher’s Phenomenology, in contrast, provides students with a stimulating introduction to contemporary phenomenological philosophizing, clearly demonstrating the way in which this path of enquiry is rooted in Husserl’s work. References Cloonan, T.F. (1995) The early history of phenomenological psychological research in America, Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 26, pp. 46–126. Gallagher, S. (2012) Phenomenology, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. BOOK REVIEWS 205 Gallagher, S. & Zahavi, D. (2012) The Phenomenological Mind, 2nd ed., London: Routledge. Giorgi, A. (2009) The Descriptive Phenomenological Method in Psychology: A Modified Husserlian Approach, Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962) The Phenomenology of Perception, London: Routledge. Moran, D. (2000) Introduction to Phenomenology, London: Routledge. Sokolowski, R. (2000) Introduction to Phenomenology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Spiegelberg, H. (1972) Phenomenology in Psychology and Psychiatry, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2013 For personal use only -- not for reproduction BOOKS RECEIVED Mention here neither implies nor precludes subsequent review Cappelen, Herman, Philosophy Without Intuitions (OUP 2012) Clark, Steve, Power, Russell, and Savulescu, Julian (eds.), Religion, Intolerance and Conflict (OUP 2013) Combs, Allan, and Holland, Mark, Synchronicity: Through the Eyes of Science, Myth and Trickster (Marlowe and Company 1996/2001) Fuster, Joaquin M., The Neuroscience of Freedom and Creativity: Our Predictive Brain (CUP 2013) Goldman, Alvin I., Joint Ventures: Mindreading, Mirroring, and Embodied Cognition (OUP 2013) Goodman, David M., The Demanded Self: Levinasian Ethics and Identity in Psychology (Duquesne University Press 2012) Howell, Robert, Consciousness and the Limits of Objectivity (OUP 2013) MacFarlane, Elizabeth, Reading Coetzee (Rodopi 2013) Miller, Christian, Moral Character: An Empirical Theory (OUP 2013) Roald, Tone, and Lang, Johannes (eds.), Art and Identity: Essays on the Aesthetic Creation of Mind (Rodopi 2013) Ross, Andy, Philosopher (Rover 2012) Schulkin, Jay, Reflections on the Musical Mind: An Evolutionary Perspective (Princeton University Press 2013) Seager, William, Natural Fabrications: Science, Emergence and Consciousness (Springer 2012) Simchen, Ori, Necessary Intentionality: A Study in the Metaphysics of Aboutness (OUP 2012) Swinburne, Richard, Mind, Brain, and Free Will (OUP 2013) Thubten, Anam, The Magic of Awareness (Snow Lion 2012) Wedemeyer, Christian, Making Sense of Tantric Buddhism: History, Semiology and Transgression in the Indian Traditions (Columbia University Press 2013) Williams Kelly, Emily (ed.), Science, the Self and Survival After Death: Selected Writings of Ian Stevenson (Rowman and Littlefield 2012) Yanay, Niza, The Ideology of Hatred: The Psychic Power of Discourse (Fordham University Press 2013) Zawidzki, Tad, Mindshaping: A New Framework for Understanding Social Cognition (MIT Press 2013) Please contact the book reviews editor, Julian Kiverstein, on [email protected] if you wish to review one of the above mentioned titles for JCS.