Download Irrational square roots

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

List of prime numbers wikipedia , lookup

Fermat's Last Theorem wikipedia , lookup

Wiles's proof of Fermat's Last Theorem wikipedia , lookup

Fundamental theorem of algebra wikipedia , lookup

Mathematical proof wikipedia , lookup

Collatz conjecture wikipedia , lookup

Quadratic reciprocity wikipedia , lookup

Proofs of Fermat's little theorem wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Irrational square roots
MichaΜ·l Misiurewicz ([email protected]), Indiana University - Purdue University Indianapolis, Indianapolis, IN
√
In the classroom. Suppose you show your students the standard proof that 2
is irrational:
Proof by contradiction. Suppose that
√
2 is rational. Then we can write
√
2 = π‘š/𝑛
for some coprime positive integers π‘š and 𝑛. This means that π‘š2 = 2𝑛2 . Thus, π‘š2
is even, and therefore π‘š is even. Hence, π‘š = 2𝑣 for some positive integer 𝑣. We get
4𝑣 2 = 2𝑛2 , so 2𝑣 2 = 𝑛2 . By the same argument, this implies that 𝑛 is even, which
√
contradicts the assumption that π‘š and 𝑛 are coprime. Therefore 2 is irrational.
Of course, the same proof works for every prime 𝑝. To prove that
√
𝑝 is irrational,
replace 2 by 𝑝 and β€œeven” by β€œdivisible by 𝑝.”
You wonder whether your students understand this principle. After all, it is not
clear that for a student the notions of β€œeven” and β€œdivisible by 𝑝” are similar. After
√
√
you prove the irrationality of 2 in class, you ask your students to prove that 3 is
irrational.
One student’s proof starts by distinguishing the cases of π‘š and 𝑛 even or odd. This
cannot be correct, you think, but before you write a big red zero on the paper, you
read the rest of the proof.
Suppose that
√
3 is rational. Then we can write
√
3 = π‘š/𝑛 for some coprime
positive integers π‘š and 𝑛. This means that π‘š2 = 3𝑛2 . If 𝑛 is even, then π‘š2 is
even, so π‘š is even – a contradiction. If π‘š is even, then 3𝑛2 is even, so 𝑛 is even
– another contradiction. Thus, both π‘š and 𝑛 are odd, so π‘š = 2𝑣 + 1 and 𝑛 =
2𝑀 + 1 for some nonnegative integers 𝑣, 𝑀. We get (2𝑣 + 1)2 = 3(2𝑀 + 1)2 , so
2𝑣 2 + 2𝑣 = 6𝑀 2 + 6𝑀 + 1. The left-hand side is even, while the right-hand side is odd
√
– a contradiction. Therefore 3 is irrational.
1
2
The proof is correct! Your student has earned a perfect score instead of 0, but did
not learn what you wanted to teach.
Next time you are teaching this course, you do not repeat your mistake! You ask
yourself: for what prime numbers does this β€œeven-odd” proof work? You easily see
that it works for all integers congruent to 3 modulo 4. It is clear what you have to
do. The smallest prime number larger than 2 but not congruent to 3 modulo 4 is 5.
√
Thus, you ask your students to prove that 5 is irrational.
One student submits this solution:
Suppose that
√
5 is rational. Then we can write
√
5 = π‘š/𝑛 for some coprime
positive integers π‘š and 𝑛. This means that π‘š2 = 5𝑛2 . If 𝑛 is even, then π‘š2 is even,
so π‘š is even – a contradiction. If π‘š is even, then 5𝑛2 is even, so 𝑛 is even – a
contradiction. Thus both π‘š and 𝑛 are odd, so π‘š = 2𝑣 + 1 and 𝑛 = 2𝑀 + 1 for some
nonnegative integers 𝑣, 𝑀. We get (2𝑣 + 1)2 = 5(2𝑀 + 1)2 , so 𝑣 2 + 𝑣 = 5𝑀 2 + 5𝑀 + 1.
Now, 𝑣 2 + 𝑣 = 𝑣(𝑣 + 1). Either 𝑣 or 𝑣 + 1 is even, so 𝑣 2 + 𝑣 is even. Similarly, 𝑀 2 + 𝑀
is even. Therefore the left-hand side of the equality 𝑣 2 + 𝑣 = 5𝑀 2 + 5𝑀 + 1 is even,
√
while the right-hand side is odd – a contradiction. Therefore 5 is irrational.
Not again! This time, as you can again easily check, the proof works for all π‘˜
congruent to 5 modulo 8. You are desperate. What can you do? To check whether
√
your students understand the idea of the proof of irrationality of 2, what can you
ask them to prove?
Problem.
For which odd numbers π‘˜ can we prove that
√
π‘˜ is irrational using the β€œeven-odd”
method?
Let us translate the β€œeven-odd” method into the rigorous language of mathematics.
√
Assume that π‘˜ = π‘š/𝑛 with (π‘š, 𝑛) = 1. Then
π‘š2 = π‘˜π‘›2 .
(1)
3
Depending on whether π‘š is even or odd, we write π‘š = 2𝑣 or π‘š = 2𝑣 + 1; depending
on whether 𝑛 is even or odd, we write 𝑛 = 2𝑀 or 𝑛 = 2𝑀 + 1 We substitute those
expressions in (1). This gives us 4 possibilities. Some of them lead immediately to
a contradiction (an even number equals an odd number), some of them may require
further analysis. β€œFurther analysis” means that we continue the same procedure with
𝑣, 𝑀 instead of π‘š, 𝑛, that is, 𝑣 may be even or odd and 𝑀 may be even or odd. Repeating this procedure β„“ times amounts to considering 22β„“ possibilities (although some may
be ruled out earlier in the process): π‘š ≑ π‘Ÿ (mod 2β„“ ) for some π‘Ÿ ∈ {0, 1, . . . , 2β„“ βˆ’ 1},
and 𝑛 ≑ 𝑠 (mod 2β„“ ) for some 𝑠 ∈ {0, 1, . . . , 2β„“ βˆ’ 1}. In fact, many cases are ruled out
because π‘Ÿ and 𝑠 are odd.
Thus, our proof is successful if, for some β„“ β‰₯ 1, all possibilities are ruled out, that
is, the equation
π‘Ÿ 2 ≑ π‘˜π‘ 2
(mod 2β„“ )
(2)
has no solutions in odd π‘Ÿ, 𝑠. When solutions exist, we continue to β„“ + 1.
Since 𝑠 is odd, it has an inverse modulo 2β„“ . Multiplying both sides of (2) by the
square of this inverse, we get 𝑑2 ≑ π‘˜ (mod 2β„“ ). We see that our problem is equivalent
to the following:
For which odd π‘˜ is there an β„“ β‰₯ 1, such that for every 𝑑 we have 𝑑2 βˆ•β‰‘ π‘˜ (mod 2β„“ )?
Solution. As we have noticed already, the β€œeven-odd” method works if π‘˜ ≑ 3, 5, 7
(mod 8). We can also see this by observing that 𝑑2 ≑ 1 (mod 8) for all odd 𝑑. We will
show that it does not work if π‘˜ ≑ 1 (mod 8). That is, we show that if π‘˜ ≑ 1 (mod 8)
then for every β„“ β‰₯ 1 there is 𝑑 such that 𝑑2 ≑ π‘˜ (mod 2β„“ ), and the β€œeven-odd” proof
will never terminate.
Let π‘˜ ≑ 1 (mod 8). Then for 𝑑 = 1 we get π‘˜ ≑ 𝑑2 (mod 2β„“ ) for β„“ = 1, 2, 3. Now
we apply induction. Namely, we show that if β„“ β‰₯ 3 and π‘˜ ≑ 𝑑2 (mod 2β„“ ) then either
π‘˜ ≑ 𝑑2 (mod 2β„“+1 ) or π‘˜ ≑ (𝑑 + 2β„“βˆ’1 )2 (mod 2β„“+1 ). Indeed, if π‘˜ ≑ 𝑑2 (mod 2β„“ ) then
either π‘˜ ≑ 𝑑2 (mod 2β„“+1 ) (and we are done), or π‘˜ ≑ 𝑑2 + 2β„“ (mod 2β„“+1 ). In the latter
4
case, since 2β„“ βˆ’ 2 β‰₯ β„“ + 1 and 𝑑 is odd,
(𝑑 + 2β„“βˆ’1 )2 ≑ 𝑑2 + 2β„“ 𝑑 + 22β„“βˆ’2 ≑ 𝑑2 + 2β„“ 𝑑 ≑ 𝑑2 + 2β„“ + 2β„“ (𝑑 βˆ’ 1) ≑ 𝑑2 + 2β„“ ≑ π‘˜
(mod 2β„“+1 ).
Thus, by induction we prove that for every β„“ β‰₯ 1 there is 𝑑 such that π‘˜ ≑ 𝑑2 (mod 2β„“ ).
This solves our problem.
Theorem. The β€œeven-odd” method of proving that
√
π‘˜ is irrational works for an odd
π‘˜ if and only if π‘˜ ≑ 3, 5, 7 (mod 8).
Conclusion. To check whether your students understand the proof of irrationality
of
√
2, ask them to prove that
√
17 is irrational.