* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Pericles and the Plague: Civil Religion, Anomie, and
History of science in classical antiquity wikipedia , lookup
Spartan army wikipedia , lookup
Ancient Macedonians wikipedia , lookup
Ancient Greek grammar wikipedia , lookup
First Persian invasion of Greece wikipedia , lookup
Ancient Greek religion wikipedia , lookup
Liturgy (ancient Greece) wikipedia , lookup
Corinthian War wikipedia , lookup
Ancient Greek warfare wikipedia , lookup
Greco-Persian Wars wikipedia , lookup
Ancient Greek literature wikipedia , lookup
Sociology of Religj~m 1996, 57:4 397-407 Pericles and the Plague: Civil Religion, Anomie, and Injustice in Thucydides* Donald A. Nielsen This paper examines the problems of "civil felicita, ""anomie," and h~justice in Athenian s,~iety as presented in Thucydides's narrative of the Peloponnesian war. Thucydides juxtaposes Pericles's funeral oration, as an embodiment of Athenian civil religion, with his description of Athenian demoralization and anomie during the subsequent plague. These c~nu:epts ate linked to the problem of injustice in the Melian Dialogue, which describes Athenian imperial behavior toward this small island people. The paper shows how Thucydides links these ideas to the notion of Fortune in the ultimate collapse of the Athenian war effort. Thucydides is a pioneer in the systematic use of these sociolo~cal concepts and he is compared briefly to more recent sociolo~sts, such as Durkheim, Merton, and BeUah. The concepts of "civil religion" and "anomie" are closely associated with the work of Emite Durkheim, although both have been subsequently developed in new directions by a host of writers, including Merton, Warner, Bellah, and others. Froma systematic standpoint, the two concepts have a symmetrical quality. While "civil religion" points to the highest level of religio-political ritual and symbolism unifying a people, "anomie" reveals the fragility of social integration and asks us to examine the sources and manifestations of social dislocation and the collapse of the moral order. Indeed, the two concepts seem to work well when paired with one another. This paper examines these two concepts, along with several related ideas, as they appear in Thucydides's history of the Peloponnesian war. This text contains one of the most famous historical illustrations of "civil religion," Pericles's funeral oration. In his discussion of the effects of the wartime plague on Athenian society, Thucydides also provides a vivid historical account of "anomie" as well as one of the first instances of this term's (i.e., anomia's) systematic use in the human sciences. Moreover, in the so-called "Melian Dialogue," Thucydides presents the problem of justice and injustice in the individual as well as in the relations among Greek states, in a manner which echoes many of the themes of the funeral oration and the plague narratŸ * Researchfor this paperwas begun duringa Narional Endounnentfor the Humanities Summer Insrituteon "Platoand the Polis," Department of Classics, Dulce Universiry, 13 June.22 July, I994, directedby ProfessorsDiskin C/ay ana[ Michael Gillespie. Ah earlier version was presented at the Annual Meeting, Southern Sociolo~cal Sociery, Atlanta, Georg/a, 9 Apr/l 1995. 397 Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 State University of New York CoUege,Oneonta 398 SOCIOLOGYOF RELIGION I will examine each of these facets of his work in turn: (1) his concept of "civil religion" in the context of Pericles's funeral oration; (2) the notion of "anomie" in the setting of the Athenian plague and Athenian society; (3) the relationship of these two narratives to the moral drama related in the "Melian Dialogue;" (4) the relevance of these concepts and narratives to the moral design of Thucydides's text. Finally, I will conclude with some briefer observations on Thucydides's place in the history of social theory. Robert Bellah defines "civil religion" asa "collection of beliefs, symbols, and ritual with respect to sacred things and institutions in a collectivity" (Bellah 1967: 8). They serve to strengthen the community's religio-political identity and solidify their sense of transcendent religious realities (Bellah 1967: 12). The beliefs and practices of the "civil religion" are also differentiated from those of other particular religious practices which might exist alongside ir within the national setting (Bellah 1967: 1). Pericles's speech, in occcasion as well as content, is a premier instance of Bellah's usage, despite the latter's American focus (e.g., on Lincoln's Gettysburg Address; for comparisons between the two speeches, see Finley 1963: 144, 183). Thucydides places it in the Winter of 431/430 BCE after the first battles of the war. It was part of an "annual custom," an Athenian public burial rite meant to honor those who have died in wartime (Thucydides 1972: 143-144). A s a rite in Athenian "civil religion," it is to be distinguished from the many other religious cults distributed throughout the Athenian calendar (see Burkert 1985). Thucydides provides a concise description of the ceremonies. They included a public funeral procession, burial of individuals in collective coffins by tribe (the units of the polis since ancient times), and final interment in the public burial grounds "in the most beautiful quarter, outside the city wall" (Thucydides 1972: 143). A speech by a notable public figure was a standard part of the ritual. Pericles's speech was also clearly meant to serve as a rallying point for the unification of the Athenian populace who were then being called upon to suffer hardship in the defense of their country and culture. Pericles therefore is made to present the highest level symbols and values associated with Athenian life. Early in his speech, Pericles states that "What I want to do is, in the first place, to discuss the spirit in which we faced our trials and also our constitution and the way of life that has made us great" (Thucydides 1972: 145). This way of life includes: political and cultural autonomy, coupled with an openness to the outside world; a harmonious blend of labors and recreation in contests and sacrifices; a balanced love of beauty, without extravagance; a desire for private gain through work and wealth, yet a willingness to sacrifice them for country; a committment to mind, debate, and rationality, without thereby becoming soft; freedom and tolerance in private affairs, yet a common democratic public life under the law; a willingness to face the dangers of war courageously, without continuous preparation and discipline in advance; in sum, a living involvement in private life, balanced with an overriding patriotic devotion to the public good on which all depend (Thucydides 1972: 145-150). In Pericles's own words, " . . . Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 I. CIVIL RELIGION A N D PERICLES'S F U N E R A L O R A T I O N PERICLESANDTHE PLAGUE 399 Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 we do not say that a m a n who takes no interest in politics is a m a n who minds his own business; we say that he has no business here at all" (Thucydides 1972: 147). His speech not only evokes the collective memory of glorious deeds performed by ancestors and holds out the promise of "praises that never grow old," but encourages those present to "fix their eyes every day on the greatness of Athens as she really is" and enhorts them to do nothing less than "fall in love with her" (Thucydides 1972: 149). Perictes is made to link eros to country in a manner familiar to more recent civil religious rhetoric. Those who have recently died, in the first battles with Sparta, "chose to check the enemy's pride" and accepted the risks involved in that choice. As for success or failure,".., they left that in the doubtful hands of Hope (elpis), and when the reality of battle was before their faces, they put their trust in their own selves" (Thucydides 1972: 149). We wiU return later to a discussion of some of these themes (including the ambiguities of "hope") in Thucydides. Pericles's speech undoubtedly gives an idealized portrait of Athenian culture and virtue. This is not surprising. It is the essense of "civil religion" to idealize the past in the interest of present and future social unity. However, we need to recall that it is Thucydides himself who has reconstructed Pericles's words and made him say what was "called for" by the situation (Thucydides 1972: 47). He has also inserted the speech into the historical narrative at this particular point. It might be thought that the author places the speech before the plague narrative because events did, indeed, follow that sequence. However, Thucydides makes significant chronological digressions elsewhere, is hardly insistent on precise sequences at every point, and moves quite freely back and forth in time in his history when it suits his needs (see the remarks by Finley in Thucydides 1972: 16-18). It would be a mistake to explain his construction solely by reference to the alleged historical "facts" or to standards of linear chronological narrative. Thucydides needs to follow Pericles's idealized picture of Athenian virtues with his plague narrative in order to achieve the desired moral and pedagogical effect. In sociological terms, "civil religion" and "anomie" need to be joined, yet opposed to one another. This view gains strength from the fact that such juxtapositions often playa key role elsewhere in the construction of his text (Rawlings 1981: 50; Gomme 1956, II: 161). A particularly central issue is the prominence given to the notions of balance and harmony of opposites in Pericles's speech. While he specifies a number of defining features of Athenian civil religion, they are generally enumerated in pairs and bound together by the balance which exists between the members of each pair. This is perhaps not surprising given the Athenian, and, in general, the Greek emphasis on the moral maxim, "Nothing in excess," as well as its companion notion of "demonic" forces which drive the individual to over-reaching (Kaufmann 1975: 65). Thucydides is not unique among the Greeks in his emphasis on measure, balance, and the weighing of opposing forces in the proper constitution of a culture. This image is found in varying forros in a large number of Greek writers. It is especially, although not exclusively, associated with the notions of justice, equality, and the health of the soul as well as the polis. It appears in writers otherwise as different as Herodotus, Euripides, Xenophon, Plato, and others (see 400 SOCIOLOGYOF RELIGION II. ANOMIE AND THE PLAGUE IN ATHENS The concept of "anomie" has become a sociological staple, used in a variety of ways (see Orru 1987). I want to focus on Durkheim's usage. He associated "anon~ie" with a condition of unregulated passions and strivings, one which threatens to become a disease of infinite desires which cannot, in principle, be satisfied. In the absense of culturally defined limits, people are thrown into an anomic condition in which the immediate and full realization of desires becomes the norm of conduct (Durkheim 1951: 248, 252-253,258). Durkheim demonstrated especially that a condition of "anomie" resulted from particular social causes (e.g., the dislocations resulting from the rapid expansion of trade and industry). Thucydides's portrayal of the plague vividly captures the breakdown of custom and morality. He writes: " . . . the catastrophe was so overwhelming that men, not knowing what would happen next to them, became indifferent to every rule of religion or of law . . . . Al1 the funeral ceremonies which used to be observed were now disorganized..." and the populace "adopted the most shameless methods" of burial, not excluding the extreme of finding another funeral pyre already burning, throwing their own dead upon it, and then leaving (Thucydides 1972: 155). In a passage of particular importance, Thucydides writes: " . . . Athens owed to the plague the beginnings of a state of unprecedented lawlessness (anomias)" (Thucydides 1972: 155). Abrupt changes of fortune took place, in which the rich died and the penniless inherited their wealth. Since everything, including money, seems ephemeral, self-indulgence and pleasure became the order of the day. Honor was cast aside, no one would abide by the laws, and only the pleasure of the moment was valued. Open display of egoism replaced the previous practice of concealing vice behind a mask of virtue, and, thus, even hypocrisy fell victim to the plague. "No fear of God or law of man hada restraining influence" (Thucydides 1972: 155). Both the good, who worshipped the Gods, and the bad, who did not, died indiscriminately. No Greeks expected to live long enough to face legal punishment for their misdeeds. The plague narrative sounds many of the same themes found in Durkheim's account of anomie, a fact which has not gone entirely unnoticed (see Connor 1984: 64; Orru 1987: 20-21). However, Thucydides not only uses the word anomia descriptively in connection with the plague's effects, but is also eager to Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 Rawlinson 1942: 24-25; Grene 1992, IV: 479; Benjamin 1965: 5; Pangle 1988: 143-44). It is featured especially in the Hippocratic medical writings (see Lloyd 1978: 26, 30, 33). I cannot now trace the complex history of this theme in Greek culture (but see Lloyd 1966). I would only emphasize that Pericles's funeral oration not only expresses the content of Athenian civic virtue, but does so in a forro which gives priority to the ideal of balance or harmony in the articulation of opposite qualities. Indeed, the particular forro assumed by the Periclean version of "civil religion" constitutes part of its distinctive character as an Athenian cultural creation. More important, it lays the foundation for the subsequent notion of "anomie." This concept involves precisely those madnesses, excesses, and imbalances which possess societies under given circumstances. PERICLESAND THE PLAGUE 401 Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 set his description of Athenian response to the plague in the context of Athenian social structure, cultural values, and norms of conduct, precisely as they are described in Pericles's speech. Indeed, it is difficult to imagine a more vivid contrast than the one between Pericles's praise of Athenian character and the actual conduct of the Athenians during the plague, which first struck Athens in the su,nmer of 430 BCE, after only one year of the war. Despite Pericles's glowing recommendation of "the spirit in which we faced our trials," Athens became rapidly and completely demoralized during this new crisis. Thucydides traces the "anomie" into which the Athenians were plunged to various objective causes. He describes the plague's symptoms, the course of the disease, and its spread through the crowded wartime city, where large rural populations had been quartered, with the eye of a modern public health official (Thucydides 1972: 151-155). He also captures the the underlying sentiment of egoistic self-interest and attachment to material goods which had taken increasing hold of Imperial Athens with the growth of trade and the seaport of the Piraeus. tndeed, his implied emphasis on the deeper moral dislocation accompanying the economic and political expansion of the Athenian empire foreshadows Durkheim's analysis of economically induced anomie as well as his sense of polit ically induced demoralization. In the above passage, Thuycidides implies that this marked the beginning of a period of chronic "lawlessness" in Athenian life (see Orru 1987: 21; but see Gomme 1956, II: 159). The plague, like Pericles speech itself, marked a turning point. The depths of Greek demoralization was reflected in their open violation of the most basic tenets of public reputability of the Greek "shame culture" (Dodds 1968). Thucydides creates a very effective mirror image in his juxtaposition of the orderly funeral customs followed on the occasion of Pericles's speech and the "shameless" practices of burial under the plague. The libertine pursuit of pleasures and self-interest, the unpredictable dispensations of fortune, regardless of merit, and the ineffectiveness of all human rule, are all featured prominently in Thucydides's rendition of "anomie" and are very much in keeping with the modern concept. I want to emphasize that Thucydides not only uses the word anomia, but also develops the concept itself in relationship to Athenian society and culture (for the distinction between word and concept, see Merton 1968). While variants of the word were used in more isolated fashion by other Greek writers (see Orru 1987:12-40, esp. 15), this is the first systematic sociological use of the term. The plague not only created new and reinforced existing anomie, it engendered a particular type of anomic response. In terms of Pericles's speech, this response involved a loss of the balance and harmony among the constituent elements of the Greek value system. The extremes of conduct became accentuated and all sense of measure was lost. It is not surprising that the term anomia should be used to describe part of this condition. The term was translated as "lawlessness" by Warner and "lawless extravagance" by Crawley, before hito (see Thucydides 1972: 155; Crawley 1910: 133; see also Gomme et al. 1956-81: II). Hobbes had rendered it as "great licentiousness" (Hobbes 1959, I: 118). While the former term is used more frequently, the latter has the merit of capturing the sense of immorality and excess which the Greeks must also have attached to t h e 402 S O C I O L O G Y OF RELIGION 1 A brief comparison is helpful between Thucydides and Sophocles's Oedipus. This play was first performed around 425 BCE shortly after the plague appeared in Athens (Berg and Clay 1978: 19). In it, Corinth reels under a disease precipitated by Oedipus's conduct. Despite Corinth's misery, Sophocles does not depict that city as utterly demoralized of led to "shameless," sacreligious conduct. On the contrary, everyone is "kneeling, offering theŸ branches, praying before the two great temples of Athena" and "the whole city smoiders with incense" (Berg and Ciar 1978: 23). The difference between the two portraits is striking. It leads us to further suspect that both moral effect as well as theoretical vision were guiding motives in Thucvdides's depiction and placement of the plague narrative. Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 "shameless" violation of customs so deeply rooted in the common conscience. But the word alone is not decisive. It is Thucydides's wider contrast between Pericles's enunciation of the ideals of Greek culture and the Greek realities, including responses to the plague, that reveals his comprehension of "anomie." The Greeks viewed diseases like the plague as the result of miasma, or moral pollution (see Dodds 1968). It might seem surprising that Thucydides took such a "scientific" view of the disease, traced its development with such objectivity, and seems to have rejected the oracles popularly associated with its appearance (see Thucydides 1972: 156). However, I would point out that his focus on lawlessness, sacrilege, and the demoralization of Athenian society during the plague reflects not only his objectivity in recounting the events as they occurred, but also conveys his sense of Athenian moral decay. This decay may not, in his eyes, have been a miasma which produced the plague, but it certainly prevented Athens from meeting it in the spirit described by Pericles. 1 When the plague struck, it is not surprising that the Athenians were unable to face it in the spirit whŸ guided their earlier responses to crisis, always exemplified best in their exploits against the Persians. Pericles portrays a value system which is no longer fully alive. The crisis brings to the sufface the standard now actually governing conduct among the Athenians. This standard is egoistic self-interest and, during the plague, it degenerates entirely into the impulses of the moment. It reflects states of the soul which are thoroughly unbalanced, Iacking in measure, and expressing a world of experience alien to that described so eloquently by Pericles. "Nothing in excess" has become "Everything only in excess." This is the condition that Plato was soon to diagnose as injustice in the soul as well as the polis (Bloom 1968; on Thucydides and Plato see also Strauss 1964). In juxtaposing these events, Thucydides seems to tell us that Pericles badly misjudged contemporary Athenian character by equating it with an idealized image of the past. Would the Athenians as described by Pericles have been as demoralized by similar events? Had fortune not dealt them equally powefful blows during the Persian war, without their moral collapse? Was the Athenian breakdown under the plague not proof that Athenian character and moral order were already in a precarious state at the very outset of the war? This contrast not only helps him achieve an immediate contrast of past and present, but also serves asa harbinger of the future. The subsequent Athenian defeat at Syracuse is prefigured in this contrast betweeen Pericles and the plague. At the war's very outset, the excesses of Athenian imperial ambition are brought to heel by Fortune (Tyche) in the form of the plague (see also Cornford 1971). Indeed, at one point, the plague is actually given an apocalyptic quality by PERICLESAND THE PLAGUE 403 Thucydides and is assimilated to the category of an event sent by the Gods to punish the Athenians' over-reaching pride (see Connor 1984:31). Here we need to examine a wider set of problems connected with Thucydides's account of the relationships among the Athenian empire, justice, and moral order. This is best achieved through a consideration of the "Melian Dialogue" (the only dialogue in a book filled with speeches; see Rawlings 1981: 243-249; Finley 1963:208-212; Connor 1984: 147-157). Although the small island of Melos was of Hellenic, more specifically Dorian population, and originally associated with Sparta, the Melians adopted a position of neutrality in the Peloponnesian war. Melos was not part of the Athenian empire and had not previously paid tribute to Athens (Zimmern 1961: 440). However, Athens now (416 BCE) wanted to absorb them into its system, despite their ~trategic insignificance, both to satisfy its insanable desire for expansion and to create an object lesson for other states that might resist. The Athenian representatives counseled the Melians to act in their own self-interest and to avoid excessive reliance on Hope (elpis), in the absence of practical actions to avoid destruction. The Melians spoke in terms of justice and insisted on Hope in the possible turn of fortune to their advantage during the uncertainties of war. The Melians are also made, by Thucydides, to foresee the collapse of the Athenian empire as proper vengeance against their injustice and the Athenians even entertain the possibility of this collapse. The outcome of the dialogue is well-known: Melian refusal to pay tribute, ensuing hostilities and, after a blockade and some indeterminate battles, the subsequent capture of Melos by the Athenians, who killed all the male citizens, sold the women and children into slavery, and colonized Melos with their own people (see Thucydides 1972: 400-408). The role of Hope and Fortune in the dialogue is striking. The Melians remark: " . . . in war fortune sometimes makes the odds more level than could be expected from the difference in numbers of the two sides. And if we surrender, then all our hope is lost at once, whereas, so long as we remain in action, there is still a hope that we may yet stand upright" (Thucydides 1972: 404). The Athenians counter by saying that hope is only a "comforter in danger" and an "expensive commodity." Practical measures to avoid destruction are better than "prophecies and oracles and such things which by encouraging hope lead men to ruin" (Thucydides 1972: 404). Moreover, self-interested action is safer, while reliance on the honorable retention of old ties (with Sparta) and on justice lead one into danger (Thucydides 1972: 405). It is interesting that Pericles had added hope in the successful outcome of earlier Athenian endeavors as a possible, if "doubtful," appendix to the uncertainties of war and viewed it as an acceptable emotion when it was added to (but did not replace) self-reliance (Thucydides 1972: 149). The Athenian representatives were unwilling to allow hope a similar place in the Melian response and insisted only on self-interested capitulation. What Pericles granted the Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 III. DISHARMONY, SELF.INTEREST, AND INJUSTICE IN T H E MELIAN D I A L O G U E 404 SOCIOLOGYOF RELIGION CONCLUSIONS The above discussion has led to several conclusions. Thucydides emerges as the first writer to create the sociological concepts of "civil religion" and "anomie." I can think of no author before him who develops these ideas so systematically. The concepts also emerge in conjunction with one another, as opposing terms, so to speak. His treatment of both ideas emphasizes the Greek notion of balance and harmony among opposites as attributes of health and justice in the soul and society. Thucydides's eye for typical situations contributes to his talents asa sociological innovator. His combination of historical detail with typical conceptualizations gives his work a very modern quality. Thucydides and Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 Athenians, the Athenians were unwilling to grant Melos. This stark emphasis on self-interest and the calculations of power politics by the Athenians does not go unnoted by the Melians. Most important for present purposes is the fact that Athenian policy reflects the same state of imbalance and lack of measure which characterized their response to the plague. The Melian request for justice takes the forro of an appeal to the Athenian sense of balance and proportion in dealing with with different states. But the Athenians reject this appeal in terms which reflect the deformation of their ethical sensibility. For them, the extremes have become the measure of normalcy in their imperial policy. The absorption of Melos into the empire becomes more important ,han the batt[e against bigger and more equally matched roes (Thucydides 1972: 402). The Melian appeal to honor, justice, and fair dealing fails. The Athenians have left honor behind, in the past, despite Pericles's talk of Athenian liberality to its friends (Thucydides 1972: 147). Their unbalanced souls have become incapable of justice in the present. Therefore, ir comes as no surprise when Plutarch later writes that one of the greatest Athenian exemplars of "exalted ambition" and "extreme inconsistency," Alcibiades, "bore a heavy share of the responsibility for the execution of all the grown men on the island [Melos], since he had given his support in the Assembly to the motion which decreed this" (Scott-Kilvert 1960: 258-260). According to Thucydides's account, Alcibiades was not only among those who wanted to put ah end to the temporary peace with Sparta (after 422 BCE), but was also "the most arden, supporter of the expedition" against Sicily, launched only six months after the Melian incident (Thucydides 1972: 375,418). The Athenian refusal of peace terms with Sparta and the vengeance of Fortune (Tyche) for their overweening conduct in the disasterous invasion of Syracuse fulfills the disputed oracle cited at the end of the plague sequence (Thucydides 1972: 156). Ir is true that Thucydides, in Sophist fashion, fought against the belief in such prophecies and viewed them as human creations open to varied interpreta, ion, depending on interest and perspective. Despite this, we have seen that a key part of his history involves juxtapositions of ethically charged, typical events, ones which contrastan idealized past anda deranged present and reveal the imbalanced and unj ust state of the contemporary Athenian soul. As such, it invites cautious comparison, if not with a mythic view of history (Cornford 1970), thenat least with a systematic sociological one. PERICLESANDTHE PLAGUE 405 REFERENCES Bell, D. 1965. The disjunction of culture and social structure. In Science and Culture, edited by G. Holton, 236-258.Boston: BeaconPress. Bellah, R. N. 1967. Civil religionin America. Do.da/us 96:1-21. Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 Durkheim have much in common. They both link the notions of "civil religion" and "anomie" to their root sense of balance and harmony as facets of a healthy soul and good society. Durkheim's treatment of anomie, indeed, his entire systematic theory in his work on suicide, makes little sense without reference to this notion of harmony and balance of opposing social forces (e.g., see Durkheim 1951: 321; 1912). On this score, Durkheim can be counted as one of the most "classical" of modern sociologists (on Durkheim, anomie, and ancient society, see Fustel de Coulanges 1864; Nandan 1977; Glotz 1904; Harrison 1912; Cornford 1912; Nielsen 1986: 27, 40-41). Thucydides's movement from "civil religion" to "anomie" also seems a logical progression and has more recent echoes. For example, Robert Bellah moved from his analytical treatment of "civil religion" to a study of its "anomic" crisis in America, and, more recently, has taken up the related problems of individualism, civic committment, and social justice (see Bellah 1975; Bellah et al. 1986). Thucydides also foreshadows central elements in Merton's promising, but highly incomplete treatment of social structure, anomie, justice, and fate. Merton's view of anomie as an "imba[ance" or "disjunction" between cultural values and operative norms of conduct not only reproduces a part of Thucydides's own emphasis (see Merton 1938; see also Bell 1965). In addition, in his other early writings, Merton had wanted to tie the problem of anomie to the ideas of j ustice and fate and to the moral question of merit and reward in human conduct. He noted that the idea of rule by a fate or fortune, indifferent to human effort or merit, is more common in situations where prized values cannot be regularly secured by following legitimate norms of conduct. The incongruity between cultural values and norms in an anomic social structure gestates not only a variety of "deviant adaptations," a Mertonian thesis widely noted by sociologists, but more importantly for present purposes a religious sensibility emphasizing the arbitrary determination of human outcomes by fate and fortune. Merton himself tells us that he planned a study of this latter complex of ideas, but he regrettably never completed it (Merton 1936). As we have seen, Thucydides already sees this complex of problems in the Athenian situation. He lived and wrote in a world where the notion of fate was still alive and had customary religious sanction (Greene 1963; Edmunds 1975). But his skepticism also allowed him to see how civil religion, anomie, and fate were linked to one another in the experience of his Greek contemporaries. We seem to be witnessing a similar conjunction of ideas and events today, and need to recapture it in our sociology. For this task, Thucydides has once again become required reading. 406 SOCIOLOGY OF RELIGION Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 .1975. The broken convenant: American civil reli~on in time of trial. New York: Seabury Press. . and P. E. Hammond, eds. 1980. Varieties of civil reli~on. San Francisco: Harper & Row. Bellah, R. N., R. Madsen, W. M. Sullivan, A. Swidler, and S. M. Tipton. 1986. Habits of the heart. New York: Harper Perennial. Benjamin, A. S. 1965. Xenophon: Recollections of Socrates aTu:lSocrates's defense before the jury. lndianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill. Berg, S., and D. Clay. 1978. Sophocles. Oedipus the King. Translated, Introduction, and Notes by D. Clay. New York: Oxford University Press. Bloom, A. 1968. The Republic of Plato, Translated with an Interpretive Essay by A. Bloom. New York: Basic Books. Burkert, W. 1985. Greek reli,~on. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Connor, W. R. 1984. Thucydides. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Cornford, F. M. [1907] 1971. Thucydides Mythistoricus. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. . [1912] 1957. From reli,~on to philosophy. New York: Harper Torchbooks. Crawley, R. 1910. Thucydides..History of the Peloponnesian War. Translated by R. Crawley. London: J.M. Dent. Dodds, E.R. 1968. The Greek~ and the irrational Berkeley: University of Califomia Press. Durkheim, E. [1897] 1951. Suicide. Translated by G. Simpson. New York: Free Press. . [1912] 1965. The elementary forros of the reli~ous life. Translated by J.W.Swain. New York: Free Press. Edmunds, L. 1975. Chance and intelligence in Thucydides. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Finley, J. H., Jr. 1963. Thucydides. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Fustel de Coulanges, N.D. 1864. The ancient city. Translated by W. Small. Garden City, NY: Doubleday Anchor. Glotz, G. 1904. La solidaritede la famille dans le droit criminel en Grece. Paris: Albert Fontemoing. Gomme, A.W. 1956-1981. A historical commentary on Thucydides. Begun by A.W. Gomme and Continued by K.J. Dover and J. Andrewes. 5 Vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Greene, W. C. 1963. Moira: Fate, good, and evil in Greek thought. New York: Harper Torchbooks. Grene, D., and R. Lattimore, eds. 1992. The complete Greek tragedies. 4 Vols. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Harrison, J. E. [1912] 1962. Themis: A study of the social ori~ns of Greek religion. New York: Meridian Books. Hobbes, T. 1959. Thucydides. The Peloponnesian War. Translated by T. Hobbes, edited by D. Grene, 2 Vols. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Kaufmann, W. 1979. Tragedy and philosophy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Lloyd, G.E.R. 1966. Polarity and analogy. London: George Allen and Unwin. . 1978. Hippocraticwritings. New York: Penguin Books. Merton, R. K. 1936. The unanticipated consequences of purposive social action. American Sociolo,~cal Review 1: 894-904. .1938. Social structure and anomie. American Sociolo~cal Review 3: 672-682. .1968. Social theory and social structure. New York: Free Press. Nandan, Y., ed. 1977. The Durkheimian School: A systematic and comprehensive bibliography. Westport, CN: Greenwood Press. Nielsen, D. A. 1986. Robert Hertz and the sociologial study of sin, expiation, and religion: A neglected chapter in the Durkheim school. In Structures of knowing, edited by R. Monk, 7-50. Landam, MD: University Press of America. Orru, M. 1987. Anomie: History and meanings. Boston: Allen & Unwin. Pangle, T. L. 1988. The laws of Plato. Translated with Notes and an lnterpretive Essay by T. L. Pangle. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. PERICLES AND THE PLAGUE 407 Downloaded from http://socrel.oxfordjournals.org/ at Pennsylvania State University on September 19, 2016 Rawlings, H. R., III. 1981. The structure ofThucydides's history. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Rawlinson, G. 1942. Herodotus: The Persian Wars. Translated by G. Rawlinson. New York: The Mr Library. Scott-Kilvert, I. 1960. Plutarch: The rise aTutfall of Athens: Nine Greek lives. Translated with an Inmxtuction by I.Scott-Kilvert. Baltimore, MD: Penguin Books. Smith, C. F. 1962-65. Thucydides: History of the Peloponnesian War. 4 vois. Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Strauss, L. 1964. The city and man. Chicago: Rand McNally Company. Thucydides. 1972. Thucydides: Hist(,ry of the Peloponnesian War. Translated by R. Warner, Inmxtuction by M.I. Fmley. Baltimore, MD: Penguin Ciassics. Warner, W. L. 1959. The living and the de.M: The symbolic life of an American community. New Haven, CN: Yale University Press. Zimmerman, A. 1961. The Greek C(rmm(mwealth: Ec~mamics aT~ politics in fifth century Athem. 3rd Ed. New York: Oxford University Press.