Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
1276 Reviews of Books idence for local police, whereas the much better developed police institutions in the Greek-speaking east display numerous local peculiarities. Modern studies, therefore, traditionally see police in the Roman Empire as almost exclusively a local affair and tend to limit themselves to specific regions such as Egypt and Asia Minor. Fuhrmann’s attempt to put diverse practices and evidence on a common ground led him not only to adopt a broader definition of policing, but also to focus specifically on the policing responsibilities of Roman soldiers who operated throughout the entire empire. The use of soldiers in protecting public order, which Fuhrmann presents as the policing role of the Roman army, is what essentially holds his thesis, and his book, together. Fuhrmann’s main arguments are that policing was the state policy, and that the role of state, or military, policing grew consistently in the first three centuries of the empire. A broader approach might have benefits, but it also creates problems. According to Fuhrmann, military policing by “outposted soldiers performing temporary police duties among civilians” on a local level increased markedly from the second century onward (p. 10). His book, however, ends in the reign of Valerian, thereby offering a very limited chronological scope of only about one hundred years. Its broad geographical scope also encounters a challenge. Trajan’s famous advice to Pliny, the governor of a Greek-speaking province, was to “keep to the laws of each city” (Pliny, Ep. 10.113). But traditions of city life, including local police institutions, were almost non-existent in the western territories beyond Italy, allowing for a much more prominent Roman influence in maintaining public order and, consequently, greater uniformity in the Latin-speaking part of the empire. The higher level of development of city life in the east also produced specific forms of interaction between local and Roman authorities, which we do not see in the west. For example, Aristides (4.72) refers to the Roman provincial governor as choosing the eirenarch from the list of ten local city councilors. A similar system seems to have survived until at least the early fifth century, when, according to the letter of Honorius and Theodosius, local city councilors nominated the eirenarchs in agreement with the Roman governor (C.J. 10.77). This evidence not only illustrates the distinctiveness of police administration in the eastern part of the empire, where the Romans demonstrated their proverbial respect for local customs, but also questions Fuhrmann’s proposed universal scheme of dividing Roman policing into levels—civilian, imperial, gubernatorial, and detached-service military. The thesis of Roman policing as a concerted policy receives no support; not even from officials with the same titles and, evidently, similar responsibilities: the defensor civitatis had local origins in the east, rather than being created from scratch as in the west. Not only did the eastern and western parts of the empire retain their differences in this field, the unifying role of military policing looks problematic as well. The locally stationed Roman soldiers (stationarii, regionarii, AMERICAN HISTORICAL REVIEW beneficiarii ) attended to many tasks, in addition to immediate police functions. Their increased visibility in the second century and later appears to have been due not only to the growing pressure on public order but also the changing relationship between the Roman state and individual cities, which itself reflected an overall transformation of the Roman imperial administration during that time. Thus, while the problem of whether we can speak about a uniform Roman policy on policing remains, this interesting book has raised many important questions and laid a useful ground for future work in the field. SVIATOSLAV DMITRIEV Ball State University SVIATOSLAV DMITRIEV. The Greek Slogan of Freedom and Early Roman Politics in Greece. New York: Oxford University Press. 2011. Pp. xiii, 524. $99.00. Sviatoslav Dmitriev seeks in this book to parse the “freedom” language commonly used in classical Greek interstate politics and sometimes taken up by Roman leaders in their dealings with the Greeks. The chronological horizons are the Peloponnesian War and the war of 146 B.C. that led to the creation of a formal Roman province in mainland Greece, with forward glances as far as the third century A.D. In the fourth century B.C. (and indeed earlier in my opinion) many Greeks discovered that freedom (eleutheria) and its cousin autonomia were highly malleable concepts, as indeed many have discovered independently in more recent ages. These concepts were constantly used by powerful states such as Macedon to cajole the leaders of Greek cities. (How a “slogan” worked in a world without mass communications is, however, a basic and fascinating question that our author does not address.) Dmitriev realizes, unlike some historians, that when Flamininus proclaimed the freedom of the Greeks on a famous occasion in 196 B.C., it was not philhellenism that was in question but an astute calculation of Roman interests, though this is a position that needs more nuances. And Rome of course found it entirely unproblematic to interfere in the affairs of Greek cities that it had declared to be free and autonomous, changing their constitutions, exacting taxes, and imposing garrisons wherever it saw fit. This is all very familiar, and a number of acute (and not so acute) scholars have been over the same material before. Dmitriev reviews many of their opinions, not always fairly, with the result that his book, though it is not a revised dissertation, is weighed down with tedious doxography. The result is a book much too plump in relation to its achievement. What is most helpful here, however, is the longue durée : it probably does help to explain the ill-concealed resentment of Roman power still felt by some Greeks in the second and indeed third centuries A.D. that freedom had been so often dangled before them during centuries of what they perceived as enslavement. Not that Dmitriev himself says this. Also useful is the detailed account of Rome’s frequently misunderstood relations OCTOBER 2012 Europe: Ancient and Medieval with the Achaean League, culminating in the destruction of the city of Corinth in 146 B.C.; these relations were marked, according to Dmitriev, by a long series of Roman provocations. Yet this slogan (if that is the right word for such a deeply held value) was a strange choice of subject for the early twenty-first century, with ancient history opening up in so many new directions. Dmitriev strains to find questions to answer. Why, for example, did it take thirty years (after their supposedly initial political contact with “the Greeks”) for the Romans “to understand the importance of Greek public opinion”? First, we hardly know this (why did Fabius Pictor write in Greek?); second, their Italian and Carthaginian experiences had not prepared them; third, they were men of war. All this should be too obvious to need saying. Half the central actors in this book are Romans, and much of it concerns Roman imperialism. Apparently it has to be pointed out yet again that you cannot understand Rome’s political and military encounters with the mainland and Aegean Greeks without the full context of Rome’s prior and concurrent expansion elsewhere. Dmitriev pays no attention to the two generations of Roman experience before 229 B.C. with the equally Greek Greeks of southern Italy and Sicily, not to mention their (admittedly not well documented) policy of leaving their Italian “allies” with a high degree of autonomy in exchange for loyalty and cooperation. It will not do to start the history of Romano-Greek relations in 229 B.C., all the less so since the publication of a Rhodian inscription by V. Kontorini (see Supplementum Epigraphicum Graecum 33 [1983]) put it beyond reasonable doubt that Rome really did have a “friendship” with Rhodes as early as about 306 B.C. (for reasons that it is easy to understand), as Polybius says. Dmitriev ignores this text. Concentrating on a slogan leads almost inevitably to exaggerating its importance. Thus we are told that Rome’s “appropriation” of the freedom slogan “would eventually lead to the foundation of . . . the pax Romana” (p. 6). Well, no: many other significant factors were involved, including Rome’s ambitions and belligerence. That Dmitriev has a long way to go before he assesses these factors more or less rightly he demonstrated in an earlier article (“The Rise and Quick Fall of the Theory of Ancient Economic Imperialism,” Economic History Review 62 [2009], pp. 785–801), an eccentric essay denying in the face of a huge range of evidence and arguments that a desire for material gain played any significant role in Rome’s imperial expansion. W. V. HARRIS Columbia University TIMOTHY BARNES. Constantine: Dynasty, Religion and Power in the Later Roman Empire. (Blackwell Ancient Lives.) Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. 2011. Pp. xiii, 266. $124.95. AMERICAN HISTORICAL REVIEW 1277 Timothy Barnes has devoted a significant portion of his long and productive career to the study of Constantine and his reign. This book represents the culmination of those efforts. An enormous range of detailed studies on points of chronology and prosopography here find their fruit. This is also a deeply polemical work, in which a huge number of contemporary scholars are criticized by name for errors of method and philology, as well as sheer sloppiness. This captiousness, combined with a caprice as regards rules of evidence, undermines the value of the book as a guide to the reign of Constantine or scholarship upon it. Constantine is not a conventional biography. It is perhaps best described as a series of small investigations into carefully circumscribed problems—or complex problems, defined so as to appear resolvable as mere questions of fact. Among the former category one might include such topics as, when did Constantine’s parents meet? What was the social rank and status of his mother, Helena? Among the latter category, perhaps foremost is the question whether it was Constantine himself who placed the date of Easter and practice of Lent on the agenda at the Council of Nicaea. The study overall aims to vindicate a series of interrelated positions that Barnes has advocated across some thirty years: namely, that Constantine was sincere in his conversion; that he involved himself deeply and intensely in the governance of the church; and that he pursued policies designed to favor Christianity and Christians while also harming pagans and suppressing their cult. Though Barnes appears not to perceive this, these topics exist in different epistemic domains and are therefore subject to different modes of proof. The question whether Constantine had a “genuine sense of mission” (p. 120) is ultimately not knowable, nor, for that matter, is it consequential to the latter questions, which can at least be rigorously addressed. I am myself broadly in sympathy with Barnes’s depiction of the latter years of Constantine’s reign: having eliminated the last of his rivals, Constantine abandoned the public stance of tolerance he had nominally advocated since 313 and moved with ever greater determination against those he found religiously deviant. What is more, like Nero, his public policies were occasionally announced and certainly pursued in ways intended to distract from the dynastic struggles within his own house. That said, the arguments of individual sections are often problematic and Barnes’s summaries of the arguments of others are regularly willful to the point of distortion. The use of ellipses to reduce a long argument of Norman H. Baynes to caricature strikes me as particularly egregious in this regard (p. 202 n. 10), but one might name, too, the somewhat hysterical section on the so-called Edict of Milan (pp. 93–97). A typical section identifies a problem, which is then characterized as one of fact; laments the errors as well as the flaws of earlier scholars; catalogs the surviving evidence; and selects a position. These last moves are misleading in two regards. On the one hand, Barnes never asks how knowledge was transmitted in antiquity: all OCTOBER 2012