* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download International Relations in a Constructed World
Development theory wikipedia , lookup
Social Darwinism wikipedia , lookup
Social contract wikipedia , lookup
Community development wikipedia , lookup
Social Bonding and Nurture Kinship wikipedia , lookup
Social psychology wikipedia , lookup
History of social work wikipedia , lookup
Frankfurt School wikipedia , lookup
Sociology of knowledge wikipedia , lookup
Structural functionalism wikipedia , lookup
Anthropology of development wikipedia , lookup
Social group wikipedia , lookup
Other (philosophy) wikipedia , lookup
Unilineal evolution wikipedia , lookup
Social theory wikipedia , lookup
Political economy in anthropology wikipedia , lookup
State (polity) wikipedia , lookup
Sociological theory wikipedia , lookup
Structuration theory wikipedia , lookup
INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS IN A CONSTRUCTED WORLD This page intentionally left blank INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS IN A CONSTRUCTED WORLD VENDULKA KusALKOvA, NICHOLAS ONUF, PAUL KOWERT Editors Routledge Taylor & Francis Group LONDON AND NEW YORK First published1998 by M.E. Sharpe Published2015 by Routledge 2 Park Square,Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017,USA Routledgeis an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business Copyright © 1998 Taylor & Francis.All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprintedor reproducedor utilised in any form or by any electronic,mechanical,or other means,now known or hereafterinvented, including photocopyingand recording,or in any information storageor retrieval system,without permissionin writing from the publishers. Notices No responsibilityis assumedby the publisherfor any injury and/ordamageto personsor property as a matterof productsliability, negligenceor otherwise, or from any useof operationof any methods,products, instructionsor ideas containedin the material herein. Practitionersand researchersmust always rely on their own experienceand knowledgein evaluatingand using any information, methods,compounds,or experimentsdescribedherein. In using such information or methodsthey should be mindful of their own safety and the safety of others, including partiesfor whom they havea professionalresponsibility. Productor corporatenamesmay be trademarksor registeredtrademarks,and are usedonly for identification and explanationwithout intent to infringe. Library of CongressCataloging-in-Publication Data Internationalrelationsin a constructedworld / editedby VendulkaKubalkova,NicholasOnuf, andPaul Kowert. p. cm. Includesbibliographicalreferencesandindex. ISBN 0-7656-0297-0(cloth: alk. paper).ISBN 0-7656-0298-9(pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Internationalrelations. 2. Constructivism(philosophy). I. Kubalkova,V. II. Onuf, NicholasGreenwood. III. Kowert, Paul, 1964JZ1305.1575 1998 327-dc21 97-46968 CIP ISBN 13: 9780765602985(pbk) ISBN 13: 9780765602978(hbk) Contents About the Editors and the Contributors Preface vii lX PART I. INTRODUCTION 1. ConstructingConstructivism VendulkaKubillkowi, Nicholas Onu/, andPaul Kowert 3 PART II. CONSTRUCTIVISM IN CONTEXT 2. The Twenty Years'Catharsis:E.H. Carr and IR VendulkaKubillkova 25 3. Constructivism:A User'sManual NicholasOnu! 58 4. What Is at Stakein the Agent-StructureDebate? Harry D. Gould 79 PART III. INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS UNDER CONSTRUCTION 5. Agent versusStructurein the Constructionof NationalIdentity Paul Kowert 101 6. FeministStruggleas Social Construction: Changingthe GenderedRulesof Home-BasedWork ElisabethProgl 123 7. InternetGovernanceGoesGlobal Craig Simon 147 PART IV. CONSTRUCTIONIN THE ACADEMY 8. RemodelingInternationalRelations: New Tools from New Science? Henry L. Hamman 173 9. Reconstructingthe Discipline: Scholarsas Agents VendulkaKuMlkowi 193 Index 203 About the Editors and the Contributors Harry D. Gould received an M.A in International Studiesfrom Florida InternationalUniversity. He is pursuingdoctoral studiesin the Department of Political Science,JohnsHopkinsUniversity. Henry L. Hamman receivedhis Ph.D. from the University of Miami in InternationalRelations.He is presidentof SociocyberneticsInc., a systems researchcompanybasedin Miami. He is the authorand editor of a number of bookson internationalrelations. Paul Kowert is an assistantprofessorin the Departmentof International Relations at Florida International University. He is the author of recent studies on foreign policy decision making and social identity in international politics. Vendulka Kubalkova is a professorof internationalstudiesin the School of InternationalStudiesat the University of Miami and the author, among other works, with AA Cruickshank,of Marxism and International Relations. Nicholas Onuf is a professorin the Departmentof InternationalRelations at Florida InternationalUniversity. His most recentbook is The Republican Legacyin International Thought. Elisabeth Progl is an assistantprofessorin the Departmentof International Relationsat Florida InternationalUniversity and the authorof recentstudies in feminist international relationstheory. Craig Simon is a databaseapplicationspecialist.He is a Ph.D. candidateat the Schoolof InternationalStudiesat the University of Miami, and is writing a dissertation"Bandwidth Rules: Standardsand Structure in Global InternetGovernance." vii This page intentionally left blank Preface Prefacesare really postscripts.Authors write them at the very end, grateful that their laborsare really over. They acknowledgethe assistanceof institutions, colleagues,and relatives,and explain the circumstancesunderwhich the book was written. It is also the last opportunity to reprise some of the book'sthemes. It is in the nature of this particular project that we have many afterthoughts.We did not want to write yet anotherbook on the parlousstateof theory in the field ofInternationalRelations(IR). The dominantapproaches and theories in any field of study are seldom without critics. The "third debate"in IR has beenespeciallyferocious,as anyonewho takesthe trouble to understandits technically difficult languagecan confirm. Somecritics have indicted mainstreamtheorists for fraud, finding them guilty by associationwith the "Enlightenmentproject." On the evidence of great changesin the world during the pastdecade,othercritics havebeencontent to showthat the theoreticalmainstreamfailed in its own terms. In this book, we do not enterinto the debate,exceptto the very limited extentrequiredto situateourselves.Instead,we try to do somethingdifferent: to develop an alternative way of studying international relations as social relations, and in the processreconceptualizethe field in relation to otherfields. The opportunity to try somethingdifferent arose when Nicholas Onuf came to teach in Miami severalyears after he had written World of Our Making (1989). In this systematicand technically demandingbook, Onuf developeda "constructivist" framework from a broad range of theoretical materials as a way beyond what was then emerging as the third debate. VendulkaKubalkova greetedOnuf's arrival acrosstown by proposingthat they convenethe "Miami InternationalRelationsGroup" as a running seminar for their colleaguesand students.Kubalkova soonprevailedon Onuf to presentan accessibleversion of his constructivistframework to the Miami Group, and other participantsfollowed suit with papersvariously relevant to that framework. In 1996,severalmembersof the Miami Group presented ix x PREFACE their paperstogether at the joint conferenceof the International Studies Associationand the JapanAssociationof InternationalRelations. At that time the editorsbeganthe processof forming the work of the Miami Group into a coherentvolume. Since Onuf introduced"constructivism"in 1989 it has generatedgrowing interest,andmany scholarshave adoptedthe namefor their approaches. There are, in fact, not one but several"constructivisms"in the literature. The appeal of the name should come as no surprise in a decadethat has witnessedepochalpolitical and economicrearrangements. The bipolar Cold War systemand the entire Soviet bloc collapsed.The world plunged into turmoil with an unprecedentednumber of nations and ethnic groups demandingsovereignstatehood,political subdivision,or at leastredrawnfrontiers. The world is abuzz with economicand diplomatic activities as new geopolitical,geoeconomic,and geostrategicchangestake place. These"international" changesoccur against the backdrop of the vast part of the planet also changing"internal" ways of running political, economic,and social affairs. No part of the world can avoid thesechangesor their consequences;the entire world is continuously"under construction."The choice of the term "constructivism"thereforeseemsparticularlyapposite. Mainstream IR failed to anticipate these changes:in theory, nothing much was supposedto change.Many critics saw this failure as evidence againstthe possibility of theory. Somecritics evensaw it as confirming that the world is neverwhat it seems.Constructivismpoints to the limitations of mainstreamthinking, but it rejects the conclusion that theory about the world-or a coherentdescriptionof the worl~iscritics impossible. Instead,constructivismoffers a way how to go about redescribingthe world. Mainstreamtheoristsand their critics leavepeopleout. Constructivism puts peopleand their activities at the forefront. It is indeedan irony that at the turn of millennium, whenpeoplehaveachievedwondroustechnological feats, scholarsdo not see how people constructthe world as a consequenceof their social relations. Many other constructivistshave also pointed out that the scopefor people in the agent-structurerelationmust be enlarged.It is one thing of course to say that people make the world or that state identities influence the internationalstructure.It is quite anotherto be specific and explain by what mechanismthis "making" or "influencing" works. The inability to figure out how theseprocesseswork so that they can be empirically exploredhas been a blindspot in many forms of constructivism.What binds people to each other and to the material world around them? Onuf's constructivism identifies the main elementthrough which this "construction"takesplace: rules. Rules provide the medium for human interactivity. Our speciesis PREFACE xi inherently social, defined by the social arrangementswe create.Endowed with free will, people(agents)are thus seenas knowledgableparticipantsin the reproductionof social rules, and thus free from the assumeddeterminism of immaterial,inanimate,factors(structure). Onuf begins with people, understandingfirst of all the simple social relationsthey have with eachother. Only then doeshe work his way up to complex relations, practices, institutions, "structures,"or social arrangements that are called statesand IR. The axioms "saying is doing," "rules makerule," and "rules put resourcesinto play" distinguishOnufs schoolof constructivismfrom positivist and Marxist philosophiessuch as realism, neoliberalism,and historical materialismas well as from otherswho claim the constructivistmantle.Thoseapproacheslook first at the ways resources determinestructure,and then at specific social outcomes.MainstreamIR specialiststry to see a single world by standingoutside, looking for that which is "objectively given": measurablestructural variables that can be said to causehumanbehaviors.The traditional mainstreamresearchinterest is the extentto which material structuremakessocial behaviorinvoluntary and predictable.Constructivists,on the otherhand,seehumanbehaviorand socialstructureas inseparable, simultaneous, co-constituted. Constructivismprovides a template for viewing the world in a fundamentally different way from that offered in the standardIR literature. Insteadof introducing a vocabularyof states,balancesof power, anarchies, and other IR terms, constructivismbegins its first lessonon international relationswith an analysisof speechacts, rules, practices,agents,agencies, and social arrangements.Theseare the building blocks of society and its institutional structure.States,balancesof power, hegemonies,and so forth are specific instances.As Onuf put it, constructivismpaints a picture of "staggeringcomplexity and constantchange"within the interwoven patterns of overlappingsocial arrangements.The complexity of the constructivist redescriptionof the world, however,doesnot precludethe possibility of focusing on any single aspectof humanrelations,internationalor otherwise. Different types of rules, different social arrangements, institutions, conventionsand societiescanall be subjectedto this type of analysis.Rules hold the key to understanding. In this reading, the different political systems,ideologies,religions, or worldviews, of North and South, of East and West, and of civilizations throughout history are built on narrativesthat can be broken down and analyzedaccordingto the types of speechactsthat sustainthem. All narratives consistof instruction-rules,directive-rules,and commitment-rulesthat work in distinctive ways. Dependingon which of the three types is more strongly represented,and on how it is mixed with the others, one might xii PREFACE classify societiesand institutions. Internationalrelationsis itself a complex institution basedon a mixture oftheserules. To study internationalrelations as constructivistsrequiresthat we study rules ratherthan imaginary, artificially reified entities such as statesor structures.Rules have ontological substance;they are therefor anybodyto see. Constructivismis not a theory, it does not claim to explain why things work as they do. Constructivismis simply an alternativeontology, a redescription of the world. Thus it does not carry any inherent ideological stance.Constructivismis not an "ism" to be addedto the list dominatedin the IR studiesby neorealismandneoliberalism. We promisedthe publisherthat this book would have severalqualities that are usually consideredmutually exclusive: the book was to introduce somethingoriginal; it was to be scholarly and educationaland yet easyto read. As we struggledto lighten our proslr-which camemore naturally in some chaptersthan in others--wediscoveredjust how hard it is to write something"easy." In Chapter1 we try to explain someof the most difficult terms, such as epistemology,methodology,ontology, and positivism, in a straightforward way. This difficult task was necessaryin order to be able to place our book againstthe backdropof currentcontroversiesin the IR discipline, the third debatein particular. Yet we stay out of the actual debate.Our purposeis only to distinguish constructivismfrom other approacheswith which it is often confused,such as postmodern,deconstructionist,post-structuralist, andcritical approachesdiscussedbriefly in Chapter2 andthe otherforms of constructivismdiscussedin Chapter4. Chapter3 is centralto the project. It is written by ProfessorOnuf in a deliberatelystraightforwardfashion, setting out the ABCs of constructivism.It introducesa different way of thinking aboutthe world and IR. The readershould approachthis chapteras one would approachlearning a new languagewith a different alphabet,grammar, rangeof sounds,andmeanings.As in learninga new languageit might be difficult at first for readersto get "their tonguesaround"the constructivist languageandbegin to think alongthe constructivistlines. The remaining chaptersare concernedwith the payoff of this effort. Their authors do occasionally revisitthe main featuresof Onufs framework, but their main purposeis to showthe empirical and conceptualutility of the frameworkby applying it to topics of contemporaryrelevancesuch as political identity (Chapter5), social movements(Chapter6), the Information Age (Chapter 7), and even the professionof IR scholarshipitself (Chapter9). Theseare but a few examplesof the ways constructivismcan be applied. Chapters5 and 6 also revealthe facility with which constructivistresearchcan proceed using case historical methods, and Chapter 7 shows how constructivists PREFACE xiii might grapple with even the "newest" topics such as the implications of Internet expansion.Chapter8 introducesthe readerto some of the recent advancesin physical scienceswhich replacedconceptualinstrumentsthat still form a bedrock of positivism in social sciences.It shows conceptual compatibility of constructivismwith thesenew developments. As we contemplatethe finished volume the daunting questionremains whether we have succeededin our goal and have managedto present Onufs constructivismas an alternative way to view the world. Will the readerget it? How sooninto the book will the readerrealizewhat a radical a changewe advocate?Irrespective of the answersto these questions,we hopethat the book will be asrewardingto readas it wasto write. It now remains only to thank all those that made this project possible. First is the University of Miami (in particular Provost Luis Glaser and ProfessorHaim Shaked) for helping us to go as a group to Japan in 1996. The prospectof a "school trip" providedthe incentivefor completion of the initial papers.M.E. SharpeExecutiveEditor Patricia Kolb and Project Editor Steve Martin extendedus invaluable encouragementand help. Craig Simon, one of the contributors to this volume, put our diversely formatted chaptersinto digital conformity with the publisher'Sspecifications. Gonzalo Porcel-Querohelped this project as researchassistant throughoutits development.Our thanksgo also to the graduatestudentsand faculty of the Miami IR theory group. They read many parts of this book and pointedout placeswhere we lapsedinto the customarilyobscureprose of professionalacademics.Their enthusiasmhas made the work on this book worthwhile. It is to themthat we dedicatethis project. This page intentionally left blank _________ Part I Introduction This page intentionally left blank 1 Constructing Constructivism Vendulka Kubalkova, Nicholas Onuf, and Paul Kowert " ... so that they will not understandoneanother'sspeech. .. " The Tower of Babel "And thus what was written was fulfilled," and a common languagewas lost. Books, articles,and conferencepapersexplainingthe world at the tum of the millennium are a Tower of Babel (Genesis11). For half a century, English has been the unofficial but universal languageof scholarly exchange. Today, scholarsspeak in many, highly specializedEnglish languages,and they barely manage to understandeach other. Specialized languageshave always characterizeddisciplines, the subjectsof study that scholarshave delimited among themselves,as if these subjects werethe natural and inevitable way to arrangethe productionand disseminationof knowledge. What is unusualand has reachedtruly biblical proportionsis the way that specializedlanguageshave swept acrosstraditional disciplinary boundaries.InternationalRelations(for convenience,IR) is a conspicuous case, in part becauseits status as a discipline is not secure,in part becauseits subject matter (international relations, in this book always spelledout in the lower case)has undergonea spectaculartransformation within a decade'stime. Indeed, the contributors to this book do not even agree among themselveson whether IR is a discipline in its own right, an interdisciplinary undertaking,or merely a field (or subdivision)of political science.Perhaps 3 4 KUBALKOvA, ONUF, AND KOWERT changesin the world make the traditional ways that scholarshave divided up the world seemincreasinglyarbitrary and irrelevant. Perhapsthe Babel of scholarly languagessignifies the dismantlingof the currentarrangement of disciplinesconventionallyknown as the social sciences.The editors do agreethat a commonlanguageof scholarshipis both desirableand possible for the subjectof internationalrelations;that this languageshouldalso suit social relations in general; and that this languageshould never be made deliberately obscurejust to maintain disciplinary boundariesor, for that matter,to keeppeoplewho are not scholarlyspecialistsin the dark. IR scholars speak in many voices. They regularly propose new "approaches"to the subject, and proponentsengagein "great debates"over their merits. They feel obliged to proposeschemesfor classifying an ever larger numberof approaches.Their students spendan increasing,and perhaps inordinate, amount of time reprising these debatesand memorizing classificatoryschemes. This volume grew out of the pedagogicalconcernsof a group of teachers and studentsat two universitiesin Miami. Although our backgrounds and interests vary, our discussionshave increasingly centeredon "constructivism," in which the discipline as a whole has taken a great deal of interestsince Nicholas Onuf (one of the group'smembers)introducedthe term in 1989. As we consideredthe version of constructivismthat he had developedin World of Our Making and beganto think about our other scholarly interestsin constructivistterms, this book gradually took form. Onufs essay(see Chapter 3) sets out his version of constructivismin languagethat any serious-mindedreadercan understand.Othercontributors explain and refine constructivism,and apply it to a variety of important topics in internationalrelations. In the process,they help to dispel some myths and misunderstandingsthat have already attachedthemselves to a term that scholarshave begun to use rather casually. One myth is that constructivismis closely relatedto the "post-modern"practice of "deconstruction";a second is that constructivismmandatesan "emancipatory"or "critical" politics; a third is that constructivism,being "post-positivist," is indifferent to empirical researchand antithetical to "positivist" science. (We shall consider these and many other terms more fully in this introductorychapter.) This book showsthat constructivismoffers an unfamiliar but systematic way of thinking aboutsocial relationsin generaland internationalrelations in particular. The book also shows the relevanceof constructivismto the empirical investigationof important topics in contemporaryinternational relations, such as national identity, genderin political economy, and the emerginginformation age. In sum, the volume addressesthesequestions: CONSTRUCTING CONSTRUCTIVISM 5 What is constructivism?Wheredoesit fit in the discipline?How it can help the discipline to move on? In this introductorychapter,we undertakeseveralpreliminary tasks.We look briefly into the relatively short history and currently confusedstateof the discipline. We discussdisciplinary boundaries,externalinfluences,and endlessdebatesas sourcesof confusion.We show that the ways IR scholars categorizeapproachesand stake out positions for debatehave led them to underestimateconstructivismas an alternativeto receivedways of thinking. Finally, and perhapsmost important, we explain a considerablenumberof conceptsthat scholarsoften use but rarely give sufficient thought to, and that readersunschooledin the scholarly languagesof philosophy and the social scienceswill find utterly baffling. The purposeof this book is not to pronounceon the stateof the discipline, to assessall sourcesof confusion,or to passjudgmenton every debate. Part I of the book does so only as necessaryto discuss the intellectual context from which constructivismhas grown. Nor is our purposeto discredit the efforts oflR scholarsto learn from otherdisciplines.Our purpose, rather, is to show that constructivismcan make senseof internationalrelations by making senseof social relations,and that constructivismoffers IR a way beyond the impasseof many discordantlanguagesand distracting debates. Disciplinesand Dialects Insular and protectedas a discipline, IR is overwhelmingly the work of scholarsfrom just two countries:Britain and the United States.Just as IR has finally begunto openitself to other disciplinesand their languages,it is ironic that the subjectmatterof internationalrelationscameto the attention of scholarsin thoseotherdisciplines.All of a sudden,"global concerns"are on everyone'sagenda.At the sametime, scholarsfrom all over the world havebegunto identify themselves withIR as a discipline. IR hasbecomea to be appliedto IR and authors major importer of ideasand author~ideasespecially to cite as sourcesof inspiration. It is especially unsettling for an older generationof IR scholarsto seeothernamesthan their own sprinkledin the footnotesof their youngercolleagues. As a discipline, IR has accumulateda huge intellectual balanceof trade deficit. Little producedin the discipline has found its way into other disciplines. IR scholarsdo not seemto lead or influence public debate.The pastdecadewas characterizedby tumultuousand far-reachingchangesthat exposedthe irrelevanceof the discipline'S accumulatedknowledge about internationalrelations.Any numberof politicians, intellectuals,andjournal- 6 KUBALKOV A, ONUF, AND KOWERT ists have declaredthe end of the Cold War, communism,modernity, and history, and the beginning of some new epoch, with no help whatsoever from IR scholars. Furthermore,most of these scholars are only slowly adjusting to a new agendaof concernr-globalwarming, environmental degradation,overpopulation,ethnic conflict-identified by somebodyoutside the discipline. Everything allegedly new and different is "post": postcommunist, post-internationalrelations, post-modern,post-positivist, post-realist,post-Soviet,post-structural,post-theory.As a universalprefix, "post" indicatesmore clearly what has been transcendedor rejectedthan what may be expectedin the future. IR is hardly alone in its bewilderment.The division of knowledge by disciplines no longer seems convincing. There are so many bodies of knowledge,eachcouchedin its own arcanelanguage,that reachingacross disciplines bringshugecostsin translation,dissipatingintellectualresources that could otherwise be used to addressnew concerns.BecauseIR combines global pretensionswith an exceptionallyinsular perspectiveon itself and its subject, it suffers more than most disciplines from this state of affairs. The creation and accumulationof knowledge in the last two hundred yearsadvancedhand in handwith the multiplication of specializationsand their institutionalization as disciplines. Since there is nothing natural or inevitable about the way scholars define their substantiveconcernsand the parcelthem out amongthemselves,someof theseconcerns--especially onesnow popularly called "global"-areshared,but the way they are studied is not. Even if scholarswere able to overcometheir parochial tendencies, disciplinary "dialects" make it difficult for them to share anything across disciplines.Indeed,the more somethingpassesmusteras knowledge within a discipline, the lesslikely it is to "translate"to otherdisciplines. Dialects develop becausethe samewords usedin severaldisciplines or their subfields begin to carry different meaningsin each. When scholars introduce and debatenew concepts,they give new meaningto old words. They separatesynonyms, realign antonyms, and invent new words. As worlds of scholarship,disciplinesare nevercompletelysealedoff from each other. The words themselvesdrift acrossdisciplinary boundarieslike snippetsof conversationfor which an eavesdropper hasno context. They tantalize scholarsdissatisfiedwith the stateof their own disciplines,who borrow themwith minimal careand adapt themto new uses. To give a few examplesrelevantto our concerns,structure, agent, and realism mean very different things in different disciplines. The structuralism of anthropologistClaudeLevi-Strausshaslittle to do with the structural Marxism of Louis Althusserand evenless to do with the structuralrealism CONSTRUCTING CONSTRUCTIVISM 7 of IR's Kenneth Waltz. Economistsand sociologistsmean quite different things by the term agent. Realismin philosophyis far removedfrom realism in internationalrelations.(SeeChapter4 for a discussionof "scientific realism.") The term critical is another,instructiveexample.Philosophershaveused the term in a specializedsensethat goes back to Immanuel Kant. In the handsof Marxist theorists,it acquireda different, though still specialized, meaning.Other scholarshad alwaysusedthe term to refer to the "ability to find defects andfaults," onceregardedas a critical faculty of every scholar. Thanks to the diffusion of a specifically neo-Marxist dialect, scholarsin several disciplines now use the term in ways that neither Kant nor any ordinary personwould understand.The antonymof the term critical is not uncritical but, in somecases,positivist(a term itself carrying severalmeanings) and in others,problem-solving.Not all scholarsare critical (although this doesnot meanthat they are "uncritical"). Not being critical might mean that a scholaris positivist or interestedonly in proposingpolicies to solve narrowly defined problems. There are powerful incentivesto perpetuatethe confusion. Who would not want to be a critical scholarif it reflects on one'sintellectual abilities? Yet becoming "critical" carries certain implications: for some scholars being critical meansopenly acknowledginga connectionto Marx, while other critical scholarsgo out of their way to deny such a connection.The distinctions are not often appreciated.Some scholarsquote post-structuralists and critical theorists in support of the sameargument,overlooking vehement disagreementsbetweenthe two groups(Kratochwil 1984). The same argumentmay once be describedas leftist or Marxist, and anothertime as right-wing and conservative.The samewords point in altogetherdifferent directions. Often scholarsand studentsblithely usewords, suchas discourseandthe other, for their sophisticatedand contemporaryflair. The word problematique(with appropriateFrenchpronunciation)is usedinsteadof problem or hypothesisin total ignoranceof the very special meaningthat the French term is intendedto convey. Similarly project is no longer just an exercisefor schoolchildren.In the history of ideas, some antecedentsare more controversialthan others,and the genesisof many currently fashionable terms in earlier leftist ideasis still a sensitivesubject.Practice is just sucha term, only somewhatseparatedfrom the Marxist notion of praxis by translationinto English. In fact, this is a term to which constructivistsare partial, andreaderswill find it usedin this book. Words are imported from all over the place, including meteorology, physics, and mathematics.Terms such as turbulence,chaos, and cascade, 8 KUBA.LKOV A., ONUF, AND KOWERT which natural scientistsand mathematicianshave adoptedfrom ordinary languagefor their own very specific use, have been borrowed by social scientists,including IR scholars,and used metaphorically.With so many casualappropriationsand mixed signals, it is not surprisingthat many IR scholarsare casting about for terms to describethemselvesthat simultaneouslyseemright for disciplinary purposes,flatter them in their ordinary meaning,and suggesta connectionto otherdisciplinary conversations(conversation is another term that scholars have favored with a specialized meaning).Justas somescholarsfeel that they ought to make sure that they are critical in some senseof the term, many are now self-proclaimedconstructivists. They often use the term to suggestwhat they are not: they are not realists or positivists in any narrow sense.They do not practice "deconstruction."Taking the middle path, as they seeit (Adler 1997), they areprotectedon both sidesby the fuzzy useof language. InternationalRelationsas a Discipline The Enlightenment'scelebrationof reasonunleasheda tremendousrangeof intellectual activities previously restrictedby the medieval acceptanceof God's revelation as the truth. By the end of the eighteenthcentury, two previously synonymousterms, scienceand philosophy,had beenredefined and separated.Thereafter,science dealt with the material world and includedsuchpursuitsas astronomy,chemistry,and physics.Scientistsmade innumerablediscoveriesthat had a cumulatively staggeringeffect on the material conditionsof daily life. Overshadowedby the dazzling successes of science,philosophywas left with "metaphysical"questionsthat no one could hopeto answerconvincingly. In the nineteenthcentury,betweenthe growing edifice of scienceandthe shrinking edifice of philosophy,ground was broken by one of the "inventors" of positivism, AugusteComte,for an ambitiousnew undertaking.The new edifice of the "social sciences"was to be built to the image of the highly successful"natural sciences."Sustainingthis developmentwas a belief, known as naturalism, that natureand society do not fundamentally differ. In positivist terms, any phenomenon,no matter how complex in appearance, canbe brokendown into units that canbe studiedscientifically. Cumulativeknowledgewill faithfully representthe world as it is, explain how it works, predict its future unfolding, and allow humanityto control its own destiny. Late in the nineteenthcentury, the separationof political economyinto politics (mainly governmentand public law) and economics,and the separation of sociology from the other two disciplines, followed the liberal CONSTRUCTING CONSTRUCTIVISM 9 practice of separatingstate, economy,and society. Anthropology came in tandemwith colonial administration,while history occupiedan ambiguous positionbetweenthe humanitiesandthe social sciences. IR came late and developedslowly, in the shadow of the other social sciences,especially politicalscience.World War I endowedit with a subject matterthat other disciplineshad relegatedto the marginsof systematic inquiry: the study of war and ways to avoid it. The first IR scholarswere, for the most part, international lawyers and diplomatic historians. Diplomats and journalists mattered,and professionaljournals were devoted to policy issuesand currentevents.Studentsof politics concernedthemselves with the subject from the point of view of international law and international organizations(chiefly the Leagueof Nations). Other social scientists were conspicuouslyabsent,and the positivist idea of sciencewas almost unheardof. (A British meteorologist,statistician,and Quaker,L.F. Richardson, is the most interestingexceptionto this generalization;his work went largely unnoticeduntil after World War II.) Betweenthe two world wars, many IR scholarswere closely connected to the governmentsof the day in Britain and the United States.To the extent that the discipline can be said to have existedat all, its dominantconcerns reflectedthe liberal internationalismof English-speakingpolitical elites. A little in Continentaltradition of concernfor statecraft-Realpolitik-figured the discipline. Marxist concernsmatteredevenless. After World War II, IR gained disciplinary momentum. The United Statesassumedan active stancetoward the world commensuratewith its power, universities in the United States expandedrapidly, and German Jewishexpatriatesbrought a Continentalconcernfor statecraftto the fore. What seemedlike a new and very powerful way of thinking, styled realism, transformedthe discipline. Realists fostered the impression that war is a permanentfeature of humanexperiencebecausehumancommunitieshad alwaysbeenorganized to expectthe worst from eachother. They dismissedthe liberal internationalist project of progressivepacification as dangerouslynaive. States,they reasoned,are hereto stay, and relationsof statesdemandconstantattention, skillful statecraft,and an unswervingcommitmentby every state'sleaders to the "nationalinterest." Furthermore,realistsarguedthat humanexperienceat the level of states and their relations is distinct from behavior at other levels. IR's subject matterwas to be uniquely its own, as guaranteedby the principle of sovereignty. Despiterecurrentdebatesover the most appropriate"level of analysis," IR was overwhelminglystate-centric.IR's raison d'etre was the study of states,andthusthe study of raison d'etat. Always haphazardaboutlevels 10 KUBALKOV A, ONUF, AND KOWERT of analysis,the first generationof realistsstill showedtracesof concernfor nationalcharacter.The behaviorof statesreflectedtheir distinctive histories and geographicalpositions;the behaviorof their leadersreflectedthe inevitable flaws of human character. Starting in the 1960s, however, realist scholarssoughtto makethe new discipline scientific. The credibility of sciencedependson findings that are themselvescredible by scientific criteria and cumulative. After two decadesof science,IR had preciouslittle to show in the latter respect.Some scholarscounseled patience, and have diligently continued with the job of science. Others began to doubt that realism provided sciencewith an adequatebasis for cumulativefindings. As a matterof theory, attentionto the characteristicsof states,no matter how scientific, missedthe point that statesmight behave alike becauseof a commonsituationthat none of them can hope to escape. In this situation, readily associatedwith ThomasHobbes'sstate of nature, statesneedonly respondrationally to the radical insecurity engenderedby their collective,unregulatedexistence. The rationality postulatepermitteda rigoroustheoryof internationalrelations, analogousto price theory in microeconomics--orso KennethWaltz proclaimedin his immenselyinfluential book, TheoryofInternationalPolitics (1979). Instead of an equilibrium of supply and demand,the theory predicted(frequentlyunstable)equilibria of powerandsecurity.Redirecting attention to the structureof the internationalsystem,Waltz attributed the "long peace"after World War II to the simplicity of a bipolar equilibrium of states.Structuralistrealiststhen resumeda familiar debateover the relative merits of bipolar andmultipolar arrangements. Observing that no set of conditions consistentwith a state of nature anticipatesgenuinelyharmoniousrelationsamongstates,other scholarsattributed the long peace instead to the United States' international hegemony. The term hegemonyhad long been used to describethe efforts of leadingstatesto besttheir peersthroughdiplomacyand war. The useof this term to describethe dominantposition of Britain in the nineteenthcentury and the United Statesafter World War II signaledtwo tendenciesin the discipline that emergedmore or less simultaneouslywith the project to rationalizerealism.Onewas a revival of liberal institutionalism,fosteredby recognition that these countries held their positions in good measureby virtue of having institutionalizeda liberal world economy.In short order, applicationof the rationality postulateto the circumstancesof liberal hegemony had the effect of joining structural realism and structural liberalism (both often called "neo-") as the discipline'scompetingbut closely related orthodoxies. A secondtendencysignaledby the term hegemonystemmedfrom its use CONSTRUCTING CONSTRUCTIVISM 11 by the Italian Marxist Antonio Gramscito refer to the importanceof ruling ideas rather than formal institutional arrangements.In the context of the world economy,liberal ideasmade the dominanceof Britain and then the United Stateseasy. Until the Vietnam War, IR had developedin almost completeisolation from the many forms of Marxist thoughtthat had proliferated over the decades.Even then, IR scholarswere slower than their colleaguesin the other social sciencesto explore the intellectual legacy of the Left. As a ritual, IR scholarsoften askedtheir studentsto reada little bit of Lenin. While sociologists and diplomatic historians strenuouslydiscussedimperialismduring the Vietnam era, nothing comparabletook place in IR. Only throughdependencytheory, which Latin Americanwriters proposed to explain the persistenceof international inequality, did the Left make its first real contributionto the discipline. Thereuponfollowed world systemstheory andthe Gramscianinterpretationof hegemony. Recognitionthat writers on the left had somethingto say took the form of an ad hoc schemesorting approachesto internationalrelationsinto three categories-realist(including mercantilist),pluralist (meaningliberal), and radical (or globalist, sometimesevencalledMarxist}-on what amountedto an ideological spectrum.The radical categorywas, however, far removed from decadesof discussionamongEuropeanMarxists, which begana great reconsiderationof Enlightenmentpremiseson philosophicalas well as ideological grounds.Only graduallyover the last twenty yearshave IR scholars begunto appreciatethe challengethat this reconsiderationof the "modem project," as it is often called, representsfor their own discipline,for positivist science,for the way that they think about languageand its uses,and for the very ideathat knowledgeis possible. As VendulkaKubalkovamakesclearin the next chapter,confrontingthe challengeof "post" thinking hashad a catharticeffect on many IR scholars. Whetherit hashad a comparableeffect on the discipline as suchis harderto say. In the short term, structuralrealists and their liberal look-alikes have succeededin maintaining their disciplinary hegemony,especially in the major graduateinstitutions in the United States. Indeed, rational choice theoryholds sway at HarvardUniversity, the University of Chicago,andthe University of California at Berkeley. The longer term may prove to be a different story, especiallyas the discipline becomesas global as its subject matter. The Forest Fire Until the "post" movementpromptedthe emergenceof new ways of thinking in IR, including constructivism,debatesin the discipline were relatively 12 KUBALKOvA, ONUF, AND KOWERT simpltr-and practically continuous. One debatenever took place. When David Singerdirectedattentionto the level of analysisproblem,he usedthe imageryof trees(read"states")and forest (read"the internationalsystem") (Singer 1961, 77). Actual forests contain many different speciesof trees, dependingon terrain, soil conditions, human intrusion, and so on. Yet Singer's forest is perfectly homogeneous,no doubt becauserealists have always dismisseda liberal concern for differences among societies and forms of governmentwithin states.In a minor debatethat still rumbleson, liberals tried to find a place for "deer or birds, also denizensof the forest," as K.J. Holsti (1985, 38) suggestedin a useful extensionof the imagery,but they failed to persuademost realists,for whom war, or "forest fire," is the only reasonto pay attentionto the forest or to think of it as composedof trees.Perhaps,from a realist point of view, "Smokeythe Bear" can alert us to the dangerof forest fires, but bearsliving in the forest cannot prevent them. We too will use the metaphoricallanguageof the forest throughout the rest of this introductorychapter. The power of this imagery is obvious when we stop to consider the terrifying speedwith which peoplehave beenburning up and cutting down tropical forests. Facedwith this sort of threat, forest rangersscanningthe horizon for signs of smoke are beside the point. Liberal scholars have always looked for ways of eliminating fire from the forest, while realists rule out elimination of fires and concentratetheir attentionon damagecontrol. Dependencytheorists are happy to explain that people destroy their forestsbecausetheir position in the world economyleavesthem no choice. The issueis not the forest as such,but a structureof planetaryrelationsthat force African women to walk miles for firewood while IR scholarsfurnish their studieswith mahoganybookcases.True to Marx, dependencytheorists would also admonishus to bewareof scholarswho claim that they have no ax to grind. Backto Basics The metaphoricallanguageof forest, trees,and fire helps to clarify the sorts of debatesin IR that havtr-Or might have--takenplace. It can also show what scholarsin the discipline have taken for grantedin conductingtheir debates,at least until they confrontedthe arrival of "post" influencesfrom other disciplines.Everyonetook for grantedscholars'ability to representthe world (or the forest) as it is. Objectiveknowledgeseemeda feasiblegoal. To put it differently, epistemology(how do we know what we know?) was not an issue.We know what we know, becausewtr-as scholars,and as children of the Enlightenment---have beenin the businessof systematically CONSTRUCTING CONSTRUCTIVISM 13 knowing more for a long time and we have gottenbetterand betterat it. In particular, we know how to separateour knowing selves,and our wishes, from the world that we know more and more about. At issue and much debatedwas methodology(how should we go about the businessof knowing?). Methodologydiffers from epistemologyin that the former inquires into proceduresfor attesting to knowledge, while the latter is concerned with the basisfor knowledge--theconviction that our sensoryexperienceis systematicallyrelatedto the world outsideourselves. Ontology (what is it that we know?) was an issue, though rarely discussedas such. We do know that there is a world out there, independentof our efforts to know more about it. We evenknow that our efforts affect the world; we are only provisionally outsideof it. At issue is the fundamental natureof the world: Is it in the enda simple matterto explainhow the world works oncewe havebrokenit down into its smallestparts?Or is it finally a matterof greatcomplexity, perhapseven more than we can imagine?Convinced that the world will reveal its simplicity to us oncewe know enough, positivists claimed that sciencecleared the way for ever more powerful theories.On the defensive,historiciststreatedtheseclaims with skepticism, only to be described,or dismissed,as traditionalistsfor doing so. Metaphysicalissueswere off limits. Scholarshad no businessasking what it all meant-whathigher purposeour earthly existencemight serve. These were private matters of faith or speculation. Ethical issues were public business,but the public consistedof consumersof knowledge,not producers.Scholarswere both. As teachers,consultants,or occasionalpolicy makers,scholarscould speaktheir minds on what peopleshoulddo and what the world ought to be like, but even then scholarly norms urged a balancedanddetachedpublic demeanor. Of the debatesthat did occur in IR, the first "great debate"ruled questions of ethics out of order, establishingthe primacy of realists over socalled idealists. The second "great debate" ratified the methodological assumptionthat scientific testing should prevail over historical reconstruction. Although the termsof the debatewere methodological,the underlying issuewas ontological: Is the world ultimately very simple, or is it irreducibly complex? The debate itself gradually petered out in quibbles over method. At the same time, philosophersand social theorists began to challenge the epistemologicalconsensusthat sustainedall such debates. Eventually these challengesprecipitateda far deeperand more divisive debatethan the discipline had previouslyexperienced,which was heralded in the 1980sasthe "third debate." Manyscholarsbeganto suspectthat there wasnothing actuallyto debate.The incompatibility of epistemologicalpositions, and the refusal to believethat a commonposition was evenpossible, 14 KUBALKOvA, ONUF, AND KOWERT meantchoosingsides and going separateways. It was in this context that constructivismemerged. Even the simplestof statementscan be usedto reinforce the understanding of someof theseissues.In everydayconversation,we do not examine everything thatwe say in orderto understandits philosophicalimplications, but we could. To illustrate this, let us start with a simple claim about the world: "There is a fire in the forest." An examinationof this claim takesus to ontology. Ontology deals with essenceand appearance,the nature of things and how they are related,and how this affects the way that things appearto us. The statement"there is a fire in the forest" claims to tell us what "it" is that we are talking about, what "it" consistsof, and how "its" parts are related. An examinationof this claim requiresus to introducecategoriesinto which the object we are talking about can be meaningfully placed: the forest in questionis but one possiblememberof a classof objectscalledforests,and its placementin that classmay be subjectto confusionor controversy.The samegoesfor the fire. The statement"there is a fire in the forest" ought not to be confusedwith the statement"the forest is on fire." Both statementsare commonsense shorthandrepresentationsof a seriesof different propositions,themselves basedon assumptionsthat anyonehearing these statemertsmust sharein orderto understandthem. The termfire probablyrefersto a commonchemical reactionthat takesplaceundercertainconditions,with a readily observable result (namely, that combustibleobjectsburn). It is unclear,however, whether the speakerintends hearersto believe that the whole forest is burning all at once; such a situation is unlikely and such an interpretation seemstoo literal. Indeed,the statement"the forest is on fire" could simply be intendedto convey an image of the forest on the occasionof a particularly magnificentsunset. Even if the statement"there is a fire in the forest" is less likely to be misconstrued,at least in English, it still dependson context for meaning. The personreportingthe fire must assumethat hearersknow that a forest is an extensive,unenclosedtract of land (its Latin root, faris, means"outside"), that particularkinds of chemicalreactionscalledfires are frequent eventsin forests, that forests contain a great deal of combustiblematerial, and that immediate conditions (such as wind and relative humidity) will havea significant effect on the combustibilityof that material.The prepositional phase"in the forest" is ontologically significant becauseit tells us to think about the propertiesand relationsof particulartrees,and not, at least initially, aboutthe forest as a whole. Furthermore,the personshouting"fire" believesthat a seriesof empiri- CONSTRUCTING CONSTRUCTIVISM 15 cal generalizationscover the situation. Flickering light, intenseheat, vohuninous smoke, or crackling noises generally mean fIre; beyond a certain size, fIres are generallyhard to control; big fIres in the forest are generallyundesirable; it is generallyresponsibleto report untendedfIres in the forest; and other peoplewill generallybelieve the report of fIre if it is appropriatelyconveyed. To report that the forest is "on fIre" invites disbelief, evenif the intention is to report, quite specifIcally, that an untendedfIre in the forest is growing rapidly and is possibly alreadyout of control. To report "there is a fIre in the forest" invites hearersto participatein the processof empirical generalizationfrom which sharedknowledgeresults.Otherswill ask: "Where is the fIre? How big is it? What directionis it moving?What shouldwe do now?" As this discussionshows, any statementcan be broken into a chain of propositionsabout the world. It may be that none of thesepropositionsis "true." As the personshouting"fIre," I may be mistakenaboutthe smokeor the cracklingnoise. I may not realizethat the fIre is uhdercontrol, or indeed that it was set for the desired goal of burning away underbrush.Craving attention,I may have cried "fIre" so often in the past that no one believes me any longer. When othersagreewith my claims aboutthe world, and acts that we take on the basisof theseclaims have the effects that we generally expectthem to, I think that I have spokentruly. If othersconfIrm that there is a fIre, if we all take what we believeare the appropriateactionsto put the fIre out, and if a numberof us then report that the fIre is no longer burning, then I may rest assuredthat I hadreportedthe truth. In the fIrst instance,speakingtruly is a methodologicalmatter. If others have doubtsabout the accuracyor relevanceof my claims, I will tell them how I fIgured out that there is a fIre in the forest. Sticking my hand in it, looking at the flames, and smelling the smoke,I have relied on my senses and comparedthe results with what I already know about fIres. I am obliged, at least in principle, to show that I have chosena methodsuitedto the circumstancesand then used it properly before others are obliged to grant that my claims are true. If we considerthe complexity of any claim that I might make about the outbreakof war in internationalrelations,it is clearhow diffIcult it is to verify suchclaims. Ever since the Enlightenment,we have assumedthat we can standapart from the world in order to "see" it clearly and formulate statementsthat correspondto the world as it truly is. Seeingthe world even more clearly dependson improving our observationaltechniquesand making our empirical generalizationsmore precise.The more we are able to offer propositions about the world, and the more we can identify relationsbetweenthem, the better able we are to capture the truth of the world. All these activities vouchfor our epistemologicalconvictions. 16 KUBA.LKOVA., ONUF, AND KOWERT If we wished, we could break down even further our propositionsabout forest fires, identifYing variousphysicalandchemicalprocesses,specifYingthe circumstancesunderwhich they take place,measuringand classifYingthemby referenceto their properties,and generalizingabout them on the basisof observedregularities.Ontologically speaking,this endeavoris positivism,which holds that the world consistsof many things held togetherby many fewer sets of relations.Methodologicallyspeaking,this is science,consistingof betterand betterexplanationsfor what we observe,buttressedby more andbetterdata. Questions As yet, nothing in this discussionchallengesthe epistemologicalconsensus that hasprevailedsincethe Enlightenment.The relationshipbetweenme, as observer,and the fire, as an objective, observablecondition, is something that I and the othersto whom I am speakingtake for granted.I observethe fire at a specifiabledistance,and my report of fire will affect the fire in a way that I or anotherobservercan also, in principle, specify: for example, we all put the fire out. If anyonewere to raise questionsabout my assumptions, then my belief that I can speaktruly has becomea matter of epistemology. I can know the truth, given certainassumptionsaboutthe world. I cannot know whether these assumptionsare true, however, preciselybecause they are assumptions.How do I know that I am not deluded in thinking that I seethe world out there?How do I know whetherwe havenot togetherinventeda world that exists (as a discerniblewhole in many parts) only in, or inseparablyfrom, the sharedmeaningsthat we give to it? Even if my propositionsabout the world are true, is not the truth of the world dependenton the linguistic propertiesofthesepropositions? The first of thesequestionsis ageless.Many a child has askedit. Treating the questionas pointlessor silly, or as somethingfor philosophersto worry about,allows us all to get on in a world that doesseemto exist pretty much as we senseit. Ifwe are deluded,thendelusionshavetheir advantages. The secondquestionchallengesthe naturalismthat most positivists espouse.The physical world may exist more or less as we senseit, but the social world existsbecausewe participatein it and bring our wishesto bear upon it. Detachingourselvesfrom the social world to observeit is something that we can only do provisionally, in a weak approximationof the requirementsof science.Framingthe problemthis way raisesthe possibility that the positivists are right, after all, to insist on the unity of the physical and social worlds, but wrong to think about it in "natural" terms. Perhaps the physical world is nothing apart from what we say it meansto us, and meaningis alwayssocial. CONSTRUCTING CONSTRUCTIVISM 17 The third questionis as old as the study of rhetoric, but with rhetoric out of fashion for centuries,it strikes us as the newestand most challenging.It makeslanguagethe central issue for epistemology:is truth contingenton the way we speak?Philosophersand social theoristswho ask this question have taken the "linguistic tum," as they call it, and their answershelpedto launch the "post" movement. One answer, "truly" radical in its implications,holds that the truth of our propositionsis strictly limited to those propositions;thereis no world apartfrom them. In effect, languagecan only representitself. At best, sucha position allows us to think of the world as a "text" and fostersan interestin "deconstructing"the propositionsmaking it up to show how truths are fabricated and for whose benefit. A second answerto the questionsuggeststhat languagecan neverrepresentthe world completelyaccurately,becauselanguageis implicated in making the world it purportsto represent.Sucha position treatsmost truths as provisionaland the world as a complex processof social construction.Standingback and observing this processis a useful activity, often to be undertakenwith scientific rigor, but not an activity that can producethe comprehensively true pictureof the world to which positivistsaspire. The Challengeof the "Post" Movement By now the readershouldbe able to appreciatethat IR as a social scienceis basedupon a more or less unexaminedset of assumptions,most of which define positivist scienceas a major undertakingof the modemworld. Positivist assumptionshave locked IR onto a particularpoint on a broad spectrum of philosophical possibilities that many scholars in the discipline might not even have beenawareof. When a few scholarsbeganto discuss thesepossibilities,often rather tendentiously,the tone and substanceof IR debatescompletelychanged.Having shapedrealismwith positivist zeal,the young radicals of an earlier generationsuddenly found themselvesdescribedas reactionarydisciplinary guardians-or,in keepingwith our earlier imagery,as forest rangerspatrolling a burned-out,desolatelandscapein magnificentignoranceofthe irrelevanceof their vocation. For most scholars,and certainly for the discipline'sleading figures, experiencing the "post" challenge was disagreeableand often mystifying. What is one to make of the preposterousclaim that none of us standon the same"ground" whenwe speakof forests?The epistemologicalchallengeto foundationsmadedemolition of the discipline or dismissalof the challenge seemlike the only possibilities. Even issuesthat seemthorny enough in ontologicaltermstook a radical, epistemologicaltum. How do I know that you and I meanthe samething by "fire" or "war"? Is my world generally 18 KUBA.LKOVA., ONUF, AND KOWERT commensurablewith Aristotle's, a Chinesevillager's, yours? Some"post" challengerswould arguethat there are as many worlds as there are beholders, and that theseworlds are impossibleto compareor relate to eachother. For most scholars,any such argument simultaneouslymocks us for our delusionsand demeansus as social beings.It hardly matterswhetherI go walking in the forest with you or with my dog. Eachof us sensesthe world as entirely, unrecognizablydifferent. Our only satisfactioncomesfrom the prospect that you, I, and the dog can at least enjoy the walk, however incommensurable our reasons! If the radical impulse of the "post" challengebrought cries of outrage from the discipline's leading figures, another predictable responsealso quickly madeits presencefelt. Perhapsthe challengecould be domesticated by taking it inside the discipline and giving it a name. Since most of the challengershad madethe linguistic tum, a label reflecting their preoccupation with languagewould seemto havebeenan appropriatechoice.Hermeneutics was a good candidate.Named after Hermes, the Greek god of messengersand interpretersof messages,hermeneuticsreferredto a quest for the correcttheologicalinterpretationof the Bible and later to the interpretationof any text. As a name,however,it suggesteda rathertoo specific intellectualgenealogyanda too narrowconcernwith meaning. Interpretiveand its cognateinterpretivistoffered a betterchoice. Widely usedin sociology, interpretivistattractedconsiderableattentionin IR when Friedrich Kratochwil and JohnRuggieusedit in 1986 to criticize positivist assumptions.While the term itself suggestsan epistemologicalconcern with the status of the knower, Kratochwil and Ruggie's exposition was concernedmore with what we know (that is, ontology) was not especially radical. For them, an interpretiviststancesuits the multiplicity of meanings that complex, normatively freighted social processesinevitably engender (Kratochwil andRuggie 1986). Two years later, Robert Keohaneused his presidentialaddressto the InternationalStudiesAssociationas an occasionto pronounceon the subject. Setting on one side scholarswith rationalistic inclinations, including himself, he thoughtthe term interpretiveleft too much out on the otherside. He proposedreflective insteadto indicate a stresson "human reflection" (Keohane 1988, 382). It was a stroke of genius for Keohaneto choosea flatteringly empty term--who wouldn't want to be thought of as reflective?--to deflect attention from the epistemologicalthrust of the "post" challenge.In effect, he resuscitatedthe earlier debatebetweenpositivists and historicists, and suggestedthat "reflection" is the appropriatemethod for historicist inquiry. Many scholarswith Keohane'srationalist sensibilities adoptedthe term reflectivistto describetheir "post" challengers. CONSTRUCTING CONSTRUCTIVISM 19 Yosef Lapid (1989) offered the challengers(himself among them) a more attractive alternative.They are post-positivists,whom he set against positivists in what he called the "third debate."Given the ferocity of the challengeand the befuddledresponseto it, styling this situation a "great debate" granted the challengersa certain legitimacy. In exchange,Lapid softenedthe epistemologicalchallengeby calling it perspectivism,skipped over ontology as such, and went on to discussthe move toward methodologicalpluralism (1989, 241-44). The term post-positivismis undoubtedlybetter than its alternatives,including critical (which we criticized above).Nevertheless,the simple symmetry of the pairedtermspositivismandpost-positivismunduly rationalizes a momentof controversyand obfuscationin the discipline'sshort history. In theseintroductory pages,we refer to the challengeof the "post" movement. We do so for convenience,and in full recognitionthat scholarshave attachedthe prefix "post" to so many, diverse nouns that it capturesthe flavor of that turbulentmoment,not to mentiona continuingsenseof disorientationin the discipline. At the same time, Onuf proposedconstructivismas a framework for social theory. Taking the linguistic tum, he settled for the second, less radical answerto the epistemologicalquestion"Is truth contingenton the way we speak?"Languageis indeedimplicated in the world it purportsto represent.This answer implies an affirmative answer to the ontological question"Is the world somethingthat we have invented?"He then developedan additional claim about language.We use languageto representthe world to ourselves,just as we have always thought, and we use language quite deliberatelyto bring our representationsof the world--as we think it is and as we want it to be-to bearupon that world. Languageis the most powerful tool availableto us for social constructionas an ongoing, largely unpremeditatedactivity in which everyone is inevitably and perpetually engaged.Constructivismeffectively leaves epistemologyto the philosophers, and takes the linguistic tum back to ontology (Onuf 1989, 36-43). Onuf thus avoidedchoosingsidesin the third debate;he dissociatedhimself from post-structuralismand its repudiationof foundations,while conceding that such foundationsas we have may be nothing more than "the rubble of construction"(1989,35). Onuf's subsequentconcern with modernity resemblesJiirgen Habermas'sin the latter's debatewith the post-moderns,and Onufs debts to Habermasare substantial.Nevertheless,Onuf does not see constructivism as a recipe for emancipation,which has always been the goal for Habermasas a critical theorist. Constructivismis normative in the sense that it takes normative phenomena-rules--as the foundation of society, 20 KUBALKOvA, ONUF, AND KOWERT but Onuf's claim that rules always result in a condition of rule has earned him criticism from scholarswho believe.that a post-positivistposition is necessarily"critical." Onuf shareswith liberal theorists (and Keohane's rationalistic positivists) an interestin the unintendedconsequences of individual choicesand acknowledgestheir importancefor social construction without succumbingto the ingenuousclaim that a harmonyof interestsor balanceof power is likely to result. As a label, constructivismconjuresup an image of intentional activity on a grand scale,of concretebeing poured and buildings and malls going up, or the Stalinist practice of giving out medalsto those constructingthe bright socialist future. Onuf shareswith Marxist theoristsan interestin the materialsof social construction(they are never simply "raw" materials), but again without becoming a historical materialistwho dismissesthe importanceof humanagency. If Onuf's constructivismis indeed a third way in the third debate,it is hardly the path of least resistance.Constructivismacceptsthe unity of nature and society, as positivists do, but does not deny society its distinctive ontological characterby doing so. Instead, constructivismsees natureas irrevocablysocial. From a constructivistpoint of view, the "forest" is not so much a metaphoras a misrepresentation: the forest shouldneverbe thought of as an extensivepieceof naturethat is somehow"outside" society.Onuf's constructivismoffers an alternativeontology,a redescriptionof the scenery. If we were to force the metaphor,the forest, as an ensembleof trees and much else,is everywhere,and we are always in it, making the treesand the forest what they are. About This Book Constructivism is a constructive responseto the challenge of the "post" movement.It rejects the "slash-and-burn"extremismof somepost-modem thinkerswho leavenothing behindthem, nowhereto stand,nothing evenfor themselvesto say. Constructivismtries to make senseof social relationsin generalin order to get beyondthe pointlessposturingthat passesfor debate in a discipline that cannot even defend its claim to a distinctive subject matter called "internationalrelations." While constructivistsjoin the "post" movementin calling into question much of the orthodoxy of postwar IR scholarship,they reject neitherempirical researchnor social scienceas such. Instead,constructivismmaintainsthat the sociopoliticalworld is constructed by humanpractice,and seeksto explainhow this constructiontakesplace. Four objectivesguided the contributorsto this book. First, they try to make Onuf's "construction"of constructivismaccessibleto a broad audience that may not wish to read his technically demandingWorld of Our CONSTRUCTING CONSTRUCTIVISM 21 Making. Onufhimselfoffers a comprehensiveoverview in simple language. Second,severalof the contributorssituateconstructivismin the context of IR's tormentedrecenthistory, the constructivistclaims of other scholarsin the discipline, and recenttrendsin the philosophyof science.Third, several contributorsexplore the relevanceof constructivismfor empirical research and offer new ways of conceptualizingkey issuesof contemporaryinternational politics. Fourth, the book concludesby consideringthe implications of constructivismfor teachinginternationalrelations,inasmuchas teaching is itself an act of social construction. Throughout, the contributors show that constructivism is a powerful, systematicway of thinking about social relations in general and international relationsin particular.Oncefamiliar with constructivism,few readers will continue to be comfortablewith the world as portrayedin academic textbooks.More to the point, they will see themselvesin a new light-as agentsin a world that makesthem what they are, and as agentsin a world that they are responsiblefor making in everythingthat they do. Bibliography Adler, Emanuel. 1997. "Seizing the Middle Ground: Constructivismin World Politics." EuropeanJournal ofInternationalRelations3 (September):319-63. Holsti, K.J. 1985. The Dividing Discipline: Hegemonyand Diversity in International Theory. Boston: Allen & Unwin. Keohane,Robert o. 1988. "International Institutions: Two Approaches."International StudiesQuarterly 32 (December):379-96. Kratochwil, Friedrich. 1984. "Errors Have Their Advantage."International Organization 38 (Spring): 303-20. - - - and John GerardRuggie. 1986. "International Organization:A Stateof the Art on an Art of the State."InternationalOrganization40 (Autumn): 753-75. Lapid, Yosef. 1989. "The Third Debate: On the ProspectsofInternationalTheory in a Post-PositivistEra." InternationalStudiesQuarterly 33 (September):235-54. Onuf, Nicholas Greenwood. 1989. World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social TheoryandInternationalRelations.Columbia: University of SouthCarolinaPress. Singer, 1. David. 1961. "The Level-of-Analysis Problem in International Relations." World Politics 14 (October):77-92. Waltz, Kenneth N. 1979. Theory of International Politics. Reading, MA: AddisonWesley. This page intentionally left blank - - - - - - - - P a r tII Constructivism in Context This page intentionally left blank 2 The Twenty Years' Catharsis: E.H. Carr and IR Vendulka Kubtilkovti This chapteris an academicmystery story with a twist: the mystery isn't just about whodunit, but about who is the victim, who was the villain, and what is the meaningof the messagethat was left behind?And at the heartof it all lies the question:"Who was Mr. Carr?" To start out, somebackground is necessary.This much we know: Few historical personalitiesor philosopherscan boast of adherentsand disciples of all stripes, including adversariesengagedin deadly combat against each other. Edward Hallett Carr (1892-1982)is one of that small band; he has beenacclaimedas one of the intellectual founders,both of the mainstreamin the International Relations (IR) discipline and of the approachesof its fiercest critics. Carr has been seen as the forefather of realism and of the "post" movement,as well as a " 'proto' constructivist" who helpedto developthe approachintroducedin this book (Dunne 1995, 373). This means that were he alive, Carr could do a circus act at IR conferencesby sitting aloneat a roundtablediscussingthreepositionsat the sametime. Or, was he really the victim of an academicmugging? Carr wrote a book, publishedin 1939, called The Twenty Years' Crisis 191~ 1939: An Introduction to the StudyofInternationalRelations(hereafter referredto as Twenty Years' Crisis and cited from the 1962 printing of the secondedition). The twenty years Carr referred to was the interwar period, during which, in his view, the IR discipline took a wrong tum. One of the purposesof this chapteris to show that the "twenty years' crisis" has in fact turned out to be a crisis lasting more than sixty yearsand that, only 25 26 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A now, long after his death, Carr's crisis might be ending. The past twenty yearshaveseen,I will argue,the ultimate, cathartic,stageof that crisis. The main purposeof this chapter(apart from solving the mystery) is to place constructivism,its intellectual sources,and its origin in the contextof these tumultuoustwenty yearsto which Carr holds the key. Who Was E.H. Carr? In his Twenty Years' Crisis, Carr labeledthe main approachto IR as "realism." He also coined a distinction between"realists" and "idealists" (the latter were also referred to as "utopians"). He said they were locked in a debate, known thereafter as the great debate. Scholars ever since have soughtto identify somethingthat would constituteanotherdebateto follow in the footstepsofE.H. Carr. A few havebeenlucky: HedleyBull identified the secondgreatdebateand Y osefLapid the third debate.The third debate, still in progress,is a part of the catharsiswith which this essaydeals.But Carr startedthe idea of having"great debates."His book hasbeendescribed as "the first 'scientific' treatment of modem world politics" (Hoffmann 1977,43).To complicatethe matter,however,in one of the most influential piecesanticipatingthe third debate,Carr was namedan intellectualprogenitor of a "critical approach"to IR when other, much more deservingcandidatessuchas Habermassurprisinglydid not makethe cut (Cox 1981).1Carr receivedapplauseand eulogiesfrom the most prominentTrotskyists(Isaac Deutscher1955; TamaraDeutscher1983). What are we to makeof this? Carr, the historian, madeit onto the 1997 Foreign Affairs list of the best books of the last seventy-five years with his twelve-volume History oj SovietRussia(Legvold 1997, 230). Carr the journalist and publicist occasionedpolitical controversyas one of the editorial writers of The Times of London, where his political views were attackedfor a variety of reasons, including his beingtoo pro-Soviet.Among the strongestcritics of his political views were prominent British politicians and scholars, including the historian Hugh Trevor-Roperand Carr's co-founderof IR realism, Hans Morgenthau(Jones1996). Were it not for the continuationof his twenty-yearcrisis and had the developmentsof the last twenty yearsnot takenplace,the political controversy about Carr would have been long forgotten and historiansof the IR discipline would not be confusedabouthim. Until recently, the central fact of Carr's IR legacy appearedto be his role as the key figure of the realist approach.Admittedly, a numberof his distinguishedcolleaguesfrom the IR discipline were critical of his work and found in it minor or major defects (Morgenthau1948; Trevor-Roper1962; Bull 1969; K.W. Thompsonet al. THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 27 1980; Fox 1985). The numberof citations endorsingCarr as the founder of realism, however, far outnumbersthose commentingon his various inconsistencies.Becauseof the increasingvisibility of the approvalof Carr by the "post" movement(Cox 1981, 131; Linklater 1990, 7; Booth 1991; Linklater 1992; Howe 1994; Jones1996; Linklater 1997), the "paternity" issuewill have to be addressedand realistswill haveto decidewhetherthey still want to claim him as a founding father. The paradoxis that Carr is now praisedand celebratedfor what earlier were regardedas seriousdefects.Errors in his judgmentwere not accidental but "rooted in a more fundamentalweaknessin his political philosophy" (K.W. Thompsonet al. 1980, 77). In sharp contrastto this view, a critical writer assertsthat Carr's "reputationfor Realism... servedto distort [his] relevanceto contemporarydebates"(Linklater 1997, 321). While earlier such labels were derogatory,they are now flattering and it is a compliment when Carr is called a "utopian realist" (Howe 1994) or an "ambivalent realist" (Jones1996). In a book on "post-realism,"Carr is usedas an example of a major IR figure who took what the authorscall a "rhetorical tum" (Beer & Hariman 1996). Whateverthat might meanexactly, the drift of the detailed"post-realist"rhetorical deconstructionof his texts concludesthat Carr played gameswith his readershipand, in a subtle use of rhetorical contradictory statements,tried to please,tease,or fool everybody. While this explanationmight go someway to explainthe attitudeof the IR discipline toward Carr, it seemsto be a bit of a stretch to impute to Carr a Machiavelliangeniusthat connivedto deceivethe discipline on a gigantic scale. Besides,even if he had had the meansand opportunity to do this, what would the motive havebeen? The Overlooked Clue? Carr agreeswith Lord Acton, who said that "few discoveriesare more irritating than thosewhich exposethe pedigreeof ideas" (Carr 1962, 71). Perhaps Carr did not mind the misunderstanding.But there is, in my view, a much less sophisticated,much simpler reading of Carr, which to a considerable extent reconcilesthe seemingcontradictionof Carr's Twenty Years' Crisis. In formal logic, A and non-A cannotbe true at the sametime. Therefore,a realist could not at the sametime be an antirealistor an idealist. However, there is a form of thought called dialectics and in dialectical logic a realist could be a nonrealist. Perhapsthen Carr was a dialectician. One of the importantmembersof the "post" movementin Australia, Jim George,briefly noted Carr's dialectical inclinations but did not think Carr was consistent evenat that (George1994,78). I will arguethat Carr was a dialectician. 28 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A Carr's Twenty Years' Crisis reveals a strong influence of Marx's thought as modified by Engels and Lenin, particularly his use of the concept of dialectics.If his Twenty Years' Crisis is rereadwith an understanding of dialectics,it becomesclear that, far from being playful or conniving, intellectually dishonest,sloppy, or inconsistent, Carr was simply using dialecticalreasoning.It is easily recognizableby anybodyfamiliar with the concept of dialectics of the genre of Soviet Marxist-Leninist textbooks. Over the years only a few IR authors noted Carr's thinking as a rather puzzling, mild caseof Marxism. Carr has beenreferredto as a "Marxist of sorts" and "a Marxist-realist" (Brown 1992, 25, 69). Carr's Marxism is clearly non-Marxist Marxism "Westernized"by Carr himselfwith no help from the "WesternMarxists." Carr's nonrelationshipwith WesternMarxists is an important reasonwhy the Marxist elementsin his thought have been overlooked.But the WesternMarxists have played an important role in the emergenceof the IR "post" movement.Again, it is curious to note that some of his contemporaryadmirers believe that Carr did parallel or anticipate Western Marxists or post-Marxists, Habermas,and Foucault (Linklater 1997). "WesternMarxists," initially the HungarianGeorg Lukacs (1885--1971), the German Karl Korsch (1886-1961), and the Russian Leon Trotsky (1879-1940),were so namedby Maurice Merleau-Ponty(1905--1961)exactly so as not to be mistakenfor the Soviet versionof Marxism-Leninism. The term Western Marxism normally refers also to the Italian Antonio Gramsci(1891-1937)and the GermanFrankfurt School. I refer to themby nationalitiesto explain the contemporarycustomof referring to them also as "ContinentalEuropean."By the mid-1930s,the WesternMarxists were united in their rejection of the Soviet Union's practiceand theory. Despite disclaimersthat they had nothing to do with the Soviet Union, the members of the famous GermanFrankfurt School,undoubtedlythe most influential centerof WesternMarxism in this century,adoptedin 1937 the term critical as a code word for Marxism, so as not to use the term Marxism. Even so, the entire school had to flee to the United Statesfrom the anticommunistand anti-SemiticHitler Germany.Carr wrote his TwentyYears' Crisis only a coupleyearslater, in the United Kingdom There is no visible connectionbetweenCarr and Western Marxists. On the contrary, Carr's sort of Marxism is very different from the distinct form of WesternMarxism already established at the time. WesternMarxists, influencednot only by Marx but by many otherthinkers, changedtheir writing style to an idiom of tremendoustechnical diffiCUlty, accessibleonly to fellow academics.Since then, WesternMarxism has stayedin the handsof academicsand the difficult idiom has becomea THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 29 characteristicfeature of social sciencesgenerally. Carr refers disapprovingly to academicswithout practical experienceas "armchair studentsof international politics" (1962, 38), using exactly the same words as did Lenin. Carr's style doesnot suffer from the opacity of proseof WesternMarxism. It is more reminiscentof the Soviet version of Marxism, which met with an oppositefate. As can be seenfrom the standardtextbooksof Marxism-Leninism from which the populacewas taught at school and in refreshercoursesthroughouttheir adulthood,Sovietsmadeout of Marxism a fairy tale in which the good characters always won over the bad characters. It was accessibleand understandableto all and for many decadeswas highly attractive in its promisesand its comforting moral justifications. In the gigantic experimentof social construction,Marxist-Leninist textbooks were publishedin millions of copiesacrossthe Soviet empire, achievinga circulation secondonly to the Bible. If anything, Carr'sproseand his definition of realismand idealismhave beenfound too simple (Brown 1992,25). If we rereadCarr's TwentyYears' Crisis with the help of dialectics,we get a different picture and a different messagealtogether.The messagebecomesmore complex once we realize that he relatedrealism dialectically to idealism. We can then seethat Carr strongly advocatedrealism, but as a transition, a station on the way. IR scholarsof the postwarperiod generallymissedthis point, which is hardly surprisingsince the discipline was alreadypermanentlyembeddedin realism, like a fly in amber. Only in the last decadehas the discipline had to reopenitself enoughto reconsiderits historical legacyand the true views of its father figure. A Caseof Mistaken Identity? There are many telltale signs of Carr's exposureto some sort of Marxism. Carr approvingly quotes Marxist classicsand even includes Marx among key representatives of "modemrealism" (1962, 65). Marx did write extensively aboutthe foreign policy of his time, but Carr is not referring to Marx in that sense.Carr doesnot talk about revolutions,classstruggles,and the proletariat.Nor is he an economicdeterminist.Carr, however,usesdialectics, at the minimum to organizehis thinking and to organizehis argument. The celebratedpassagesof his rejectionof utopianismconstitutemuch less thanhalf of the story containedin Carr'sbook. I will briefly overview some key elementsof Carr's reasoningand conceptssuch as dialectics,not only as they relate to Carr, but as a useful introduction in simple terms to the languagerequiredfor the understandingof the "post" movement. 30 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A TheMysteriousFormula Dialectics has a quite respectable,if limited, place in Westernphilosophy; its progenitors include not only Marx, Engels, and Lenin, but also Aristotle, Heraclitus, and Hegel. American Marxist Bertell Oilman uses it as the key conceptof his versionof Marxism, and HaywardAlker, who is by no meansa Marxist, defines dialectics as one of the three approachesto IR (Alker and Biersteker1984). Alker alonepublisheda numberof piecesaboutthe application of dialecticsto IR with a large cooperativeproject in progressdealingwith the subjectof dialectics (Alker 1981, 1982, 1996). Dialectical thinking is not unheardof in Western sociology (Ritzer 1983). Dialectics has been used in mathematicalmodeling(Mitroff andMason 1982 andRescher1977). Using dialecticsalone does not make one into a Marxist. The choice of dialectics simply indicatesa rejection of the monocausalapproachand the notion of unilinear developmentin favor of the dynamic, multicausal,and multidirectional. Where a liberal thinker seesharmonyas the normal state of affairs and views conflict as a deviation; for a dialecticianit is the other way around. Dialecticiansregard conflict as normal and harmony as only temporary.(Soviets referred to detenteas peredyshka,meaning"breathing space," betweenstretchesof peaceful coexistencewhich had little to do with peace.)Preoccupiedwith conflict and contradiction,thoseapplying the dialectical method seek to understandchangethrough a study of the past and the presentthat establishesa connectionbetweenfuture developments and the present.Dialecticianstherefore study history and look for change over time. Dialectics sees things as inevitably interconnectedand interdependent.Dialecticiansare by definition holistic in their approach,arguing that eventscannotbe tom out of context. Dialecticiansneverseecauseand effect as isolated, but perceivereciprocal causalitiesin which both events and processesexert influence and are influenced by each other. In other words, dialecticiansbelievethat eachpart influencesthe whole just as much as the whole influenceseach individual part. Dialecticianssee things and processesin a stateof constantflux andchange. Dialecticiansthink in terms of relatedpairs of concepts;let us say A and B, where thesepairs are construedin a binary thesis-antithesisway. A is in a causalrelation to B, but the relation is reciprocatedsince B is also in a causalrelation to A. Realism and utopianism,or idealism, in Carr's book are in this relationship. The tension leads to a resolution which contains both A and B in a transcendedform in a resulting synthesis.The synthesis in turn becomesa thesisin contradictionto an antithesis,and so the process goesnot in a straightline but-asit were--ona spiral. It then follows that if A and B are in a dialectical contradiction,then B could not simply vanish THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 31 leaving A intact. Nothing remains intact. Everything is in some sort of dialecticalrelationship.So A cannotbe separatedpermanentlyfrom B or B from A. Such an outcome is not conceivable,nor would it representa resolutionof the contradiction.Dialecticscanrepresentan ontologicalposition, finding mutually contradictoryrelationshipsbetweenthings and processes"out there," in the world and history. The standardSoviet textbooks used Friedrich Engels's(1820-1895)butterflies cavorting in the butterfly mating seasonto convey the point. The mating of the first butterfly ("thesis") with the second("antithesis")gives rise to thousandsof butterflies. Dialectics, however, need not be fatuous. Apart from its ontological claims, dialecticscan be usedalso as an epistemologicaltheory concerning the nature of knowledge of the material world. It can also be used as a method,a tool whoseunderstandingadvancesthe questfor truth andknowledge.In what Marx's closestfriend and coauthor,Engels,called dialectical materialism(which meansin ordinary languagesimply "Marxist philosophy"), dialecticshas both ontological and epistemologicalsubstance.Both the material world and the human mind are believed to follow dialectical rules. This is importantfor our argument.Marx conceivesof man as a "real, active man." Cognitive action is materialand practical,and thus knowledge is not merely a cognitive reflectionupon an externalworld, but becomesthe meansfor shaping,constructing,and changingreality. To simplify it even further, formulating thoughts, analyzing, becauseit is going on in one's mind and the mind is a part of the world, meansthat, as the thought is formulated,the world undergoesa change.Thus thinking is doing, making or changingthe world. Theory fuses with practice, values with facts, and man in his thinking alters the world. Or, as Carr put it, "in the processof analyzingthe facts, Marx alteredthem" (1962, 4). Carr hints hereat Marx's notoriousEleventh Thesison Feuerbach,so well known in certain circles that he did not need even to cite it. And Carr adds, "Nor is it only the thinking of professionalor qualified studentsof politics which constitutesa political fact" (41). Deciphering Carr Like the thinking of a contemporaryIR dialectician, ProfessorHayward Alker, who spells out the relationship more clearly (1981, 1982), Carr's understandingis basedon perceivingthe effect of one party to a contradiction interpenetratingthe other in sucha way that the original distinguishing featuresof both parts of the contradictionare blurred. To Carr what was wrong with idealism is that it developedwithout realism. Realism is the necessarycorrectiveto the "exuberanceof utopianism,just as in otherperi- 32 VENDULKA KUBA.LKOV A. ods, utopianismmust be invoked to counteractthe barrennessof realism. Immaturethought is predominantlypurposiveand utopian. Thought which rejectspurposeis the thought of old age.... Utopia and reality are thus the two facets of political science.Soundpolitical thought and soundpolitical life will be found only where both have their place" (1962, 10). Or, more bluntly, "the characteristicvice of the utopian is naivety; of the realist, sterility" (12). By that logic, having suppressedmuch of what Carr would call idealist thought,the IR discipline, until recently, hasbeengeriatric and sterile. Carr'swhole book is basedupon a seriesof dialectically relatedpairs of concepts,like realism and idealism. Parallel to realism and idealism, Carr construesa chain of binary dialectical relationships.The point is the parallel construction:A and B, C and D, and X and Z. There is a link between the first of the pairs, A, C, X, on the one hand, and the secondof the pairs B, D, Z, on the other hand. Carr calls these"antitheses"and arguesthat "these antithesesreproducethemselvesin different forms." As he puts it, the "most fundamental utopia-reality antithesis is rooted in a different conceptionof the relationshipof politics and ethics,the world of value and the world of nature, purpose and fact" (1962, 20-21). Other than this sequencethat leads to the utopian-realist distinction, he sees the same theme, as it were, metamorphosedinto relationshipsbetweentheory and practice, voluntarism and determinism, Left and Right, intellectual and practitioner(bureaucrat),radical and conservative,ideals and institutions, immature and old, inexperiencedand experienced,and many others. He links theory, voluntarism,Left, intellectual,radical, ideals,immature,inexperienced.He links practice,determinism,Right, bureaucrat,conservative, institutions,old, experienced. The Message:"It Is All in E.H. Carr" Carr's impressionsof the nascentIR discipline were derived from his experiencewith it in the late 1930s. He did not know either structural realism or logical positivism and empiricism in their full-blown forms in IR. However, the current philosophical debatesin the IR discipline would appearto him long overdue and trivial. The essenceof the last twenty years could be summarizedas idealism-utopianismcorrecting realismand thus man and his mind being returnedto the world and to the theory now cleansedof its positivist distortions. Neither realism nor idealism would be the outcomeof this process.One of the leading contemporaryBritish critical IR theorists,an admirer of Carr, suggeststhat THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 33 Carr himself provides "outlines of the third way" (Linklater 1997, 323). Carr was neitherrealistnor idealist. Thus, just as realists maintain about their wisdom that "it is all in Thucydides,"it can be claimedwith evengreaterjustification that, as far as the current debateis concerned,"it is all in E.H. Carr." Carr anticipatesan application of the dialectical approachto IR. Carr championsintellectual pluralism. Carr anticipatedthe creationof the InternationalPolitical Economy. Having had a go at both practice (as a diplomat and journalist) and theory (as a professorof IR in Aberystwyth and a CambridgeUniversity Fellow), Carr calls for more stresson policy relevanceof theoreticalefforts. Carr strongly urgesan inclusion of Leftist thought in any academicpursuit. "The Right is weak in theory and suffers through its inaccessibility to ideas," while the Left suffers from a lack of practical experienceand a failure "to translateits theory into practice." However, he says,"the intellectual superiorityof the Left is seldomin doubt. The Left alone thinks out principles of political action and evolves ideals for statesmento aim at" (1962, 19). If it would be too early to describeCarr as postpositivist,then he is certainly antipositivist.For Carr, positivism in the form he knew in the 1930s was unacceptable,mainly becauseof the disagreementhe would havewith the totally nondialecticalseparationof man and natureas subject and object, and treating social phenomenaas if they were natural phenomena. As he put it, "By an easy analogy, the Newtonian principles were appliedto the ethical problems... oncetheselaws were determined,human beings would conform to them just as matter conformed to the physical laws of nature."In natural sciences"facts exist independentlyof what anyone thinks of them. In the political sciences,which are concernedwith humanbehavior,there are no suchfacts. The investigatoris inspiredby the desireto cure someill of the body politic" (22). "The purposeis not, as in the physicalsciences,irrelevantto the investigationand separablefrom it; it is itself one of the facts" (3-4). Theory, says Carr, is for a purpose.R.W. Cox, anotherof the contemporarycritical theoristsof IR, becamecelebrated for saying somethingvery similar fifty years after Carr (Cox 1981, 128). Carr distinguishesthree interdependentcategoriesof "political powerin the international sphere": "military, economic and over opinion" (l08). No doubt the membersof the "post" movementwill cringe at the suggestion, but it can be arguedthat the main and lasting contribution of the "post" movementis to be found in the attention it has drawn precisely to what perhapsCarr clumsily calls "power over opinion." The "post" movement hasshifted IR concernsto include the fundamentalhumanmentalprocesses of people,both IR theoristsand states,which are madeof people. 34 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A The Missing Pieces In very simple tenusCarr alludedto central philosophicalissuesdebatedin the field of IR today. In a variety of esoteric ways and in a technically difficult idiom they becamecatapultedinto prominencein the social sciencesand, in the last twenty years, also in the discipline of International Relations. But what do these questionshave to do with the affairs of statesand statecraft?As we arguedin the introduction, the answeris, in the view of the "post" movement(and also of Carr), a greatdeal. The "post" movement doesnot pick an argumentabout specific issuesand internationalrelations per se. Instead,the targetsof criticism are the philosophicalfoundation of how, in the IR discipline, the world is viewed; how what we call knowledge is put together; and for what purposethat knowledge is used. All of the strands of the "post" movement have in common an assertionthat the philosophicalfoundationsof IR lead to misinterpretationand misrepresentation of the world including internationalrelations. In that view, not only did IR get stuck at a stage of penuanentrealism; it is also basedon a fundamentallyflawed understandingof the relationshipbetweenman and the world-"reality"-in the usual parlance.Some,of course,arguethat it is deliberate.This is where the argumentbeginsto be too difficult to simplify, but the points that the "post" movementmakesare too important to set themasidejust becausethey aremadein a difficult language. Did Waltz Do It? None of this was everconsideredof any relevanceto the IR discipline. Why and how did the situationchange,and how did thesetopics get introduced? In the IR discipline therewas an increasingdissatisfactionwith the positivist portrayalof reality as reflectedin man'smind in an "objective" way. The positivism of this position has been further compoundedin the work of Kenneth Waltz, particularly in his book Theory of International Politics (publishedin 1979) but circulating aroundthrough the earlier publications of its parts (Waltz 1979; Waltz in Polsby and Greenstein1975). If previously positivism was objectedto becauseof its disregardfor the human mind underthe guise of objectivity, then Waltz's new theory of realism, to be known as "neorealism"or "structural realism," made this characterization evenmore valid. Waltz addeda componentof structuralismto positivism. It hasbeenthis particularmix of positivism and structuralismaddedto realism that has stirred a more effective opposition to realism in IR than ever before. In my view, it also set off the processesI describeas catharsis THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 35 and the creationof the "post" movement.To make at least a dent on the new form of what appearedto be indestructible realism, IR authors startedwheeling into IR studies intellectual weaponry of the Left from all over humanitiesand social sciences,and the "post" movementcame into existence. Structuralismwas nothing new. It had beenusedin different fields many times before.The term refersto a distinct approachto social phenomena.As its critics claim, structuralismpushesman even further out of the picture. Man is lost as "systemsand subsystems,elementsand structuresare drilled up and down the pages[of history] pretendingto be people" (Ashley 1984, 226-27, quoting E.P. Thompson 1978). Structuralistsassertthat only by looking into that which is hidden and underpinsthe apparentcan we reach beyondthe study of self-conceptionsandmotivesof individuals (or individual entities such as states).Structuralistslook for a structureand structural forces becausethey believe that individuals, or in this case, states, are constrainedby structuralforcesover which they haveno control. Structuralism, in otherwords, sharpenssomeof the featuresof positivism. It is worth mentioning that the line cited above about structuresbeing drilled into the pagesof history was a quotation used by an IR scholarto attack the structuralismof Waltz. Characteristically,however, this scholar borrowedit, togetherwith the overall argument,from an attack on a structural Marxist. The early pieces of this genre were characterizedby extremely eclectic borrowing, in which Ashley typically spendspage after page explaining at length to the IR audienceconceptsquite well known elsewhere. Kuhn as an Accomplice Waltz was by no meanssolely responsiblefor the turmoil in the discipline. He had a helper namedThomasKuhn. Kuhn himself did nothing, but his slim volume (Kuhn 1970), not even intendedfor the IR discipline or social sciences,played a role. His concept of "paradigm" was enthusiastically usedin the IR discipline. Why would that makeany difference? Becauseof the way the IR discipline has beenconstituted,it has proved extraordinarily difficult to challengethe reigning approach.When the concept of paradigmwas introducedto the IR discipline, a subtle terminological substitutiontook place.IR scholarstalked suddenlynot about"theories" or "approaches"but about "paradigms,"a term that Kuhn used. They did not always explain what was the difference in this terminology, giving an impressionthat the three terms are more or less synonymous,and many scholarsin fact usedthem interchangeably. 36 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A Kuhn's conceptof paradigm,however,hasa very specialmeaning.Kuhn wrote about physics and not about social sciencesbut-asin the case of Carr-it is what was made of Kuhn rather than what he himself said that was important. The slow arrival of the concept of paradigm and IR as "paradigmaticdiscipline" is fascinatingto follow in a sequenceof writing spanningmore than a decade(Phillips 1974; Inkeles 1975; Lijphart 1981; Banks 1978; Rosenau 1979; Pettman 1981; Alker and Biersteker 1984; Holsti 1985; Banks 1985). Those IR scholarsimpatient with realism and its staying power obviously found solacein the useof the term. Therewere several veryattractive points about the conceptof paradigm,which undoubtedlyexplainswhy IR discipline so enthusiasticallyembracedKuhnian analysis: first, the content of the termparadigmruns counterto the basicpremisesof positivism. Thus as soonas the term is used,thosethat understandits meaningknow that an attack on positivism and its belief in the value-freenatureof knowledgeis taking place. Second,accordingto Kuhn, the term paradigm conveysthat any theoretical effort is only of temporary nature. Thus there can be no continuity of knowledge but instead a successionof paradigmsoffering different ways of viewing the world. Third, since there is an elementof contingencyin the creationof a paradigm(via consensus inthe discipline), additional doubt is cast on the proclaimedgoal of an objective searchfor truth. Fourth, thus knowledgeon which paradigmsare basedis not regarded as certain, but as fallible and open to refutation. Fifth, hencethe apparent monopolyof one approachin the discipline is takeninto question.Sixth, out goes the axiom that realist knowledge has been accumulatingsince Thucydides.And finally, since it is reasonableto anticipatethe demiseof any paradigm,that of realism and positivism shall one day also pass.The use of the expressioninterparadigmaticfor IR simply institutionalizedan acceptanceof a plurality of approachesas the discipline's feature, if a replacementof a paradigmturned out to be out of reach.The door was left ajar for an introductionof influencesunheardof in the disciplinebefore. Carr: "Power Over Opinion" Cox quoted mainly Gramsci, and Ashley quotedHabermasand Foucault, authorswho did not write specifically on the subjectsof internationalrelations. In fact, Foucault'swork rangesfrom suchunlikely subjectsas prison systemsand psychiatryto the history of sexuality. The Italian communist Gramsci also seemsto be an unlikely candidatefor extensionto IR. He wrote his major work in a fascist jail pondering the failure of Marxist strategiesin WesternEurope in the aftermath of World War I. Both his THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 37 concernsand those of the GermanFrankfurt School, either in Germanyor in exile in the United States,would appearto be far removedfrom anything remotely relevant. How could Ashley, Cox, or any of the later scholars working in this genre stretch any of these apparentlyunrelatedideas to internationalrelations? Except in the new Soviet Union, the dreamof a revolution was quashed. Only in Soviet Russia wasthere a likelihood of man "constructingreality" in his image as envisagedby Marx in his concept of praxis. The first generationof Marx's heirs had different concernsto address:namely, why the fiasco of Bolshevik-stylerevolutionseverywhereother than in the Soviet Union and, generally, why a permanentretreat and pessimismwere warrantedin contrastwith the optimism of Marx. Both Gramsciand particularly the contemporaryGerman critical sociologist Jiirgen Habermas turned their attentionto the pathologyof Westernsocietiesand the pathology of the human mind, problems that Marx envisagedwould be swept awayin what he wrongly predictedto be forthcomingrevolutions. When we examine Gramsci'sconceptof hegemony,Habermas'sknowledge of constitutive interests, and even post-structuralist,post-Marxist Foucault'sidea of power-knowledgeand discourse,Carr'sideaof "power over opinion" comes to mind. Carr's concept soundsprimitive comparedto the sophisticatedconceptualizationsof contemporarysocial science.His concept, however,resonateswith the imageof the ideasconveyedin the more sophisticatedterminology: the world of distortedsocial constructiondesignedto subordinate, dominate, and oppressunder the veil of positivist philosophiesthat presentit as objectively given. Overt coercion need not be resortedto; full consensusand cooperationof the populationis achieved,ironically without so much as a murmur of protestfrom the targetsof oppressionand domination. This feat is accomplishednot by overt military or economicpower, the two forms of power Carr identifies in the fmale of his dialectical reasoning.It is accomplishedthrough the third form of power, which Carr calls "power over opinion." To Gramsciand his followers, and to thosethat espousethe critical approach,this situation is still reversible: to Gramsci by meansof revolution; to the critical school by meansof what they call emancipation.For post-structuralists andpost-modernists,thereseemsto be no way out. All approachesof the "post" movementseethe societiesof the twentieth century as basedon social construction,though the particular labels attachedto the idea may vary. Although the movementis eclectic, its originality and creativity lie in applying the borrowedconceptsto international relations. To understandjust how difficult this "stretch" might be, let me briefly summarizesomeof the main conceptsbefore they were introduced in a duly "internationali~ed" summarizesome form to IR. 38 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A Gramsci argued that the defeat of the Marxist revolution in Western Europe in the early 1920sand its victory in the Soviet Union were due to different stagesof developmentof the respectivesocieties.In the Western societiesit was not possibleto replicatethe Bolshevik successand violently overthrow governmentsas it was done in 1917 in Russia and tried with disastrousresults in Hungary, Slovakia, and the Weimar Republic. Overthrowing governmentwould only show that the state was but "an outer ditch" within which lay "civil society." Civil societyin the Gramsciansense (the sameterm usedwith different meaningsin other social sciences)consists of people---thosethat are subjectto oppressionand dominationabove all. Civil society is a social constructiondesignedin such a way that the oppressionis disguisedand is madeeasywith the active participationof its victims. By a skillful use of cultural and ideological instrumentswhich Gramscicalled hegemony(again usedin a different sensein the IR discipline) the society at large was deflectedfrom its true path an~ot especiallyto put a fine point on it-fooled. The only strategy for overthrowing the "hegemonic" rule proposedby Gramsciwas to devisea "counterhegemony"that would usethe samemethodas "hegemony":constructionand manipulation of a consensusin society.EuropeanEurocommunism,inspiredby this idea, cooperatedwith any available group of the civil society, including the Church, as a part of its counterhegemonic strategy.I arguedelsewherethat Gorbachev's"new thinking" had distinct features of Gramscian counterhegemony,a point confirmed by the heightenedinterest in Western Marxist and radical thought at the time by Gorbachevand his appeal to Westerncivil societies(KubaIkovaandCruickshank1989b). None of thesestrategiesworked. Beyond this point social construction has ceasedto be a romanticist celebrationof man's creativity. It is now creativity perverted,an indictment of man as a social being, man divided and bent on ruthless domination of whomeverhe can through the clever constructionof knowledge,consciousness, andmanipulationof minds. There are variations and subtletiesin different sources,but the theme remainsthe same:how could this giant fraud have beengotten away with? The answer is consistentwith Carr's phrase: by exercising "power over opinion" in a muchmore profoundway thanthe propagandathat Carr refers to. In 1939, when he wrote his Twenty Years' Crisis, the major Western Marxist, post-Marxist, and post-structuralistand critical works were still to be written. None of the other more subtle ways of expressing"power over opinion" were in circulation. However, in their work WesternMarxists now focus on this generaldirection: namely,on stripping the facadeof objectivity and analysisof how and in whoseinterestsand for whosepurposethe twentieth-centuryWesternsocial world hasbeenconstructed.To thosefew critical THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 39 theorists, in IR and outside, who still believe in emancipation,the term often meansno more than a full realization and understandingof the oppressivenature of the social constructionof societiesin this century. The corollary of unveiling the pathologiesof contemporarysocietiesis an absolute denial that anything to do with social reality, or any of its representations or theories, canever be objective. Theory is always constructedfor someone,and for someone'spurpose.As Carr says,"Purpose,whetherwe are consciousof it or not, is a condition of thought; and thinking for thinking's sake is as abnormaland barren as the miser's accumulationof money for its own sake" (1962, 3-4). Or, in Habermas,class domination takes place through the medium of distorted ideologies. In his theory of distorted communication,Habermasallegesthat those that are subjugated are encouragedto subordinatetheir intereststo thoserepresentingthe social order, whose injusticesremain hidden and repressed.They are hidden behind the veil of objectivity, objective science,appealto the commongood, the nation, and so on. A similar themeappearsthrough the work inspiredby structuralisttheories of linguistics andpost-structuralisttheories.Languagehas now broken loose from reality and become autonomous(Callinicos 1983, 25). The "power over opinion" of Carr reachesanotherheight. Foucault'sepisteme (his parallel to Vanguihelm's, Bachelard's, and Althusser'sproblematique, to Kuhn's paradigm, and to Lakatos's research program) is in fact an autonomoustheoretical structuredetermininghow we perceivethe world and how we identify and organizeits elements.To put it more simply, we see the world through lensesartificially implanted in our eyes that we do not even know we have. Foucaultnow studiesnot how we know what we know, but how these lensesare distorting our vision and how they were inserted into our eyes. Foucault's antiepistemology,his archaeologyof knowledge,unlike epistemology,now tries to determinethe conditionsthat permit (or require) certain statementsto be utteredand to excludethe utteranceof others (Callinicos 1983, 100). This way of thinking culminatesin Foucault's concept of power-knowledgeand discourse.Not only is the relationshipbetweenreality and knowledge suspended,but the pursuit of knowledgeand truth is renderedimpossible,becauseknowledgeis inseparably wedded to power. Statements,the constituent elements of what Foucaultcalls "discourses,"do not derive at all from objective reality, but are constructedon the basisof power-relations.There is, in fact, no power without the correlativeconstitutionof a field of knowledge;nor, conversely, is thereany knowledgethat doesnot presupposeor constituteat one andthe sametime power-relations(Foucault1977,27-28). This line of reasoningreacheseven further when we come to those 40 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A scholarswho, like Gadamer,believethat the world is createdby words. We have now moved to the last stop, the post-modernists.The languageis, in the handsof post-modernists,reducedonly to text. The real world is constituted like a text becauseone can only refer to interpretativeexperience. Attention turns to time and spaceand their suffocatingeffect. As Anderson describesDerrida's work, Derrida often evadescomprehension.But this is part of the point he wantsto get us to see. Clarity is not the only virtue in writing, and at times it may evenbe a disadvantagesinceclarity of expressionand easeof comprehension encouragethe belief that languageis under control. ... [He] also refusesto be bound by the conventionsof normal academicreading. He is determined to challengeour expectationsand so highlight what we do when we give text a reading.(1986, 120) To Derrida no accuraterepresentationof reality in thought is possible. "Modes of writing," interpretations,and the textual interplay refer to mutually constitutiverelationsbetweendifferent interpretationsin the representation and constitutionof the world. This conclusionis uncoveredthrough deconstruction--aninterpretive techniqueaimed at a radical unsettling of stable concepts.The author of the text is dead. If the era of modernity is connectedfirmly to man, then it is possibleto agreewith post-modernists that modernitybuilt aroundman hascometo an end. The Historiography of the Last Twenty Years in the IR Discipline These thoughts, duly applied to international relations, have been introducedto the IR discipline in the courseof the last twenty years. There are certain milestonesthat suggeststagesof this period. Roughly I see two stages:1977-1987and from 1987 on. I take for the starting point approximately the year 1986. Many important books and articles were published aroundthat year. In 1977 R.O. Keohaneand J.S. Nye stagedan unsuccessful coup intended to unseat the dominant realist approach. Their book, Power and Interdependence:World Politics in Transition, according to somereviewers,was to becomethe new Bible, replacingin that role Hans Morgenthau'sPolitics Among Nations (1948) and, as the title suggests, replacinga conceptof "power" with "interdependence."In that sameyear (1977) StanleyHoffmann publishedhis "An American Social Science:International Relations" article in Daedalus,chastisingIR discipline in the United Statesfor excessiveparochialismand isolationismand warning that the discipline will decayif certainchangesare not adopted.Also published THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 41 in 1977 was a codification of the English School wisdom in Hedley Bull' s AnarchicalSociety.Also in 1977, Robert Tucker'sInternationalInequality was an eloquentresponseand rebuttalto the neo-Marxistand radical liberal theoriesof imperialism and dependencyon behalfof mainstreamrealism. Most important, however, as mentionedearlier, Kenneth Waltz published his Theory ofInternational Politics. Although that book cameout in 1979, an earlier version of the theory was published as a chapterin an edited volume in 1975 (PolsbyandGreenstein1975). The watershedseparatingthe two stagesof the last twenty yearsis around the years 1986-87,the namingof the new approachesthat we refer to as the "post" movement(Kratochwil and Ruggie 1986; Keohane1988; and Lapid 1989).The"nameless"first stagethen was over. It is interestingthat the two prominentfoundersof the "post" movement,Cox (1981) andAshley (1984), returnedthe favor and coinedtwo namesfor Waltz's approach:"neorealism" and "structural realism." Both labels have stuck. Though the two articles naming Waltz's approachwere published in 1981 and 1984, respectively, they reacheda wider audiencewhen they were reprintedin an editedvolume by R.O. Keohane entitled Neorealism and Its Critics and published in 1986. Ashley and Cox were now granteda "statusof critics." The Pedigree When we add the main intellectual sourcesthat havecometo play in assisting the formation of the "post" movementand put them into one family tree, we get a pedigreemore impressivethan any Europeanroyal houseor racehorsecanboast(Figure2.1). Figure 2.1 is divided into four horizontalrows, numbered1-4. The philosophicallineageof the mainstreamIR literature (and what is called realist and pluralist approaches)is at the top, in row 1. To realists and pluralists most classificationsof approachesadd globalists, whose roots come from row 4. The lineageof the two bottom rows of the figure, namely the determinist andnondeterministand post-Marxistrows 3 and4, are consistentnot only with Perry Anderson'smagisterialaccountsof the Left's intellectual history (Anderson1976, 1983) but with a similarly construedpedigreeof Leftist sociology (Burawoy 1982, S5ff.). Figure 2.1 shows the contemporary divisions and currentsas they can be tracedalong approximatelyhorizontallines.For lack of space,not all namesthat ought to be are included. The figure is intended to show how difficult it is to attach labels. If the cross-referencingand influenceswere to be markedwith arrows, the page would be black and illegible. As Perry Andersononce put it, lateral bourgeois influences make Marx just one of the names among others. The Functionalism Sociolinguistics Logical Empiricism Hempel(1905-) Kelsen (1881-1973) Levl-Strauss (1908) Structural Functionalism Merton(1910-) Parsons (1902-1979) Structuralism Ordinary Language Philosophy i J.L Austin (1911-1960) Legal Positivism H A L Hart (1907-1992) Logical Positivists Vienna Circle (1920-1930) Kamap Nagel (1901-1985) | Utopian Tradition and World Constitutionalists Wittgenstein (1889-1951) Wobor (1864-1920) Durkheim (1858-1917) Structuralism Comte (1795-1857)| Hume (1721-1776) Kant (1724-1804) Figure 2.1 1 (1900-Continued on next page Hermeneutics Gadamer (1900-) Structuration Giddens Lakatos (1922-1974) I Popper (1902-1994) Behaviorism Hermeneutics 3 Structuration 2 IR Discipline 1 44 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A Political Economy Smith (1723-1823) Ricardo (1772-1823) Hegel (1770-1831) Utopian Socialists Saint Simon (1760-1825) Fourier (1772-1837) \ Trotsky' (1879-1Mo} Gramsci (1891-1937) Hegelian Marxism Lukacs (1885-1971) Luxemburg (1870-1919) Engels (1820-1895)1 | Lenin (1870-1924) Marx (1818-1883) Young Hegelians Feuerbach (1804-1872) Freud (1856-19391 Anarchists Bakunin (1814-1876) Economic Determinism Kautsky (1854-1938) Fourth International Critical School Horkheimer (1895-1973) Adorno (1903-1969) Marcuse (1898-1981) Nietsche (1844-1900) Heidegger (1889-1976) Sartre (1905-1980) Revisionist Historians W.A.Williams (1921-) Alperovitz (1936-) G. Kolko (1932-) Mandel (1923-) Hobsbawm(1917-) Structural Marxism Althusser (1918-1990) Poulantzas (1936-1979) PostStructuralism Foucault (1926-1984) Bourdieu (1930-) Economic Marxism Sweezy(1910-) Baran (1910-1964) Braverman (1920-1976) ! Annates Braudel (1902-1985) Structural Linguistics de Saussure (1857-1913) 3 Neo-imperialism Dependencia Wallerstein (1930-) World System Anderson (1938) E.P. Thompson (1924-1993) Habermas (1929-) Post-Modernism Lyotard(1924-) Derrida (1930) Kristeva (1941) Lacan (1901-1981) ^Historical ' ^/Materialism 3 | World System Critical Theory Dialectical Approach PostStructuralism PostModernism 3 cont. THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 41 44 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A influence of Croce on Gramsci; of Weber on Lukacs; of Freud, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche,Dilthey, and Bergsonon the Frankfurt School,of the FrenchSchool of Annaleson Wallerstein;and of the variousstructuralists on Marxist Frenchstructuralistsand post-structuralistshas beenas potent an influenceas hasbeenthe Marxian (AndersonPerry 1976). Looking at Figure 2.1 from the bottomup, one notes,fIrst of all, the shaded areaof economicdeterminism(row 4). This is the familiar Marxist legacy. Many IR scholarsare unawareof any other school of thoughtthat might be derivative from Marxism other than "economicdeterminism."The "globalist" approach referred to in most IR textbooks originates from these sources.Among thoselisted in this row, there is the North Americanschool of the Monthly Review,of Baranand Sweezyin particular,to whosecontribution we owe to a large extent the renaissanceof classical theories of imperialism and the impetus for the developmentof dependencytheories. Wallerstein'smore recentanalysisof the world capitalist systemhas welldocumentedaffInities with this school. Second,there are the American "revisionist" historiansassociatedwith the University of Wisconsinand journals such as Studieson the Left (and later with Socialist Revolution and Socialist Review): W.A. Williams, G. Kolko, G. Alperovitz, and others. They are important for their persistent argumentthat the Cold War was constructedby the United States.Finally, there is the Trotskyist tradition as perpetuatedin works of high scholarly value by such prominentLeftist writers as British historian E. Hobsbawm and Belgian economistErnst Mandel. The Trotskyist tradition, as David MacLellan haspointedout, was extremelyimportantuntil recently, since it was the dominant form of Marxism in English-speakingcountries (MacLellan 1979,308)and was an obviousinfluenceon more authorsthan would admit to it, including I. Wallerstein. Above the shadedband, there is row 3, which begins with historical sociologistswho gaveup or subduedthe economicdeterministinclinations underthe influenceof the FrenchSchoolof Annalesor Max Weber.Generally speaking,abovethe shadedband we enterwhat to many international relations specialistshave been until recently, areas that they never connectedto Marxism: Referredto as HegelianMarxism, this is a tradition that hasheld sway over continental(Western)Europeand that only recentlyhas found its way to Britain and the United States,displacingthere Trotskyist influences. As I mentionedin discussingthe changesin emphasisof the contemporaryMarxists, HegelianMarxism is virtually freed from suchconcernsas economicsubstructure,political economy,and the historical materialist method. Here are the origins of a "nondeterministic" Marxism characteristicof this century. Hegelian Marxists still explore society as a THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 45 complex network of social relations and material interests,and insist that none of thesecan be understoodin isolation from the others,but that ideas play an increasinglyimportantrole. The beginningsof the tradition of HegelianMarxism in this century are associatedwith the work in particularof (Hungarian)Georg Lukacs, (German) Karl Korsch, and (Italian) Antonio Gramsci. Into the sameHegelian tradition falls the work of membersof the GermanFrankfurt School, such as Horkheimer, Benjamin, Adorno, and Marcuse, and later the work of Jiirgen Habermas.Their work is known as critical theory or sociology.The work of the late E.P. Thompson,the major figure of the British and Europeanpeacemovement,has recognizableaffinities with someof the themes of Germancritical theory. I list Gadameron behalf of hermeneuticsas a significant influence on Habermasin particular.I list structuralfunctionalismbecauseof its influence on both FrenchMarxism and "post-Marxism"as well as on the dependency theory. I list the work of FrenchstructuralistsAlthusserand Poulantzasonly for the sakeof completeness.With the tragic departurefrom the sceneof the main protagonistsof the approach(after Poulantzas'ssuicideandAlthusser's deathin a mentalasylum)we are left mainly with many of their terminological innovationsandtermsthat havebecomea part of scholarlylanguagewith no heed to their initial meaning, such as problematique,conjecture,2and manyother terms.It is interestingthat nobodyhastried to explorethe contribution of the exceptionally talented Nicos Poulantzas,who in fact wrote quite explicitly on internationalrelations. It is the post-structuralistssuchas Foucaultand Bourdieuwho appearto have attractedconsiderableattention. They are not only post-structuralist but also "post-Marxist." As I mentioned, the critical sociologist Jurgen Habermasmaintainsthat post-structuralistsand anyonebeyondthem, that is, post modernists,have nothing to do with Marxism. It has been noted, however, that, despite these protestations,Habermasand Foucault reach strikingly similar conclusions. With the exceptionof Max Weber, the area into which we enter next (row 2 in Figure 2.1) will likely be as alien to IR scholarsas the oneswe have alreadyexplored.There are the late 1940s Oxford analytical philosophers H.A.L. Hart and J.L. Austin. The former played a major role in the transformationof the philosophyof law and the latter was a key influence on the later developmentof "linguistic philosophy."Ludwig Wittgensteinis the giant of philosophyin this century. He hasa connectionto the pedigree of the "old" IR discipline through his associationwith the Vienna circle (from which the IR discipline derivesits versionof positivism). Someof the ideas of Wittgensteinwill be known to the studentsof the IR discipline 46 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A through a slim book by Wittgenstein'sstudent,PeterWinch (1958), which was widely read by students of IR. In it, Winch adapted some of Wittgenstein'sideasto social sciences.Hart, Austin, and Wittgensteinare all associatedwith what is calleda "linguistic tum": a recognitionoflimitations imposedon philosophyby the imperfectionsand inadequaciesof language, calling into question positivists' belief in objective knowledge. Anthony Giddens'sprolific work hasunderstandablychangedits focus over the years: Hisearlier work shouldbe listed in the historical materialistrow. His later work is more influencedby Weberand particularly by Durkheim, and I list him close to the "old" IR discipline (row 1 in Figure 2.1) because of his idea of structuration thathas been drawn upon by a range of IR scholarsin their attemptsto developa constructivistapproach. The top row depictsthe philosophicalroots of the mainstreamIR discipline as we usedto know it, beforethe arrival of the "post" movement.Here in row 1, we can see the distinction betweenthe utopian-idealist tradition and the "post-Carr"realists.I list Hempel, Popper,and Lakatosas philosophersof sciencewhom IR studentshearaboutin connectionwith the different mixes of logical positivism, logical empiricism,and falsificationismand their different modifications,as taughtin mostAmericanIR programs. If we look in today'sIR literature for a continuationof Carr's realismidealism distinction in terms of partnersin a debate,it is obvious that the intellectual resourcesnecessaryto mount a meaningful dialogue and critique of the mainstreamrealist approachhave been exhaustedinside the discipline. What Figure 2.1 makesclear is just how important the opening up to the sourcesfrom outside the discipline in the last twenty years has been. Most of theseapproaches,idealist in the senseof dealing with ideas and their dominanceor influence over the world, haveall drawn on outside sources,particularly from the scholarshipthat can be found in row 3 in Figure 2.1. Many topics of IR publications,Ph.D. dissertations,and conference papersreflect influencescoming from all strandsdepictedin Figure 2.1. It is not surprisingthat very few IR scholarscareto examinethe roots of the new approaches.However,whetheranybodylikes it or not, this is the intellectual pedigreeof the IR discipline as it has beenenlargedin the last twenty years. First Stage: 1977-1986 In Table 2.1 I list chronologically the first important works. For lack of space,I do not go into detail of all the works that influencedthe arrival of the new approaches:works of Galtung, Krippendorff, Brucan, and others. The presenceof new influencesin the IR field was first noted becauseof THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 47 Table 2.1 Selected Publications of the "Post" Movement, Stage 1: Until 1986 Cox, RW. 1979. "Reflections of Some Recent Literature." International Organization. McGowan, P., and Harmer, F. 1979. "Teaching International Political Economy: The Role of Values, History, and Theory." Teaching Political Science. Ashley, R.K. 1980. The Political Economy of War and Peace: The Sino-Soviet American Triangle and the Modern Security Problematique. Galtung, J. 1980. The True Worlds. Alker, H.R. 1981. "Dialectical Foundation of Global Disparities." International Studies Quarterly. Cox, RW. 1981. "Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations Theory." Millennium. Reprinted in Neorealism and its Critics, ed. Keohane, 1986. Cox, RW. 1981. "In Search of International Political Economy: A Review Essay." New Political Science. Maclean, J. 1981. "Marxist Epistemology, Explanations of 'Change' and the Study of International Relations." In Change and the Study of International Relations, ed. Barry Buzan and R.J.B. Jones. Maclean, J. 1981. "Political Theory, International Theory, and Problems of Ideology." Millennium. McGowan, P., and Walker, S.G. 1981. "Radical and Conventional Models of U.S. Foreign Economic Policy Making." World Politics. Ashley, RK 1981. "Political Realism and Human Interests." International Studies Quarterly. Alker, H.R. 1982. "logic, Dialectics, Politics: Some recent controversies."ln Dialectical Logics for the Political Sciences, ed. H.R. Alker. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences of Humanities. Ashley, R.K. 1983. "The Eye of Power: the Politics of World Modeling." International Organization. Ashley, R.K. 1983. "Three Modes of Economism." International Studies Quarterly. Mittelman, J.H. 1983. "World Order Studies and International Political Economy." Alternatives. Cox, RW. 1983. "Gramsci, Hegemony and International Relations: An Essay in Method." Millennium. Halliday, Fred. 1983. The Making of the Second Cold War. Alker, H.R., and Biersteker, T.J. 1984. "The Dialectics of World Order: Notes for a Future Archaeologist of International Savior Faire." International Studies Quarterly. Ashley, R.K. 1984. "The Poverty of Neorealism." International Organization. Reprinted in Neorealism and Its Critics, ed. Keohane, 1986. Maclean, J. 1984. "Interdependence-an Ideological Intervention in International Relations?" In Interdependence on Trial: Studies in the Theory and Reality of Contemporary Interdependence, ed. R.J. Barry Jones and Peter Willetts. Walker, R.B.J. 1984. ed. Culture, Ideology and World Order. Cox, R.W. 1986. "Postscript 1985." In Neorealism and Its Critics, ed. Keohane. 48 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A ratherunusualfootnotes.Insteadof Thucydides,Machiavelli, Hobbes,Grotius, Rousseau,or Kant and the IR exemplarssuchas Carr, Morgenthau,and regular academicsciting eachother,the footnotesof the internationalrelationsjournals becamepopulatedby suchnew and unfamiliar namesas Grarnsci,Habermas, Bourdieu, and Foucault, with works dealing not with IR but rather with a decayedcapitalistsystem,madness,prisons,psychiatry,social medicine,mental institutions,sexuality, architecture, and tribal rituals. Practicallynobodyand nothing in the IR discipline escapedattack, although structural realism or neorealismwas the prime target. Significantly, the teachingof IR was criticized. On the basis of a survey of syllabi of IR coursesoffered at leading Americanuniversities,the authorsfound not only ordinary geographicalparochial attitudesbut also "paradigmatic"parochialism.Paradigmaticparochialism was definedas the exclusionfrom syllabi andstudents'reachof one or two of the threeparadigmsthat the authorsidentified-includingthe radical dialectical paradigm-andthat were found to be in a dialectical relationshipto each other (Alker and Biersteker1984). Alker and Biersteker'sarticle was also the first attemptto presenta full-fledged and comprehensiveclassification of the IR paradigms,as could be found not just in the IR discipline but acrossthe world and time. The authors'own "radicaldialectical approach" was proposedas a designationfor all the new theoretical developments, what we call herethe "post" movement. In this first period, the main activities of the protagonistsof the new approachconsistedoften of discovering and lifting conceptsfrom those sourcesthat might be applied to IR and trying to stretch them in various ways to make them fit. Though very small, the group was heterogeneous: virtually everyLeftist thinker listed in the two bottomrows, andparticularly in row 2, of Figure 2.1, has "auditioned" for an internationalrelationsrole. What is noticeableis how underrepresented in its influence on this emerging group is the economic determinist "band"--confirming the developments of Leftist thought in other social sciencesin this century. Indeed, if anything, the emerginggroup of writers, Ashley in particular,were critical of economicdeterminism,ofeconomism,of dependency,and of the World Systems approach. Marx's ideas were directly extendedto IR mainly through the work of McLean. Alker deriveshis conceptsof dialecticsfrom Lenin. The other influencesincludedin Figure 2.1 tendedto be drawn upon randomlyandquite indiscriminately. As I have alreadymentioned,R.W. Cox combinesin his work the concept of critical theory, Gramsci'sconceptof hegemony,and civil society, which for the internationalcontext he redefinesas being basedon "hegemonic consensus,createdby a variety of cultural and ideological instruments." (Cox 1981, 165ff.). Academics like ourselvesare by no means THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 49 excludedfrom the processesof creating such as "hegemonicconsensus." Instrumentalin fostering the hegemonic consensus is the "historical bloc" of bourgeoisintellectuals,including academics.Gramsci'shegemony,as applied to the international level by Cox, refers to "an order within the world economyexpressedin the dominantmode of productionsupporting universalnorms, internationalinstitutions, and mechanismsfor the behavior of statesand other actors" (171-72). Most of this literature was introduced to IR through articles by Richard Ashley. Despitehis denial of the fact, Ashley's intellectual path began with a Lenin-inspired dissertation, subsequentlypublishedas a book. He progressedsoon after through more esoteric ideas ranging from critical to post-structuralistand then to postmodem.Ashley was obviously "learning on the job," often taking up a lot of spacesimply paraphrasingand explainingconceptsto his IR colleagues, often not even getting far enoughto show the relevanceto international relations. The SecondStage: 1987 On Stage2 marks a clear shift from the footnotesinto the texts of IR studies. Table 2.2 lists again only samplesof full- fledged literature of this kind. In the incredibly short period of one decade,the new generationof IR scholars, most of whom would still have been at graduateschools during the first period, have more than made up for the time lost by the chronic absenceof Leftist thought from the IR discipline. Marxism madea fleeting appearancein the IR discipline and was fast replacedby its Hegelian or indeedpost-Marxistversions.There is no longer any hesitation.The main approaches,as I have identified them in Figure 2.1 (right-hand column), have not just one or two, but a contingent of full supporterswho have written book-lengthstudiesinspiredby this or that source.Therehasbeena continuousoutpouringof work on historical sociologywhich challengesthe IR discipline'sneglectof theoriesof stateand which, for lack of space,I do not include in Table 2.2. There is the historical materialist approach,initially clearly Trotskyist,of Fred Halliday. The critical schoolhasnew energetic supportersin many authors such as Linklater, in addition to Cox. Many post-structuralistauthors have moved on to post-modernism,and both of theseinfluenceshave been taken up by a large group of feminist authors,a new and rapidly growing sectionof the IR discipline. Walker and Der Derian lead the field of post-modernisttreatisesofIR. Walker's work in particular has been earmarkedas a future classic.The main featuresof the sourceswhen applied to IR are kept intact. Thus the distinguishing featureof critical theory and post-structuralismcontinuesto be the stressof 50 VENDULKA KUBA.LKOV A. Table 2.2 Selected Publications of the "Post" Movement, Stage 2: After 1986 DIALECTICAL Alker, Hayward R. 1995. Rediscoveries and Reformulations. CRITICAL THEORY Cox, R.w. 1987. Production, Power, and World Order: Social Forces in the Making of History. - - . 1992. "Multilateralism and World Order." Review of International Studies. - - . 1995. Approaches to World Order. Hoffman, M. 1987. "Critical Theory and Inter Paradigm Debate." Millennium. - - - . 1988. "Conversations on Critical International Relations Theory." Millennium. Linklater, Andrew. 1990. Beyond Realism and Marxism: Critical Theory and International Relations. - - . 1992. "The Question of the Next Stage in International Relations Theory: A Critical Theoretical Point of View." Millenium. Neufeld, Mark. 1995. The Restructuring of International Relations Theory. POST·STRUCTURALIST-POST·MODERN Ashley, R.K. 1987. "The Geopolitics of Geopolitical Space: Toward a Critical Social Theory of International Politics." Alternatives. ----. 1988"Untying the Sovereign State: A Double Reading of the Anarchy Problematique." Millennium. - - - . 1989. "Living on the Border lines: Man, Post-Structuralism and War." In Internationalllntertextual Relations. Der Derian ed. Ashley, R.K., and R.B.J. Walker. 1990. "Reading DissidencelWriting the Discipline: Crisis and the Question of Sovereignty in International Studies." International Studies Quarterly. --.1990. "Speaking the Language of Exile: Dissident Thought in International Studies." International Studies Quarterly. Bartelson. J. 1995. A Genealogy of Sovereignty. Campbell, David. 1990 "Global Inscription: How Foreign Policy Constitutes the United States." Alternatives. - - . 1992. Writing Security: United States Foreign Policy and the Politics of Identity. - - . 1993. Politics Without Principle: Sovereignty, Ethics, and the Narratives of the Gulf War. Der Derian, James. 1987. On Diplomacy: A Genealogy of Western Estrangement. - - - . 1988. "Philosophical Traditions in International Relations." Millennium. ---.1989. "Boundaries of Knowledge and Power." In Internationalllntertextual Relations. Der Derian and Shapiro, eds. - - - . 1989. "Spy Versus Spy: The Intertextual Power and International Intrigue." In Internationalllntertextual Relations. Der Derian and Shapiro, eds. - - . 1990. "The (S)pace of International Relations: Simulation, Surveillance, and Speed." International Studies Quarterly. - - . 1992. Antidiplomacy: Spies, Terror, Speed and War. THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 51 - - . ed. 1994. International Theory: Critical Investigation. Der Derian, J., and M.J. Shapiro, eds. 1989. Internationallintertextual Relations: Postmodern Readings of World Politics. Dillon, Michael. 1996. Politics of Security: Towards a Political Philosophy of the Continental Thought. George, Jim, and Campbell, David. 1990. "Patterns of Dissent and the Celebration of Difference: Critical Social Theory and International Relations." International Studies Quarterly. George, Jim. 1994. Discourses of Global Politics: A Critical (Re)lntroduction to International Relations. Klein, Bradley S. 1987. Strategic Discourse and Its Alternatives. - - . 1987. "Hegemony and Strategic Culture: American Power Projection and Alliance Defence Politics." Review of International Studies. - - . 1988. "After Strategy: Toward a Postmodern Politics of Peace." Alternatives. --.1989. ''The Textual Strategies of Military Strategy: Or, Have You Read Any Good Defence Manuals Lately?" In Internationallintertextual Relations. Der Derian and Shapiro, eds. Shapiro, Michael. 1989. "Textualizing Global Politics." In Internationallintertextual Relations. Der Derian and Shapiro, eds. Walker, R.B.J. 1987. "History and Structure in the Theory of International Relations." Millennium. - - . "Realism, Change and International Political Theory." International Studies Quarterly. - - . 1988. One World, Many Worlds: Struggles for a Just World Peace. --.1989. "The Prince and 'The Pauper': Tradition, Modernity, and Practice in the Theory of International Relations." In Internationallintertextual Relations. Der Derian and Shapiro, eds. - - . 1993. InsidelOutside: International Relations as Political Theory. FEMINIST POST-STRUCTURALIST-POST-MODERN Enloe, Cynthia. 1989. Bananas, Beaches and Bases: Making Feminist Sense Out of International Politics. Flax, Jane. 1990. Thinking Fragments: Psychoanalysis, Feminism and Postmodernism in the Contemporary West. Grant, Rebecca, and Kathleen Lewland, eds. 1991. Gender and International Relations. Peterson, V. Spike, ed. 1992. Gendered States: Feminist (Re)Visions of International Relations Theory. - - . 1992. "Transgressing Boundaries: Theories of Knowledge, Gender and International Relations." Millennium. Peterson, V. Spike, and Runyan Anne Sisson. 1993. Global Gender Issues. Sylvester, Christine, ed. 1993. "Feminists Write International Relations." Alternatives. Special Issue. - - . 1993. Feminist Theory and International Relations in a Postmodern Era. HISTORICAL MATERIALISM Halliday, Fred. 1994. Rethinking International Relations. 52 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A purposeor interestthat createsknowledge,allegedby positivists to be objective and value-free.The critical school addsits importantleitmotif--the possibility of emancipation.A number of IR scholarstried their hand at deconstructinga variety of IR traditional texts, reinterpretingIR as intertextual relations and deconstructingits main concepts,such as anarchyor sovereignty. Constructivism Throughoutthis chapterthe verb constructhas frequently appeared.If the use of the term alone is a qualification, then everybodyI havereferredto is a constructivist.There is no doubt about the importanceof the active creation of societalstructuresand their purposefulmanipulationin the "post" movement.The thrust of this approachderivesfrom the notion of a perversion of the conceptof praxis, the abuseof "power over opinion" so loosely termed by Carr, disguisedand marketedas value-free objectivity. I now tum to constructivismas Onuf defined it in 1989 and as he himself introducesit in this volume in Chapter3. Here it will suffice to say that Onufs constructivismis totally different from the other varietiesand it is his approachalone which shouldcontinue using that designation.My discussionof the "post" movementwould have shown how tenuousany similarities are if only we review the intellectual origins in Onufs case,markedin Figure 2.1 by arrows: Onuflinks together the old and the new IR pedigree,as the arrows in Figure 2.1 indicate. Through Habermasand the early Giddens,there is a distant connectionto Marx, while his startingpoint is an attemptto overcomethe impassein the "old" IR. The other sources,which he alone in the IR discipline uses, provide him with tools totally different from any of those used in the extendedIR discipline. Onufs constructivismabandonsobsessivecritique of structuralrealismor Westernsocietyand simply offers an alternativeontology of what the social world is all about. Nor is Onufs constructivism mainly an epistemologicaldevice providing a layer of unreal or surreal "construction"over reality to disguisethe underpinningontology. While for other constructivistapproachesdescribedin Chapter3 in this volume, the act of the constructionis restrictedto "states,"for Onuf constructivismis a universalexperience.His constructivismis not only a contributionto the IR discipline; it is a full-fledged social theory as well. Onufs constructivismis applicablenot simply to the level of states,but to humansin any dimension of their social activity, internationalrelations being merely one, albeit an extremelyimportantone,amongmany. Unfortunately, instead of welcoming this developmentas a positive THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 53 trend, someof his IR colleaguesexpressconcernabout his challengeto the central IR concept of anarchy, without which international studies fears losing its claim to having a distinct subjectmatter(Buzan,Jones,and Little 1994). Onuf obviously does not sharethesefears. His constructivismmakesit possibleto seelayers of mutually constructedrelationsoperatingalong the samebasic lines. The key point is that speechacts,rules, and norms,which are at the heartof his approachand at the heartof humanexistenceas social beings, are generatedfrom within people; that is to say, they are endogenousto real peopleas active, creativebeings,and to their practice.They are not dictated by some outside, exogenousstructure(as in Waltz or Wendt) which has taken a life and dynamism of its own. Onuf opens a broad theoreticalavenuefor incorporatinginto the IR discipline a host of phenomenaof the post-ColdWar world for which there is no apparentplace in the traditional approaches.In contrastto theseapproaches,Onufs framework makes it easy to understandconceptssuch as identity and culture, or the implications of the Information Age, conceptswhich are am'.Jvgthe central issuesof our time. E.H. Carr, Realism,and Idealism To return to E.H. Carr: An IR discipline that does not exclude Leftist influences and that allows for an interplay of a whole spectrumof ideas would seem to be something Carr called for. Onuf might be portrayed within Carr's terms as trying to integrateor transcendrealist and idealist traditions as defined by Carr, althoughthere are candidatesfor exactly the same role---Carr himself, at least in broad outline, or critical theory, as Linklater suggests(1997). For those of us who are not dialecticians,Onufs approach,as he describesit in Chapter3, offers a constructiveway forward, away from the unabatingwar wagedin the IR discipline. One thing is for sure. The discipline of IR is now complete.It is no longer like an airplanetrying desperately to lift off without its left wing. It can now fly. And out of the turmoil of the cathartic last twenty years a brand-newapproachto IR, to which Chapter3 and the rest of this volume are dedicated,hasbeenborn. Whodunit? There was no body, no villain; no crime was committed; no chargeswere pressed.We all did it in our characteristicacademicway, shooting ourselvesin the foot. Did I just use Carr to constructan argument,and did I 54 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A misunderstandhim or cite him out of context?Certainly no more than the IR discipline has done, over the last fifty years.Unpleasantthoughit might be, thereexiststhe empirical evidenceto prove it! Notes I would like to thank Nicholas Onuf and Henry Hammanfor their suggestions:the idea that I write this chapteras a whodunit story was Henry Hamman's.Nick Onufs general commentswere invaluable. 1. It was the Frankfurt School's seconddirector, Max Horkheimer, who in 1937 coined the term critical theory, taking his inspiration from the understandingof Marxism as a "critique of political economy,"a phraseusedby Marx. It is thereforesurprising that Habermas,the main contemporaryfigure of the same Frankfurt School, is not namedamongthe sourcesof Cox's inspiration for the "critical theory" that he defined and introducedto the IR discipline. In fact, a negativefootnote referenceto Habermas suggeststhat Cox's and Habermas'sunderstandingof the same expression,"critical theory," is not in any way related. 2. Theseterms have beenusedso frequently that it is worth reminding ourselvesof their original meaning. Problematiqueconveys an ipso facto antipositivist attitude. It refers to a "theoretical or ideological framework" whose "production" necessarilyinvolves a value judgment as to what is important in the world, namely "the objective internal referencesystemof its particularthemes,the systemof questionscommanding the answersgiven by the ideology" (Althusser1969, 67, note 30). That is, the use of the term hasantipositivistimplications. The term conjectureis the "central conceptof the Marxist scienceof politics." It "denotesthe exactbalanceof forces at any given momentto which political tacticsmust be applied" (Althusser 1969,250).The term is used by Cox as "historical conjecture" and also by Halliday (1983). Bibliography Alker, Hayward R. 1981. "Dialectical Foundationof Global Disparities."International StudiesQuarterly 25: 69-98. - - - . 1982. "Logic, Dialectics, Politics: Some Recent Controversies."Dialectical Logicsforthe Political Sciences.PoznanStudiesin the Philosophyof the Sciencesof Humanities,ed. H.R. Alker, 7. Amsterdam:Rodopi. - - - and T.I. Biersteker, 1984. "The Dialectics of World Order: Notes for a Future Archaeologist of International Savoir Faire." International Studies Quarterly 28: 121-42. Althusser,Louis. 1969. For Marx. New York: Pantheon. Anderson,Perry. 1976. Considerationson WesternMarxism. London: New Left Books. - - - . 1983. In the Tracks ofHistorical Materialism. London: Verso. Anderson,R.I., lA. Hughes, and W.W. Sharrock. 1986. Philosophyand the Human Sciences.Totowa,NJ: Barnes& Noble Books. Ashley, Richard. 1984. "The Poverty of Neorealism." International Organization. Spring38(2): 225-61. Banks, Michael. 1978. "Ways of Analyzing the World Society." In International Relations Theory: A Bibliography, ed. A.I.R. Groom and C.R. Mitchell. London: Frances Pinter, 195---215. THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 55 - - - . 1985. "The Inter-ParadigmDebate." In International Relations: A Handbook of Current Theory, ed. Margot Light and A.J.R. Groom, London: FrancesPinter, 195-215. Beer, Francis A., and Robert Hariman. 1996. Post-Realism:The Rhetorical Turn in InternationalRelations.EastLansing: Michigan StateUniversity Press. Booth, Kenneth. 1991. "Security in Anarchy: Utopian Realismin Theory and Practice." InternationalAffairs 67(3): 527-45. Brown, Chris. 1992. International RelationsTheory: New NormativeApproaches.New York, Oxford: ColumbiaUniversity Press. Bull, Hedley. 1969. "Twenty Years' Crisis: Thirty YearsOn." InternationalJournal 24: 625-38. ---.1977. The AnarchicalSociety.London: Macmillan. Burawoy, Michael. 1982. "Introduction: The Resurgenceof Marxism." AmericanSociology 88. Supplement.Sl-lO. Buzan,Barry, CharlesJones,and RichardLittle. 1993. The Logic ofAnarchy: Neorealism to StructuralRealism.New York: ColumbiaUniversity Press. Callinicos, Alex. 1983. Marxism and Philosophy.Oxford: ClarendonPress. Carr, Edward Hallett. (1939) 1962. The Twenty Years' Crisis 1919-1939:An Introduction to the StudyofInternationalRelations.London: Macmillan. Cox, R.W. (1981) 1986. "Social Forces, Statesand World Orders:BeyondInternational RelationsTheory." Millenium: Journal of International Studies10(2): 126-55. Reprinted in Neorealismand Its Critics, ed. Keohane,204-54. Deutscher,Isaac. 1955. Heretics andRenegades.London: HamishHamilton. Deutscher,Tamara. 1983. "E.H. Carr-A PersonalMemoir." New Left Review 137: 78-86. Dunn, Timothy. 1995. "The Social Constructionof International Society."European Journal ofInternationalRelations. 1 (3, September). Foucault,Michel. 1977. Discipline andPunish.Harmondsworth,London: Penguin. Fox, William T.R. 1985. "E.H. Carr and Political Realism: Vision and Revision." Review ofInternationalStudies11: 1-15. Galtung, Johann. 1961. "A Structural Theory of Imperialism." Journal of PeaceResearch8: 81-117. George,Jim. 1994. Discoursesof Global Politics: A Critical (Re)Introductionto International Relations.Boulder,CO: Lynne Rienner. Halliday, F. 1983. The Making ofthe SecondCold War. London: Verso. Hoffmann, Stanley. 1977. "An American Social Science: International Relations." Daedalus106 (3): 40--59. Holsti, K.J. 1985. The Dividing Discipline: Hegemonyand Diversity in International Theory. Boston:Allen & Union. Howe, Paul. 1994. "The Utopian Realismof E.H. Carr." Reviewof International Studies 20: 277-97. Inkeles,Alex. 1975. "The EmergingSocial Structureof the World." World Politics (4): 467-95. Jones,Charles. 1996. "E.H. Carr: Ambivalent Realist." In Post-Realism,ed. Beer and Hariman,95-119. Keohane,Robert 0., ed. 1986. Neorealismand Its Critics. New York: Columbia University Press. - - - . 1988. "International Institutions: Two Approaches."International Studies Quarterly 32 (4): 379-91. - - - and JosephS. Nye. 1977. Powerand Interdependence:World Politics in Transition. Boston:Little, Brown. 56 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A Kratochwil, F., John Gerard,and Ruggie. 1986. "InternationalOrganization:A Stateof the Art on an Art of the State."InternationalOrganization40 (4, Autumn): 763---{)6. Krippendorff, E. (First publishedin Germanin 1975) 1982. InternationalRelationsas a SocialScience.Sussex:HarvesterPress. KubaIkova, Vendulka, and Albert A. Cruickshank. 1989a.Marxism and International Relations,rev. ed. Oxford Paperback:Oxford University Press. - - - . 1989b. Thinking New About Soviet "New Thinking." Berkeley: Institute of InternationalStudies,University of California, Berkeley. Kuhn, ThomasS. 1970. The Structureof Scientific Revolution.Chicago: University of ChicagoPress. Lapid, Yosef. 1989. "The Third Debate:On the ProspectsofInternationalTheory in the Post-PositivistEra." InternationalStudiesQuarterly 33 (3): 235-54. Legvold, Robert. 1997. "The Soviet Union and EasternEurope."In "Significant Books of the Last 75 Years."Foreign Affairs (September-October): 214-38. Light, Margot, and A.J.R. Groom, eds. 1985. International Relations:A Handbookof Current Theory. London: FrancesPinter. Lijphart, Arendt. (1975) 1981. "Karl W. Deutschand the New Paradigmin International Relations. In From National Developmentto Global Community, ed. R.L. Merritt and B.M. Russett.233-51,Londonand Boston:Allen and Unwin. Linklater, Andrew. 1990. BeyondRealismand Marxism: Critical Theory and International Relations.New York: St. Martin's Press. - - - . 1992. "The Questionof the Next Stagein International RelationsTheory: A Critical TheoreticalPoint of View." Millennium 21 (I): 77-98. - - - . 1997. "The Transformationof Political Community: E.H. Carr, Critical Theory andInternationalRelations."ReviewofInternationalStudies23: 321-28. MacLellan,David. 1979. Marxism After Marx. London: Macmillan Press. Mitroff, 1.1., and R.O. Mason. 1982. "On the Structureof Dialectical Reasoningin the Social andPolicy Sciences."TheoryandDecision 14. Morgenthau,Hans. (1948) 1962. "The Political Scienceof E.H. Carr." World Politics 1. Cited in The Restorationof American Politics, ed. Hans Morgenthau.Chicago: University of ChicagoPress. Pettman,Ralph H. 1978. Stateand Class: A SociologyofInternationalAffairs. London: CroomHelm. - - - . 1981. CompetingParadigmsin InternationalPolitics." ReviewofInternational Studies7: 39--50 Phillips, W.R. 1974. "Where Have All the TheoriesGone?" World Politics XXVI (2): 155-58. Polsby, W. Nelson, and Fred I. Greenstein,eds. 1975. Handbookof Political Science VII. Reading,MA: Addison-Wesley Rescher,N. 1977. Dialectics: A Controversy-OrientedApproach to the Theory of Knowledge.Albany: SUNY Press. Ritzer, G. 1983. SociologicalTheory.New York: Alfred Knopf. Rosenau,N. James. 1979. "Muddling, Meddling and Modelling: Alternative Approachesto the Study of World Politics in an Era of Rapid Change."Millennium: Journal ofInternationalStudies8: 130-44. Smith, Michael. 1986. Realist Thoughtfrom Weber to Kissinger. Baton Rouge, LA: LouisianaStateUniversity Press. Thompson,E.P. 1978. ThePovertyofTheoryand OtherEssays.London: Merlin Press. Thompson,K.W., et al. 1980. MastersofInternational Thought: Major Twentieth-Century Theoristsandthe World Crisis. BatonRouge,LA: LouisianaStateUniversity Press. Trevor-Roper,Hugh. (1962) 1963. "E.H. Carr's SuccessStory." Encounter.Quotedin THE TWENTY YEARS' CATHARSIS 57 Fly and the Fly-Bottle: Encounterswith British Intellectuals, ed. Ved Mehta. London: WeidenfeldandNicolson. Tucker,RobertW. 1977. TheInequalityofNations.New York: Basic Books. Wallerstein, Immanuel. 1979. The Capitalist World Economy.Cambridge:Cambridge University Press. Waltz, Kenneth N. 1979. Theory of International Politics. Reading,MA: AddisonWesley. - - - . 1986. "A Responseto My Critics." In NeorealismandIts Critics, ed. Keohane. Winch, Peter. 1958. The Idea of a Social Scienceand Its Relation to Philosophy.London: Routledgeand KeganPaul. 3 Constructivism: A User's Manual Nicholas Onuf Constructivismis a way of studying social relations--anykind of social relations. While it draws from a variety of other ways of studying such a broadand complexsubject,it standson its own as a systemof conceptsand propositions.Constructivismis not a theory as such. It doesnot offer general explanationsfor what people do, why societiesdiffer, how the world changes.Instead,constructivismmakesit feasibleto theorizeaboutmatters that seemto be unrelatedbecausethe conceptsand propositionsnormally usedto talk aboutsuchmattersare also unrelated. As presentedhere, constructivismappliesto all fields of social inquiry. In recentyears,dissidentscholarsin many fields have selectivelyusedthe languageof social constructionto criticize existing social arrangementsand scholarly practices.A great deal of discord has ensued.(Also see Part I, Introduction.)When constructivismis usedsystematically,it has the opposite effect. It finds value in diverse materialsand forges links where none seemedpossible. Full of discordantvoices, InternationalRelations is the field to which this particularsystemof conceptsand propositionswas first applied.While this manual is intended for the use of anyone with methodical habits of mind, its usersare most likely to have an interestin the subjectof international relations.They may havealso had someexposureto the field's scholarly controversies.If this is indeedthe case,they will soondiscoverthat the subject is less distinctive, but more complex, than they have been led to believe. 58 CONSTRUCTIVISM: A USER'S MANUAL 59 Overview Fundamentalto constructivismis the propositionthat humanbeingsare social beings,and we would not be humanbut for our social relations.In otherwords, the kind of beings social relationsmakeor constructpeople-ourselves-into that we are. Conversely,we makethe world what it is, from the raw materials that natureprovides,by doing what we do with eachotherand sayingwhat we say to each other. Indeed, saying is doing: talking is undoubtedlythe most importantway that we go aboutmakingthe world what it is. Countriessuch as France,the United States,and Zimbabwe are among the social constructions,or societies,that peoplemake throughwhat we do. Countries are self-containedworlds becausepeople talk about them that way and try to keepthem that way. Yet they are only relatively self-contained. Relationsamongcountries---internationalrelations---constitutesa world in its own right. This is a self-containedworld for the simple reasonthat it coversthe earth, but it is still nothing more than a world of our making--a societyof relatively self-containedsocieties. Constructivismholds that peoplemake society, and society makespeople. This is a continuous,two-way process.In order to study it, we must start in the middle, so to speak,becausepeopleand society, always having made each other, are already there and just about to change.To make a virtue of necessity,we will start in the middle, betweenpeopleand society, by introducing a third element,rules, that always links the other two elementstogether.Social rules (the term rules includes,but is not restrictedto, legal rules) make the processby which peopleand society constituteeach othercontinuousand reciprocal. A rule is a statementthat tells peoplewhat we shoulddo. The "what" in questionis a standardfor people'sconductin situationsthat we can identify as being alike, and can expectto encounter.The "should" tells us to match our conductto that standard.If we fail to do what the rule tells us to, then we can expectconsequences that someotherrule will bring into effect when other peoplefollow the rule calling for suchconsequences. All the ways in which peopledeal with rules---whetherwe follow the rules or break them, whetherwe makethe rules, changethem, or get rid of them--maybe called practices.Even when we do not know what a rule says,we can often guess what it is aboutby looking at people'spractices. Among much else, rules tell us who the active participantsin a society are. Constructivistscall these participantsagents. People are agents,but only to the extent that society,through its rules, makesit possiblefor us to participatein the many situationsfor which there are rules. No one is an agentfor all suchsituations. 60 NICHOLAS ONUF Ordinarily, we think of agents as people who act on behalf of other people. Consideringthe matter more abstractly,we see that rules make it possible for us to act on behalf of social constructions,which may be ourselves,otherhumanbeings,or evencollectionsof people,alongwith the rules, the practices,and the actualthings that we makeanduse.Conversely, agentsneednot be individual humanbeingsto be able to act on behalfof others(hereI refer to agentsin the third personto emphasizethat the terms peopleand agentsare not completelyinterchangeable).Agency is a social condition. Thus the governmentof a country is a collection of peopleand a social construction.According to the relevant rules, thesepeople act, together and in various combinations,on behalf of that country as a much largercollectionof people. Rules give agents choices. As we have already seen, the most basic choice is to follow the rule-to do what the rule says the agent should d()-{)r not. Only human beingscan actually make choices, becausewe alone(andnot all of us) havethe mentalequipmentto considerthe probable of making the choicesthat are availableto us. Nevertheless, consequences we always make such choices on behalf of, and in the name of, social constructions,whetherourselves,other peopleor collections of other people, or practicesand artifacts. Agentsact in societyto achievegoals.Thesegoalsreflect people'sneeds and wishesin light of their material circumstances.Every societyhas rules telling agentswhich goals are the appropriateones for them to pursue.Of course,thereare situationsin which peopleareperfectlyaimless.For example, when we freeze up in fear or fall asleepfrom exhaustion,we are no longeragentsor, for that matter,socialbeings. When we, as humanbeings,act as agents,we havegoalsin mind, evenif we are not fully aware of them when we act. If someoneasks us to think about the matter, we can usually formulate thesegoals more or less in the order of their importanceto whomeverwe are acting as agentsfor, starting with ourselves.Most of the time, agentshave limited, inaccurate,or inconsistentinformation about the material and social conditionsthat affect the likelihood of reaching given goals. Nevertheless,agentsdo the best they can to achieve their goals with the means that nature and society (together-alwaystogether)makeavailableto them. Acting to achievegoalsis rational conduct,and agentsfaced with choiceswill act rationally. Viewed from outside,thesechoicesmay appearto be less than rational, but this is due to the complexitiesof agencyandhumanfallibility. Agents make choices in a variety of situations. Rules help to define every such situation from any agent'spoint of view. In many situations, rules are directly responsiblefor presentingagentswith choices. Agents CONSTRUCTIVISM: A USER'S MANUAL 61 have made or acknowledgedtheserules in the belief that following rules generallyhelpsthemreachtheir intendedgoals. In these situations, rules are related to agents' practices,and to each other, through the consequencesthat agents intend their acts to have. Whether by accident or by design, rules and related practicesfrequently form a stable (but never fixed) pattern suiting agents' intentions. These patternsare institutions. As recognizablepatternsof rules and relatedpractices, institutions make people into agentsand constitutean environment within which agentsconductthemselvesrationally. While it is always possible, and often useful, to think of agents--allagents--asinstitutions in their own right, we more commonly think of agentsas operating in an institutional context thatgives themat leastsomeopportunitiesfor choice. Exercising choices, agentsact on, and not just in, the context within which they operate, collectively changing its institutional features, and themselves,in the process.Nevertheless,from any agent'spoint of view, society consistsof diverse institutions that seem,for the most part, to be held in place by rules linking them to other institutions. Any stablepattern of institutions (including agentsof all sorts) is also an institution. Agents are awareof the institutions populatingtheir environments,and not simply becausethe rules forming theseinstitutions directly bearon their conduct. To the extentthat someagentsmake choices,and other agentsare affected by these choices, institutions produce consequences for other agentsthat they cannothelp but be awareof andrespondto. In a complexworld, agentsoften make choicesthat have consequences, for themselvesand others,that they had not anticipatedor do not carevery much about.Unintendedconsequences frequently form stablepatternswith respectto their effect on agents.A perfect market provides a compelling illustration of this phenomenon.One by one, a large numberof sellersand buyers are incapableof affecting the supply of, and demandfor, a good. Collectively, their rational choiceshave the unintendedconsequence of setting a price for that goodwhich they mustindividually acceptas fixed. In Anyone may notice such stablepatternsof unintendedconsequences. the caseof a market, no one could fail to notice it in the form of a good's price, over which no agent seemsto have any control. Sometimesagents will chooseto preventchangesin such patternsby adoptingrules that are intendedto have this effect. A rule fixing the price of a good undercertain conditionsis only the mostobviousexample. Any stable pattern of rules, institutions, and unintendedconsequences gives society a structure, recognizableas suchto any observer.Agents are always observers.Insofar as they observeconsequences that they had not intended, andacceptthem, suchconsequences are no longer unintendedin 62 NICHOLAS ONUF the usual senseof the word. If agentsdecide that theseconsequences are bad for them, they will act to changethem, perhapswith other unforeseen consequences resulting. Outside observers(agents from a different society) may recognize a more complex structurethan agentsdo as observers.Outsiderscan stand back, so to speak,and seepatternsthat insiderscannotseebecausethey are too closeto them. As agentson the inside becomeawareof what observers have to say, observersbecome agents, whatever their intentions. When agentsin generaltake this new information into account in making their choices,an evengreatercomplexityof structureresults. Scholarswho think of themselvesas constructivistshave given a good deal of attentionto the "agent-structureproblem." (SeeHarry Gould'scontribution to this volume in Chapter4 for a thoroughreview of thesediscussions.) The term structureis the sourceof much confusion(an ontological confusion), becausescholarscannot agree on whether structuresexist in reality or only in their minds. The important point to rememberis that structure is what observerssee, while institutions are what agents act within. Nevertheless,structurecan affect agents.We are often affectedby phenomena,natural and social, that we do not or cannot see,but we then respondas agentsby putting what has happenedto us in an institutional context. When agentsdo this, they institutionalize structure by bringing rules to bearon their situations. Generally speaking,scholarstoday tend to think that the structure of internationalrelationsis not institutionalizedto any greatdegree.This is so even for some scholarswho think of themselvesas constructivists.They believe that countriesare highly institutionalizedas states,but that states, through their agents,conducttheir relationsin an anarchicworld. The term anarchypoints to a condition of rule amongstatesin which no one stateor group of statesrules over the rest. It also implies that there is no institution above statesruling them. When we say that statesare sovereign,we are sayingthe very samething. By calling internationalrelations anarchic,scholarsare not saying that there is an absenceof rule. This would be chaos,not anarchy.Instead,they sellerssellersespeciallya stable pattern of uninseemto be saying that structur~nd tendedconsequences--rules the day. In the samesense,we might say that the marketrulesthe behaviorof sellersandbuyers. Starting with rules, as constructivistsoften do, leadsquickly enoughto patternsof relationsthat we can only describeas a condition of rule. Usually this condition is sufficiently institutionalized that we can recognize specific agentsas rulers. Sometimesthere is very little evidenceof institutionalization, as in mob rule, but there is also little reasonto think that this CONSTRUCTIVISM: A USER'S MANUAL 63 condition will persist as a stable pattern without institutions emerging.In other words, where there are rules (and thus institutions), there is rule-a condition in which some agentsuse rules to exercisecontrol and obtain advantagesover other agents.Rule is a stablepatternof relations,but not a symmetricalone. Anarchy is a condition of rule in which rules are not directly responsible for the way agentsconducttheir relations.To be sure,there are rules in the of agents' background.They make sure that the unintendedconsequences many choices, and not rulers, do the job of ruling. If unintendedconsequencesseemto rule, it is becausesome agentsintend for themto do so. Someagentswant to be ruled in this indirect sort of way becauseit suits their goalsmore than any otherarrangementwould. Other agentshave little or no choice in the matter. Perhapspatternsjust happen,but agentsmake arrangements.Arranging for anarchyis just onepossibility. Constructivistsshould seriously consider dropping the word structure from their vocabularies.Socialarrangementis a betterchoice.Appearances recognizablya aside, internationalanarchyis a social arrangement-aninstitutio~n grandscale.Within its scope,many other institutionsare recognizablyconnected. In every society, rules create conditions of rule. The society that statesconstitutethroughtheir relationsis no exception. Whetherwe, as constructivists,start with agentsor with social arrangements,we come quickly enoughto particularinstitutions and thus to rules. If we start with rules, we can move in either direction-towardagentsand the choices that rules give them an opportunity to make, or toward the social arrangements that emergefrom the choicesthat agentsare making all the time. Whicheverway we go, we ought to keep in mind that rules yield rule as a conditionthat agents(as institutions)canneverescape. The practicalproblemis that, as constructivists,we want to move in both directionsat the sametime. Yet if we try to do so, we come up againstthe staggeringcomplexityof the social reality that we want to know about.It is impossibleto do everything.The practicalsolution is to start with rules and show how rules make agentsand institutions what they are in relation to each other. Then we can show how rules make rule, and being ruled, a universalsocialexperience. The remainderof this user'smanual is dedicatedto thesetwo tasks. To makepoints as clearand understandable as possible,it repeatsmost of what the readerhas now had a tasteof. In the process,it introducesmany additional conceptsand propositions,expressedin the simplest terms that its author can think of. Used consistentlyand systematicallyrelated, these conceptsandpropositionsconstitutea comprehensiveframeworkfor understandingthe world in constructivistterms. 64 NICHOLAS ONUF Rules Make Agents, Agents Make Rules Rulesmakeagentsout of individual human beingsby giving them opportunities to act upon the world. These acts have material and social consequences,someof them intendedand somenot. Through theseacts, agents make the material world a social reality for themselvesas human beings. Becauseagentsare human beings, acting singly or togetheron behalf of themselvesor others, they act as they do for human purposes--theyhave goalsreflecting humanneedsand wishes.The tangledconnectionsbetween agency(who is acting on whose behalf?),goals (whose goals are affected by what acts?),and circumstances(which features of the world actually matter?)make it difficult for agentsto explain fully and convincingly why they act as they do. Even if they seemconfused,observerscan often figure the reasonsfor their conductfrom the evidenceat hand. Agentsusewhatevermeansare availableto them to achievetheir goals. Thesemeansinclude material featuresof the world. Becausethe world is a social place, at least for human beings, rules make the world's material features into resourcesavailable for agents'use. Some resourcesare not directly material-rulesalso constituteagentsand institutionsas resources. Whetheragentsare able to spell out their reasonsfor using the resources availableto them, or observersfigure themout from the evidence,recognizablepatternsin the resultsconstituteagents'interests. Agentsneednot know what their interestsare to act on them. Oncethey learn more from other agents(as observers)about their own interests,they may act differently. Indeed,humanbeingsdo not needto think aboutthemselvesas agentsto be agents.While being an agent does not require the degree of self-consciousnessthat we associatewith having an identity, agentsare usually awareenoughof their identities, singularand collective, to havean interestin fosteringthoseidentities. As agents,peoplecan makeother peopleinto agentsby giving the latter the opportunity to act on the former's behalf for particular purposes.The former may do so individually or collectively, and the latter may be one or more individuals acting on the former's behalf. Agents acting collectively becomea singularagent.By using resources,they acquirea material existence, and, as the previous paragraphsuggests,they become objects of identification. Agency is always limited. Agentsare neverfree to act upon the world in all the ways that they might wish to. Many limits have a material component. We need air to breathe;we do not have wings to fly. No rule can readily make things otherwise,even though rules allow us, agents,to use resourcesto alter theselimits, for example,by fashioning scubagear and CONSTRUCTIVISM: A USER'S MANUAL 65 airplanes.Rules that give any agentan opportunity to act createlimits for other agents.Rules in generallimit the range of acts that other agentsare free to take. It follows from this proposition that no individual human being, as an agent,has full autonomy.By the sametoken, agentsacting togethernever have full independence.As noted, agentsare always limited by rules that give other agentsopportunitiesto act. Agents acting togetherare additionally limited by the very rules that give them the opportunity to act collectively. Rulesallowing otheragents,individual and collective, to act on their behalflimit themevenfurther. When a very large number of people collectively operateas an agent, when they have agentsacting for them, when they have someconsiderable measureof identity (including some place identified as theirs), and when they are free to act within very wide limits, thesepeopleconstitutea country. For severalcenturies,agentshave had a consistentinterest in talking aboutcountriesas if they are independentof eachotherand anyothersocial construction. This is made clearest by defining sovereignty as absolute independenceand describingcountriesas sovereignstates.As constructivists, however, we should always bear in mind that full independenceis a useful fiction, andsovereigntyis a matterof degree. The freedomthat agentsdo havedependson their ability to recognizethe material and social limits that apply to them. They must also be able to evaluatethe consequences of exceedingthose limits. To be an agent requiresthe mentalequipmentthat individual humanbeingsnormally develop over the course of their social lives. Agents exercise their freedom by choosingto act one way or another,in an unendingseriesof situationsthat make choosingunavoidable.It hardly needssaying that not choosingis a choice, presumablytaken, as all choices are, to advanceagents' goals. Agents make choices in light of the skills that they possessand the resourcesthat they haveaccessto, for reasonsthat they are more or lessable to articulate.In short,they makechoicesin pursuitof their interests. Rules offer agentsthe simplestkind of choices.Agents may chooseto follow a given rule, or to break it. Comparedto most situationsin which agentsmake choices, the choice of following a rule or not following it involves consequences that are easyto calculate.While unintendedconsequencesare always possible, rules give agents the opportunity to make rational choices--choicesdictatedby referenceto goals--with someassurancethat they are makingthe bestchoicesavailableto them. A rule makes rational choice relatively easy by telling the agents to whom it referswhat they shoulddo in somesort of situationthat they might find themselvesin. Theseagentsmay act on the contentsof the rule without 66 NICHOLAS ONUF realizing that the contentsform a rule. In principle, however, any agent (including any observerwith enoughinformation) canformulate contentsof a rule in the form of a rule. Thereis nothing tricky aboutthis. Sayingwhat a rule is-putting its contentsin the right fonn--is exactly the sameas speaking in a form that gets anyonewho is listening to respondto whateverwe are saying. The point of speakingin this way is to have somethingtake place-toaccomplishsomethingwith the assistanceof someoneelse. The act of speakingin a form that getssomeoneelseto act is commonly called a speechact. The form that a speechact must havewill be clearfrom the following examples:(1) You assertthat duck seasonhas begun (you might actually say, "Duck seasonhasbegun!"). (2) Shedemands thatwe all go duck hunting (she might actually say, "Let's go duck hunting!"). (3) I promise to roast duck for dinner (I might actually say, "I'll cook!"). The genericform for a speechact is: I (you, etc.) herebyassert(demand,promise) to anyone hearing me that some state of affairs exists or can be achieved.The threeexamplessuggestthat speechactsfall into threecategories, here called assertivespeechacts, directive speechacts, and commissive speechacts. Whether speechacts accomplishanything dependson whether others respondto what they hear. The responseto your assertionabout duck season was obviouslypositive. I, at least,acceptedher inclusive but imperative demandto go hunting when I promisedto cook. We may surmisethat both of you acceptedmy offer, andwe all threewent duck hunting, perhapsafter we checkedthe newspaperto be surethat duck seasonhad indeedbegun. Whatevercategorya particularspeechact falls within, particularspeech acts imply nothing about future situations. We start all over again when deer seasonbegins. A speakermay assertthe existenceof some state of affairs and others may agree, or may requestsomethingand others may comply, or may make a commitmentthat othersaccept,without any necessary consequences in the long run. If, however, speakersfrequently repeata particular speechact with the samegeneraleffect, everyoneinvolved begins to think that the repetition becomessignificant. We end up hunting with each other all the time becausewe go through the samecycle of speechacts wheneverhunting season begins. Constantly repeated,the same old speech acts turn into conventionas everyonecomesto believethat the words themselves,and not the speakersmouthing them, are responsiblefor what happens.Hunting togetheris what we do at certaintimes, whetherany of us evenhave to say anythingmuch aboutit anymore. Conventionscomecloseto being rules. Recall that rules tell agentswhat they shoulddo. A conventionremindsagentswhat they havealways done. CONSTRUCTIVISM: A USER'S MANUAL 67 The borderlinebetweenknowing that we have always done somethingand probably will continueto do it, and believing that we shoulddo it because we have always done it, is exceedingly fuzzy. If a convention prompts agentsto think that they should do somethingthat they have always done, then the conventionis indeeda rule. We should considerthe rule in question a weakrule becauseit is normative,which meansthat agentsacceptthe "should" element, only to the extent that the regular pattern of conduct (suchas huntingtogether)continues. As agentsbegin to realize that they should act as they always have,and not just becausethey always have acted that way, the convention gains strengthas a rule. Rules keep the form of a speechact by generalizingthe relation betweenspeakerand hearer.Within the generalform of a speech act, given rules make hearersinto agentsto whom those rules apply. Finally, agentsrecognizethat they shouldfollow the rules in questionbecause they are rules and for no otherreason. Rules can take the general form of speechacts in each of the three categoriespresentedabove:assertivespeechacts,directive speechacts,and commissivespeechacts. Rules in the form of assertivespeechacts inform agentsabout the world--the way things are, the way it works--andinform them what consequences are likely to follow if they disregardthis information. The information containedin suchrules may be statedin very general terms, in which casewe might call it a principle. The principle of sovereignty is a conspicuousexample. At the other end of the spectrumof possibilities, rules in the form of assertivespeechacts may be statedin very specific terms. Instructionsfor operatingappliances,filling committeeseats,or presentingdiplomatic credentialsare useful examples.Whereverrules in this form fall on the spectrum, they are instruction-rules.Providing information is not normative,but telling agentswhat they should do with that information is. Agents always know what they should do becausethe rule tells them somethinguseful abouttheir relationto the world. Directive speechactsare recognizableas imperatives.If the speakersays that you must do something,the speakerwants you to believe that you should do it. Rules in the form of directive speechacts, directive-rules,are emphaticallynormative.By telling agentswhat they must do (no hunting!), theserules leave no doubt as to what they shoulddo. Directive-rulesoften provide information aboutthe consequences for disregardingthem. Having this information (sixty days in jail!) helps rational agentsto make the right choicein decidingwhetherto follow theserules or not. Commissivespeechacts involve promises.Speakersmakepromisesthat hearersaccept.Commissivespeech acts give form to rules when hearers,as 68 NICHOLAS ONUF speakers,respondwith promisesof their own. Oncethesewebsof promises become sufficiently generalizedand normative in their own terms, they becomecommitment-rules.Agents are most likely to recognizetheserules in their effects.Theseeffectsare the rights and dutiesthat agentsknow they possesswith respect to other agents.Any given agent'srights constitute dutiesfor otheragents(privateproperty--nohunting!). Rights may entitle the agentspossessingthemto specific benefits.Rights may also empower agents to act toward other agents in specific ways. Obviously, powers and limits on powers tum people into agents. More generally,right and dutiestum peopleinto agentsby defining opportunities for them to act upon the world. Instruction-rulesand directive-rulesalso tum peopleinto agentsfor exactlythe samereason. Speechacts fall into three categoriesbecausethey perform different functions--theyget things done for speakersand hearerstogetherin three, and only three,ways. The samethreecategorieshold for niles becausethey work in the samethree ways that speechacts do--they get things done by instructing,directing, and committing agents.As observers,we seerules in eachcategoryperformingdifferent functions for society.Quite a few scholars in such fields as law and sociologyhave worked out variationson this functional scheme,but they have never used all three of thesecategories, andjust thesecategories,at the sametime. Philosophershavedeviseda different schemefor categorizingrules, and a numberof constructivistscholarshaveadoptedit. On functional grounds, there are two categoriesof rules: constitutive rules and regulative rules. Constitutive rules are the medium of social construction.Regulativerules are the mediumof socialcontrol. While this schememight seemto be constructivist,it is actually a source of confusion. From a constructivist point of view, all rules are always constitutive and regulative at the sametime. By definition, rules regulate the conduct of agentsbecauserules are normative--theytell agentswhat they shoulddo. Furthermore,the regulationof conductconstitutesthe world within which such conduct takes place, whetheragentsintend this consequenceor not. Acting in the world meansacting on the world, often as an unintendedconsequence.Intentions might be a useful way to categorize acts,but they are nevera decisivebasisfor categorizingrules. Even when agents intend that a particular rule serve only to regulate conduct(an intention that other agentsmay thwart by choosing,for example, to disregardthe rule), the conduct in questionwill have the effect of strengtheningor (if agentschooseto disregardit) weakeningthe rule. In the sameway, a rule that agentsintend to be constitutive will have to affect conductif it is to succeed.Often agentsintend rules to be simultaneously CONSTRUCTIVISM: A USER'S MANUAL 69 constitutiveand regulative.To give an obviousexample,whenagentscalled players take turns in playing a game, the rule instructing them to do so constitutesthe gameas one in which playersregularly take turns. As we have seen,rules servethreepossiblefunctions. Agentsmakerules and use them for instruction, direction, and commitment. Within each of these three functional categories,rules differ in the extent to which they have been formalized. Rules are formal if agentsencounterthem as fixed and unavoidablefeatures of their world. Rules also differ in the extent which they are linked to other rules. Agents often discover that particular rules are linked to other rules telling other agentswhat to do in the event that the relevant agents disregardthe particular rules in question. Formal rules that are effectively backedup by otherrules are legal. Formality strengthensa rule by making its normative characterclearer, in the processseparatingit from rules that are normativelymore ambiguous (conventions,for example).A rule supportinganotherrule strengthensthe latter by increasingthe chancesthat agentswill chooseto follow the latter rule. The more frequently agentsfollow a rule, the strongerthe rule will be, normatively (and the easierit will be to make it formal). For example,the principle of sovereigntyis a highly formal instruction-ruleconstitutingthe societyof states.It is supportedby commitment-rulesempoweringstates,as agents, to bring new membersinto this society. These supporting rules, which we know as rules of recognition,are supportedby instruction-rules that spell out a numberof social and the material conditionsthat must be satisfiedbeforestatehoodis possible. Agents are inclined to make rules legal and to follow them if they are legal becausethey know what the rules are, how much they matterto other agents,and what consequences they can expect from not following them. When agentsfind themselvesin a legal environment,it is rational for them to follow rules as a general proposition. It costs them less than careless conduct will. International relations is a peculiar environmentin this respect,but still a legal environment.While there are very few formal directive-rules to be found, there are large numbersof other, quite formal rules intricately linked in support of each other. Relevant agentsare perfectly awareof the situationandproceedaccordingly. Rules Form Institutions, Institutions Form Societies Rulesare linked to eachother in contentas well as function--bothby what they say and by what they do. Standingback, agentscan easily identify the ways that rules reinforce each other in what they say and do. Speaking figuratively, we might say that rules come in families, and that somefami- 70 NICHOLAS ONUF lies of rules come with rules documentingthe family pedigree.Other families of rules dependon observersto documentfamily resemblances.These and many other practiceshelp to give families of rules their distinguishing features.Rules and related practicesare almost impossibleto separatein practice, becauseevery time agentsrespondto rules, whether by making choicesor by observingthe choicesthat other agentsmake, they have an effect on thoserules and on their placesin families of rules. By recentconvention,scholarly observersof internationalrelationscall thesefamilies of rules and relatedpractices"regimes." At an earlier time, they called them "institutions," and this remains the usual term for most scholarswho devotetheir attentionsto social relations.In practice,the two terms are indistinguishable.International regimes are said to consist of principles, rules, norms,and procedures.By whatevername, theseare all categoriesof rules. Principles and proceduresanchor the two ends of a spectrumof possibilitiesdistinguishableby how generalthey are in content. Rules and norms are distinguishableby how formal they are, norms being sufficiently informal that observersare not always sure that they are rules until they seehow otheragents respond to them. Internationalregimesdiffer in size. They have rules that work in different ways (assertive-,directive-, and commitment-rules)in different proportions. Additionally, regimes differ in the extent to which they have rules backing up other rules. Institutions differ in exactly the sameways. They are madeup of rules that vary, not just in generalityand formality but also in numberandarrangement. Somesimple institutions consistof a small numberof rules whosecontent makesthem a family, even if the rules seemto give little support to eachother, andto get little supportfrom otherinstitutionsto which they are connected.In the world of internationalrelations,the balanceof poweris an exampleof suchan institution. Instruction-rulesconstitute,andregulate,the balanceof power. Theserules tell the great powers what to expect when they chooseallies and go to war. Yet even the balanceof power, as an institution, is not as simple as it seems.Treatiesgive allies rights and duties. Rules limiting the conduct of war help to keep the balancefrom being permanentlyupset. In the context of international relations, spheresof influence are also simple institutions made up of informal directive-rules.Theserules direct weak stateswithin the sphereto carry out a much strongerstate'swishes. When theserules are backedup by principlesjustifying sucharrangements, the sphereof influenceis no longerquite so simplean institution. As formal equals,statesmay also adopttreatiesdistributing rights and dutiesthat have unequal consequences within the sphere. Treaties are themselvessimple CONSTRUCTIVISM: A USER'S MANUAL 71 institutions minimally consisting of fonnal commitment-rulesthat apply only to the states adopting such treaties. The principle that treaties are binding, andthereforelegal, automaticallyprovidesthemwith supportfrom other,highly fonnal rules. Institutions suchas the balanceof power, spheresof influence, and treaties are simple only becauseobserverscan easily pick them out of an institutional environmentcharacterizedby a large number of linked rules and related practices. Agents act as observerswhen they recognize any institution as such, no matter how complex it is. Scholarsoften think of internationalregimesas somethingthat they alonecan see,while agents can see only the simpler institutions making up the regime. Yet observersbecome agents, and regimes become institutions, when other agents learn what observershaveto say. Internationalregimes are hard to see becausethe rules connectingthe institutions that make them up tend to be infonnal. Agents take them for granted.Fonnal rules make things clearer,and agentsneednot standback. For a long time in the context of international relations, agentshave had accessto a legal institution, conventionallyknown as the sourcesof international law, through which they can make legal rules and thus institutions whoseexistenceno one can doubt. Treatiesare one such institution, thanks to the legal principle that treatiesare binding on the statesadoptingthem. Agentsrespondto rules with goals in mind; institutionsservetheir interests. As a generalmatter, simple institutions have a more straightforward relation to agents' intereststhan do more complex and more difficult to recognizeinstitutions.We think of relatively simple institutionsas perfonning distinct functions for agentsand for other institutions. Dependingon what theserelatively simple institutionsdo, they give priority to rules in one of the functional categoriesthat we havealreadyidentified. When instruction-rulesare most in evidence,agentsare situatedin networks of rules and relatedpractices.The balanceof power is an example. Its rules assignan elevatedstatusto a few greatpowers(ideally five states) that must act as if they are roughly equalin the resourcesavailableto them. If states'agentsact as instructed,the consequences are supposedto be an ever-shifting and relatively peacefulbalanceof alliancesamong the great powers,whateverthe immediateintentionsof their agentsmight be. Recognizing the balanceof power as an institution whose function suits their interests,agentsintentionally foster those sameconsequences in the name of the balance. When directive-rulesare most in evidence,agentsare situatedin a chain of command,a finn, or an organization.A sphereof influenceis a rudimentary institution of this sort. Its very infonnal rules assigneachagentto an 72 NICHOLAS ONUF office, as we would call it in a more formal organization.Officers report up the chain of commandand carry out ordersthat come down the chain. By this logic, the top officer decideswhat the organization'sfunction is. In practice, most organizationsare more complex than this. Nevertheless,a sphereof influence is so rudimentary in organizationthat its function is nothing more than to fulfill the wishes of a leading power, as top officer, over the weakerstateswithin the sphere. Finally, when commitment-rulesare most in evidence,agentsend up in partnerships,or associations,with other agents.In the institutional context of international relations, the principle of sovereigntyand the supporting rules of recognition make states into formal equals. When two or more statesadopt a treaty, they act as membersof an associationgiving them at least somerights in common, including the right to commit themselvesto eachother. Underthe termsof the treaty, all partiestake on additionalrights and duties with respectto the others. In this situation, statesare formally equal becausethey all have the samerole. The function of any association is to distributeroles to agentsthroughits commitment-rules. Only states(and the associationsthat they have createdby treaty) can adopt treaties, becausethere is a commitment-ruleassigningthis role to them exclusively. To return to an earlier example, markets function by assigning agents either of two roles---they are either sellers or buyers. Every seller is formally equalin possessingthe right to buy, and so is every buyer. Note, however,that neithersellersnor buyershave a right to a fixed price. Formally speaking,agentsin these roles are free to competewith eachother, presumablyfor the good of every agentin the association.The function of this, or any, associationis implied by the commitmentsthat agentshavemadeto a given distributionof roles. It is importantto note, however,that an association'sroles are not generally equal in the rights and duties that they create.Think, for example,of the roles that membersof most householdshave. For that matter, agents holding the samestatus(for example,white males)are equal to eachother within the terms of that status, even if different statusesare unequal in relation to each other. This is no less true for agentsholding the sameor similar offices (for example,foreign ministers).Nevertheless,commitmentrules are especially useful for making large numbersof agentsformally equalfor limited purposes. Agency consistsof statuses,offices, and roles. Dependingon the institutional context, every agent must have a status,an office, or a role. Most, perhapsall, agentshaveall threein somecombination.This is becausemost peopleare agentsin a variety of institutions,andmany institutionscombine featuresof networks,organizations,andassociations. CONSTRUCTIVISM: A USER'S MANUAL 73 Institutionssuchas theseare complex in function and structure.Instruction-, directive-, and commitment-rulesare all present,even if the proportions differ from institution to institution. Observersusually have no difficulty in picking out the patternof rules, becauseinstitutions are social arrangements that alwaysreflect agents'interests.From an observer'spoint of view, institutionshavepurposes.It seemsthis way evenif the observeris an interestedagent. A complex institution will have generalinstruction-rules,or principles, telling agentswhat the purposesof that institution are. Detailedinstructionrules may provide support for theseprinciples by spelling out all relevant statuses.Directive-rulesmay also repeatand elaborateon what theseprinciples have to say and then supportthem by demandingthat officers do what theserules say that they should. In situationswhere there are no conspicuous instruction-rulesor directive-rulessupportingprinciples, commitmentrules createroles for agentsthat have, from anyoneagent'spoint of view, the unintendedeffect of supportingthe institution'sprinciples. Rules in all three categoriesoften work together to support an institution'sprinciples. Sometimes,however,institutions developin such a way that rules from one or eventwo categoriesare scarceor not to be found at all. If we considerinternationalrelationsas taking place within a single, overarching institution, its rules constitute a conspicuouslylopsided arrangement.Thanks to the principle of sovereignty,there are few if any formal directive-rules.Observerswill discover informal directive-rulesin practice,evenif someagentsroutinely denythat suchrules exist. Consideredas a complex institution, international relations takes place in a context where agentsand observersfind a large number of formal commitment-rules(rules of international law), behind which there is an even larger number of instruction-rules.These latter rules differ enormouslyin formality (quite a few are legal rules), detail, and the degree to which they are linked to each other. They support the principle of sovereigntyand a few other principles more or less directly and effectively. Thanks again to the principle of sovereignty,statesare complex institutions within which formal directive-rulesallow agentsto act on behalfof statesin their relations. The contextwithin which any institution functions as an agentis itself an institution. Societyis a complexinstitution within which many otherrelated institutions are to be found. Agents are likely to act as if their society's boundariesare clearand accepted,evenif observers,including agents,have a hard time specifyingthoseboundariesto anyone'ssatisfaction.Statesare societiesthat have exceptionallyclear boundariesas well as highly developedinstitutionsfor conductingrelationswith otherstates. 74 NICHOLAS ONUF The complex institution within which statesfunction as relatively selfcontainedsocietiesis itself a society. Within international society, states function as primary agentssimply by conductingrelationswith eachother. Internationalsocietyincludesmany other, more or less self-containedinstitutions. Some of them add secondaryagents,such as officers of international organizations,to that society. The sum total of institutions and their relationsadd up to a societyof staggeringcomplexity and constantchange, even though its large patternsseemat least to some observersto call for generalization. Rules Yield Rule We have seenthat institutions consist of related rules and practices.It is possibleto think of a single rule as an institution. As a practicalmatter,we never find a single rule standingby itself. Every rule gives the agentsto whom it appliesthe choice of following the rule, or not, with more or less predictableconsequences. Most of the time, agentschooseto follow the rule. The patternof agents' choiceshasa generalconsequence, whetheror not it is intendedby particular agents--it has the effect of distributing material and social benefits amongagents.An extremelyimportantcategoryof such benefitsis control over resourcesand control over other agents and their activities. Some agentsbenefit more than other agents.Over time, institutions work to the advantageof someagentsat the expenseof otheragents. As rational beings,thoseagentswho benefit the most from the rules that apply to them are the most inclined to follow those rules. Agents who benefit less are still inclined to follow the rules becausedoing so still benefitsthem more than not doing so. Nevertheless,agentsmay proceedto break any given rule after weighing the consequences of either choice for themselves.As a generalconsequence, rule breakingis likely to involve a loss of benefitsto otheragents. Agentswho are negativelyaffectedby the breakingof a rule also havea choice. They may acceptthe consequences (including a weakenedfaith in the broken rule and a greaterchanceof its being broken again). Alternatively, they may chooseto follow a rule that has the consequenceof presenting the rule breakerwith a loss of benefits, which the rule breakeris either preparedto acceptor had thought would not be likely to occur. The second choice, which we think of as enforcing the rule, involves using resourcesthat might otherwisehavebeenput to beneficialuse. This loss of benefitsis still lessthanthe loss that comesfrom not enforcingthe rule. Insteadof breakinga given rule, agentswho do not benefit from follow- CONSTRUCTIVISM: A USER'S MANUAL 75 ing it may chooseto usewhateverresourcesare neededto changethat rule, and thus to changethe distribution of benefits that results from the rule's existence.If some agentstry to changethe rule, other agentswho would benefit less from the changesmay chooseto use the necessaryresourcesto keep the rule from changing. Furthermore,those agentswho benefit the most from a given rule will probably have to use fewer of the resources availableto them to keep the rule from changingthan will agentswho want to changethe rule. Clearly, rules say what they say, and institutions are slow to change, because agentsmakerational choicesin circumstancesthat alwaysgive the advantageto someagentsover others. The general consequenceof agents' respondingto rules with the resourcesavailableto them is that someagentsexercisegreatercontrol over the contentof those rules, and over their successin being followed, than other agentsdo. In other words, rules yield rule. By making agentsand society what they are, rules make rule inevitable. Rule is somethingthat agentsdo to, and for, otheragents,and they do it by following rules. Rule is somethingthat happensto agents when they follow rules or when they of not following rules. suffer the consequences Specific institutions may formalize rule by seemingto limit its exercise to a particularagentor set of agents---torulers. Justbecausewe can identify rulers, we shouldnot concludethat they alonedo the ruling. Whereverthere are informal rules (which is everywhere),there is informal rule, either supporting or undercuttingformal institutions of rule, or both (probably in a complex and hard to observepattern). Even if the formalities of rule are nowhereto be found, rule remains apervasivecondition for that society. Loadedwith rules but lacking rulers, internationalsocietyis a casein point. Rules in different functional categoriesyield different forms of rule. Where instruction-rulesare paramountand status is a defining feature of society,ideasand beliefs seemto do the ruling. Despiteappearances, agents actually do the ruling by getting other agents to accept their ideas and beliefs. They do so by exampleand by indoctrination. Rule in this form is hegemony. Any society where principles get most of their support from detailed instruction-rulesis hegemonicallyruled. Castesocietiesare examples.Each hegemonicallyruled castehas clear boundariesand a fixed position in the network of castesconstituting the society. Membership in a caste gives agentsso much of their identity, defined as a set of ideas about self and position in society, that casteidentity seemsto rule the societyas a whole. Hegemonicallyruled institutionsexist in societieswhereothersortsof institutions and a mixed form of rule can be identified. The professionsoffer an example.Detailed instruction-rules,ordinarily learnedthrough a long ap- 76 NICHOLAS ONUF prenticeship,supportprofessionalstandardsand rule agentsto their advantagein their relationswith clients needingtheir professionalservices. In institutionswheredirective-rulesare paramountandoffice is a defining feature of society, offices are vertically organizedin a chain of command. Officers at eachposition in the chain use resourcesthat their offices make availableto themto carry out the rules that their offices requirethem to carry out. From top to bottom, such an arrangementof offices is called a hierarchy, and so might we call the form of rule that resultswhen officers carry out directive-rules.The stateas a legal orderexemplifieshierarchicalrule. When directive-rulesare legal, hierarchyis formal. Despitethe minimal description of the state as a legal order, formal hierarchiesrarely stand alone.Hegemonicalideastypically reinforceformal hierarchy.The result is authority, conventionally defined as legitimate control. Military officers possessauthority accordingto their rank, which is their statusand office formally joined togetherin mutual reinforcement.Finally, informal hierarchy may reinforce hegemonythat has achieveda relatively high level of formality. After World War II, the so-calledpaxAmericanamay be thought of as a condition of rule in which the United Statesruled, in the name of freedom and prosperity, by intervening wheneverand whereverit chose. Proclaimingprinciples had the effect (perhaps initiallyunintended)of formalizing the statusof the United Statesas leaderof "the free world," while acting on thoseprinciplesgaveit an informal office. Where commitment-rulesare paramountand role is a defining featureof society, agentshold a variety of roles that are defined by referenceto the roles that otheragentshold. No one role, or institution, evencomesclose to making particularagentsinto rulers. On the contrary, formal commitmentrules mostly seemto reinforce formal hierarchy. They do so by granting officers well-definedpowersto help them issueordersand carry them out, and by granting agentswell-defined rights to help protect them from officers abusingtheir powers.The result is a constitutionalstate,in which the constitutionformalizes commitment-rulesthat limit the governmentof the stateandmakeit responsible. Takenas a whole, roles may yield rule on their own, and not just because they reinforce other forms of rule. Agents in associationare the rulers--all of them together--evenif none of them have the statusor office to make them rulers. Ruled by association,agentsdo not seerule in their roles. As agents,they are mostly concernedwith their roles and what they are free to do within them. To return once more to the exampleof a market, agents participatingin it generallyhave the sensethat this is an institution free of rule. As sellers and buyers, they are neverthelessruled as an unintended consequenceof the exerciseof their right to buy and sell. Adam Smith's CONSTRUCTIVISM: A USER'S MANUAL 77 invisible hand is a hand that rules, and it rules to the advantageof some agentsover others. As we saw, quite a few scholars describe international relations as anarchical.An anarchyis rule by no one in particular, and thereforeby everyone in association,as an unintendedconsequenceof their many, uncoordinatedacts. Recall that agentswho observea generalpattern of unintendedconsequences can no longer be said to act without intending consequences, even if they continueto act as they had beenacting. They intend to be ruled for good reasons,and if they did not have good reasons,they would makeother choices. If anarchyis a condition of rule unrelatedto any agent'sintentions, then international relations is no anarchy. We need another term to indicate the form of rule in which agentsintend that they be ruled by what seem to be unintendedconsequencesof exercising their rights. Heteronomyis a better term. Autonomousagentsact freely, while heteronomousagents cannot act freely. Both terms refer to agents, not society. From a constructivistperspective, however,agentsare always autonomous,but their autonomy is always limited by the (limited) autonomy of other agents.The exerciseof autonomy makes heteronomy a social condition, which agents accept as an apparently unintendedconsequence of their individual, autonomouschoices. International society is heteronomouslyruled becausestates exercise their independenceunder the principle of sovereigntyand under a number of commitment-rulesgranting them rights and duties with respectto each other. One state'sindependenceis a limit on every other's,and all states' agentsacceptthe unintendedconsequences that result from their many individual choices.Within this generalcondition of rule are to be found a large numberof institutionscontributingto rule in a variety of ways. Agents(and not just states' agents) constantly work on these institutions and work within them. Despitetheir numberand variety, and the complexity of their relations,they are arrangedas they are on purpose,by agents'intentions,to servetheir interests--includingtheir sharedinterestin beingruled. Note Kurt Burch, Harry Gould, and Vendulka KubaIkova persuadedme to write a concise expositionof constructivismas I had developedit in World of Our Making (1989). The result is "A ConstructivistManifesto" (Onuf 1997), which I wrote in a telegraphicstyle for a scholarly audience,introducing somenew material and leaving a great deal out. While I had plannedmy essayfor this book as a sentence-by-sentence reconstructionof the "Manifesto" for a larger audience,I ended up making quite a few substantive additionsand changes,and I deletedall of its relatively few citations. I am grateful to 78 NICHOLAS ONUF membersof the Miami InternationalRelationsGroup for their questionsand suggestions. Bibliography Onuf, Nicholas Greenwood. 1989. World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social TheoryandInternationalRelations.Columbia:University of SouthCarolinaPress. - - - . 1997. "A Constructivist Manifesto." In Constituting International Political Economy, ed. Kurt Burch and Robert A. Denemark, 7-17. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner. 4 What Is at Stake in the Agent-Structure Debate? Harry D. Gould Introduction As notedin the introductorychapterto this volume, the division of international relations (IR) into a series of debateshas becomea conventional device for making senseof the field. Beyond the "great debates,"at least three and possiblyfive in number(Wrever 1997, 12-25), two debatesare of interesthere: the "levels of analysis"debatetouchedoff by David Singerin 1961 and especially the "agent-structure"debate initiated by Alexander Wendt in 1987. Simply put, the conceptualproblem at the heart of the agent-structure debateis: How are agentsand structuresrelated?Over the course of the debate,this problem has disappearedfrom view, or, more to the point, the debateitself hasbecomeproblematic.There are severalproblems:the positions held by someof the participantshave changedover time, the terms of debatehave changed,and the serial subdebateshave becomefurther removedboth from the core issueand from IR' s substantiveconcerns. The purposeof this paperis to put Onufs constructivisminto the context of the agent-structuredebate,expandingon his contributionto this book, his book World of Our Making (1989), and several articles which have also servedto refine his position (Onuf 1994, 1995, 1996, 1997). This will entail a brief review of constructivism,as well as a detailed analysisin which I shall put constructivisminto dialoguewith the various positionsstakedout during the debate. The concluding discussionwill look at the levels of 79 80 HARRY D. GOULD analysis debatein IR, the relation of which to the agent-structuredebate formed an important part of Wendt'sseveralexchangeswith Martin Hollis and SteveSmith. Constructivism At its barest,the constructivistposition on the relation of agentsto structures is that they each constitute the other. Simultaneously,agents and structureenableand constraineachother. In itself, this advancesvery little beyondAnthony Giddens's"structurationtheory" (Giddens1979, 1984),to which Onuf is obviously indebted. The relation of constructivism to structuration is complex. Constructivism'sdebt to structuration is plain enough,but the origin andnatureof the differencesare important.The most importantdifferencelies in the indispensablerole playedby rules in Onufs constructivism.A fuller accountof structurationis to be found below; what is importantto note at the presentis that Giddens'sconcernwas to answer the question, which dominates: structure (determinism) or agency (free will)? His answer,put in the mostbasicway, is that eachshapesthe other. Both accountstake as their starting point the rejection of ontological individualism and pure ontological structuralism.As we shall see, this is true of all of the perspectivesvoiced in the debate.Both claim that agents and structuresactively and continuouslyconstituteand changeeachother. Structuration,however, lacks a fully developedmechanismcapableof explaining the meansby which agentsand structuresconstituteone another. Onuf found this mechanismin the conceptof rules, as developedin legal and linguistic philosophy.In his words: The co-constitutionof peopleas social beingsand of societyis a continuous process.Rules are central to this processbecausethey make people active participants(or agents)in society, and they give any society its distinctive character(or structure).Rules define agentsin tennsof structures,and structures in tenns of agents.... As rules changein number, kind, relation and content, they constantlyredefine agentsand structures,always in tenns of eachother. (1996, 6) For Onuf, the solution to the structurationistdilemmaof how to deal at the level of methodwith the continuous,dynamic processof co-constitution-where to cut into the process--isto "emphasizerules, but neverrules considered in a vacuum. To begin with rules simultaneouslyleads in two directions--towardagents and their choices, and toward social arrangementsthat eventuatefrom agentschoices"(Onuf 1997,8). Concomitantwith the focus on rules, andby necessitypresupposingit, is THE AGENT-STRUCTURE DEBATE 81 a focus on deeds.Deedsare responsesto and constituentsof the circumstancesin which peoplefind themselves.Peopleuselanguageboth to representtheir deedsand to perform them. Speakingis doing. Utterancesthrough which peopleaccomplishsocial endsdirectly-performdeeds-arespeech acts. Furthermore,rules take form from speechacts. Ruleslink agentsand structuresin a commonprocessof constitution,but only if rules have an ontologicalstandingappropriateto their dual function. Giddensdid not see this; he saw rules as a property of structure,not as a material property (Onuf 1996, 8--9). Rules have propertiesof their own. Languagegives rules an autonomouscharactersuited to their function; throughlanguagerules exist in their own right. "Competencewith rules is a defining featureof humancognition, and the presenceof rules is a defining featureof the humancondition" (9). According to Onuf (9-10), rules describe some class of actions and indicate whethertheseactionsconstitutewarrantedconducton the part of thoseto whom the rules are addressed.They can do this because,as stated above,rules come from performativespeech.Speechacts convey propositional contentand elicit an appropriateresponse.Becausepeoplerespondto these(speech)actswith their own performances,the patternof speechactsand their responsesmake human life intelligible. The pattern of speechacts endows practiceswith normativity, giving rise to rules. As we shall see below, this is part of the way in which we "construct"structure. As far as Giddensand Onuf are concerned,all rules are simultaneously constitutive and regulative. Rules are regulative by definition. Regulation yields constitutionas an effect. Even if a particularrule is strictly intended to regulateconduct,it will have an additional constitutiveeffect. The converseis also true: rules intendedto be only constitutivewill haveregulative consequences. Agents are, or consist of, individuals whose acts materially affect the world. Rules constitutinga societydefine the conditionsunderwhich individuals may intervenein the world. Rules make individuals into agentsby enabling them to act upon the world in which they find themselves.As shown above, these acts have material and social effects; they make the world what it is materiallyand socially. Onceconstitutedas agents,individuals intervenein the world by respondingto choicesofferedby rules. Wendt situatedthe agent-structureproblem in a debatefew scholarsin IR had encountered:the debatein philosophyof sciencebetweenpositivists and scientific realistsover the ontological statusof phenomenathat cannot be directly observed.Pure positivists refuse to considersuch phenomena, even if their effects are observable.Most scientiststake unobservablephenomena,suchas magnetism,for granted.For purposesof debate,scientific 82 HARRY D. GOULD realists attribute so much impOltance to unobservablesthat someonedipping into the debatemight be inclined to underestimatethe practicalsignificance of observablephenomena.We see this particularly in Wendt's scientific realist treatmentof structuration,in which he not only ignores Giddens's sense of the importance of rules and resources,but rejects Giddens'saccountof structurefor this very emphasis.! Above we saw that rules have an ontological status. Rules constitute themselvesin regular patternsthat mayor may not be observed,but are always observablein principle. We observea world of regularitiesupon which the mind seeks toimposeorder. The regularitiesare not themselves structures.They are better called "institutions," which is an ontologically unambiguousterm. It is through the cognitive functions of the mind that patternedregularitieshave order, or structure,imposedupon them. When agents"see"structuresandact on them, rulesand institutionsare affectedstructuresare real, evenif "structure"is not. Agents act on observableregularitiesfor the samereasonthat scientific realists attribute causal significance to unobservablestructures--tomake the world a more orderly place for instrumentalreasons.Insofar as observers imposestructureson the phenomenalworld, or perhapsmakethe world phenomenal,observersalso act as agents.This tends to give phenomenal propertiesto structures,which then createsthe feedbackloop which constructivistsand structurationistsemphasize,the patternof co-constitution. This synthetic structureimposedupon the world functions like a template. In imparting order it imputesfunction; parts are relatedto wholes. Beyond this implicit teleology, function is also ascribedto structures;we assignmeaningto what structuresdo. Theseconjoined problemsbetray an Aristotelian, teleological bias implicit in structuralism-partsare functionally related to wholes-to which both structuration and constructivism can all too easily faU prey. To avoid this, it must be remembered that structures have only those functions ascribed to them by agents;therc is nothing natural (necessary)about either structuresor the functions they perform. For this reason, structuresare perhaps better thoughtof as institutions,becausethis term more adequatelyconveysthe constitutiverole played by agents,thus avoiding the functionalist road to structuraldeterminism. Constructivismand the Agent-StructureDebate It shouldby now be plain what the constructiviststanceon issuesof agency and structureis, but to clarify at the outsetjust how this stancerelatesto the debateover agencyand structurein JR, 1makethe following claims: THE AGENT-STRUCTURE DEBATE 83 1. The agent-structureproblemraisesissuesof importanceto IR' s second debate,not (asmost scholarsseemto think) the third debate. 2. The issuescentral to the debateare primarily of method,and to an extentontological;they arenot epistemologicaL 3. Structuration theory cannot resolve the debate; it does not adequately delineatethe meansby which agentsand structuresconstitute oneanother. 4. The scientific realist focus on efficacious unobservablesdoes not addthe neededcorrective. 5. The constructivistfocus on rulesis what is needed. 6. Scientific realismis not necessaryto explainthe ontologicalstatusof rules. 7. Rules are necessaryto agency.They make statesinto agentsat the macro level in much the same fashion that they make individuals agentsat the micro leveL 8. Rules form institutions. They link agents and institutions, which mustbe accordedequalontologicalstatus. 9. Structureis in the mind's eye. Structuresexist becauseagentssee patternsto which they imputestructure. 10. Once structuresare "produced," knowledge about them takes on phenomenalproperties.They becomea propertyof institutions,any of which may function as agents. The agent-structuredebatehas been remarkablyone-sided.In IR, no selfconsciousadvocateof methodologicalindividualism has taken up the debate. The nature of agency is so neglectedthat it is misleading even to speakof an "agent-structuredebate."By and large, what we shall seeis a fight over the middle, in which eachtheoristmakesthe claim that his or her representationof the effectsthat agentsand structureshave on one another is the mostaccurateor usefuL2 In what may be reasonablycalled the prehistoryof the debate,Kenneth Waltz (1979) attackedthe rampant reductionismin the field becausethe of state behaviorproduce irreducible structures unintendedconsequences that have consequencesfor behavior. This unequivocal claim providcd Wendt an opportunity to introduce the issue of structurefrom a scientific realist point of view. If his discussionof world systemstheory seemscursory by comparison,reductionistsciencegot no attentionat alL Waltz's defenseof structural realism as good sciencelinks the agentstructuredebateto IR's seconddebate.On the face of it, the seconddebate is about method. Should IR continue to be historicist in orientation,as it had been in its first decades,or should it follow the other social 84 HARRY D. GOULD sciencesand adopt the model of positivist natural science?Many scholars believedthat all the secretsof human behavior,from individual to social, political, and economic,could be fully understoodby properapplicationof positivist methodsof inquiry. The actual debatelargely pitted the British "traditionalists,"trained in diplomatic history and law, against"scientists" from the United States. Among the latter we find a running subdebate,which has probably engagedmore intellectual energyand filled morejoumal pagesthan the second debate proper, pitting behavioralistsagainst systemicists.The behavioralistsprobably made a better claim to being "scientific" by the standardsof the day-theirorientationwas more explicitly empiricist than that of the systemicists,who came from the largely discreditedrationalist epistemologicaltradition? Ratherthan constructmodelsof the workings of unobservablestructures,the behavioralistsstudiedregularitiesof behavior. Their methodwas inductive, beginning with observationof the actionsof parts, rather than deductivelyworking out the relationsof parts in a hypothetical whole. In articulating the concept of levels of analysis, Singer (1961) tried to give both sides legitimacy, which each side acceptedfor itself but deniedto the other. Waltz overturnedthe preeminenceof the behavioralists.He placedsystemicism on top. In effect, he rejectedbrute empiricism, which had been dominant in its various forms since Hume, and the notion that knowledge progressivelyaccumulatesin the absenceof deductive theory. Waltz acof the complishedthis by treating structureas the unintendedconsequence interactions(behavior) of self-interestedactors (here, states;in the microeconomictheory he emulated,firms). Structureis observable,irreducible, efficacious.4 Wendt1987 "The Agent-StructureProblem in InternationalRelationsTheory" (Wendt 1987) is noteworthy on several counts, not least of which is that it was written when Wendt was still a graduatestudent, and it was IR's first sustainedexplorationof questionsof agencyand structure.Wendt had two purposesin this piece, first to demonstratethe inadequacyof both Waltz's version of structuralismand that of Immanuel Wallerstein, and secondto advocatestructurationtheory as a replacementfor structuralismgenerally. Wendt madethe startling claim that Waltz was, in fact, not at all the structuralist he claimed, but, to the contrary, an ontological individualist. Conversely,he found Wallerstein'sworld systemstheoryto be too holistic. In the case of Waltz's implicit individualism, Wendt claimed that the THE AGENT-STRUCTURE DEBATE 85 systemand its structureare the creationsof the states;despitethe influence exertedby the structureover the states,the statesmust, by Waltz's logic, predate(be ontoiogically prior to) the systemand its structure.Therefore, the unit exhibits a controlling influence over the structure.The exact converse is true of Wallerstein: the system both predatesand creates the states--thisis pure holism, the units derive all meaningfrom the generative structure. The problem with each position, as Wendt quite correctly asserted, is that, in each case, the ontologically prior entity is taken to be given and unproblematic. In short, Waltz has no theory of the state, Wallersteinno theoryof the system. In contrastto theseextremes,Wendt advocatedapplicationof Giddens's structurationtheory. As used by Wendt, structurationtheory incorporates the bestof both individualism and structuralism.The philosophicalfoundations for structuration,Wendt claimed,are to be found in scientific realism. Realistscan be rigorously scientific about "unobservablegenerativestructures." They are treatedas if they are real if their effects can be observed (Wendt 1987,350). The importanceof scientific realism to structurationbecomesevident when one considersthe scientific realist claim that to make an explanatory claim, it is necessaryto identifY the underlying causal mechanismsthat makean eventa necessaryoccurrence.Ifwe can explain the physicaldispositions and causalpowersof unobservableentities,we can make legitimate inferencesaboutnecessarycausalrelations(354). Having establishedwhat he takesto be the scientific realist bonafides of structuration,Wendt proceededto discussstructurationitself. His central claim on behalfof structurationis that the "capacitiesand even the existence of human agentsare in some way necessarilyrelated to a social structuralcontext-thatthey are inseparablefrom humansociality" (355). For Wendt, structurationtheory is analyticalin nature,not substantive;it is what he would later call metatheory--atheoryabouttheory. It addresses the typesof entitiesto be found in the socialworld and their relations. Wendtoffered four core claims on behalfof structurationtheory: 1. In oppositionto individualists, structurationistsacceptthe reality and explanatoryimportanceof irreducible and potentially unobservablesocial structuresthat generateagents. 2. In oppositionto structuralists,structurationistsopposefunctionalism that and stress"the needfor a theory of practicalreasonand consciousness canaccountfor humanintentionalityandmotivation." 3. Theseoppositionsare reconciledby joining agentsand structuresin a "dialectical synthesis"that overcomesthe subordinationof one to the other, 86 HARRY D. GOULD which is characteristicof both individualismand structuralism. 4. Finally, structurationistsargue that social structuresare inseparable from spatialandtemporalstructures,and that time and spacemusttherefore be incorporateddirectly and explicitly into theoreticaland concretesocial research(Wendt 1987,356). Although structuration is Giddens'sterm, Wendt relied more heavily on the work of Roy Bhaskar(1979), undoubtedlybecauseBhaskarwas more explicitly scientific realist in orientationthan Giddens.This is reflected in their respectiveconceptionsof social structure. For Giddens, structureis conceptualizedin termsof rules and resources,while Bhaskartreatedstructure in realist terms, as unobservablebut still causallyefficacious (Wendt 1987,357,note 57). Following Bhaskar,Wendt definedstructurein generativeterms as a set of internally related elements(agents,units). Becausethese elementsor agentsare internally related,they cannotbe defined or conceivedindependently of their position within the structure.This translatesto a view of the statesystemwhereinstatesare viewed in relational terms. They are constituted by the internal relations of individuation and penetration.Statesare thus not conceivableas states,apartfrom their position in a global structure of individuatedand penetratedpolitical authority. States,thus, are not conceivableas suchoutsideof their positionin the internationalsystem(357). As a set of possibletransformations,social structuresarenot reducibleto the relations between the structure'selements. Structuresmake a given combinationof elementspossible,but they are not limited to the combinations that have already manifestedthemselves.Becausesocial structures generateagentsand their behavior, and becausethey have observableeffects, we can claim that they are real entities despitebeing quite possibly unobservable(357). Dessler1989 Two yearsafter Wendt'scelebratedessayappeared,anotheryoung scholar, David Dessler,published"What's at Stakein the Agent-StructureDebate?" (1989) in the samejournal. It is not clear what motivatedDessierto substitute the term debatefor problem, which is the term Wendt used. There is little easily construedas "debate"before the Wendt, and Hollis, and Smith exchangesbeginningin 1991. DessleraddressedWendt only at one point, and then only parentheticallyin a footnote, which will be discussedbelow. The changewas,however,prescient. For Dessler,the root of the agent-structuredebatelies in the recognition THE AGENT-STRUCTURE DEBATE 87 of humanagencyas the only force behindactions,events,and outcomesof the social world; human agencycan be realized, however, only within a structure.Thus, while the needexiststo acknowledgethe powersof agents, we mustconcurrentlyrecognizethe causalrelevanceof structuralfactors. In Dessler'sconception,"all social action presupposessocial structure, and vice versa. An actor can only act socially becausethere exists a social structure to draw on, and it is only through the actions of agents that structureis reproduced"(Dessler1989,452). For reasonssimilar to Wendt's,Desslerwas critical of Waltz's approach. Desslercalled the ontology of Waltz's structural realism "positional" becausethe system'sstructureresults from the positioning of ontologically prior units. The systemis, as discussedabove,the productof the unintended of interactingunits. Desslercounteredthis with his own transconsequences formational ontology. To do so, he too relied on scientific realism, which, on his reading,holds that a theory'sexplanatorypower is derived from the richncss of its ontology. Central to this transformationalontology are the following two claims. First, structureboth enablesand constrainsthe possibilities for agent actions, and, second,structureis both medium and outcomeof agentaction. In both claims, he is well in line with structurationist andconstructivistthought. For scientific realists,the structural approachto international relations starts with the recognition that state action is possibleonly if the instruments of action exist to carry it out. Dessleridentified two such instruments: resourcesand rules. Resourcesare material capabilities. Rules he defined as "the media through which action becomepossibleand which action itself reproducesand transforms"(1989, 467). Desslerfurther identifies two typesof rules. Regulativerules prescribeand proscribebehaviorin particular circumstances;constitutiverules createtypes of behavior. In practice, however,the regulativehave constitutiveimplications,and vice versa (453-56). It is interestingto note at this point that Desslerand Onuf concurrently made rules ontologically central to the agent-structurerelation, although Dnuf did so without embracingscientific realism. Furthermore,"What's at Stakein the Agent-StructureDebate?"and World of Our Making cameout nearly simultaneously,althoughthe authorswere unawareof one another's efforts. In Dessler'stransformationalontology, rules are the material conditions of action, which agentsappropriateandthroughwhich action reproducesor transforms.Structureis a mediumof activity that in principle can be altered throughactivity. Any given action will reproduceor transformsomepart of the social structure.Social action is both a productand a by-product.This 88 HARRY D. GOULD ontology groundsconsiderationof rules not only by making their existenee explicit, but also by providing a useful model of how they exist in relation to agentsand structures(458-66). Dessler specifically addressedWendt's paper only with respect to Wendt'sinterpretationof scientific realism. On this crucial conceptualpoint [the realist definition of structureas "the social fonns that preexistaction"], Wendt misinterpretsthe scientific realist understandingof structure.... Wendttilts toward a structuraldetenninismin his analysis of the relation between state and system, conceptualizingthe stateas an effect of the internaJly related elementscomprisingstructure.... According to scientific realism, agentsand structuresare not "two moments of the sameprocess"but "radicaJlydifferent kinds of thing." (Dessler1989, 452, note45, quoting Bhaskar1979,42) Wendt 1991 Wendt's 1991 pieeeis an extendedreview essayofOnufs book, World of Our Making (1989), and Hollis and Smith's book, Explaining and UnderstandingInternationalRelations(1990). In the courseof this essay,Wendt reiteratedsome aspectsof the position he took in his 1987 paper.He was largely approvingof Onuf for his relianceon Giddens,but more critical of Hollis and Smith. Wendt'sprimary criticism of Hollis and Smith's work is that they conflate the levels of analysisproblemwith the agent-structureproblem.Wendt went back to Singer for his formulation of the former: "Levels of analysis had to do with determining which level of social aggregationoffers the most promise for building theories" (Wendt 1991,387).What Wendt felt Hollis and Smith importantly overlook is that, regardlessof the level, the same unit of analysis is utilized as the dependentvariable: the foreign policy of states.As formulatedby Hollis and Smith, the phenomenonto be explainedchangeswith the level. First, it is the behaviorof states,then the behaviorof the system(387-S8). This is, for Wendt, an ontological problem with methodological implications. The questionseemsto be whetherthe propertiesor behaviorof one unit at one level of analysiscan be reducedto thoseof another.Nevertheless,Wendt thought that methodologicalargumentsabout individualism and holism are really about agencyand structure,not about analytic practices. The efforts of Hollis and Smith to defend structural realism as an exemplarof holistic theory at the systemiclevel of analysisare surprising (or so Wendt thought), since they argueat severalpoints that international society containstoo few constitutive rules and collective forms of life to THE AGENT-STRUCTURE DEBATE 89 sustaina truly social or constitutiveanalysisof stateaction. While questioning whether international society is developedenough to support a holistic worldview, they continueto endorsestructuralrealism'sclaim to do just that. Hollis andSmith1991 Hollis and Smith usedtheir reply to Wendt'sreview article to critique his and Dessler'sstructurationistpositions,the scientific realism underpinning them, and the radical ontological individualism associatedwith Jon Elster, not articulatedelsewherein this debate.This is done in the context of a warningaboutfollowing "gurus"-here,Giddens,Bhaskar,andElster. Hollis and Smith were particularly suspiciousof Wendt's version of structurationtheory, which they likened to trying to find the correctproportions of agentand structureto blend. "Agents and structuresdo not blend easily in any proportions,and the solutionstend to be unstable"(Hollis and Smith 1991,393).They contendedthat structurationcomplicatesthe problem by employing both structural relations betweenunits which are not necessarilyhuman,and hermeneuticconceptsthe referentsof which must be human.For them, structurationis more an ambition than an established body of theoreticalachievements(405--6). In advocatingclarity aboutthe termsepistemology,ontology,andmethodology, which they found lacking in Wendtand Dessier,Hollis and Smith identifY three sets of questions: ontological, epistemological,and methodological. There are three ontological questions:Is there a real-world difference in what it is to which the systems-termsand the unit-terms refer? How do systemsrelate to units? Is the sharedreferent primarily that of systemsterms or unit-terms?They also identifY a basic epistemologicalquestion: How are statementsabout internationalrelationsknown to be true or false? The methodologicalissue questionswhat forms of explanationor understandingare to be attempted,and how they are to be achieved.Thereis no disputeamongall partiesto the debatethat all threekinds of questionsare involved in the debate.The disputeis over which questionor questionsare primary; as Hollis and Smith saw it, empiricists favor epistemology,and scientific realistsfavor ontology (1991,394). Hollis and Smith claimed that Wendt focused on theoretically interdependententitieswithout any self-evidentway to conceptualizethe entities or their relations, which yields the ontological problem of knowing how many entitiesthereare and what their relationsare. In responseto Wendt's claim that Hollis and Smith conflatethe levels of analysisand agent-structure problems,they askedwhetheranalysisshouldproceedfrom systemto unit, or vice versa, but pointed out that this is not automatically reducible to 00 HARRY D. GOULD ontology. Foreshadowingtheir responseto Walter Carlsnaesand their later exchangewith Vivienne Jabri and StephenChan,Hollis and Smith claimed that the ontologicaljustification of a theory is connectedto its explanatory merits, which is an epistemologicalissue. Wendt1992 In a rejoinder, Wendt maintainedthat Hollis and Smith conflatedtwo (presumably)distinct problems,and he disputedtheir interpretationof Waltz. It is this secondpoint which defines this exchange.Hollis and Smith imply, he claimed,that therecan be only one typeof systemictheory, that of Waltz and microeconomics.All else is reductionism. Wendt refused the choice betweenreductionismand systemicism.He arguedthat the idea of systemic theory shouldbe broadenedto include a concernwith the processof identity and interest formation which should not be treated as exogenous(as per Waltz). This led him to argueagain for the distinctivenessof the levels of analysisproblemand the agent-structureproblem(Wendt 1992a, 181). The structural realist attitude toward causationat the systematiclevel was, in Wendt's opinion, too behavioralist. Waltz did not claim that the system shapesstates,but ratherthat statesare exogenouslyself-interested.What is affectedby the systemis their behavior. For Wendt, the central issue dividing individualists and holists is whetherit is the propertiesof actorsor their behaviorthat can be reducedto structural determinants.Here Waltz seemsto be a holist, but, becausehe treated the identity and interestsof statesas exogenous,rather than as a "socially constructedfunction of interaction,"and did not thereforeaddress how these interestsare produced,he is, in fact, an individualist. It is this inconsistencyin Waltz which allowed Hollis and Smith to reducethe question of systemiccausationto the questionof whetherthe internationalsystem conditionsthe behaviorof states.They thus reducedthe agent-structure problemto the levelsof analysisproblem(Wendt 1992a,182-83). Wendt saw two answersto the questionof how to explain the actionsof statesif they cannotbe reducedto the anarchicalsystem.The holistic position is particularly interesting to Wendt. In such a view, identities and interestsare constructedby a processof interactionwithin anarchy(1992b). If they were lesswed to a behavioralistvocabulary,Waltz, as well as Hollis and Smith, would see this. The difference, according to Wendt, is that a world in which thesevariablesare exogenous--orare not variable-isnecessarily one where the patternsof interaction do not change. In Waltz's language,the ordering principle does not change;anarchy is therefore an inescapablefeature of international life. If identity and interests are re- THE AGENT-STRUCTURE DEBATE 91 gardedas capableof change,then the natureof internationallife can similarly change(1992a,183). RoUisand Smith 1992 Answering Wendt, Hollis and Smith contendedthat a holist needconcede nothing in recognizingstatesas self-interested.A holist would only needto add that theseinterestsare shapedby the system,becausea holist considers the systemthe sourceof what matters.However,sucha top-downexplanation does need some kind of mechanismto explain the means by which agentscontributeto the process,even if only in ways limited by the system (Hollis and Smith 1992, 187). Although Wendt thoughthe was speakingonly aboutthe levels-of-analysis problem, his argumentpresupposesa stanceon the agent-structureproblem. This is becauseboth levels of analysis involve questionsabout agency-not just abouthow to explainbehavior,but also aboutwhat it meansto be an actor. The latter questionis necessarilycentralto the agent-structureproblem.Therefore, asHollis andSmith reiterated,the two cannotbe separated. Carlsnaes1992 In "The Agency-StructureProblem in Foreign Policy Analysis" (1992), Carlsnaesclaimed that the problem can be overcome.He warned against solutions of the problem which make either agentsor structuresthe sole ontological primitive, and then attemptto explain the otherby reductionto it. On this point he, Wendt, Dessler,and Onuf are, at least in principle, in agreement.Reducingeach one to the other tends to rule out the interplay identified by structurationand constructivism.Since neither structuresnor actors remain constantover time, good social theory must be able to account for social changeas a dynamic phenomenon,in respectof which, neither factor "determines"the other, but both are independentvariables linked in a "temporalprocess."He felt that Giddens(and anyonefollowing in his footsteps)had failed to capturethe dynamic interplaybetweenagents and structures.For Giddens,the two merely presupposeone another.Each is irrcducibleto the other,but they are still conflated. To overcomethe problemof conflation,Carlsnaesfound a new "guru" in MargaretArcher. From Archer, Carlsnaesborrowedthe term morphogenesis. As used by Archer and Carlsnaes,morphogenesiscontrasts with structuration.Accordingto Archer: The emergentpropertieswhich characterizesocio-culturalsystemsimply discontinuity between interactionsand their product, the complex system. In turn this invites analytical dualism when dealing with structureand action. 92 HARRY D. GOULD Action of course is ceaselessand essentialboth to the continuation and further elaborationof the system,but subsequentinteractionwill be different from earlier action becauseconditioned by the structural consequencesof that prior action. Hencethe morphogeneticperspectiveis not only dualistic but sequential,dealing in endlesscycles--of structural conditioning/social interaction/structuralelaboration--thusunraveling the dialectical interplay betweenstructure and action. (Carlsnaes1992,259,quoting Archer 1982, 458; emphasisin original) The analytic strategyat work involvesuncoveringthe morphogeneticcycles that can be analytically broken into intervals in order to penetraterelations betweenstructureand action. This representsfor Carisnaesthe core to the solution of the epistemologicalpart of the problem (Carisnaes1992, 259). This solution is predicated,however,on two ontological assumptions.The first is that "structure logically pre-datesthe action(s) which transformit," and the secondis that "structural elaboration logicallypost-datesthose actions." Sucha position is strongly in contrastto the structurationistposition, which views structure and structurationas processbut not product (Carlsnaes1992,259, quoting Archer 1982,468). The rationalebehindmorphogenesisis that structural factors logically predateand postdateany action affecting them; and that action logically predatesand postdatesthe structural faetors conditioning it. This encapsulatesthe ontological notion of a continuouscycle of action-structureinteractions. Hollis and Smith 1994 Returningto the debate,Hollis and Smith felt that Carlsnaesfailed to overcome the agent-structureproblemmerely by allowing for time as a variable ("adding a dash of diachronics")(Hollis and Smith 1994, 244). For them, one cannotsettle an ontological problem without worrying aboutthe more fundamental epistemologicalone. They identified two presumptionsat work in Carlsnaes'spiece. First, Carlsnaesassumedthat agentsand structurescan be placedon the sameontologicalfooting, as if they were distinct objects in the social world. He then assumedthat their relation is one of causal conditioning (Hollis and Smith 1994, 244). In effect, Carlsnaes claimed to solve the agent-structureproblem by treating agentsand structuresas if they take turnsaffecting the social world. For Hollis and Smith, morphogenesisis no solution. If Giddensis to be criticized for conflating agentsand structuresat any given time, how does addingtime as a variable help? How doesit help to judge rival accountsof agentsand structuresover time? (247-50). Furthermore,Carlsnaeswent too far in claiming that ontology is para- THE AGENT-STRUCTURE DEBATE 93 mount; it does affect what can be acceptedepistemologically,but importantly, the reverseis also true. "[E]pistemology can only be secondaryif you arc unpuzzledby what is a cause."If one is unclearas to what constitutes a cause, then one's position on epistemologyis similarly unclear (250-51). Carlsnaescan only have claimed to have resolved the agentstructureproblem becausehe is, in Hollis and Smith'sterminology,a resolute "interpretivist," for whom issuesof causalityare distinctly secondary. In 1994, Wendt publishedan article that is not directly relevant to the agent-structuredebate, but, like his immensely influential "Anarchy Is What StatesMake of It" (Wendt 1992b),is professedlyconstructivist.Both piecesevince a drift toward structuralism,and an avoidanceof the role of rules in the co-constitutionof agentsand structures.Wendt (1992b) turned insteadto symbolic interactionismas an explanationfor the constructionof collective identity. Still wed to a realist philosophyof science,Wendt has yet to confront the fact that symbolic interactionismis rootedin an antithetical tradition, pragmatism.5 Jabr; and Chan 1996; Hollis and Smith 1996 This latestphaseof the debateis particularly unhelpful, especiallythe confused piece by Jabri and Chan, which takes the debatein new and unproductiveepistemologicaldirections. Jabri andChanfelt that any critical post-positivistIR necessarily requires abandoningcriteria for "universal epistemologicallegitimacy" in favor of focusing on ontological claims. Jabri and Chan claimedto follow Giddens in granting the primacy of ontology. They also claimed that "an assumed universalistepistemologynegatesdifference"(1996, 107; emphasisin original). In their view, Giddens's"duality of structure"expressesnot causality, but relationsof mutual constitution.Structurationis an attemptto showhow agentsand structuresare mutually constitutive. In this conception(as we have seenso many times before),action is meaningfulonly in terms of its relations to structure,just as structure is definitionally dependentupon agentsandtheir actions. With regard to Hollis and Smith's claim that epistemologymust be regardedas beingof equalimportanceto ontology,Jabri and Chanconcluded that, for Hollis and Smith, thereis only one correctepistemology.They also concludedthat such a position does violence to difference (109-10). In response,Hollis and Smith accusedJabri and Chan of misconstruingthe relationship betweenepistemologyand ontology in their "discussion of what is a cause"(1996, Ill). They never said that epistemologywas as important as ontology, merely that, contra Giddens, Wendt, Dessler,and 94 HARRY D. GOULD Carlsnaes,it does matter. Any ontology that assertsitself without establishing what it holds as standardsof epistemologicalwarrant is, for them, meredogma(Ill). For Hollis and Smith, epistemologymatters becauseontological disputes can almost never be solved by "direct appealto how the world is." Each side in a dispute must give reasonsfor believing what it does. To make senseof the world, they claim, we needan ontology, an epistemology, and a methodology.This has, however,nothing to do with questions of whetheragentsand structuresare causallylinked (112). Appearing too late for the complete assessmentit deservesin these pagesis RoxanneDoty's highly critical review of the agent-structuredebate from a post-structuralperspective(1997). For Doty, the generalproblem is that scientific realism, "which either explicitly or implicitly underpinsthe various 'solutions' to the agent-structureproblem, remains wedded to an essentialistnotion of structure" (366). Attempts to make rules "the basic constitutiveelementsof structures"illustrate the problem becauseconnectingrules to structuredisconnectsthem from "the intersubjective understandingsof agentsin their immediate and local practices" (371). Doty's critique makesno mention ofOnufs constructivistemphasison rules as having an independentontological basis.If indeedscientific realism is the problem, Onufs version of constructivismoffers a solution that Doty should find appealing,becauseit affirms (as she does) the importance of practice.It also insists that practicealways takes place in a ruled context (a reality that her emphasison the "play" of practice neglects). While Doty's conceptionof practicewould seemto deny agentsan ontological statusin their own right, at least she has broughtagencyback into the debate. If individualists and post-structuralistswere capableof talking to each other, at leastthey would agreethat scientific realism'spreoccupationwith structural properties is the problem with the agent-structuredebate. Instead, participants in the debate toss around philosophical terms that bounce off their targets like defective grenades.Hollis and Smith seem generally to have meant "methodology"when they talked about "epistemology," and the "interpretivism" they seeaboutthem is merelya methodological responseto the difficulties in observing complex relations of causality.If Jabri and Chan are right about the epistemologicalconsensus underlying the debate(they are, as Doty more successfullydemonstrates), then the ontological issuesthey pursueare besidethe point. From a poststructuralpoint of view, thereis literally nothing to debate. THE AGENT-STRUCTURE DEBATE 95 Levels of Analysis The relationship of the levels-of-analysisdebateto the agent-structuredebatehas beena running themein this chapter.While neverdirectly entering the agent-structurefray, Onufs 1995 article, "Levels," may be considered an oblique entry. As we have seen, when behavioralistsand systemicists took sideson levels of analysis,they placedthe issue squarelywithin IR's seconddebatt}-theontological debatebetweenpositivists and historicists. The positivist focus on units as positivities brings the discussionof levels back to its ontological core, an effort well servedby analyzingthe relation betweenlevels and social constructionsas an ontologicalissue. It is essentialto note at the outsetthat all positivities are always simultaneously parts and wholes. A level is the imputed demarcationat which a whole ceasesto be relevantas such, and becomesa part. By necessity,the conversemust be true. Before exploring the meansby which this comes about, let us look more closely at the assertionthat parts are wholes, and vice versa. Any given positivity, any thing, a whole, is composedof parts, each of which is further composedof smallerparts. In this respect,we seethat these (initial) parts are also wholes. This regressioncan hypothetically continue ad infinitum. Returning to the original positivity, which we had initially treatedas a whole, we see that it too is a part of a larger whole, which is part of a yet larger whole, again conceivablyad infinitum. Any object can thus be seenas part or whole, as well as being seenas part and whole. Even the individual as a social being is reducible,althoughthe relations of partsare no longersocial nor the being herself.Every whole is composed of many parts, which are the units of analysisof one discipline, while the aggregationis the unit of interest to the first. Further, there will be yet anotherdiscipline for which the initial aggregation/wholeis the unit/part. This is the great insight of Comteanpositivism: wholes are systematically stratified into levels, and discretefields of study occupythe spacesbetween levels. As has been said of structures,levels are methodologicalcontrivances, templatesimposedby the observerto order the world for instrumentalpurposes.As such,they haveno phenomenalexistenceuntil they are contrived. Onuf identified two meansby which levels are constructed,identified respectivelywith Comteanpositivism and Kantian historicism, and linked to the Aristotelian conceptionof parts and wholes. "[W]holes have like attributes defining them as parts; parts have continuousand limited relations defining them as a whole" (1995,50). 96 HARRY D. GOULD The positivist method (which is linked to the first part of Aristotle's conception)revolvesaroundthe stipulationof a criterion for membershipin one level that clearly setsit apart from that of adjacentlevels. The focus is on attributes. "All positivities possessingthat attribute are deemedalike; they and only they qualify as parts in the whole; the whole and the space thus createdare effectively the same"(50). Onufs secondmethod focuses on relations rather than attributes. ImmanuelKant distinguishedrelationsof causalityand relationsof community; in this Kantian schema,relationsof causalityare unidirectional,while those of community are reciprocal.For Kant, causalrelations take place between wholes,while relationsof communitytake placebetweenparts(51). However,as explainedabove,all wholesare also partsof greaterwholes. This causesan apparentparadox, since as both parts and wholes, they should engage in relations both causal and communal, which is (stipulatively) nonallowable. The operational question is to determine wherecommunalrelationsend andcausalrelationsbegin. In the instanceof social relations, a constructivistseestheseboundariesas createdby rules. "Rules work to make some relations more consistentlycausal in pattern than would otherwisebe the case"(52). At the level of the social, rules empowerindividuals to act-to become agents. Such rules are responsiblefor demarcatinglevels in the social realm. "Each level containssetsof rules and arrangementsthat include as parts all of thosesetsof rules and arrangementsin the level beneath"(52). Whether one choosesthe Comteanpositivist formulation or the Kantian historicist formulation, it is importantto note that both are appropriateways to study social construction. With regard to the distinctnessof the levels of analysis and the agentstructureproblems,it should by now be clear that for a constructivist, in agreementwith Hollis and Smith's assertions,the questionof the primacy of agentsand structuresis repeatedat eachunit The agentis the part. The structure is the whole. At the next level of analysis, the original structure/wholeis now the agent/part,while at the next level down, the original agent/partis now the relevantstructure/whole.Bearing this in mind, however, the determinationof the degreeof structuralconstraintimposedupon the agentis still left to be determined,or, in line with constructivistthought, the co-constitutionof agentsand structuresis still thereto be observed. Conclusion From a constructivistpoint of view, agentsand structuresmake eachother real. They do so throughrulesthat are real becauseagentsmakethoserules, THE AGENT-STRUCTURE DEBATE 97 know what they are, and generallychooseto follow them. The agent-structure debate arose becausestructure is not observableas such, and especially becausethe idea that the unintendedconsequencesof agents' conscious choicescanhave an efficaciousstructureseemsdoubly removedfrom reality. In this context,Onufs increasingaversionto the term stroctureand his effort to show that agents,as statusholders, officers, and role occupants, always act in institutional settings,may be construedas an effort to keep thingsreal. Are rules real enough?Can social sciencedo without the concept of structure?What are we to make of the "institutional turn" now so much in evidencein several disciplines?These are questionsthat might bring the agent-structuredebatebackto earth. Notes I thank Nick Onuf for patiently reading multiple drafts, and Archie Arghyrou, John Clark, Lourdes Cue, Heidi Hobbs, Vendulka Kubalkova, Dario Moreno, Ellie Schemenauer, and John Woolridgefor supportand criticism. I. "Giddens indicates that he also acceptsa realist conceptionof science,but his realism is generally less explicit and thus more attenuatedthan Bhaskar's. A more important reasonfor relying on Bhaskarrather than Giddens, however, is the latter's weakerconceptionof social structureas rules and resourcesrather than as a set of real but unobservableinternal relations"(Wendt 1987,357,note 57). 2. I am grateful to Paul Kowert for this astuteobservation. 3. On this matter,Hollis (1995,chaps.2-3) is particularly useful. 4. On the matter of unintendedconsequences, cf Waltz (1979, chaps. 3, 5) with Hollis (1987,47-58). 5. For discussionof the tensions between scientific realism and pragmatism,see Bhaskar(1991). Thesetensionsare further discussedin Hollis (1994). Bibliography Archer, Margaret. 1982. "StructurationversusMorphogenesis:On CombiningStructure and Action." British Journal ofSociology33 (December):455-83. Bhaskar,Roy. 1979. The Possibilityc:f Naturalism. Brighton: Harvester. - - - . 1991. Philosophyand the Idea ofFreedom.Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Carisnaes,Walter. 1992. "The Agency-StructureProblem in Foreign Policy Analysis." InternationalStudiesQuarterly 36 (September):245-70. Dessler,David. 1989. "What's at Stake in the Agent-StructureDebate?"International Organization43 (Summer):441-73. Doty, Roxanne Lynn. 1997. "Aporia: A Critical Exploration of the Agent-Structure Problematiquein InternationalRelationsTheory." EuropeanJournal c:lInternational Relations3 (September):365-92. Giddens,Anthony. 1979. The Central Problemsin Social Theory: Action, Structureand Contradiction in SocialAnalysis.'BerkeleyandLos Angeles:University of California Press. 98 HARRY D. GOULD - - - . 1984. The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Theory of Structuration. Berkeleyand Los Angeles:University of California Press. Hollis, Martin. 1987. The CunningofReason.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press. - - - . 1994. The Philosophyof Social Science:An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. - - - . 1995. Reasonin Action: Essaysin the Philosophy of Social Science.Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press. - - - , and SteveSmith. 1990. Explainingand UnderstandingInternationalRelations. Oxford: ClarendonPress. - - - and - - - . 1991. "Beware of Gurus: Structure and Action in International Relations."ReviewofInternationalStudies17 (October):393-410. - - - and- - - . 1992. "Structureand Action: FurtherComment."Reviewof International Studies18 (April): 187-88. - - - and - - - . 1994. "Two Stories About Structure and Agency." Review of InternationalStudies20 (July): 241-51. - - - and - - - . 1996. "A Response:Why EpistemologyMatters in International Theory." ReviewofInternationalStudies22 (January):111-16. labri, Vivienne, and StephenChan. 1996. "The Ontologist Always Rings Twice: Two More StoriesAbout Structureand Agency in Reply to Hollis and Smith." Reviewof InternationalStudies22 (January):107-10. Onuf, Nicholas Greenwood. 1989. World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social Theoryand InternationalRelations.Columbia: University of SouthCarolinaPress. - - - . 1994. "The Constitution of InternationalSociety." EuropeanJournal of International Law 5: 1-19. - - - . 1995. "Levels." EuropeanJournal of International Relations I (March): 3558. - - - . 1996. "Rules, Agents, Institutions: A ConstructivistAccount." Working Papers on International Societyand Institutions 96-92. Global Peaceand Conflict Studies at University of California, Irvine. - - - . 1997. "A Constructivist Manifesto." In Constituting International Political Economy, ed. Kurt Burch and Robert A. Denemark, 7-17. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner. Singer,1. David. 1961. "The Level-of-Analysis Problem in International Relations." World Politics 14 (October):77-92. Wa!ver, Ole. 1997. "Figures of International Thought: Introducing PersonsInsteadof Paradigms."In The Future of International Relations: Masters in the Making, ed. Iver B. Neumannand Ole Wa!ver, 1-37. London: Routledge. ---.1979. TheoryofInternational Politics. Reading,MA: Addison-Wesley. Waltz, KennethN. 1979. TheoryofInternational Politics. Reading,MA: Addison-Wesley. Wendt, Alexander. 1987. "The Agent-StructureProblemin InternationalRelationsTheory." InternationalOrganization41 (Summer):335-70. - - - . 1991. "Bridging the Theory/Meta-TheoryGap in InternationalRelations."Review ofInternationalStudies17 (October):383-92. - - - . I 992a. "Levels of Analysis vs. Agents and Structures: Part III." Review of InternationalStudies18 (April): 181-85. - - - . I 992b. "Anarchy Is What StatesMake of It: The Social Constructionof Power Politics." InternationalOrganization46 (Spring): 391--425. - - - . 1994. "Collective Identity Formation and the International State." American Political ScienceReview88 (June):384-96. ________ PartIII International Relations Under Construction This page intentionally left blank 5 Agent versus Structure in the Construction of National Identity Paul Kowert But how will eachsingle individual succeedin incorporating himselfinto the collectiveman, and how will educativepressure be appliedto single individuals so as to obtain their consent and their collaboration, turning necessity and coercion into 'Jreedom"? Antonio Gramsci(1971,242) How can nation-statesmade up of citizens whose interestsmight diverge sharplychooseforeign (or any other) policiesto servethepublic good?This problem of collective action, and the related problem of how statesthemselvescan cooperate,dominatesinternationalrelations.It animates debates over whetherwar can serve a general interest or only particular interests (munitions producers,for example),or whetherlower barriersto trade are good for the whole country or only for some groups within it (perhaps favoring importersover domesticproducersand laborers). The collective action problemalso lies at the heartof disagreements over whetheror not internationalrelationscan be a positive sum game (Grieco 1988). As AlexanderWendt argues,many of the contortionsto which both neorealistand neoliberal theoriesare forced to subjectthemselvesas they addressthis problemare madenecessaryby their failure to offer an account of national (or other actor) identity and interests. Instead, "they either bracketthe formation of interests,treating them as if they were exogenous, or explain interestsby referenceto domesticpolitics, on the assumptionthat 101 102 PAUL KOWERT they areexogenous"(Wendt 1994,384).Becausetheseapproachesincorporate no theory of national identity or collective interest formation, they cannot explain collective behavior by referring to collective goals. They must focus, instead,on the mechanismsthat allow rationally egoisticagents to integrate their goals. To explain intemational cooperation,neorealists might look to hegemonyor coercionfor incentivesthat restrain the ambitions of particularnations. Neoliberalslook insteadeither to the "shadow" of future interactionor to the coordinatingrole of institutionssuchas international regimesthat reducetransactioncosts.Neither approachenvisions collective ambitions grounded in a common political identity (although neoliberalism'spositive-sumview of internationalrelationsat least admits to the possibility). In opposition to the individualism and rationalism of such approaches (which eitherdenycollective identitiesor treattheir formation as exogenous and usually imposed), Wendt offers the rival claim that state identity is endogenousto structuredinteractionamongstates.Drawing on integration theory and some versions of interpretivist scholarship(see Chapter 1), Wendt proposesthat the structural context of state interaction, systemic factors such as interdependence and the transnationalconvergenceof domestic values,and even the manipulationof symbolsin the strategicpractice of rational agentsall contributeto the formation of collective identities. To put this more plainly, Wendt points out that: (1) states often share interpretationsof their environment (e.g., as "Cold War," "detente," or "new world order"); (2) statesdependon each other, at least in part, for someof theseinterpretations(e.g., a commonfate might encouragea common identity); and (3) the strategicinteractionof statesfurther contributes to sharedunderstandings(1994, 389-91). Each of these relationshipsbetweenstatesnot only shapesbehaviorbut also shapesthe self·understanding of the agentsinvolved. Thus, Wendt concludes,neorealistsand neoliberalsare not constrained--asthey have themselvesgenerallyassumed--totreat collective identity and interestsas exogenous.Many of the processeson which they alreadyfocus shapeidentity. Yet one neednot makethe dualistic assumptionthat identity must either be given intrinsically (and determinedexogenously)as an actor propertyor else be determinedby the social structuresof the environmentthat actors inhabit. The first approachis broadly rationalist (assumingintrinsic preferencesand constantidentities) and ontoiogically naturalist(ignoring collec· tive interpretation).The secondapproachis dynamic (becauseit permits identity to change)and ontologically interpretivist (insisting that material and social reality are always the product of collective interpretation).But what these two approachesshare is structuralism (for discussionsof THE CONSTRUCTION OF NATIONAL IDENTITY 103 structuralismin internationalrelations,seeAshley 1984; Dessler1989; and Wendt 1987). The first approachassumesthat the structuresof international politics constrainstatebehavior; the seeondarguesthat internationalstructuresaffect both behaviorand identity. Neorealistand neoliberal theoriesordinarily focus on the material determinantsof structuresuch as the distribution of physical,technological,geographical, or other material determinantsof power. Even when discussing suchintangiblesas political ideologyand identity, neorealistsand neoliberals take care to trace ideas to an underlying physical reality (see,for example, Goldsteinand Keohane1993). The intersubjectivestructuresto which Wendt refers,on the otherhand,aremore broadly defined.They leave"room for the emergenteffects of material capabilities" but consist themselves"of the sharedunderstandings,expectations,and social knowledgeembeddedin international institutions and threat complexes"(Wendt 1994, 389). In both cases,however,identity is shaped(to the extentit is malleable)by structural constraintsand incentives.Such argumentsde-emphasizethe ways the behavior of agents within structuresshapesidentity (although Wendt's description of strategicinteractionamong statesis a partial exception; 1994, 390-91).While Wendt'scritique of materialrationalismis a valuableontological corrective, it pays less attention than it might to the active role peopleand nationsplay in the fabricationof their own political identities. This chapter will offer no defenseof the proposition that theories of political identity are a useful things to have (see Katzenstein1996; Lapid andKratochwil 1996; andLegro 1996). That much, it assumes,is evidentin light of the way competition to define identity currently plays (and has always played) a prominent role in both domestic and international conflicts. The next section will examine the contribution constructivismand psychologicaltheoriesof social identification can togethermake to an account of nationalidentity. It arguesthat, in concert,they yield an accountof national identity that explainschanginginterestsand foreign policy behavior and that more fully appreciatesthe role national leadersplay in forging national identities. The remainderof this chapterillustrates this synthetic approachto nationalidentity by examiningthe evolution of British attitudes toward Egypt prior to and during the Suezcrisis. From Agency to Identity Constructivism(seeChapter3 and Onuf 1989) holds that social structure, by itself, cannot serve as the basis for a complete account of identity. Agents and their behaviormust also be considered.Speakingis doing, and constructivistsmaintain that social meanings,institutions, and structures 104 PAUL KOWERT (aU, in a sense,the samething) are constructedout of practical linguistic rules. The instruction-, directive-, and commitment-rulesthat are the foundation of Onufs approach,for example,are all instancesof behavior as well as social acts (see Searle 1969). They occur at the nexus of biology, psychology,and sociology. But constructiviststake biological, psychological, or social performanceone step further. They argue that people strive not only to make senseout of their world and to act within it, but also to communicatetheir understandingsto others.At the sametime, the process of communicationis a processof making sense.This extendsthe syllogism offered above:speakingis doing is knowing. As communicationis a social act, so is knowledge.This is preciselythe bridge that constructivismoffers betweenontology (the socially constructedworld) and epistemology(our ability to know somethingaboutit). Although the "semanticdimensionsof the language"permit somesocial constructions,they render other constructionsunintelligible (see Giddens 1984; Kratochwil 1989). JohanGaltung (1990) describesU.S. foreign policy as a theologicalsystemin which certainconstructionsmake sense(such as orderversusdisorderor hierarchyversusanarchy)and other alternatives do not (see also Campbell 1992). While American presidentsmight occasionally denounceother statesas "evil empires,"for example,they engage in no sustaineddiscussionof the morality of foreign policy. The language of realism offers little purchaseto those, such as PresidentJimmy Carter, who might wish to do so. For Galtung, languageis pivotal. Once discussions of international politics are framed in certain terms, interestsand identitiesbecomeobvious: "With anarchysufficiently decriedthis option is rejected;what is left is hierarchy. In hierarchythe strongesthave to be on top.... The rest becomesalmosta tautology" (Galtung1990, 138). In such a discussion,one's own identity--presumably--shouldbe "on top" (e.g., that of the "hegemon"). Kratochwil's (1996) analysisof "belonging" and "citizenship"exploresanothersetoflinguistic polaritieswith similar consequencesfor identification. Here, too, languageis structuredto promote identity. Who would not wish to "belong"? Feministinternationalrelationstheoristshavealso devotedspecialattention to the role of languagein identity formation, arguing that traditional and androcentricmetaphorsof internationalpolitics not only ignore but in fact preventconsiderationof alternativepolitics and identities(Enloe 1989; Peterson1992; Sylvester1994; Tickner 1992). Accordingto Tickner (1992, 36), the languagein which most (traditional) discussionsof international politics are conducted "comes out of a Western-centeredhistorical worldview that ... privileges a view of security that is constructedout of valuesassociatedwith hegemonicmasculinity." Sheargues,moreover,that THE CONSTRUCTION OF NATIONAL IDENTITY 105 the masculine discourseof internationalpolitics directly informs national identities and "has all but eliminated the experiencesof women from our collectivenationalmemories"(138). The intensificationof concernwith languagehas led someto proclaim a "linguistic tum" in internationalrelations.1 Although some scholarsview the linguistic tum as emancipatory(George and Campbell 1990; Lapid 1989; Neufeld 1995; Sylvester1994), in that it permits alternativeconceptions of international politics, they must also reckon with the problems posedby this very malleability. Languageis not just a social mechanism that createsand reinforcesmeaningand identity; it can be manipulatedby speakers(especiallythosewith power). Soviet officials who spokeof "new thinking," to take one example,not only challengeda conceptionof history that hadnot admittedthe possibility of perestroikabut also servedtheir own political interests. These liberal reformers especially benefited from the vaguenessof the category they created.Becausemany people with very different political agendascould all seethemselvesas "new thinkers," perestroika was a useful idea around which to mobilize (see Herman 1996). Thus languageis not simply the repository of what exists. It is also the meansthroughwhich things are broughtinto and out of existence.Political leadersare able to manipulatethis process,but they are also constrainedby it. 2 Scholars,who havetheir own ambitions,also participatein this process, certainlycomplicatingtheir own effortsto studyit. The incentivesof academia encouragea bias toward novel constructions.Perhapsit is no accident that Soviet reformers were also influenced by academicexchanges that broughtSovietandAmericanphysicists,socialscientists,andotherscholars together(Herman1996; Mendelson1993; Zisk 1993). Recognizingthe way people and nations manipulatelanguageto "construct" themselveschallengescommonassumptionsaboutthe fixity of the main charactersin the dramaof internationalrelations.But the purposeof this chapteris to show what constructivismcontributesto researchon national identity, not to play with language.It is easyto show how linguistic rules and proceduresare implicated in the formation of social identities. This is unsurprising.All languageconsistsof distinctions.Instruction-rules distinguish one thing from another. Directive-rulesand and commitrnentrules distinguishone stateof affairs (desired)from another(actual) and, in so doing, also specifY who (the listener Of the speaker,respectively) is expectedto reconcile the two states.At a very basic level, languageand identity thus dependon eachother. Identity exists throughthe "distinguishing" function of language.But language--directivesand commissivesin particular-alsodependson the identitiesof selfand other. As Dnuf (1989, 109) puts it, "constituting practices in categories(even perceptiontakes 106 PAUL KOWERT practice)is not just universal,it is fundamental."And yet, "if categorization is fundamental,no set of categoriesis" (109). This is as far as constructivism can proceed toward a theory of identity. It does not prescribe any particular set of categoriesor identities. It simply acknowledgesthat languagefunctions, in part, to constrain uncategorized experienceand transform it into categorizedmeaning.For languageto function, there must be categories.But it is up to agentsto determinewhich categories. Cognitive psychology picks up where constructivismleaves off in its discussion of identity: with the claim that the ordinary functioning of humancognition cleavesthe social world into "self' and "other" categories of agency.3 Psychologistshave shown that, even when no obviousgrounds for categorizingexist, peoplewill invent them. MuzaferSherif(1961, 1966) arguedthat two groups given competing(interdependent)goals will form negativeattitudesabout eachother--evenin the total absenceof infonnation about the personalqualities of out-group members--aswell as more positive and cohesiveattitudes about themselves(the in-group). Placing people in situationsof objective conflict, he reasoned,would promotedistinct identities, while providing superordinategoals for the groups would erode these identities and reduce out-group bias.4 Later researchshowed that the presenceof objective conflict or competitionwas not necessaryto producedistinct identities, leading to a "minimal group paradigm."Henri Tajfel (1978, 1981) found that wheneversocial divisions are salient,people will invent correspondinglydivergent identities. In other words, one need do little more than divide peopleinto groupsfor distinct identities to begin to emerge.And when groupsare in competition,their identities and biases will becomeevenmore distinct (CartwrightandZander1968). The minimal group paradigm(MGP) suggeststhat distinct group identities will quickly and inevitably emergein social interactions.A variety of explanationsfor this phenomenonare consistentwith the MGP. One interpretation, appealingin its simplicity, is that social identity emergesfrom individual cognitive "miserliness."According to John Turner, "[t]he first question determining group-belongingnessis not 'Do I like these other individuals?', but 'Who am I?' " (1982, 16). Individuals are continually confrontedwith the problemof locating themselves,and others,in a web of social categoriesthat periodically confront them as salient. They have limited cognitive resourcesto devoteto this task and, as a result, must make use of certain simplifying and memory-enhancingstrategies(see also Turner 1991). In constructivisttenns, "rules" presentagentswith simpler ways to interpretthe world and to makechoices. Psychologicalexperimentsindicate that the earlier and the more frequently individuals are exposedto information about the attributesof oth- THE CONSTRUCTION OF NATIONAL IDENTITY 107 ers, the more extremewill be their ratings of the otherson theseattributes (Oakesand Turner 1986; Tajfel 1981,62-89,110-14).Put succinctly,people tend to exaggeratetheir perceptionsof others in order to make memory and categorizationeasier.And they particularly exaggerateattributesthat, perhaps becauseof priority (early exposure)or frequency, are more salient. One implication of this finding is that distinctionsbetweenmembersof different social groupsare often exaggerated.This tendencyto perceiveintergroupdistinctions is matchedby a correspondingtendencyto perceiveintragrouphomogeneity. Members of one group are consistentlyperceivedas more similar to one anotherthan to membersof othergroups(McGarty and Penny 1988; Tajfel 1969). Again, the cognitive advantagesof such a simplifying assumption are apparent.Gordon Allport (1954) made a similar point in his classic work on prejudice, arguing that the classification of others into distinct social groups(with group-relatedidentities)facilitatesprocessesof identification and adjustmentin new social situations.Fine distinctionsrequirethat one remembermore information, and this in tum increasesthe difficulty of . recallingthe information. Consistentwith the cognitive biasesdescribedso far-towardintergroup differentiationand intragrouphomogeneity-isanotherbias in causalattribution. Becauseout-groupsare perceivcdas homogeneous,their behavior canmore easily be explainedas the result of positive intent (seeDeschamps 1977; Hewstoneand Jaspars1982). This attributional bias is, in effect, a social identity versionof what cognitive psychologistshavecalled the "fundamental attributionerror"-the attribution of other people'sbehavior to their intent or dispositional qualities rather than to some situational constraint.s In this ease,the behaviorof other groupsis more readily explained by attributes of group members(presumablyshared homogeneouslyby members)than by external constraintson their behavior. A particularly interestingvariation of this argumentis Jean-ClaudeDeschamps'ssuggestion that when out-groupsare perceivedas powerful, then the attributional error will be enhanced(1982). Powerful groups, even if they face situational constraints,could presumablyuse their power to overcomethese constraints.This bias leadsto the tautologicalperceptionthat all behaviorof powerful out-groupsis intentional ("since they are powerful, they can do whateverthey want"). Much of the literatureon self-categorizationsuggeststhat in-groupswill also be seenas homogeneous(althoughthis effect is not as robust as with out-groups; see Mullen and Hu 1989; Park and Judd 1990). For several reasons,however, this homogeneitydoes not necessarilyimpede a sclfserving (in-group-serving)bias. First, even though one's own group may seemhomogeneousrelative to others--therebyestablishingits identity- 108 PAUL KOWERT some differences between group members will neverthelessbe apparent (Judd, Ryan, and Park 1991; Park, Ryan, and Judd 1992). The behaviorof one's own group can thus readily be explainednot only as the product of situationalconstraintsbut also as the result of negotiationswithin the group (Bendor and Hammond 1992; Welch 1992). Moreover, infonnation about situational constraintson the behavior of one's own group may be much more readily available than similar infonnation for out·groups(Hewstone and Jaspars1982). Thus,while a cognitive intragrouphomogeneitybias may exist for all social categories,the processof behavioralattribution might be very different (andmore forgiving) for in·groupsthanfor out·groups. It is one thing for psychologiststo explain how cognitive bias affectsthe way we view ourselvesand others.It is a much bolder step to suggestthat the sameprocessworks at the level of nation·states.Mercer (1995) takes just this step, arguing that even if constructivistsare correct in assuming that the world can be constructedin different ways, the MOP nevertheless predicts that internationalrelations will be constructedin the highly competitive and egocentricmold of neorealism.There are two problemswith this daring analytic leap: first, the MGP is not so detenninisticthat it pre· diets only one fonn of national identity (egoistic) or internationalrelations (anarchical);and second,the linkage betweenindividual biasesand images (or identities)ascribedto nation·statesdeservescloserattention. Just as people are not highly suspiciousof every other personthey encounter, So states are not equally threatenedby (or suspiciousof) every other statethey "encounter."Democraciesmay find, for example,that they belong to a common in-group (Chafetz 1995; Doyle 1986). Some states seemmore trustworthythan others,and it is preciselysuchdifferencesthat a theory of national identity must explain. To apply the insights of social identity theory and the MGP to international relations, then, narrower hypothesesmustbe considered. Many different hypothesesabout the creation,maintenance,and impact of social identity might be derived from the complex body of researchon the MGP, self-categorization,prejudice, stereotyping,cognitive balancing, and social attribution. For presentpurposes,however, three fairly simple lessonswill suffice: 1. Wheneverdistinctive categoriesfor political groupsare salient,group members will perceive strengthenedgroup identities (ordinarily evaluatively positive for in-groups and negativefor out-groups).Conflict betweengroupswill strengthentheseidentitiesand encourageexaggeration of groupattributes. 2. People will also tend to exaggeratedifferences between political THE CONSTRUCTION OF NATIONAL IDENTITY 109 groups and to underestimatedifferenceswithin thesegroups. Again, conflict will strengthenthis tendency. 3. Finally, people will tend to attribute the behavior of political outgroupsto the intent or desiresof thosegroups;in-group behavior,however, will more often be attributedto the influence of environmentalconstraints. Perceivedincreasesin the powerof out-groupswill strengthenthe tendency to assumeintent (attributionalbias). Theselessonsseemplausiblegiven the extensivebody of researchsupporting the MGP. At the level of individuals, they are well tested. But the problemof the leap to internationalrelationsremains. Constructivismmakes this leap possible by insisting that people construct larger social realities--inciudingnational identity. To make this leap reasonable,however,we must once again tum to the relationshipbetween languageand psychology.The MGP predicts a linguistic bias in the relationship betweeninstruction-rulesand directives or commissives.In short, people should not be equally willing to commit themselvesto action on behalf of all groups. Once instruction-rulescategorizethe social world, demandswill be madeof out-groups,while commitmentwill occur primarily on behalfof in-groups. Constructivismthus provides an important link acrosslevels of analysis. Cognitive bias not only shapesthe identities of otherpeople(as they are meaningfulto oneself);it biasesthe functioning of languageto create (biased) identities at every level of human relations. Languagetranslatesindividual bias eveninto internationalrelations.Agents at all levels are mademeaningful,then, becauseindividuals confer identity on themselvesand on the institutions that representthem (such as the nation-state).Seriousstudentsof diplomatic history might decry the tendency of novicesto reify statesand to treatthem as pseudo-individualswith coherent objectives. But doing so is not merely an error to be correctedin the graduatetraining of historians.It is, in fact, a widespreadand unavoidable tendency-withsomenegativeconsequences--on which ordinary usageof the term national identity depends.Constructivismand psychologytogether predictthat nationalidentity is rarely (if ever) neutralwith respectto self. An Illustration: National Identity in the SuezCrisis The 1956 crisis provoked by Egyptian presidentNasser'sdecision to nationalize the Suez Canal brought questionsof identity to the fore in dramatic fashion. At the time, both Egypt and Israel confronted wrenching dilemmasas they attemptedto carve out new sovereign,national identities for themselves.Similarly, the United States and the Soviet Union both 110 PAUL KOWERT faced the problem of accommodatingthemselvesto their new roles as superpowersin a competitivebipolar world. Franceand Britain, meanwhile, were playing out the last act of their rapidly erodingcolonial identities.The remainder of this chapter will focus exclusively on the evolution of Britain's perceptionsof identity (both its own and Egypt's), first taking up the origins of theseperceptionsand then briefly consideringtheir impact on British policy. It may be helpful, at the outset, to restatethe above hypothesesin the context of this case.First, as political categoriesbecomemore salient,participants in the crisis will exaggerateboth their opponent'sand their own identities. We might thereforeexpectthe British prime minister, Anthony Eden,to regardthe Egyptianprime minister (later, president),GamalAbdel Nasser,as more and more "typically Egyptian" as the crisis wears on, and himselfas more "typically British." Second,we might expectEdento exaggeratethe distinctionsbetweenthesetwo identities,assigningnegativeattributes to the outgroup. Nasser will be seen, therefore, not only as increasingly Egyptian, but as increasingly different from--and somehow inferior or opposedto--theBritish. 'Finally, as the exaggeratedin-group and out-groupidentities develop,they will encouragein tum a seriesof attribution errors. We might expectEden to view Nasser's(or Egyptian) behavior as purely intentional while readily perceiving the constraintson British optionsandbehavior, Long before the crisis, both Eden and his predecessor, WinstonChurchill, were well aware of Egyptian discontentwith the British presencein Egypt. For this very reason,and becausethe lone British base along the SuezCanal was of comparativelylittle strategicvalue in any case,English policy favored a gradual withdrawal from the region. Earlier, thesetroops had servedthe important function (from London'sperspective)of securing easyBritish accessto India via the SuezCanaland then, in the early twentieth century,to Middle East oil depositsas well. Yet, althoughthe accessto oil reservesremainedimportant, its value was increasinglyovershadowed by the negative consequencesof Egyptian hostility toward the foreign troops.By the early 1950s,Churchill confidedto an associatethat "not even a single soldier is in favor of staying there" (Neff 1981, 56). As Britain preparedto withdraw from the Middle Eastat the conclusionof World War II, therefore,it hopedto fill the resultantpolitical and military vacuum by promotingan alternativesecurityarrangement:the BaghdadPact. The BaghdadPactwas actually one part of a two-partBritish strategyfor the Middle East. The Pact itself sought to organize"northern tier" Arab states(Turkey, Iraq, Iran, and Pakistan)into a defensiveallianceagainstthe Soviet Union. To this end, Britain joined an existing alliance betweenTur- THE CONSTRUCTION OF NATIONAL IDENTITY 111 key and Iraq, hoping that other Arab countries and the United States would follow its lead.6 The other part of British Middle East strategy, "OperationALPHA," was a joint effort with the United Statesto resolve the Arab-Israeli problem. Operation ALPHA sought rapprochementbetween Egypt and Israel and, in consultationwith Jordan,a negotiatedterritorial settlementfor Palestinianrefugees.Unfortunately,the two objectives of British policy worked againsteachother. As Sir Evelyn Shuckburgh(one of the chief architectsof ALPHA) later reminisced,"We did not face up soonenoughto this basiccontradictionin our strategy"(Shamir1989,90). Nasser and other Egyptian nationalists certainly approved of British withdrawal from the region. But Nasserrecognizedthe Pact for what it clearly was: an attemptto maintain some Europeaninfluence over the region and, as such, a direct affront to the pan-Arab collective security arrangementhe favored. Nasser'sblunt appraisal of the Pact was that it representedan attemptby the West "to get [the Arabs] to unite to fight your enemy[Russia] while they know that if they show any intention of fighting their enemy [Israel] you would quickly stop all aid" (Neff 1981, 76). Despite thesestrongreservations,however,Nasserremainedwilling for a time to work with the British, hoping therebyto securethe first completewithdrawal of British troops from Egyptian soil since 1882. And despite Nasser'sclear opposition to the BaghdadPact, the British governmentremainedconvinceduntil early 1955 that it could work with Nasser.In fact, after his only face-to-facemeeting with Nasserin February 1955, Eden reportedto Churchill that he was "impressedby Nasser,who seemedforthright and friendly" (Kyle 1991, 39). Roger Allen, the British assistant undersecretary for the Middle East,similarly concludedthat Englandshould attempt"to consolidatehis (Nasser's)position ... it looks as though he is our bestbet" (Louis 1989,48).One way of achievingthis, clearly, would be to withdraw from Egypt--somethingBritain had long promised.The irony of the Suezcrisis, therefore,is that Nassersimply pushedBritain further in a direction it was alreadymoving. In the year after Eden met with Nasser,a seriesof eventsdramatically changedthe relationshipbetweenthem. The first of theseeventsoccurred only eight days after their meeting: on the night of February28, a special detachmentof Israeli commandosled by Ariel Sharonattackedan Egyptian military baseat Gaza,ostensiblyin responseto a seriesof borderincursions by Palestiniansfrom the Gaza Strip. In this attack, thirty-eight Egyptians were killed, and "from this momenton Nasser's... overriding needwas to ensureEgyptian rearmamentfrom whateversourcesit could be obtained" (Kyle 1991, 65). Nasserquickly appealedto the American ambassadorin Cairo, Henry Byroade,for arms. But, despitea barrageof telegramsfrom 1I2 PAUL KOWERT Byroade to Washington requestingthese anns, PresidentDwight Eisenhower and Secretaryof StateJohn FosterDulles moved aheadcautiously, facedwith oppositionto an annssaleboth from abroad(Israel) and at home (in Congress).Inevitably, Nassersoughtassistanceelsewhere,and on September27, he announceda sizablecontractto buy Soviet annamentsfrom Czechoslovakia. From this point onward, British perceptionsof Nasserbeganto change inexorablyfor the worse. Even beforethe annsdeal becamepublic, Eden's impressionof Nasserhad soured. When Egypt backedSaudi Arabia in a disputeover Buraimi (an oasisin the Saudi desert),Eden reactedstrongly: "This kind of thing is really intolerable. Egyptiansget steadily worse.... They should surely be told finnly no more annsdeliverieswhile this goes on" (Lucas 1991, 49). The anns deal was the first overt confinnation of Eden's fears, indicating that Nassermight not only challengeBritain but perhapsevenside with the Soviets.Yet Britain hadnowhereelseto tum. As Shuckburghconcludedat the time, "the plain fact is that, howeverdisappointedwe may be in the attitude of Colonel Nasserand his colleagues,we can see no alternativeEgyptian Governmentin sight which would be any better" (Lucas 1991, 49). The absenceof a clear alternativeto Nassermade it even easier for Eden to view Egyptian leadershipas monolithic-and increasinglythreatening. If Nasser'sstanceon Buraimi and his acceptanceof the Czechoslovakian annsdeal had begunto call his "identity" into question,a seriesof intelligence reports received beginning in November from a British agent in Nasser'sentourageswiftly pushedEden and his cabinet toward an even of this "emergingenemy."The agent,codemore pessimistic reassessment named"Lucky Break," raised the disturbing prospectthat Nasserplanned once again to tum to the Soviets for assistance,this time for funding to build the Aswan High Dam. Eden himself had pushedhard for a $200 million Westernaid packageto help financethe dam, but Britain lackedthe resourcesand the United States(especiallythe Americanpublic) lackedthe will for such a massiveloan program.Despitetheir awarenessthat Nasser believedthe situation to be pressing,Eden and his advisorswere shocked by the newsthat Nasserwas actually consideringa Soviet aid package.The specterof communistEgypt loomedevenlarger. Ironically, the final straw for Eden was an event for which Nasserbore no direct responsibility--theremovalof GeneralJohnBagot"Pasha"Glubb from his post commandingthe Arab Legion in Jordan. In fact, Pasha Glubb's ouster was, indirectly, a product of the British decision to seek Jordanianmembershipin the BaghdadPact. After Britain's clumsy efforts to woo Jordandestabilizedthe Jordaniangovernment,Glubb was forced to THE CONSTRUCTION OF NATIONAL IDENTITY 113 stepin and restoreorder. This action, in tum, convincedKing Husseinthat Glubb himself had becomea threat. The Pashawas orderedto leave the country on short notice, and British officials leapt to the conclusion that Nasser had somehoworchestratedthe .whole affair. The British foreign minister, Selwyn Lloyd, was in Cairo at the time. In a meetingwith Nasser the morning after Glubb's dismissal,Lloyd musedthat the Egyptian leader "had deterioratedsincetheir first meeting.... 'He smileda greatdeal more, for no apparentreason.He had lost the simplicity I rather liked in 1953' " (Kyle 1991,94).Eden'sreactionwas far stronger. The news of Glubb's removal convulsedEden with fury. Anthony Nutting was with the Prime Minister until 5 A.M. trying to calm him: "[Eden] put all the blame on Nasserand brushedaside every argumentthat mere personal considerationshad in fact influenced Hussein'sarbitrary decision.... He decidedthat the world was not big enough to hold both him and Nasser." (Lucas 1991,95) In fact, when Nutting did try to reasonwith Eden,the Prime Minister could not contain himself. " 'You love Nasser,'he burst out, 'but I say he is our enemy and he shall be treated as such'" (Nutting 1967, 29). After this incident, Eden began to compare Nasser to Mussolini. In the prime minister'sview, there no longer remainedany room for compromise:"It is eitherhim or us" (Kyle 1991,96). By this time, Nasser'sidentity (and Egypt's to a lesser extent) had clearly becomevery salient to Eden and his cabinet. They made frequent referenceto his untrustworthinessand his sympathyto communism.Their opposition to him thus came more from who he was and what he represented--acommunist,or possibly a fascist, and clearly an enemy of Britain--thanfrom what he hadactuallydone.Nutting's(1967,28) observation that it "was almostas if No. 10 itself had beenattackedand a howling mob of Arabs were laying siegeto Downing Street" is a vivid illustration of the new identity the British hadconferredon Nasser.But more thanNasserwas at issue. The new "out-group," Egypt, would thereafter be treated as a homogeneousentity--a "howling mob of Arabs"-with just one more of the "mob" at the helm. And Eden's responseto Nutting's ill-considered attempt to defend Nasser-thatNutting must "love Nasser"-showsthe strengthand extent of this new social categorization.By this point, Eden could conceiveof only two camps:thosewho "loved" Arabs and thosewho did not.7 Not only was this social categorizationincreasinglysalient but, with the frequent(if inconsistent)referencesto Hitler, Mussolini, and communists,it was greatlyexaggerated. As one might expect, this negative redefinition and exaggerationof 114 PAUL KOWERT Nasser'sidentity also encouragedattribution bias within the British government. Eden's strong reaction to the Lucky Break intelligence suggestsa failure to appreciatethe constraintsthe Egyptian leader faced. After the Czechoslovakianannsdeal, the British ambassadorto Egypt reportedthat he "saw no reasonthat [Nasser]would not havepreferredto get annsfrom the West and [he] only decidedto acceptthe Soviet offer when he felt he could wait no longer in the face of increasedtension on the Gazafrontier and internal pressure"(Lucas 1991, 65). But while Eden was well aware that Washingtonwas onceagaindraggingits heelsand, in the end,unlikely to provide financing---andalthoughNasscrtook stepsto minimize Western criticism, emphasizingthat "it was a once-for-all deal" and that "there would be no Soviet technicians"-Edencould not help but jump to the conclusionthat the Soviet financing representeda fundamentalshift toward communismon Nasser'spart (Kyle 1989, 107). In otherwords, Edenfound it easierto attributethe Sovietoffer to Nasser'sown (changing)desiresand identity than to the constraintsthat the Egyptian leaderfaced. This attribution bias is set in further relief by the fact that the Americansinterpretedthe sameintelligencemuch differently. From the CIA's perspective,there"was a sweepingand absolutequality about [the British] analysisthat gratedon the American agentsand was not borne out by their own sources"(Kyle 1991, 102). And if Eden's reaction to Lucky Break exhibited attribution bias, his responseto Glubb's dismissalis an evenbetterexampleof serious attribution error. In this case,without any supportingevidenceat all, Eden blamedNasserfor the behaviorof the king of Jordan.The apparentrise of Nasser'spower and prestigein the region, after he assumedthe Egyptian presidencyand then successfullynegotiatedthe Czechoslovakianannsdeal, may have further contributedto Eden'sbiases.Nasser'sincreasingpower madeit that much easierto blamehim for British setbacks. By the summerof 1956, the prospectof Westernsupportfor the Aswan High Dam had becomeremote. Dulles fonnally withdrew American support for the loan packageon July 19. Sevendays later-perhapsin retaliation and perhapsin an effort to secure a new source of funds--Nasser announcedthe nationalizationof the SuezCanal. By this time, little further damagecould be done to Eden's exceedinglylow estimation of Nasser. Nationalizationmerelyservedto confinn what Edenalreadybelievedandto intensify his already-strongtendencyto view Middle East politics through the singularlens of Anglo-Egyptianconflict. From this point onward,Eden "was out of sync with his old cautious, compromising self. He was obsessed,a driven man, his vast experienceand intellect reducedto tunnel vision. At the end of the tunnel was Nasser"(Neff 1981, 278). Of course, after the seizureof the Canal, Eden was hardly alone. The generalconsen- THE CONSTRUCTION OF NATIONAL IDENTITY 115 sus in the British cabinet, according to Andrew Foster (the U.S. charge d'affaires in London), was that "Nassermust not be allowed to get away with it" (Lucas 1991, 142). And the British pressthereafter "maintaineda steadydrumbeatof shrill criticism againstNasser,"ranking him amongthe worst threatsto freedom and democracy(Neff 1981, 204). Even Winston Churchill, who up this point had been concernedabout Eden'snewly aggressiveattitude toward Egypt, swungquickly into line with the prevailing national mood. "We can't have that malicious swine sitting across our communications,"he proclaimed(277). What is particularly notableabouttheseexpressionsof British outrage is their emphasison Nasser'spersonalcharacter(that is, his identity) as the explanationfor his behaviorand as sufficient reasonfor British reprisals. The problem was not the nationalizationper se, which British lawyers quickly agreed was legal since the Suez Canal Company was registeredas an Egyptian companyand since its shareholderswere all to be compensated.The problem was that Hitler had been reincarnatedin the Middle East. And, as social identity theory predicts,Nasser'sbehavior was assumedto reflect on all Egyptians.Consistentwith this form of social stereotyping,the British ministersconcludedin a cabinetmeeting on July 27 that "[t]he Egyptians... did not possessthe technicalability to manage the Canal effectively" (Kyle 1991, 138). As the London Times put it, "An internationalwaterway of this kind cannotbe worked by a nation with low technical and managerialskills such as the Egyptians" (Neff 1981, 277). The crisis was not simply a personal matter betweenBritish and Egyptian leaders.Their mutual animosity was writ large in the way they viewed their antagonist'Snational identity and in their diplomatic practice. Once the crisis was truly underway, the leaders'own national identities came into playaswell. When out-group identity becomessalient, a correspondingtransformationshould occur in definitions of the in-group. The available documentaryevidenceon the Suez crisis provides less evidence for this than for exaggeratedattributionsto out-groups.Nevertheless,there is at least some evidenceto support the claim that in-group identity also becameincreasinglysalient during the courseof the crisis. The principal manifestationof this transformationin Britain was an increasedemphasis on the potential damageto British reputation (thus, identity) as a major power if Nasserwere allowed to succeed.Indeed,Harold "Macmillan flatly declaredto Dulles that Britain would be finished as a world power if Nasser won: 'This is Munich all over again'" (Neff 1981, 290). And Sir Ivone Kirkpatrick (the permanentundersecretaryat the Foreign Office) managed to take, if possible,an evenmore alarmistposition: 116 PAUL KOWERT [I]fwe sit back while Nasserconsolidateshis position and gradually acquires control of the oil-bearingcountries,he can, and is, accordingto our information, resolvedto wreck us. If Middle Eastoil is deniedto us for a year or two our gold reserveswill disappear.If our gold reservesdisappearthe sterling areadisintegrates.If the sterling areadisintegratesand we have no reserves we shall not be able to maintain a force in Germanyor, indeed, anywhere else. I doubt whetherwe shall be able to pay for the bareminimum necessary for our defence.And a country that cannotprovide for its defenceis finished. (Kyle 1989, 123) Although Kirkpatrick strikes an alannist tone, his point was essentially correct: Britain faceda test of its survival as a greatpower. The importanceof both British and Egyptian national identity in this casewas far-reaching.One obvious effect of the changingBritish views of Egyptian identity, as already noted, was the tendencytoward attribution error that thesechangesencouraged.In the year following Eden'smeeting with Nasser,English officials tendedmore and more often to blameNasser for setbacksto Britain's Middle East policy. This becamea self-fulfilling prophecy. The more the British focused on Nasser,the more they attributed every failure to him, and thus the larger he loomed. The increasingly negative British view of Nasser contributed in tum to the collapse of project ALPHA, undenninedfinancing for the Aswan Dam, and made Nasser'seventual retaliation all the more likely. And when Nasserdid nationalize the Suez Canal Company,the British conceptionof him left only one conceivableresponse.To simply acceptnationalizationhad, for Eden, becomesynonymouswith appeasinga new Hitler. In short, British leaders constructedthe very threat to which they were ultimately compelled to respond. Ironically, the British tendencyto demonizeNasserhad the unintended effect of enhancingthe Egyptianleader'spopUlarity. Egyptiansmight well concludethat "if the West hatedNasserso much then surely he must be powerful" (Neff 1981, 205). The strong emotions evoked among British leadersby defining Nasseras anotherHitler had the further effect of blinding Edenand his colleaguesto the likely American responseto their invasion plan. Even after Eisenhowersent a letter explicitly warning against the use of force, Eden simply refusedto comprehendthe line the Americans had just drawn. "Eden's passion so clouded his reason that after reading Ike's forceful letter he concludedthat 'the Presidentdid not rule out the use of force.' True, but there were so many qualifiers in the letter that only Eden in his blind hatredof Nassercould have missedthe point" (Neff 1981,291).And, as Eden soon discovered,Britain was no longer in a position to undertakesucha project without American support.After this THE CONSTRUCTION OF NATIONAL IDENTITY 117 crisis, the British "habit of using the languageand assumptionsof a Great Powerhadbeensmothered"(Kyle 1989, 130). Conclusion The elaborateedifice of constructivismin not required simply to observe that, in British eyes,the imageof Egypt and its leaderchanged dramatically in the year leading up to the Suez crisis.But cognitive theoriesof social stereotypingdo not addressthe problemof how in-groupbias is inscribedin higher levels of collective behavior.One might thus dismissthe cognitive account of Egypt's changing identity, viewed from London, as so many individual perceptionswith no particular relevanceto international relations. Or, at best,theseperceptionsmight be deemedrelevantonly insofar as they affectedthe beliefs and policies of Britain's prime minister. Morgenthau (1948) warned long ago that rationalizationsand justifications shouldnot be allowedto concealthe true natureof foreign policy-that it is dangerousto take states at their "word" and that perceptionsare often misleading. Yet, misleadingor not, rationalizationsand justifications are foreign policy. The contribution of constructivismis to make it clear that theseperceptionswere internationalrelations in this case.They were the instruction-rulesthat formed the reality to which Edenresponded. A constructivistapproachwould be unnecessaryif this reality were uncontested.A simpler alternativeto the accountoffered here is that Nasser's actionsrepresenteda genuinethreatandthat Britain's response was dictated by considerationsof power politics and national security. Indeed, the frequent referencesby British leaders to Nasser'sresultant control over Europe'soil lifeline evoke a straightforwardconcernwith material issues (and a concernnot too different from the concernsvoicedaboutIraq during the PersianGulf War). But Britain's reaction remains difficult to explain on these grounds alone. As Nasserhimself pointed out during the crisis, Egypt was already eligible to purchasethe Suez Canal Company beginning in 1968. "Why should Britain say that this nationalization will affect shipping in the canal?" he complained. "Would it have affected shipping twelve years hence?"(Neff 1981,283).Moreover,the threatthat Britain apparentlyperceivedto its oil supplycould well havebeenmitigatedby lessdrasticmeans than a military invasionof the canalzone. One approach,advocatedby the United Statesduring the crisis as a way of dissuadingBritain from more bellicoseaction, was the creationof an internationalboardto overseecanal operation.Britain's responseseemstoo hasty and too disproportionateto the actual threat posedby nationalization,therefore,to explain on material 118 PAUL KOWERT groundsalone. Indeed,the fact that Britain finished withdrawing its troops from Suezlittle more than a month beforeNasserannouncednationalization indicatesthe limited practicalimportanceof British control of the canal.Not surprisingly,"when Anthony Nutting pointedout to Eden that Britain might not actually haveany worry aboutthe canalstayingopensince it was now in recognizably ~gypt's bestintereststo collect as many tolls as possible,the prime minister 'merely replied that I shouldknow that the capacityof the Arabs to cut off their noses to spite their face was infinite'" (284). Apart from being a striking example of negative out-group identification, Eden's remark suggeststhat he found it impossible,by this point, to believe that Nasserwas remotely capableof rational action--<iespiteNasser'sconsiderableeffort to assurethe smoothfunctioning of the canal and to carry out the nationalization plan in accordancewith Egyptianandinternationallaw. Eden's responsemakesit plain that his attention focused not on what Nasserhad done (or could reasonablybe cxpectedto do) but on what he thought Nasserhad become.The act of nationalizationitself was not the problem. It was what the act said aboutwhat Nasserand Egypt had become (a growing nationalistand possibly communistthreat) and aboutwhat Britain was in dangerof becoming(a declining power). Nationalizationwarrantedto Edenthat Egypt was no longer competentto deal with a complex environmentof internationaldirective-rulesand commitment-rules,no matter the carethat Nasseractually took to obey theserules. The British interpretationof Egyptianbehaviorhingednot on the behavioritself but on the ascribedidentity of Egyptian agents.Moreover, Eden and his cabinetnot only redefinedEgyptianidentity but increasinglyexaggeratedboth the identity itself and the distinction betweenthis identity and their own (the Egyptians would not respect the rules; the English were honorable and law-abiding). Finally, with these exaggerationsof political identity came attribution errors, generallyascribingto Nassermalicious intent regardless of the constraintshe may havefaced. Not only were thesetransformationsof identity endogenousto the interaction betweenBritain and Egypt, but they dependedheavily on the behavior of political agents. No international structures(not even those of the Cold War) completelydeterminedthe patternof interaction betweenEden and Nasser.Even if the Westmight eventuallyhave found Nasser'snationalism intolerablefor other reasons,greatercooperationon the Aswan Dam might well have forestalled that conflict long enoughto preventthe Suez crisis. The crisis occurred becauseof "who" it involved, not becauseof what it involved. And long before the crisis, the characterof the states involved in it was conceivedand reconceivedin the minds of a small group of individuals. THE CONSTRUCTION OF NATIONAL IDENTITY 119 Notes The author is grateful for support in the fonn of a National ScienceFoundationgrant (DIR-9I13599)to the Ohio StateUniversity'sMershonCenterResearchTraining Group (RTG) on the role of cognition in collective political decision making. DeborahAvant, Martha Finnemore,Richard Hernnann,PeterKatzenstein,Jeffrey Legro, NicholasOnuf, participantsin threeSocial ScienceResearchCouncil/MacArthurFoundationworkshops on "Nonns and National Security," membersof the MershonCenterRTG, and members of the Miami InternationalRelationsGroup at Florida InternationalUniversity and the University of Miami have all offered helpful commentsand advice that enrichedthis paper.This chapteralso drawson ideasdeveloped,in part, in Kowert and Legro (1996). I. Actually, appreciationof the relationshipbetweenlanguageand identity is nothing new. In his classicstudy of Europeannationalism,for example,Karl Deutsch(1953) recognizedthat communicationwas a key to social identity. Seealso Kubalkova's"The Twenty Years' Catharsis,"Chapter2 in this volume. , 2. In a superb illustration of the way political leaders are affected by their own manipulations,Jack Snyder (1991) shows that not only may domestic interest groups benefiting from national expansionbe very successfulat promoting imperialist ideologies, but also their leadersmay come to believe passionatelyin theseideologies,blinding them to the dangersof overexpansion.Snydercalls this process"blowback." 3. For a psychologicalapproachdifferent from the one developedin this chapter,see Kratochwil's brief discussionof social nonns,eros, and thanatosin Freudianpsychology (1989, 126-29). Also seeBrewer'stheory of social distinctionsthat relies on motivational psychology(1991). 4. In an experimentnotableperhapsas much for the ethical issuesit raisedas for its results, Sherif (1961) tested his hypothesisby dividing children attending a summer campinto two groupsand giving them first competingand then superordinategoals.Not only did Sherif find that the competinggoals producedconsiderablehostility toward out-groupmembers,but it was much harderto restorecollective identity with superordinategoalsthan to fracture it. Seealso Blake and Mouton (1961). 5. A natural complementto the fundamentalattribution error is the attribution of one'sown behaviorto situational constraints("I had to do it") rather than to personal desires("I didn't want to"). For an excellentdiscussionof this and other relatedattributional biases,seeFiske and Taylor (1984,72-99). 6. Unfortunatelyfor Eden,once Britain hadjoined Turkey and Iraq to fonn the core of the BaghdadPact, the United Stateshad little incentive to follow. Britain's presence alone would serveas a deterrentto Soviet expansion,and joining the Pact would only alienate Egypt-the opposite of what Eisenhowerand Dulles hoped to achieve (see Louis 1989,44-46). 7. Ironically, Eden had studiedArabic and was himself on many earlier occasionsa strong advocateof Arab positions,often in the face of a Frenchforeign policy that was generallymore supportiveof Israel. In 1941, Eden admittedto his private secretarythat "if we must have preference,let me murmur in your ear that I prefer Arabs to Jews" (Neff 1981, 206). Eden's interest in Arab culture does not, of course, necessarilyimply a positive imageof the "other"; seeSaid'sdiscussionof "orientalism" (1979). The dramaticreversal of Eden'sviews toward Nassermay also have beenhastenedby the prime minister's physicalailments.Eden'shealthdeterioratedmarkedlyprior to and during this crisis as a result of a damagedbile duct and chronic infections. To compensate,he routinely took both antibiotics and amphetamines.This condition may account for much of Eden's 120 PAUL KOWERT irritability and perhapseven his emotional responseto Nasser'sbehavior. See Neff (1981,182-83). Bibliography Allport, Gordon. 1954. The Nature ofPrejudice. Reading,MA: Addison-Wesley. Ashley, Richard K. 1984. "The Povertyof Neorealism."International Organization38: 225-86. Bendor, Jonathan,and Thomas Hammond. 1992. "Rethinking Allison's Models." AmericanPolitical ScienceReview86: 301-21. Brewer, Marilyn. 1991. "The Social Self: On Being the Sameand Different at the Same Time." PersonalityandSocialPsychologyBulletin 17: 475-82. Blake, Robert R., and Jane S. Mouton. 1961. "Reactionsto Intergroup Competition Under Win-Lose Conditions."ManagementScience7: 420-35. Campbell, David. 1992. Writing Security: United StatesForeign Policy and the Politics ofIdentity. Minneapolis:University of MinnesotaPress. Cartwright, Dorwin, and Alvin Zander.1968. Group Dynamics.London: Tavistock. Chafetz, Glenn. 1995. "The Political Psychologyof the Nuclear Nonproliferation Regime." Journal ofPolitics 57: 743-75. Deschamps,Jean-Claude.1977. L 'Attribution et la CategorisationSociale.Berne: Peter Lang. - - - . 1982. "Social Identity and Relations of Power Between Groups." In Social Identity and Intergroup Relations,ed. Henri Tajfel, 85-98. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press. Dessler, David. 1989. "What's at Stake in the Agent-StructureDebate." International Organization43: 441-74. Deutsch, Karl W. 1953. Nationalism and Social Communication:An Inquiry into the FoundationsofNationality. Cambridge:M.I.T. Press. Doyle, Michael. 1986. "Liberalism and World Politics." American Political Science Review80: 1151--69. Enloe, Cynthia. 1989. Bananas,Beaches,and Bases:Making Feminist Senseof InternationalPolitics. Berkeley: University of California Press. Fiske, Susan,and ShelleyTaylor. 1984. Social Cognition. New York: RandomHouse. Galtung, Johan. 1990. "U.S. Foreign Policy as Manifest Theology." Tn Culture and InternationalRelations,ed. JongsukChay, 119-40. New York: Praeger. George, Jim, and David Campbell. 1990. "Patternsof Dissent and the Celebrationof Difference."InternationalStudiesQuarterly 34: 269-93. Giddens, Anthony. 1984. The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Theory of Structuration.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press. Goldstein, judith, and Robert O. Keohane,eds. 1993. Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change.Ithaca:Cornell University Press. Gramsci, Antonio. 1971. Selectionsfrom the Prison Notebooks,ed. and trans. Quintin Hoareand GeoffreyNowell Smith. New York: InternationalPublishers. Grieco, Joseph.1988. "Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation:A Realist Critique of the NewestLiberal Institutionalism."InternationalOrganization42: 483-508. Herman, Robert. 1996. "Identity, Norms, and National Security: The Soviet Foreign Policy Revolution and the End of the Cold War." In The Culture of National Security: Norms and Identity in World Politics, ed. Peter Katzenstein,271-316. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Hewstone,Miles, and J.M.F. Jaspars.1982. "Intergroup Relationsand Attribution Pro- THE CONSTRUCTION OF NATIONAL IDENTITY 121 cesses."In SocialIdentity and Intergroup Relations,ed. Henri Tajfel, 99--133. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press. Judd, Charles M., Carey S. Ryan, and BernadettePark. 1991. "Accuracy in the Judgment of In-Group and Out-Group Variability." Journal 0/ Personality and Social Psychology61: 366-79. Katzenstein,Peter, ed. 1996. The Culture 0/ National Security: Norms and Identity in World Politics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Kowert, Paul, and Jeffrey Legro. 1996. "Norms, Identity, and Their Limits: A Theoretical Reprise." In The Culture 0/ National Security: Norms and Identity in World Politics, ed. PeterKatzenstein,451-97. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Kratochwil, Friedrich. 1989. Rules,Norms, and Decisions:On the Conditionso/Practical and Legal Reasoningin International Relations and Domestic Affairs. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press. - - - . 1996. "Citizenship: On the Border of Order." In The Return qf Culture and Identity in IR Theory, ed. Yosef Lapid and Friedrich Kratochwil, 181-97. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner. Kyle, Keith. 1989. "Britain and the Crisis, 1955-1956."In Suez1956: The Crisis and its Consequences, ed. W. RogerLouis and RogerOwen. Oxford: Clarendon,103-30. 1991. Suez.New York: St. Martin's Press. Lapid, Yosef. 1989. "The Third Debate: On the Prospectsof InternationalTheory in a Post-PositivistEra." InternationalStudiesQuarterly 33: 235-54. and Friedrich Kratochwil, eds. 1996. The Return of Culture and Identity in IR Theory. Boulder,CO: Lynne Rienner. Legro, Jeffrey. 1996. "Culture and Preferencesin the International CooperationTwoStep."AmericanPolitical ScienceReview90: 118-37. Louis, W. Roger. 1989. "The Tragedyof the Anglo-Egyptian Settlementof 1954." In Suez1956: The Crisis and Its Consequences, ed. W. Roger Louis and RogerOwen, 43-72. Oxford: Clarendon. Lucas, W. Scott. 1991. Divided We Stand: Britain, the US and the SuezCrisis. London: Hodderand Stoughton. McGarty, c., and R.E.C. Penny. 1988. "Categorization,Accentuationand Social Judgement." British Journal (if SocialPsychology22: 147-57. Mendelson,Sara. 1993. "Internal Battlesand External Wars: Politics, Learning,and the SovietWithdrawal from Afghanistan."World Politics 45: 327--60. Mercer,Jonathan.1995. "AnarchyandIdentity." InternationalOrganization49: 229--52. Morgenthau,HansJ. 1948. Politics AmongNations.New York: Knopf. Mullen, Brian, and Li-tze Hu. 1989. "Perceptionsof Ingroup and OutgroupVariability: A Meta-Analytic Integration."Basic andAppliedPsychology10: 233-52. Neff, Donald. 198L Warriors at Suez.New York: Linden Press. Neufeld, Mark. 1995. The RestructuringofInternational RelationsTheory. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press. Nutting, Anthony. 1967. No End 0/a Lesson: The Story ofSuez.New York: Clarkson N. Potter. Oakes, Penelope,and John Turner. 1986. "Distinctivenessand the Salienceof Social CategoryMemberships:Is There an Automatic PerceptualBias TowardsNovelty?" EuropeanJournal ofSocialPsychology16: 325-44. Onuf, Nicholas. 1989. World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social TheOlY and InternationalRelations.Columbia,SC: University of SouthCarolinaPress. Park, Bernadette,and Charles M. Judd. 1990. "Measuresand Models of Perceived Group Variability." Journal o/PersonalityandSocialPsychology59: 173-91. - - - , Carey S. Ryan, and Charles M. Judd. 1992. "The Role of Meaningful Sub- 122 PAUL KOWERT groups in Explaining Differences in PerceivedVariability for In-Groups and OutGroups."Journal ofPersonalityandSocialPsychology63: 553--67. Peterson,V. Spike, ed. 1992. GenderedStates: Feminist (Re)Visions of International RelationsTheory. Boulder,co: Lynne Rienner. Said, Edward. 1979. Orientalism.New York: Vintage. Searle, John R. 1969. SpeechActs: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press. Shamir, Shimon. 1989. "The Collapseof Project Alpha." In Suez1956: The Crisi~ and its recognizably Consequences, ed. W. RogerLouis andRogerOwen,73--100.Oxford: Clarendon. Sherif, Muzafer. 1961. Intergroup Conflict and Cooperation: The RobbersCave Experiment. Norman: University of OklahomaBook Exchange. 1966. In CommonPredicament:Social Psychologyof Intergroup Conflict and Cooperation.Boston: HoughtonMifflin. Snyder, Jack. 1991. Myths of Empire: DomesticPolitics and International Ambition. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Sylvester, Christine. 1994. Feminist Theory and International Relations in a PastmodernEra. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press. Tajfel, Henri. 1969. "Cognitive Aspects of Prejudice." Journal of Social Issues 25: 79-97. ed. 1978. DijJerentiation BetweenSocial Groups: Studies in the Social PsychologyofIntergroup Relations.London: AcademicPress. 1981. Human Groups and Social Categories: Studiesin Social Psychology. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press. Tickner, J. Ann. 1992. Gender in International Relations: Feminist Perspectiveson AchievingGlobal Security.New York: ColumbiaUniversity Press. Turner, John C. 1982. "Towards a Cognitive Redefinition of the Social Group." In Social Identity and Intergroup Relations,ed. Henri Tajfel, 15-40. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press. ---.1991. SocialInfluence.Buckingham,UK: Open University Press. Welch, David. 1992. "The OrganizationalProcessand BureaucraticPolitics Paradigms: Retrospectand Prospect"InternationalSecurity17: 112-46. Wendt, Alexander. 1987. "The Agent-StructureProblemin InternationalRelationsTheory." InternationalOrganization41: 335-70. - - - . 1994. "Collective Identity Formation and the International State." American Political ScienceReview88: 384-96. Zisk, Kimberly. 1993. Engagingthe Enemy: Organization Theory and SovietMilitary Innovation, 1955--1991.Princeton:PrincetonUniversity Press. 6 Feminist Struggle as Social Construction: Changing the Gendered Rules of Home-BasedWork Elisabeth Priigl "Thosewho were marginalare now enteringthe mainstream"was the hopeful conclusion of Ela Bhatt, secretary general of the Self-Employed Women's Association (SEWA) of India, at the Meeting of Experts convenedby the InternationalLabor Organization(ILO) in Genevain the fall of 1990. The meeting explored the situation of homeworkers(i.e., those who work at home for pay), their conditionsof work, governmentpolicies toward them, and the possible role of the ILO in improving their lives. Ubiquitous in urban and rural areasaroundthe world, home-basedworkers sew garments;embroider; make lace; roll cigarettes;weave carpets;peel shrimp; preparefood; polish plastic; processinsuranceclaims; edit manuscripts; and assembleartificial flowers, umbrellas,and jewelry. Somesubcontractwith factories,large firms, intermediaries,or merchants;othersare quasi-independent and sell their goods and services--oftenin a highly dependentfashion. Some work by themselves;others are embeddedwithin family enterprises.Virtually all receivelow wagesand work underadverse conditions. While the meeting in Genevawas divisive, Bhatt's sentiment proved visionary: in June of 1996 the International Labor Conference of the ILO, passedan internationalcon(ILC), the policy-making assembly vention (multilateral treaty) committing ratifYing statesto developnational policies on home-basedworkers, which recognizedthem as employeesand securedthem basicworker rights and protections. 123 124 ELISABETH PROGL The fight for an internationalconventionon homeworkprovides a case for the study of genderedrules in global politics and for the centralrole that social movementsplay in the reconstructionof such rules. A network of women in nongovernmentalorganizationsfrom Asia, Europe, and South Africa lobbied for the homeworkconvention.Their efforts built on thoseof the global women'smovement,which had long arguedthat female workers were no different from male workers and that women'shome-basedwork, both paid and unpaid, was as valuableas work outsidethe home. Employing a constructivistframework allows me to interpreteventsthat led to the conventionas a processof changing,institutionalizing, and codifYing different categoriesof rules. A disproportionatenumberof home-basedworkers are married women with children. Their work is embeddedin a numberof overlappinginstitutions, and both conformsto and clasheswith the rules of theseinstitutions. As membersof households,home-basedworkersoccupythe roles of wives, mothers,daughters,or sisters,and are expectedto fill theseroles according to culturally diverse expectations.As agentsin a polity, women workers gain rights and duties of citizenship which carry strongly genderedovertones.As participantsin a labor market, women workers are subjectto the rules of sex-typingand the unequaldistribution of rewardsthis engenders. Frequently,genderrules in households,the economy,and stateshave functioned to disempower women. The disadvantagedstatus of home-based workers is one result, and has spawnedthe movementto rectifY this situation. Changingrules abouthome-based work thus implies a wider changeof rules in households,the economy,and the state. The focus of my investigationis the practicesof the "homeworkermovement," embeddedwithin the global feminist movementand the labor movement. Social movementsconstitute a counterpartto the globalization of production and the accompanyinginternationalizationof states which in~ recognizably creasinglyorient their economic and social policies to the systemic imperatives of global capitalism. In finding alliances across borders and focusing their activities "aboveand below the state" (Wapner1995), social movementsquestion the reality of statesas the containersof legitimate politics and open up spacefor the democratizationof global politics. They do so by seekingto influence internationaltreaties,conventions,and other commitments.They do so as well by establishingthe legitimacy of new claims to rights (e.g., human rights), and by creatingcommitmentson the part of those in power to honor theserights. But they exercisedemocracy perhapsmost importantly by changingthe rules of identity. Arguably the main accomplishmentof the global women'smovementhas beento funda- FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 125 mentally challengeunderstandingsof proper womanhoodand manhood, which havelong servedto subordinatewomen. Feminism and Constructivism Although feminism is not a monolithic body of thought, and although it thrives on disagreementsand multiple perspectives,most contemporary feminists agreeon one issue: genderis a social construct.The rejection of biological determinismwas at the base of early feminist critiques in the second wave of the women's movement. Today many feminists have shifted from talking about sex and women to talking about genderin order to focus attention from the biological to the social. This is reflected in SandraHarding's characterizationof genderas "a systematicsocial constructionof masculinityand femininity that is little, if at all, constrainedby biology" (1987, 8). As a social construct, gender has history and is an integral part of politics. Joan Scott'sdefinition complementsHarding's in framing genderpolitically as "a constitutiveelementof social relationships basedon perceiveddifferencesbetweenthe sexes,and .. , a primary way of signifYing relationshipsof power" (Scott 1986, 1067). As a constitutive elementof social relations,genderinvolves symbols,norms, organizations, institutions, and subjectiveidentities. As a way of signifYing relationships of power, genderdivides the world in a binary fashion which providesthe meansfor the articulationandlegitimation of power. Feminist writers on internationalrelationshave long arguedthat gender is a useful categoryfor understandingglobal politics and have insistedthat gender constructionsare pervasive. Unfortunately, feminist international relations(IR) literaturetypically doesnot connectthe term social construction to a body of theory. This usagepapersover considerabledifferencesin approachof authorssteepedin different theoreticaltraditions.At the risk of oversimplification,it is possibleto suggesttheoreticalinfluencesin recent tcxts. Michel Foucault's concerns with the formation of identities and JacquesDerrida's method of deconstructionresonatein Christine Sylvester'susageof the term. Sylvesterdescribesmen and women as "socially constructed"in the sense"that men and women are the stories that havebeentold about 'men' and 'women'andthe constraintsand opportunities that have thereby arisen as we take to our proper places" (1994, 4). Foucaultianand Marxist themesappearin CynthiaEnloe'semphasison the practicesof variousglobal actorsto describemanipUlationsof and contests over definitions of masculinityand femininity (Enloe 1989, 1993). Similar frameworksmay underlie JanJindy Pettman'srecentbook in which social 126 ELISABETH PROGL constructionsemergeas the manipulationsof stateswhich, sheargues,construct the public/private divide, "manufacture" citizens, and construct "'deviant' forms of sexuality" (Pettman 1996). Spike Petersonand Anne SissonRunyan draw on sociological and Marxist conceptsto suggestthat social construction involves the socialization and social reproduction of stereotypesand ideologies(1993. 19--26). SandraWhitworth and Deborah Stienstra,in Coxianlneo-Gramscian fashion, conceptualizesocial construction as an interaction of material conditions,institutions, and ideasor discourses(Whitworth 1994,4;Stienstra1994). Thesetexts use social constructionto convey two ideas. First, the term signalsa concernwith "the social" as opposedto material :::apabilities,static structures,unquestionedpositivities, or "pre-given" identities.The social becomes real in discourses,stories, practices,and ideas. Second,the term is meantto indicate impermanence,historicity, and malleability. Storiescan be rewritten; discoursescan be deconstructed;practicescan change;stereotypes can alter; ideologies can be revealed; and material conditions, institutions, and ideas can change. The texts thus do capture basic insights of social constructivism,especially those which are useful to an understandingof feminist struggleand in this way to informing feminist practice.Yet, what is lacking is an understandingof the processesof institutionalization,of the way in which agency and structure are co-constitutedin the social. This gives rise to both theoretical and practical problems. Closer looks at two exemplaryauthors,Whitworth as an advocateof the materialist framework and Sylvesteras a protagonistof post-structuralideas,showthe difficulty. I see two weaknessesin Whitworth's approach,which result from not following throughon social constructivism.First, Cox's materialistfoundations trap her in modernistdualisms inimical to some of the most consequential feminist theorizingwhich insists that the biological and bodiesare as much part of the social as other expressionsof gender.Whitworth (and Cox) insist that the relationship betweenideas, institutions, and material conditionsis reciprocal and that no one determinesthe other. Yet, material conditions appearto have a reality of their own, not outside history but outside politics and social construction.This leads to problematicconclusions when Whitworth grafts nonclasscategoriesonto Cox's class-based framework. "Age, race, sex, sexualorientation,etc." emergeas prepolitical givens, material realities which may be politicized in particular contexts but, like class, exist as categoriesin themselves(Whitworth 1994, 69). However, human sexuality and sexual orientation are not prediscursive. Social orderscreatebiological conceptionsthat perpetuateunequaldistributions of power. Genderdiscourserequiresthat therebe a coherencebetween sex and gender,and this coherenceis built on a compulsoryheterosexual FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 127 matrix (Harding 1986, 12&-30; Butler 1990). From a social constructivist perspective,the distinctionbetweenthe materialandthe ideal is not tenable; ideascontaminatematerial reality. From the perspectiveof many feminists, the distinction is at a minimum problematic;at a maximumit participatesin the naturalizationof sexandgender. A secondproblem with Cox's approaeharisesfrom its failure to adequately addressthe agent-structureproblem. While Whitworth discusses extensivelythe needfor an approachthat accountsfor both individual purposeandthe social constraintsof history, Cox doesnot provide her with the analytical tools to follow through on this insight. To be sure, her analysis explores theinterests,intentions,and agitationsof activists, states,and the ILO, togetherwith material conditions in various phasesof history. But asidefrom statingcorrespondences, Whitworth is not able to connectideas, institutions, and material conditions. Ideas and material conditions appear ontologically separate,and institutions emergeas reflections of ideas and materialconditions.One is left to wonderhow thesereflectionsare generated and how ideas, institutions, and material conditions relate to agency and structure.Cox and Whitworth miss an opportunity in not taking seriously Cox's own definition of institutions as social constructs,as "the broadly understoodand acceptedways of organizingparticular spheresof social action" (Cox 1996, 149). Sylvester'sFeminist Theory and International Relations in a PostmodernEra tacklesa major debateamongcontemporaryfeminist theorists, which pits "post-structuralists,"who destabilizeand questionthe unity of subjects,against"humanists,"who argue that such practicehas pernicious effects. Critical of the implications of modernistlogocentrism,of its concern with origins and foundations,and of its silencingof "Others" through the naturalizationof identities, post-structuralistfeminists reject an understandingof "women" as subjectsof politics and insist that "women" needto be analyzedas an outcomeof discursivepractices.Humanistfeministsreply that this understandingdelegitimizes emancipatoryclaims on behalf of womenas a group and doesaway with historical agents.As subjectsdisappear, so do notions of intentionality, accountability, self-reflexivity, and autonomy,ideaswhich they claim are central to feminist critique and practice (Benhabibet al. 1995). Sylvesterjoins a growing numberof feminist thinkers who seekto combine the insightsof post-structuralistsandhumaniststo makethe casefor "a position of negotiation between standpoint feminism [which privileges women's experiencesas constitutedsubjects] ... and postmodernskepticism [which questionsthe constitutionof thesesubjects]"(Sylvester1994, 12; seealso Alcoff 1988; Ferguson1993).Thus, Sylvesterrescueshumanist 128 ELISABETH PROGL valuesby mergingthe standpointapproach'sinsistenceon a fusion of being and knowing with post-modernunderstandingsof the variability and multip!icity of identities. She insists that subjectscan find temporary "homesteads"from which they can speak.Such homesteadsenablea politics of emancipation.In this way "people called women" do not need to have a unitary, immobile, and monolithic identity. They speakfrom ever-shifting anddifferent standpoints. Sylvester'sformulation is appealing. It foregrounds feminist practice while cautioningabout the totalizing implications of fixing a unitary feminine identity. However,Sylvester'spost-structuralistpoint of departureprevents her from developinga theory of agency,in which not only are men and women the "stories that have been told about 'men' and 'women'" (Sylvester1994,4),but also discoursesare continuouswith everydaycommunicationand subjectsactively constructeachother through communicative practices.Sylvesterremainscaughtin an ultimately static methodology that puts congealedtexts at the centerof its analysis.We learn that women at GreenhamCommonsand in the cooperativesof Zimbabwe challenge meaningsand interpretations,but we do not learn how these challenges enterthe storiesabout thesewomen. What is lacking is a theory of agency that illustratesthe institutionalizationof narratives.Constructivismprovides sucha theory. Indeed,there is a significant strandof feminist constructivist theorizing in the social sciences(e.g., Connell 1987; Kesslerand McKenna 1978; Lorber 1994). Constructivism in International Relations: A Method for Gender Analysis Constructivismhas emergedas one of the major strandsof the "third debate" in internationalrelations. The central tenet of constructivismis that people and societies,agentsand structures,construct, or constitute, each other. Constructivistsargue that internationallife is social, that is, that it follows norms and rules which make up social structures.Thesestructures reproduceonly through the practicesof knowledgeableagents.Structures and agentscannotexist without eachother: they are mutually constitutive. Actors draw on the rules that makeup structuresin their everydayroutines, and in doing so they reproducethese rules. They have the capacity to understandwhat they are doing and why they are doing it, which allows them to "reflexively monitor" the social practicesthey engagein. Structures make possiblesimilar social practicesacrosstime and space,thus ensuring the relative stability of social life. Like the post-structuralistswho influencedSylvester,constructivistsput FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 129 languagein the centerof their understandingof the social. But unlike poststructuralists,constructivistsfocus on processesthat producethe social, not on the social as an effect of relatively static discourses.They approach languageas social practice,not as a textual artifact or discursivefonnation. They are interestednot only in identities signified in narratives,stories,and discourses,but in the intersectionof signifYing and doing. The fluidity of the social is well capturedin Jtirgen Habennas'stheory of communicative action,which roots socialpracticein communicationandargumentationand which fonns the basisof NicholasOnuf's constructivistdiscussionof rules. Onuf's refonnulationmakespossiblean understandingof the multiple ways in which genderfonns, perpetuates,and mutatesthrough communicative action. According to Habennas,all communicativestatementsentail validity claims; that is, a speakerclaims that a statementis factually correct, nonnatively right, andnondeceptive.If the heareracceptstheseclaims,understanding is accomplishedand speechacquiresa binding force. Communicativeagents renew their interpersonalrelationshipand afftnn their agreementaboutobjective facts of the world andaboutSUbjectiveexperiences(Habennas1984, 295-305).Onufarguesthat the speechact agreementsthat underliecommunicative action produceand reproducesocial structures.Rulesprovide the "missing link" betweensocial structuresand temporaryagreementsresulting from understanding.The nonnative force of a speechact agreement becomesa conventionwhen othersjoin in the agreementand repeatpropositions with complementarycontent.Conventionsbecomerules oncepeople follow conventionsas a matter of routine and once they recedefrom consciousdeliberations(Onuf 1989,78--95). Various authorsin the field recentlyhavethrown light on the importance of studying nonns and rules in international politics from a sociological perspective.Onuf criticizes this work, togetherwith post-positivistliterature, for treating nonns as context. He arguesinsteadthat rules (a tenn he prefersto nonns)arepositivitiesandas suchare capableof empirical investigation and classification(Onuf 1997). His classificationof rules into instruction-rules,directive-rules,and commitment-rulesprovides a heuristic tool for investigatingthe interlacing ways in which genderis constructed. Instruction-rulesdefine, describeidentities,and statebeliefs about the way things are. They makeclaims aboutfacts, elicit agreementaboutthesefacts on the part of others,and therebybring about confonnity. Directive-rules imply commands,requests,demands,pennissions,and warnings. They elicit compliance,obeisance,submission.Commitment-rulesimply promises and offers that oblige individuals to act accordingly.All three types of rules are both regulative and constitutive. In other words, all three elicit 130 ELISABETH PROGL action on the part of otherswhile also establishingsocial facts(Onuf 1989, 78-95). Constructivismprovidesa promisingmethodfor studyingthe struggleof homeworkeradvocates.First, constructivismallows for a specificationof genderas a constellationof rules and in this way providesa tool for investigating a social fact which, as many feminists have correctly argued,is both historical and fluid. Second,the focus on rules uniquely puts activism in the center and allows for an understandingof the ways it effects changes. Ratherthan depictinga singularoppressivestructure,reflectionsof material or ideological changes,or the economicsof a static text, a constructivist approachallows for a specification of the types of rule changeswhich different forms of activism accomplish.Third, constructivismprovides for an understandingof how rule changeseffect new realities within institutions, themselvessetsof rules. Suchinstitutionsmay be individuals or other agents,such as householdsor states(seeOnufs essayin Chapter3 of this volume). In addition, genderitself constitutesan institution, one that cuts acrossother institutions and supportsthe constellationsof rule and power they constitute.Altering rules of genderthus inevitably affects the rules of other institutions as well. A focus on institutions allows me to trace such interlockingchanges. The Gendered Rules of Home-BasedWork Home-basedwork carriesvery different meaningsin different contexts.For somewomen it meansan extensionof their domesticactivities to provide an additional "service" to their families, for some it is an opportunity to savein a honorableway for their dowries, for someit is a tradition, and for some it is the equivalentof factory jobs in the absenceof a factory. For example,in Rio de Janeiro,Brazil, cultural ideasaboutproperwomanhood and religious identifications mergewith exploitativepracticesof employers as housewives.In Lahore, Pakistan, to constructhome-basedseamstresses understandingsof honor, respectability,and family status,togetherwith the needto savemoneyfor their dowries,encourageyoung womento engagein home-basedwork. For rural, home-basedTurkish carpetweavers,weaving is part of a girl's socialization,and is integral to farming householdswhere female householdmemberssharetheir labor power and weavingsubsidizes agricultural investments.In Thailand, rural homeworkersfall into two groups:a group of older women and men for whom homeworkis a supplementary activity that easily integratesinto the agricultural cycle, and a group of younger women who produce for export-orientedfirms and for whom home-basedpieceworkis the main sourceof income. FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 131 Despite the differences in contexts and the divergent meanings they spawn, understandingsof home-basedwork have one thing in common: they invariably define such work as secondary.On the one hand, homebasedwork emergesas subsidiary to either male income or agricultural income. On the other hand, it appearsas transitional for those moving toward marriage or for those who think of themselvesas unemployed. Instruction-rulesthat associatehome-basedwork with women are grafted onto a basic principle that identifies women as subordinateto men; in this way instruction-rulesfacilitate a constructionof home-basedwork as supplementary.This goes along with an identification of men as primary incomeearnersand of women'swork as "not real work." The genderedrules of households,labor markets, and statespowerfully conspire to effect a constructionof home-basedwork as secondary. RulesoftheHousehold Householdsare institutions defined largely by commitment-rules.These rules pervasivelycommit women to take on the duties of motherhoodand housework,duties that come with marriage.There is considerablevariation, as expectationsabout women's roles within householdsrespondto local rules of custom and religion. A woman in Pakistanmay have to commit herselfto live in one of various degreesof seclusion,while custom tells a woman in Ghana to work the fields and grow food for the family, or a working-class woman in the United Statesmay be expectedto make an economiccontributionto the householdin additionto perfonningherdomestic duties. Despite these differences,married women in particular tend to share a tie to the home, which limits their work options. In the Western context it is appropriateto describethis limitation as implied in a "marriage contract"throughwhich womenin effect give up part of the propertyin their own person,including full control over their labor power (Pateman1988). The languageof contractsmay be inappropriatefor describingthe situations of women in other cultures, but for them marital status and motherhood equally are definedthrough a seriesof commitment-ruleswhich often function to tie their labor power to the needsof the household.Not surprisingly, statisticsconfinn that a disproportionatenumberof home-basedworkers in countries all over the world are not only female but married with small children. Home-basedwork allows such womento combinetheir household andmotheringdutieswith earningan income(Priigl 1992). From thosein the gannentindustry in Delhi to thosein white-collarjobs in Great Britain and Silicon Valley, many home-basedworkers see themselvesprimarily as housewives,mothers,or dutiful daughtersand only sec- 132 ELISABETH PROGl ondarily as income-earners;they consciouslysubordinatetheir paid work to family commitments (Rao and Husain 1987, 62-63; Hakim 1987, 98; Lozano 1989, 122). Women who participatedin the clerical homeworker program of the Wisconsin PhysiciansServicesInsuranceCorporationbelieved that a woman'splace was in the home with her family and that she should not take away a male breadwinner'sjob (Costello 1989, 201). In Rio, 50 percent of the seamstresses who said they preferred to work at homedid so becauseof family or domesticreasons.They perceivedbeing a seamstressnot as a profession but as a service to themselvesand their families (Sorj 1991, 7f.). Garmenthomeworkersin CentralJavawere often their families' main income earnersin a context of high levels of male unemploymentYet they insisted that they were only "working for salt," and that the men were the true breadwinners.They maintainedthat their domesticwork camefirst, eventhoughthey had no time to cook during the peak sewing seasonand frequently bought food from local vendors(Susilastuti 1990,9). Despite this primary commitment to the family, home-basedincome earning often conflicts with householdduties, and home-basedworkers draw negativeconsequences from violating their promisesto be good mothers and housewives.Husbandsof home-basedworkers rarely reducetheir expectationsabout domestic work. For example,a homeworkerfrom the u.K. complainedthat "if I haven'tmanagedto get some houseworkdone becauseI've been too busy doing homework then I'm asked--'Whatdo you do all day long(?]' as ifI just sit around all day long" (Trivedi 1985, 18). The attitude of men in Pakistanwas that home-basedwork was something which women indulged in and which therefore should not cut into their time for housework:"Well, we did not ask them to work. If shewants to work it's her responsibilityto make sure she can handleher housework first, which is her first duty as mother and wife" (Shaheedand Mumtaz, n.d., 53-54). Women'shome-basedwork affected genderroles in the householdby questioningwho was the breadwinner.Husbandsusedvarioustechniquesto deny this challengeand to uphold the notion that they were breadwinners and their wives were nonworking housewives.In Narsapur,husbandsdid not produce lace but created a myth that they invested money in their wives' work and portrayed themselvesas entrepreneurs.In Turkey and Afghanistan,men sold the carpetsthat womenin their householdmade,and kept the money. In this way they retainedcontrol over householdspending decisionsand appearedto be the true breadwinners(Mies 1982,95;Berik 1987,72). The rules of householdsare one elementin definitions of genderand the FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 133 privilegesthey distribute. They are a centralelementin a set of interlocking institutions that keepshome-basedworkers subordinate.The commitmentrules of marriageand the householdthus emergeas a crucial challengefor homeworkeradvocates. Rulesofthe State Many statestoday are built on liberal understandingsthat divide a society into a public and a private sphere.The line that divides the two spheresis a matter of social agreement,but liberal statestypically have treatedhouseholds as private and out of the reach of the state. Since the industrial revolution moved most manufacturinginto factories, and with the creation of welfare states, work outside the home has become a target of state interventioneffectedby law, or fonnal directive-rules.In parallel, the home increasinglyhas been defined as the sphereof women and has been constructed ideologically as outside the regulatory reach of the state. In an effort to reducethe unfair competition home-basedworkers posedto factory workers, legislatorsin Europe, the Americas, and Australia regulated home-basedwork in the first half of the twentieth century. But in most countriestoday legislation on home-basedwork is severelylacking. Out of 150 countriesthe ILO surveyedin the early 1990s, only 18 (mostly European) countries had specific homework legislation; another 22 (mostly Latin American) countriesaddressedthe matter in their labor codes. With the exceptionof Japan,India, and the Philippines,no country in Africa or Asia regulatedhome-basedwork. The definition of householdsas homes, supposedlyout of the reach of the state and ruled by private convention under the authority of male headsof households,preventedregulation (InternationalLabor Office 1994,28). In most casesif home-basedworkerswant to qualify for legal protection, they have to claim that they are not only membersof householdsbut also employeesof a finn. But legal testsof employmentstatustypically address the situationof office and factory workers. Under a numberof commonlaw legal criteria, home-basedworkers.often emergeas self-employed.Such criteria test whether work is carried out on the employer's premises, whether the worker owns any of the tools, whether the worker works for more than one employer, or whether the worker has been engagedfor a continuousperiod of time. Many home-basedworkers would fail to qualify on all thesecriteria. Furthennore,home-basedworkers often are preempted from benefitsbecausebenefitsare frequently conditionalupon the length of serviceor upon the numberof hoursworked. It is thereforenot surprisingthat lawyers, legislators,and other officers 134 ELISABETH PRUGL of the state have arguedthat home-basedworkers are not real employees. For example,the Indian SupremeCourt, in a 1961 ruling, interpretedthe Indian FactoriesAct to apply only when "workers were working on the premisesof the employer,had no liberty to work at homeand the employer could exercisethe power of control by rejecting the sub standard[products]" (Mahajan 1985, 8). And while the Indian Bidi and Cigar Workers Act of 1966 clearly defined home-basedbidi (cigarette)rollers as employees,the chief labor inspectorin Gujarat"insisted on questioningas to how somebodyworking in a private house could ever be an employee" (31). When based on an instruction-rule that defined home-basedworkers as nonworkers, directives geared toward improving the status of workers failed home-basedworkers. The JapaneseIndustrial Homework Law of 1970 is one of the few homework laws which explicitly excludeshomebasedworkers from protection under various labor laws and from social security protection. As a result, they do not receive benefits in casesof injuries or sickness,maternity benefits, unemploymentbenefits, or retirement benefits(Kamio 1991, 25-26). In other countries,laws do not exclude home-basedworkers explicitly, but confusionabout their statusoften functions to exclude them de facto. In parallel to instruction-rulesthat define public and private, work and home, as separate,home-basedworkers are confirmednot to be real workers and are excludedfrom directivesthat gain employeesbenefitsandprotection. Statistical practices reinforce these instruction-rules.National surveys routinely undercounthome-basedworkers becausesuch surveystypically take placeat one point in time and miss seasonalor intermittenthome-based work, becausehome-basedwork sometimesresemblesproduction for domestic use, becausemale heads of householdswho respond to surveys considerthe women'swork a leisure-timeactivity or would like to hide this work for reasonsof family honor, becausesurveysrarely ask about "secondary" employment,becausecensustakersmay not speakthe languageof home-basedworkers who-especiallyin England,the United States,Canada, and Australia-are often immigrants, becausehome-basedworkers themselvesmay not want to reveal their work and alert tax authoritiesand enforcersof labor law, and becausesurveysof businessestablishmentsdo not cover thesetypes of activities (Dixon 1982, 543-46). The practice of undercountingwomen'shome-basedwork producesstartling outcomes.For example, in Narsapur, India, the 1971 censusshowed 6,449 personsinvolved in householdindustries.But the main industry in town, with 8 million to 9 million rupeesa year in turnover, was home-basedlace making, employingan estimated100,000women. Becauselace making was considereda leisureactivity of housewives,lace makersdid not appearas workers FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 135 in the census(Mies 1982,49,54).In Turkey, carpetweaving was similarly deemeda pastimesuitable for women and national employmentstatistics did not count weavers,although they earnedabout half the householdincomeof poor families (Berik 1987,2,15,61). In changingthe practicesof states,homeworkeradvocatesneedto combine changesin instruction-ruleswith Jaws that direct employersto define homeworkersas employeesand with administrativeregulationsthat ensure the properimplementationof suchlaws, as wen as making sure that homebasedwork is countedin censuses.Such directivesare likely to strengthen changedimages of what home-basedworkers are and also are likely to facilitate a sensethat home-basedworkersare entitledto workers' rights. Ruleso/theLaborMarket Labor market practicesreinforce rules that constructhome-basedworkers as nonworkersand their work as secondaryand subordinate.On the face of it, the rules of supply and demandare systemicand outside social control, and genderbiasesare an unintendedconsequence resultingfrom constraints external to the labor market. But feminist critique has denaturalizedthe rules of the market,pointing out that employersdraw on instruction-rulesof gender in making employment decisions. Genderednotions of skill (women's skills, such as sewing, are usuany defined as natural) and the sex-typing of jobs form the labor market counterpartto the rules of the household.They conspirewith the understandingthat home-basedworkers are housewiveswho earn merely supplementalincome and whosework is not important for family survival, to provide a powerful legitimation for denyingsuchworkersbasicrights. Most perniciously,theserules legitimate the puny wagesof home-basedworkers. There is overwhelmingevidence that home-basedworkers almost invariably earn less than minimum wages and less than their factory counterparts,lending credenceto the assertion that theseworkers are "superexploited"(Mies 1982, 172-78; Prtigl 1992, 226-39,323-32). Becausehome-basedworkers are definedas nonworkers,by the rules of the labor market they often becomeself-employed(even though they may actually qualify for employeestatusundernationallaw). The self-employed constitutea default category, comprising all those who do not have employeestatus.In practice,the self-employedhaveconsiderablyfewer rights and protectionsthan employees.Their role in the labor market is defined througha "contractfor services;'in which they appearas individual sellers, not of their labor power, but of a service. They negotiatethe price of that service, are not coveredunder minimum wage laws, and fall outside the 136 ELISABETH PROGL umbrella of collective bargaining. They set their own hours, do not earn incomewhen sick or on vacation,and are responsiblefor their own training. They lack any type of job security. The rules of the market encourageself-employmentstatusfor all workers. From the perspectiveof employers,self-employedworkers are desirable becausethey reducelabor costs: Employerscan circumventstatutory minimum wages and collective bargaining agreements,and they do not have to provide a workplace and pay the overheadcosts associatedwith maintaining a workplace. Furthermore,self-employedworkers allow employers flexibility: Employersdo not have to keep workers on the payroll when no work is available and thus effectively transferpart of the risk of doing businessto the workers.By resortingto self-employedworkersrather than employees,employersincreasetheir chancesof successfullycompeting in the market. Conditions of surpluslabor encouragesituationsin which workers will make themselvesattractive to employersby assumingthe status of seIfemployment.As a result, most home-basedworkers in Africa, Asia, and Latin America are defacto self-employed.The marketfunctions as a heteronomousinstitution in which workers becomecomplicit in their own exploitation. For women in addition, the rules of the householdand the state encourageself-employment.Becauselabor laws have beenwritten largely for male workers who have full control over their own labor power, they make no allowance for flexibility. Women workers need such flexibility becausethey needto integratefamily and householdduties with earningan income.Despitethe considerablepotentialfor exploitation,rigid labor laws leaveself-employmentas a desirableoption. Thus the seeminglyinnocuousrules of supply and demandconspireto keephome-basedworkersin a subordinateposition in the labormarket.The challengefor homeworkeradvocatesis to shapethe rules of employment contractsso that employerstake on the obligationsof ensuringbasicworker rights while maintainingthe flexibility of home-based work. HomeNet International and the Struggle for Home-basedWorkers In March 1994, a group of homeworkactivists, representativesof international union federations, and ILO officers met in Brussels to launch HomeNet International,a loose network of individuals and organizations with the sharedaim of improving the lot of home-basedworkersaroundthe world. HomeNet'spurposewould be to facilitate the exchangeand dissemination of information about home-basedworkers and their organizations FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 137 and to coordinate an international campaign to improve the living and working conditions of theseworkers. It was the Self-EmployedWomen's Association(see p. 123), a nongovernmentalgroup from India, that called the meeting.SEWA had worked with home-basedworkers for many years and had actively lobbied the ILO to draft an internationallabor standardfor such workers. SEWA was concernedthat homeworkeradvocatesmobilize supportfor sucha standardin their countriesbecausethe 1995 International Labor Conferencehad placed homework on its agenda.Among those atof SEWA, the National tending the founding meetingwere representatives HomeworkingGroup in the United Kingdom, the Associationfor the Establishment of a Self-EmployedWomen's Union in South Africa, and the International Ladies' Garment Workers' Union in Canada; officers of HomeworkSupportCentersand the CleanClothesCampaignin the Netherlands; and delegatesfrom internationalunion federationsand the International Labor Office (Ramirez 1995, 29-30). An all-female gathering,the meeting constituted a section of the organizationalface of the global women's movement.Feminists in nongovernmentalorganizationsjoined forceswith thosein the ILO to pushthe casefor an internationalconvention on homework. The homeworkeradvocates'successin realizing the formalization of rules to regulatehomework was built on long-standingefforts within the of what it meansto be global women'smovementto changeunderstandings a home-basedworker. The "women in development"(WID) movement provideda devastatingcritique of technicalassistanceefforts and economic policies formulatedunderthe presumptionthat all womenwere nonworking housewives.Such policies had a detrimentaleffect on women'sstatusand frequently dcrailed developmentprojects. The WID critique initiated a change in instruction-rules,creating awarenessthat home-basedwomen contributed to national wealth. Increasingly, plannersand policy makers understoodthat thesewomenwere workers.Homeworkeradvocatesparticipatedin this redefinition through researchand public advocacyas well as throughconsciousness raisingamonghome-based workers. The fight for an ILO conventionon homework drew strengthfrom the degreeto which changedunderstandingsof women workers had become accepted.Homeworker advocateshoped that the convention would lead statesto issuedirective-rulesaboutthe way in which employersand officers of the statewere to treathome-based workers. Indian, British, and Canadian advocatesespeciallyfound national legislation to be insufficient. Neither country had homeworking laws, and all had encounteredthe damaging effects of neoliberal economic restructuringfor unprotectedworkers. In Britain, the Thatcheradministrationabolishedthe "trades boards,"which 138 ELISABETH PROGL sincc the beginningofthe centuryhad establishedminimum wagesin "lowpay industries."While many advocatesfound the boardsproblematic,doing away with them left British homeworkerswithout any legal recourse.In the Canadiangarmentindustry, the effects of the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA) showed in the form of jobs moving south and in increasedsubcontractingto home-basedworkers, many of them immigrants. Intensive lobbying yielded a few changesin regulationsbut no substantivereform of the law. In India, SEWA had managedto get introduced to the Indian parliamenta homeworkerprotection bill, but the bill neverreachedthe floor. In the contextof talk aboutopeningthe economyto foreign investment and making the country intemationally competitive, home-basedworkers and new regulationscarried low priority for Indian lawmakers.Having encounteredless than sympatheticgovernments,Indian andBritish advocatesin particulartumedto the internationallevel. While advocatesexpendeda considerableamountof energyin lobbying for an ILO conventionon homework, they retaineda realistic view of its potentialeffects.Advocatesknew that legislationwas uselessin the absence of strongorganizationsto standguardover its implementation.To makethe laws a reality--to tum governmentorders into workers' rights---would require the interventionsof strong workers' organizations.But in India, the Bidi and Cigar WorkersAct had taughtadvocatesthat having a law was in itself a powerful organizing tool. SEWA activists used the act to gather workers in the tobaccoindustry into their union while gaining them their legal rights. Knowing that the Indian governmenttook very seriouslyany ILO action, SEWA's aim was to use the conventionto lobby for a law for all home-basedworkersand to maketheserights a reality for all. ChangingInstruction-Rules At the 1995 ILC, conflict arose over a photo exhibit, organized by HomeNet,which was displayedat the entranceto the meetingroom of the Committeeon Homework. Australian union representativescriticized the exhibit as "too pretty," becauseit showed British homeworkersin tidy homes, Indian homeworkersin colorful saris working togetherin front of their houses,and Philippinehomeworkerscollaboratingon decorativecrafts items. The Australiansaddedtheir own imagesof homeworkers: black-andwhite photos showing tired immigrants at sewing machinesin dilapidated houses.HomeNet representativesdefendedtheir pictures, insisting that it was necessaryto get away from the image of homeworkersas victimized dupeswho haveno powerto changetheir own situation. The photo exhibit constitutedan attack on instruction-rulesabouthome- FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 139 basedworkers prevalentin union circles. Theserules define such workers as outsidethe working class,unable to act in concerton their own behalf. The advocates'attackson instruction-rulesabout home-basedworkers also targetthe imagethat they are nonworkinghousewives.Researchand media projectshaveprovidedtwo of the most salienttools in this effort. Many homeworkeradvocacygroups have a close relationshipwith researchersand carry out considerableresearchthemselves.The Leicester Outwork Campaign, one of the most successfulhomeworker advocacy groups in Britain, has coordinatedresearchwith academicsand provided them with data(Allen and Wolkowitz 1987). In turn, the British homeworking campaignsgained support from researchconductedby the Low Pay Unit, a nongovernmentalorganizationwhich advocatesfor workers in lowpay industries.During the 1970s,its national surveyon homeworkin Britain had a strong impact in the media and fueled a national debateabout introducing a law on homework (Tate 1995, 84). In South Asia, several studies, some sponsoredby the ILO's Employment and Development Branch,havegiven visibility to homeworkand preparedthe groundfor ILO action (Singh and Kelles-Viitanen 1987; Bhatty 1981; Mies 1982). In SoutheastAsia, an ILO project on improving the protectionof home-based workers sponsoredand published researchfindings from Indonesia, the Philippines,and Thailand,which laid the ground for organizingefforts and raisedinterestwithin governmentalbureaucracies,including social security agencies,which beganto look for ways to covertheseworkers(Homeworkersof SoutheastAsia 1992). Typically, these studies unveil as a myth the image that horne-based workers are housewives.They documentthe long hours theseworkers put into their work; the significant contribution they make to family income; and the importanceof their work in the local, national,and global economy. They also documentthe variety of activitieshome-basedworkersengagein, to counteraetunderstandingsthat homeworkis marginal and limited to the gannentindustry. In doing so, they instruct their readersthat homeworkis not just a hobby for housewives,but centralto the functioning of the economy. Thereforehomeworkersmust be consideredworkersjust like thosein factoriesand offices. Thosewho organizehome-basedworkers extensivelyuse researchas a tool to effect change of consciousnessand as an entry to organizing. Through interviews, they educatehome-basedworkers about their rights and about ways to improve their situation. Researchalso helps them identify potentialleadersamonghome-basedworkers.Often organizersdraw on home-basedworkers themselvesto becomeresearchersof their own situation, and suchinvolvementhas given workers a chanceto participatein the 140 ELISABETH PROGL attackon unwarrantedinstruction-rulesin the processof defining their own alternatives. For example, when studentsstarted the Leicester Outwork Campaignin the early 1980s, they believed that homeworkerswould be interestedin strugglingfor betterchild care,which would allow them to go out and find better work. Action researchtaught the studentsthat most home-basedworkers preferred to stay home with their young children. Ratherthan wanting to agitatefor better child care, they were more interestedin strugglingfor betterand more flexible work arrangements.Homebased workers in effect disagreedwith the students' implicit view that home-basedwork was undesirable--thatgood work and real work was that which took place outsidethe home. Action researchfosteredan identification of thesehome-basedworkersas workers--althoughin a nontraditional workplace. By changing self-identifications,action researchweakensinstruction-rulesthat definehome-basedworkersas not real workers. In addition to research,advocatesuse audiovisualmaterialsto publicize the notion that home-basedproducersare workers. British campaignshave contributedto severalvideo productionswhich have beenmadeavailableto national and international television. For example,"A-Z Homework" is a short, professionallymade film that shows the different kinds of products homeworkersmake, interspersedwith demandsfor just wagesand working conditions.Its messagesare: first, homeworkis pervasiveand homeworkers makemany everydayitems; and second;homeworkersare real workerswho deserveto be treatedas such. The British campaignsalso participatedin an ILO documentarymadefor and distributedon the occasionof the 1995 ILC. Similarly, SEWA has beenthe object of at leastone documentaryshownon U.S. public television, andit runs its own video project, through which its membersdocumenttheir situationand demandtheir rights as workers. Through these diverse interventions, homeworker advocateseffect changesin an instruction-rule that is pervasivethroughout society. The messagethat it is a myth to considerhome-basedworkershousewivesneeds to reacheveryonefrom husbandsand neighborsto employersand governments. Defining home-basedworkers as workers is a first step toward changingtheir inferior statusin society. Adding directive-rulesto instruction-rulescansupportthis change. ChangingDirective-Rules The establishmentof HomeNetInternationalsignals astep toward greater coordination and organization among homeworkeradvocates.HomeNet builds on the strengthof SEWA in particular,an accomplishedorganization with tensofthousandsof members,its own bank,social insuranceschemes, FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 141 severalcooperatives,and a good track record of using technical assistance funds from internationaldonors. When SEWA leadersdecidedto push for an ILO conventionon homework,they establishedlinks with and membership in internationaltrade union federationsand won their supportfor the convention. This organizationalstrengthening,of which the formation of HomeNetwas a part, positionedthe movementwell to begin formulating directive-rules andto demand that stateswrite these directive-rulesinto laws. HomeNet members'most important demandwas that home-based workers shouldbe consideredworkersand gain the sameprotectionas other typesof workers. The ILO convention on homework achievesprecisely that. It directs ratifying states to "adopt, implement and periodically review a national policy on home work," and setsas the guiding principle for such a policy "equality of treatmentbetweenhomeworkersand other wage earners."It then lists the areas where equality of treatment should apply: "(a) the homeworkers'right to establishand join organizationsof their own choosing ... ; (b) protection againstdiscrimination in employmentand occupation; (c) proteetion in the field of occupational safety and health; (d) remuneration;(e) statutorysocial securityprotection;(1) accessto training; (g) minimum age for admissionto employmentor work; and (h) maternity protection" (International Labor Conference1996, 3). In legislative and administrativepracticethis list will translatcinto directive-rulesdemanding that employersand agenciesof the stateensureequaltreatment. A home-basedworker who subcontractsfrom an intermediaryor from an employerclearly belongsto a hierarchicalorganizationin which the provider of work rules by giving directives.Indeed,the commondefinition of a dependentemployeeas "under the direction" of a work giver signals precisely this situation. Much of the discussionin formulating the convention on homework centeredaround Article 1, which defined homeworkers: Shouldthey be consideredpart of the work giver's organization,or did they run their own enterprise?Were they in a dependentrelationship,or were they self-employed?Employers insisted that it was impossible to decide which home-basedworker was an independentcontractorandwhich was an employee.Workers, on the other hand, insistedthat a combinationof criteria, mostimportantlygaugingeconomicindependence, allowedfor sucha decision. In defining a broad group of home-basedworkers as dependent, the conventionnot only changedan instruction-rulethat identified homebasedworkers as nonworkersbut acknowledgedthat they were part of an employer-definedorganizationalsetting and were guided by the directives of this setting. The task homeworkeradvocateshave setfor themselvesat this point is 142 ELISABETH PRUGL not to changethesedirectivesbut to gain a broadacceptanceof the principle that home-basedworkers are indeedpart of an employer'sorganization.At the sametime, they seekto combinehome-basedworkersinto organizations that will provide them the opportunity to more effectively negotiatetheir interestsvis-a-vis firms and organizedemployers'interests.Changingdirectives is the bread and butter of such organizations.While a loose network may be sufficient to supportglobal aspirationsand efforts to change instruction-rules,networkscannotsubstitutefor organizationsas actual vehicles effecting changesin the pay and treatmentof workers. Changing Commitment-Rules In most industrialized countries,employeescan expect employersto pay minimum wages and to abide by certain regulations of working hours. There is also a broad expectationthat workers will be allowed to organize in unions and other associationsrepresentingtheir interests.The rules of a "contract for services"are quite different. They commit the worker to produce an item by the time agreedupon and they commit the employerto do no more than pay a price upon delivery. Self-employedworkers may, in most democraticsocieties,have the right to join various groups, but their right to organize in unions may be severelycircumscribed.For example, when SEWA tried to register as a union, its requestwas denied because, accordingto the registrar, self-employedworkers could not organize into unions. Only after two years of argument and after the intercessionof powerful union leaderscould SEWA registerlegally as a union. The ILO conventionon homeworksignals a changeof theserules by setting, as a standardfor home-basedworkers,the rules of the employmentcontract. The challengesfor homeworker advocateswill be to turn the directive-rulesimplied in the conventionand in laws that may result from the convention into employer commitments,and to create among home-based workers a senseof entitlementto employmentrights and protections.Unions and homeworkeradvocacygroupsplayacrucial role in effecting suchcommitment-rulesby acting as watchdogsover the implementationof laws. Someare doing so already.In Australia,the garmentunion hasincludedhomeworkersin collective bargainingagreements;in India, SEWA watchesover violations of the Bidi and Cigar Workers' Act and has taken employersto court to gain workers their rights; in England,homework campaignsadvise homeworkers about their rights underexisting law and publicize violations. For most homeworkers the problem is still that the laws are lacking, but the homeworkconvention provides a significant step toward writing better laws nationally and toward realizingbasicworker rights for home-basedproducers. FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 143 Conclusion The purpose of this chapter is to illustrate the value of a constructivist approachfor studying gender in global politics: that which is meant by "womanhood" or "manhood," that which is demandedfrom women and men, and the different roles women and men play in contractuallydefined situations. It uses the caseof home-basedworkers to trace definitions of gender through the mutually supportive rules of households,states,and labor markets,and it showshow feminist activism unfolds as a challengeto instruction-, directive-, and commitment-rules.In attackingrules, feminist activists changeinstitutions. Householdsin which men no longer are the undisputedbreadwinnerscan no longer uphold men'sauthority on the presumption that they ensurehouseholdsurvival. Statesin which supposedly feminine preoccupationssuchas child care and the distribution of power in householdsmove into the public realm can no longer legitimize thenotion that men are better at ruling and administeringthe affairs of states.And in labor markets where supposedlyfeminine skills and notions of women's pay as supplementalare denaturalized,discriminatorytreatmentis no longer justified. Activism changesrules, and rules changeinstitutions. Yet structuresand institutions also circumscribethe activism of advocates. Employeestatusand union organizing surfaceas the logical methodsof improving the wagesand working conditions of home-basedworkers, because employeestatusand unions exist as well-establishedinstitutions with supporting rules codified in national and internationallabor laws and laws of association. Lobbying govemments(and by extensionthe ILO) for changesin laws presentsitself as an effectiveapproach,becausethe rulesof democraticgovernment prescribe this venue. In contrast, advocatesabstain from demanding ehangesto rules of supply and demandthat have assumedthe status of a systemicimperativeundera capitalistmodeof flexible accumulation,andhave beendefinedasoutsidehistory, no longeramenableto change. Genderstatusesappearas bundlesof social rules anchoredin institutions that reachfrom the local to the global. Gendercrucially definestheseinstitutions by "engendering"distributions of power within them (rules create rule), and complementaryrules in different institutions effect a global subordinationof women. Feminist strugglehas targetedall types of rules in all types of institutions, from the local to the global, and has destabilizeda form of subordinationbasedon the fiction that women are housewives.For home-basedworkers as well, instruction-rules that define them as true workers are becominginstitutionalized;achievingpervasivedirectives and commitmentsfrom governmentsand employers to gain equal rights for home-workersremainsa taskto be accomplished. 144 ELISABETH PRUGL Note I would like to thank Nick Onuf for his thorough readingsof this paper and for his constructivesuggestions. Bibliography Alcoff, Linda. 1988. "Cultural FeminismversusPost-Structuralism:The Identity Crisis in Feminist Theory." Signs: Journal of Womenin Culture and Society13 (Spring): 405-38. Allen, Sheila, and Carol Wolkowitz. 1987. Homeworking: Myths and Realities. London: Macmillan. Benhabib, Seyla, Judith Butler, Drucilla Cornell, and Nancy Fraser. 1995. Feminist Contentions:A PhilosophicalExchange.New York: Routledge. Berik, Giinseli. 1987. Women Carpet Weaversin Rural Turkey: Patterns of Employment, Earningsand Status.Geneva:InternationalLabor Office. Bhatty, Zarina. 1981. The EconomicRoleand Statusof Womenin the BeediIndustry in Allahabad,India. Saarbriicken:Verlag Breitenbach. Butler, Judith. 1990. Gender Trouble: Feminismand the Subversionsof Identity. New York: Routledge. Connell, R.W. 1987. Genderand Power: Society,the Personand SexualPolitics. Stanford: StanfordUniversity Press. Costello,Cynthia. 1989. "The Clerical HomeworkProgramat the WisconsinPhysicians ServicesInsuranceCorporation."In Homework: Historical and ContemporaryPerspectiveson Paid Labor at Home, ed. Eileen Boris and Cynthia Daniels, 198214. Urbana:University of Illinois Press. Cox, Robert W. 1996. "Towardsa PosthegemonicConceptualizationof World Order: Reflections on the Relevancyof Ibn Khaldun."In Approachesto World Order by RobertW. Cox with Timothy Sinclair, 144-73. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press. Dixon, Ruth B. 1982. "Women in Agriculture: Countingthe Labor Forcein Developing Countries."PopulationandDevelopmentReview8 (September):539--69. Enloe, Cynthia. 1989. Bananas,Beaches,and Bases:Making Feminist Senseof InternationalPolitics. BerkeleyandLos Angeles:University of California Press. - - - . 1993. The Morning After: SexualPolitics at the End ofthe Cold War. Berkeley and Los Angeles:University of California Press. Ferguson,Kathy E. 1993. The Man Question: Visions of Subjectivityin Feminist Theory. Berkeleyand Los Angeles:University of California Press. Habermas,Jiirgen. 1984. The Theory of CommunicativeAction, Volume 1: Reasonand the RationalizationofSociety,trans.ThomasMcCarthy. Boston: BeaconPress. Hakim, Catherine. 1987. "Homeworking in Britain: Key Findings from the National Surveyof Home-BasedWorkers."EmploymentGazette95 (February):92-104. Harding, Sandra.1986. The ScienceQuestionin Feminism.Ithaca: Cornell University Press. - - - . 1987. "Introduction: Is there a Feminist Methodology?" In Feminism and Methodology,ed. SandraHarding, 1-14. Bloomington: Indiana UniversityPress. Homeworkersof SoutheastAsia. 3 volumes. 1992. Bangkok, Thailand: International Labor Office. InternationalLabor Conference.1996.83rd Session."Authentic Texts: ConventionConcerning HomeWotic" In RecordofProceedings(Geneva:InternationalLabor Office). FEMINIST STRUGGLE AS SOCIAL CONSTRUCTION 145 InternationalLabor Office. 1994. Home Work. Report V(I) to the 82d Sessionof the InternationalLabor Conference,1995. Kamio, Kyoko. 1991. "Homeworkersin Japan."Yorkshire and HumbersideLow Pay Unit Newsletter,no. 12 (March): 25-26. Kessler, Suzanne1., and Wendy McKenna. 1978. Gender: An Ethnomethodological Approach.New York: John Wiley and Sons. Lorber, Judith. 1994. Paradoxesof Gender.New Haven: Yale University Press. Lozano, Beverly. 1989. The Invisible Workforce: Transforming American Business with Outsideand Home-basedWorkers.New York: The FreePress. Mahajan, Krishan. 1985. "Bidi Workers: Laws, Implementationand Alternatives." In WomenWho Roll Bidis: Two Studiesof Gujarat by RenanaJhabvala,RevaDhawan, andKrishan Mahajan.Ahmedabad:Self-EmployedWomen'sAssociation. Mies, Maria. 1982. The LaceMakers ofNarsapur: Indian HousewivesProducefor the World Market. London: Zed Press. Onuf, Nicholas Greenwood.1989. World of Our Making: Rulesand Rule in Social Theory and International Relations. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press. - - - . 1997. "How Things Get Normative,"unpublishedmanuscript. Pateman,Carole. 1988. The SexualContract. Stanford:StanfordUniversity Press. Peterson,V. Spike, and Anne SissonRunyan. 1993. Global GenderIssues.Boulder, CO: WestviewPress,1993. Pettman,Jan Jindy. 1996. Worlding Women:A Feminist International Politics. London: Routledge. Priigl, Elisabeth. 1992. "Globalizing the Cottage:Homeworkers'Challengeto the InternationalLabor Regime."Ph.D. Dissertation,The AmericanUniversity, Washington, D.C. Ramirez,Elia. 1995. "HomeNetInternational:Launchof the InternationalNetwork for Home-BasedWorkers." Newsfrom IRENE: International RestructuringEduction NetworkEurope(Tilburg, Netherlands)(22, March): 29-30. Rao, Rukmini, and SahbaHusain. 1987. "Invisible Hands: Women in Home-Based Productionin the GarmentExport Industry in Delhi." In Invisible Hands: Womenin Home-BasedProduction, ed. Andrea Menefee Singh and Anita Kelles-Viitanen, 51-67. New Delhi: SagePublications. Scott, Joan. 1986. "Gender: A Useful Category of Historical Analysis." American Historical Review91 (December):1053-75. Shaheed,Farida, and Khawar Mumtaz. n.d. "Invisible Workers: PieceworkLabour Amongst Women in Lahore." Islamabad: Governmentof Pakistan, Women's Division. Singh, Andrea M. and Anita Kelles-Viitanen, eds. 1987. Invisible Hands: Women in Home-BasedProduction.New Delhi: SagePublications. SOIj, Bila. 1991. "Le travail 11 domicilelLe travail domestique."Paperpresentedat the Groupede Etudesur la Division Socialeet Sexuelledu TravaiUCNRS,Paris,September. Stienstra,Debprah.1994. Women'sMovementsand International Organizations.New York: St. Martin's Press. Susilastuti,Dewi Haryani. 1990. "Working for More than Salt: FemaleHome-based Workers in a GarmentIndustry." Paperpresentedat the Fourth InternationalInterdisciplinary Congresson Women,New York, 2-7 June. Sylvester, Christine. 1994. Feminist Theory and International Relations in a PostmodernEra. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press. Tate, Jane. 1995. "National Group on Homeworking-UnitedKingdom." In Action 146 ELISABETH PRUGL Programmesfor the ProtectionofHomeworkers:Ten Case-Studies from Aroundthe World, ed. Ursula Huws, 81-98. Geneva:InternationalLabor Office. Trivedi, Bindu. 1985. "Asian Women Homeworker&-smashingthe Myths." Mukti (UK) 4. Wapner, Paul. 1995. "Politics Beyond the State: EnvironmentalActivism and World Civic Politics." World Politics 47 (April): 311-40. Whitworth, Sandra. 1994. Feminism and International Relations: Towards a Political Economyof Genderin Interstateand Non-GovernmentalInstitutions. New York: St. Martin's Press. 7 Internet GovernanceGoesGlobal Craig Simon Architectureis politics. -Mitch Kapor In the architectureofcontent,information becomesthe interface. -EdwardTufte The story that new ideasand technologiescan transform a societyand undermine establishedauthority is a familiar one. What will makethis telling different, I believe, is my use of the vocabulary of constructivism,following the works of Nicholas Onuf (1989). The framework presentedby Onuf and other constructivistsoffers far more power than traditional International Relations (IR) frameworksto explain the rising significanceof the Internet and its governing institutions. Though kindred structurationistslike sociologist Anthony Giddenshave beencited in various studiesofInternetpolicy (Zurawski 1997; Uncapher 1994; Helmers, Hoffman, and Hoffman 1996), it is new territory evenfor constructivistsengagedin IR. I argue in this essaythat the standards-making processfor global telecommunicationsis moving out of the handsof traditional state authorities into the hands of people whose goals and loyalties are less national than commercial. Statesare not preparingto recapturethis power. Since the natureof the newly constituted authority is inherently global, the effect, if trends continue,will be to fortify the expansionof global rule, a processwhich is alreadyunderway. Onufs framework is particularly well equippedto eval147 148 CRAIG SIMON uate whether Internet expansion representsa shift in effective authority, whereasother IR frameworks overlook its counterhegemonicsignificance. By explaining how rules make rule-how standardsmakers becomestandard bearers--{;onstructivismdraws attention to the most potent agentsof global rule making. We begin, therefore,by consideringthe generalplan of the new system's vanguards,known to popularculture as the "digerati." This will be followed by a discussionof the different ways constructivismand competingIR perspectives approachthe topic of rule making in telecommunications.The last section appliesa constructivistanalysisto the ongoing efforts of the Internet'screators to build new institutions and proceduresfor operatingthe Internet'saddressing service,known as the domainnamesystem(DNS). If successful,thesechanges would enlist the InternationalTelecommunicationsUnion (ITU) and other Geneva-basedorganizationsas agentsin support of global, rather than intergovernmental,goals. The Digerati Agenda The term digerati, a play on "digital literati," was coined by Nicholas Negroponte, whoseBeing Digital (1995) exalted the impact of computerson society. The word can refer loosely to anyonewho has facility with computers, but is often appliedto industry pioneersand opinion leaders,severalof whom are glamorizedin John Brockman'sDigerati: Encounterswith the Cyber Elite (1996). Given their generally high level of media savvy and skill at selfmarketing,it is tempting to attribute their stardomto our society'sWarholian obsessionwith wealth and fame. Thesemastersof microelectronicart are ready made for celebrity, but their conspicuousstation in societyraisesan analytical problem. Giving the digerati seriousconsiderationas an organizedmovement might exaggeratetheir significance,imparting a substantivecoherenceto their views that otherwisewould not exist, and therebycrediting them with an undeservedhistorical status. Suchconcernsare outweighedby the unmistakableevidencethat the digital telecommunicationsinfrastructurereachesnearly everywhereon the globe and that, whereverit reaches,it transformssociety. Moreover, many people who play key roles in designingthat structuredeclarethey are building a new order which threatensthe primacy of sovereignstates.Healthy skepticismdemands asking whether those assertionsare overblown, but we should not ignore the fact that embellishedclaims to power play a role in any system of social organization. The digerati agendais bestsummedup in Metcalfe'sLaw, a term coinedby economistGeorgeGilder in honor of Bob Metcalfe, owner of 3COM Corporation and inventor of Ethernet,the electronicprotocol usedby most networked INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 149 personalcomputers.Metcalfe's Law states,"The value of a network can be measuredby the squareof its numberof users."In short, "Connectedcomputers are better" (Metcalfe 1996). This suggeststhat connectingeveryone(and perhapseverything)in the world througha global network of computerswould be a beneficial and desirableproject. Adding membersto the system would enable the network to achieve its fullest potential, and promises individual empowermentas a consequence. Metcalfe'sLaw is all-inclusiveand imperious. It explicitly assertsthat global networking is a universal social good, and implicitly challengesthe exclusive norms of a world order basedon statesand social divisions. The explicit part of the formulation is especiallyinteresting becauseof a congruencewith formal theories of public goods and network externalities.Economistsdefine public goodsas things whoseutility cannotbe divided in a way that one person'smaximum use would diminish another's benefit. Externalitiesrefer to the ways that investors recover costs from free riders. The conceptof network externalitiesholds that the wider use of a thing increaseseveryone'spotential benefit from it, as if a lighthouse could shine more brightly when more ships find its beam, or as if the utility of a phone systemimprovesby addingphonesto it, evensubsidizedones. The implicit, counterhegemonicaspectof Metcalfe'sLaw follows from the indivisible notion of public goods. Digerati trailblazerssharea tenaciousand outspokendesireto overcomelimits on humancommunication.It is considered heroic to build systemsthat enable escapefrom the binds of physical and political space.Metcalfe's 1973 invention of Ethernet, for example,was inspired by an earlier engineeringfeat called AlohaNet, a wireless digital data systemspanningthe Hawaiian islands. Tim Berners-Lee,creatorof the protocols that underlie the World Wide Web, summarizedhis work as creating a "global information system" operatingacrossa "seamlesshypertext information space" (1992). His present activities involve developing systems of "metadata"to providea universalcontentlabeling standardfor commercialand social applications. Jaron Lanier, who pioneeredvirtual reality, describes TransmissionControl ProtocollInternetProtocol (TCPIIP), the underlyingsoftware of the Internet,as a political "masterpiece"which will endureas a collaborativeachievementgreaterthanthe AmericanConstitution. Embeddedin this rathersimple pieceof codeis a whole philosophyof life. A whole philosophy of equality among people, of equal accessof people to other people.A philosophythat anythingthat everyonehas to say is equally worthwhile. A philosophythat peopleshould never be separatedfrom each other, that there shouldn'tbe any standardhierarchythat tells them how to relateto eachother. (Lanier 1997) Consideralso the Teledesicventure,a digital communicationssystemconnectedthrougha backboneof 288 satellitesin low earthorbit, allowing usersto 150 CRAIG SIMON bypass the national seamsnow crimping land-basedphone and data lines. Competingsystemswill also be deployed,but Teledesicis distinguishedby its ambitious size and its high-profile founding investors---<:ell phone industry pioneerCraig McCaw and Microsoft's Bill Gates.McCaw describedTeledesic to a WashingtonPost reporteras "the ultimate egalitarianproduct" which will "changedramatically the cultural patternsthe world was built on." "We are granting peoplethe right to interactwith eachother," he said. "This will have an impact on central authorities"(Mills 1997). Ironically, those sameauthorities are eagerto competefor contractsto launch such satellites from within their presumablythreatenedborders. To mix a famous phraseby Newt Gingrich with a lesserknown but equally acuteone by a leadingconstructivist,AlexanderWendt, the Information Revolution is what we make of it. Many digerati considerthemselvesto be revolutionarieswho are particularly adeptat enlisting followers to their cause.A few are becoming quite skilled at exploiting confusion and divisions among the political leadersof the world's nation-states.Telecommunication,like sovereignty or religion, can serve as a tool for anyone who seeksto manageor reorganizea society. Such tools offer a set of behaviors,institutions, and conceptsof social goodsthat amountto a kind of grammarthrough which leaders and followers interact. Just as religious evangelismproducesconverts,just as political ideas often acquire an imprimatur of substanceas they circulate, the digerati ideologyadvancesits own self-fulfilling prophecies. And considerhow many futurologistsand social soothsayershavebegunto argue, quite persuasively, that acquiringand learning to use computerswill advancea person'seconomicviability. As Gatestold readersof his column in the New York Timessyndicate,"a Web lifestyle will take hold" as peoplelearn it is the best way of adapting to life's bothers."You'll take the network for granted," he wrote, "turning to it instinctively without a second thought" (1997b). Within ten years,he foretells (perhapsoveroptimistically),all adults will live a form of that lifestyle, and eventually everyonewill rely on it to managefinancial transactions.In expressingchallengesto "central authority," Gates tends to be far less confrontational than his partner McCaw, but his prediction neverthelesscontainsa demandingadmonition. The Web lifestyle will presumablyoffer such a reliable, trustworthy, and universally available facility for the conduct of commercial activity that it will be considereda necessity.Any individual who shunsit will be foolhardy. Any collectivity that tries to do so will be handicappingitself at greatperil. Few technologieshave spurredsuch quick and dramatic social changesas telecommunications,but neverbefore have the championsof an industry been so bold aboutseekingto build an infrastructurethat can be both self-governing and not only independentof the regulatorypowersof establishedstateauthorities but immuneto them. This ideologicalposition, promotingtelecommunica- INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 151 tions as a meansto a wider social end, is what distinguishesthe digerati agenda from numerousother tradeandprofessionalassociationsthat decry government regulation. No other social movementhas dared to take such great practical stridestowardtransformingstatesinto vestigial organsof the global body. Judgingthis movementto be good or bad is anotherquestion.It is clear that many digerati expressa desire to changethe world for the better, but it is far too early to speculateabout whetherthey can effectively remedy the kinds of injustice associatedwith the presentsystemof internationalrelations.The time is ripe, however, to formulate a critique of their normative preceptsand their philosophyof action. Since inequalitiesare inherentin every rule-basedpower system,and since it is now becomingpossibleto sketch out the grandestfeatures of a digerati-styledsystem,one can try to anticipatewhat types of inequalities may result if the digerati agendareachesfruition. In other words, how will it impact the circumstancesin which peoplefind themselves? Cyber Shockwaves Though information technologyis widely acceptedto be the hallmark of our age, it is not necessarilya boon for humankind.The impact of electronicmedia on culture is much discussedthese days, as is the rise of "internetworked" computing in businessand education,and not always in glowing terms. Advancedindustrial economieshave experiencedhigh investmentin computers, making the machinesnearly ubiquitous. Yet growth in workplaceproductivity has not kept pace (Sichel 1997; Thurm 1997). As cognitive psychologist ThomasLandauerdemonstratedquite clearly in The Trouble with Computers (1995), computersare too complexfor most peopleto useany more effectively than typewriters and regular mail. Still, we who depend onthesedevicesfeel that we could not get by without them. Despite the trials they force us to endure,and despitethe degradationof our skills and investmentswrought by eachnew generationof software and hardware,we generally feel these tools have enabledus to do new things, more quickly, and in greaterquantities.We are convincedthey are an essentialtool for the future. Unfortunately,we have good causeto doubt whetherthe next versionof a programwill fix more than it breaks, or whether the next model of a machine will perform any more smoothly than the last. We have learnednot only that we must abide by new standardsas they emergebut also that the standardsto which we submit may all too soon be declaredobsolete.Inability to completea task becausea computer "won't take it," either becauseof inflexibility or flaw in design, is an increasingly familiar refrain. Technology'sbenefits may be inconsistent,but its broad social impact is undeniable,especiallywith regardto telecommunications.Landauer'sfindings show that computerizationof the public telephonenetwork has brought about 152 CRAIG SIMON significant boosts in worker productivity while adding carrying capacity and switchingspeedat a fast pace(Landauer1995, 169-70;also Noll 1997; 64-71). Now financial and media sectorshave joined the market to createeven more advancedtopologies.The nerve centerof the telecommunicationsindustry has becomethe showcaseperformerof the information age. Its improvementscorrelate with other transformationsin society, including vast changesin investment patternsand workplace organization,a steady seriesof giant corporate mergers,historic changesin law, and heateddebatesin public policy regarding censorship,monopoly, and tariff regulation. Much of the boom in telecommunications focuses on the Internet, which not only is a catch-all term for a burgeoningcollection of infrastructuresand applicationsbut also may prove to be the platform throughwhich personalcommunicationsand massmedia technologiesconverge(Akimaru, Finely, andZhieseng1997). As digital telecommunicationsbecomemore pervasivearoundthe globe, its applicationsare likely to intrude more and more deeply into people'slives. The currenttrajectoryof investmentinvites informedspeculationthat, within two or three decades,innovations in the delivery of television, radio, and traditional voice phone servicesmay transform digital data servicesinto a qualitatively new form of technology.The scientistswho are developingthe prototypeplatform for future media convergencerefer to it as Nexus (Low 1997). Prognosticating further, by the middle of the next century, basic facility with that integratedtechnologywill likely be as essentialto humansocializationas mastering skills like telling time, using money, reading maps, or recalling one's addressand phone number. New generationsof surveillanceequipmentand personalinformation collection softwarewill increasinglyassaultour concepts of privacy and autonomy,enforcing an omnipresentdiscipline of social monitoring that many theorists call panoptic (Gandy 1993; Boyle 1977; Ashley 1983). The implicationsof the Web lifestyle far surpassthe novelty of ordering pizza through the Internet: As did the making of clocks and maps in antiquity, creation of the Web lifestyle involves the constructionand applicationof devices that extendhumanknowledgeand activity past local boundsof time and space.These devices free us to coordinateourselvesacrossthose bounds in dramatically new ways, but they limit us as well. Imbued with the belief that those devicesshow the way to prosperity,we are forced to keep step with the world beator elsebe trampledin the march. In a similar vein, Anthony Giddens usesthe metaphor"Riding the Juggernaut."Modernity, unharnessed, threatens to run amok, crushingeverythingin its path (1990). This raisesinterestin how to assessthesephenomenain theoreticalterms. It is one thing to identify these global drummers--thepeople who make "the rules." It is anotherto ask what they think they are doing and how they define their interests.Digerati culture hasspawnedits own forms of political ideology, theoriesof economics,and canonsof literature,as well as a few martyrs. There INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 153 is considerableevidenceshowing that the membersof that culture are becoming consciousof their collective identity on the basisof their sharedinterestin expandingand securingthe Internet. It is also possibleto reveal their strategic assaulton the ability of statesto regulateInternetand othertelecommunications activity within national borders.Therefore,my inquiry concernsthe intentions of the central agents of modem technological change, recognizing that the sociopoliticalimplicationsof their work may be profound. Let us briefly review how other observersof global affairs approachthese questions. Making Senseof the Information Revolution Much of the currentgrowth in the scaleand scopeof digital telecommunications is due to technical innovation, but the far-reaching economic initiatives of the Reagan-Thatcher era earn specialcredit. An apt metaphorregardingthe deregulatory, pro-competitive legacy of those years was invented by New York Times columnistThomasFriedman.The "goldenrecognizably strai~acket," he wrote, "is all the rules set down by global markets for how a country has to behaveeconomicallyif it wants to thrive in today'sworld" (1997). The "golden straitjacket"is the tendency of political leadersto tie their handsand pledgenoninterventionin their national economies,in exchangefor the promisesof growth andprosperity.The breakupor privatizationof national telephoneand telegraphmonopolieshasplayedout differently aroundthe world, however.The contrastis especiallystarkbetweenindustrialized nationsand underdevelopedones.Ben Petrazzini,for example,reflects the conventionalwisdom in the field of comparativepolitics, concludingthat the "demise" of public phone monopolies in less developedcountries was motivated primarily by fiscal decline,promptingpolitical leadersto sell off nationalindustries in exchangefor infusionsof foreign capital (1995). Legal scholarsfind themselves in rich but unchartedterritory. The Information Age has spawnedwhole new sorts of crimes,augmentedby real confusionaboutwhere suchcrimes occurand about who hasjurisdiction in cyberspace(Kahin andNesson1997). IR specialistshave also begun to take notice. JosephNye and William Owens(1996) have written aboutthe strategicopportunitiesand vulnerabilities thesetechnologiescreatefor the United Statesin the global balanceof power. Jill Hills (1994), following SusanStrange,showsthat advancedWesternindustrial stateshave foisted a liberal economicorthodoxy (basedon open markets and monetarypolicy) upon the world, granting wide autonomyto large multinational corporations,while essentiallyprivatizing internationalorganizations. This allows such states to translate the structural power they once enjoyed (when outright coercionwas more easily applied) into a relationalpower better suitedto currentcircumstances.Shefinds thesechangeslamentablein that they subjectweakerstatesto new forms of dependency. 154 CRAIG SIMON Other studiesoffer practical guidanceto policy makerswho favor interstate cooperation.Peter Cowhey (1990) upholds the fashionableIR theories of regimes and epistemic communities.His widely read study of the norms and principles at work in intergovernmentalorganizationsfocused on the ITU's predecessor,the InternationalTelephoneand TelegraphConsultativeCommittee (CCITT). Cowhey rejects the functionalist notion that the telecommunications regime is a supranationaltechnocraticexercise,describingit insteadas a negotiating venue between separateentities committed to efficient national operations. Large transnationalcorporate consumersof telecommunications services,primarily banksseekingto reducethe cost of operations,were the first to press their governmentsfor systemic reform in an organized way. This promptedthe leading industrial statesto reassessthe costsof maintainingtheir national telecommunicationsmonopolies,allowing them to accept privatization, competition, and the end of protectionismas a bargain that promised betterpayoffs. Despite contrastsin perspectivesand conclusions,all these authors work within frameworksthat representstatesas rationally motivated,seeminglypersonified, territorial-basedactors. Their intent is to discussthe forces that constrain and propel thosestates,and how other statescan perhapsbe outfinessed in light of those forces. An alternative,nonterritorial perspectiveis presented by Craig Murphy's neo-Gramsciangeneralstudy of global governance(1994). What Murphy shareswith the other authors,however, is the assumptionthat somemasterscript is in play, guiding if not determiningthe behaviorof actors on the world stage.The distinction for Murphy is that the leadingprotagonistin this historic dramais global capitalism. Each of thesescholarsseeksto understandan actor'sessenceby way of the actor's environment.To postulatethat systemic forces like the drive for efficiency or strategicadvantagecan motivate transformations of the telecommunications infrastructureis to posit that suchforces can rule internationalbehavior. Following this logic, exogenous(external) structural forces would rule human behavioras well, cagingpeople within fixed bars of the social world. An antithetical perspectivecomesfrom the post-modemmovement.Denying that substantivematerial factors of the environmentcan exert such rule, Andrew Barry seestelecommunicationstechnologysimply as an instrumentthat mediatescommunication in society, enabling self-governancerather than constraining it (1996). By suchlogic, self-governanceis an endogenous(internal) voluntary act which may foster liberation or punishment,but the deviceswhich transmit the gazeof socialdiscipline receiveno credit or blamefor the outcome. Consideringtheseissuesas a constructivistrequiresformulating a position that subsumesthe exogenous-endogenous dichotomy, a split that echoesin debatesbetweenpositivists and the various post-positivists,post-modernists, and post-structuralistswho constitutethe post-modemmovement.Reconciling INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 155 thesepoleswill give a clearersenseof how technologystandardsconstrainand enable human activity, and how standardscan provide the mechanismsthat simultaneouslyregulateand constitutehumansociety. Constructing Standards Unlike the authors just mentioned, constructIvistsrely on an interpretive schemethat explains social rule by categorizingthe origins and outcomesof social rules. The axioms that "rules make rule" and "rules put resourcesinto play" distinguishconstructivismfrom positivist and Marxist philosophiessuch as realism, neo-liberalism,and historical materialism,which look first at the ways resourcesdeterminestructureand then at specific social outcomes."Post" movementauthorsoften focus on the materialoppressionand feelingsof meaninglessnessthat result from a world ruled by positivist philosophies.Critical authorsof the "post" movementexpressa desireto developpracticalstrategies for emancipationfrom thosedilemmas.We canclarify the distinctionsbetween the philosophiesof positivism and the "post" movementby recognizingthat they are often taken to be equivalentto thosethat divide modernismand postmodernism.The former may be understoodas faith in efficiency, rationality, perfectibility, the accumulationof knowledge, and collective progress. The latter insists on existentialidentity and self-expression,often in the context of free-floating relativism. Post-modernistsregardpeople'simaginationsas situational and unlimited, unboundedby the possibility of resolving down to a common interpretationof the world. One might say that the positivists try to seea single world by standingoutsideit, while the "post" movementgrantsthe existenceof infinite perspectives,placing individuals inside our own myriad worlds, looking out in endlessdirections. Constructivismplays both sidesagainstthe middle, but not as a facile compromise. The challenge is to retain the positivists' scientific commitment to inquiry, probing for the fundamentalstructureof things while understandingthat interpretationis a humanact, limited by the necessityof symbol, the gravity of memory,and the imperfectibility of language.When studyingsociety,positivists look for measurablestructuralvariablesthat can be said to causehumanbehaviors. Their traditional researchinterestis the extent to which material structure makessocial behaviorpredictableand involuntary. Constructivists,on the other hand, see human behavior and social structure as inseparable,simultaneous, co-constitutedoccurrences,but rooted in deeds of human urgency. Whereas adherentsof the "post" movementare keen to celebratethat urgency, their observationsoften scatter into solipsistic relativism, denying that any claims aboutcausecan be trusted.In distinction, constructivistslook for the institutionalized routines of social practicethat stem from humanperformance.One can and should seek to identify constantsacrosssocial structures,with the caveat 156 CRAIG SIMON that doing so is itself an act of social constructionwhich inventsand reproduces contingentbelief in that constancy.To establishhabitsthat comportwith "Reality," wrote logician CharlesS. Peirce in 1877, "we seekfor a belief that which we shall think to be true" (1955, 11). Constructivisminevitably reflectsthe limits of language.Like all myths and scientific theories, IR's "isms" offer grand statementsabout the world, instructing people how to make senseof reality so that they can comprehendit and thereforeact within it. We humansare not as unfettered as the "post" movement imagines us to be, or as limited in our freedomsas the positivistsexpect.The point is to rememberGiambattistaVico's principle ofverumJactum:what we recognizeas true is what we havemade. The constructivistoutlook attemptsto recognizethat all humandeedsstandas moral choices,with constitutiveeffectsthat extendbeyondimmediatesituations. And regardlessof the mind-setreflectedin an instruction, a person'sacceptance of that instructionwill fortify the hegemony-theauthoritativeinfluence----ofits originators and its vocal proponents.For Onuf, social instructionsplay out in two sorts of ways. In fonnal organizationswhere the instruction might be "the boss is in charge," they situate people in offices requiring compliancewith directionstransmittedthrougha hierarchicalchain of command.Alternatively, in more opensocial environmentswhere the instructionmight be "buy low and sell high," people will tend to behave like membersof a heteronomyin which behavioralroles are regulatedand constrainedby commitmentsnegotiatedwith otherswho adhereto the sameinstruction. Applying constructivismmeansanalyzing socialbehaviorsand rules embedded in the speechacts of peoplewho occupy somestatus,office, or role, within variousnetworks,organizations,and associations. Understandingthe instructive, directive, or commissivenature of those rules gives an insight into who is "in charge,"and what kind of rule--hegemonic,hierarchical,or heteronomous--is being exercised.It is beyond the scope of this work to explain the source of constructivism'svarious trichotomies,exceptto note that it revealsthe influence of three-partcategoricalschemesdevelopedby Peirce,Giddens,and others.As a constructivist,to ask an individual who or what is "in charge"is not only to ask what meaningthat ruler or rule has for them, but to appreciatethat a person's interactionwith a rule ascribesmeaningto it. Rules arise from intersubjectivity, and cannotexist without humanauthorship.This fonnulationallows constructivism to cleave the positivist-"post" divide. We can acknowledgethat the rules that define a person'sidentity and interestmay seemfixed and persistentfor that individual at a certainpoint in time, but suchrules are transfonnable.An observation madeby Peirce'scolleague,psychologistWilliam James,providesa useful illustration. The antimilitarist Jamesis still rememberedfor asking whether a "moral equivalentof war" could be fosteredin peacetime.Intrigued by the "supremest and extremist" fonns of sacrifice and effort displayed by men in battle, he INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 157 wonderedhow to summonthe passionate "spiritualenergy" of soldiers for a common good, rather than internecineconflict (l972b, 295). After inquiring into the sourceof "martial virtues," which he admired, Jamesconcludedthat the "oughts" that motivate a person stem from the individual's pride in the body (tribal, national, etc.) by which he or she is "owned" (l972b, 298). Anyone who can inculcatein othersa senseof oughtand, consequently,obligation in social situationsis simply telling peoplewhat rules to follow (l972a, 220). More to the point, anyonewho can inculcatea senseof belongingand identity in addition to this or that "ought" has madea biggermove, facilitating a system of rule. Let us saythat someone'ssenseof being ownedis equivalentto feeling part of somethingbiggerthan oneself:a faith, a nation,an institution, a club, or a meeting. To pledgeallegianceto that group, to obey that group'srules, to perform someother social interactionwith referenceto that group, or evento say it exists is to instantiatethat momentof ownershipin which the institution transforms identity. Jamesrecognizedthat interactionas a pragmaticopening.Social constructioncan involve the simplest tasks of coordination or the grandest schemesof ethical unification. Society makes "man" just as "man" makes society,simultaneously,all the time. In the caseof the digerati agenda,then, it is important to investigateany canonicalinstruction or principle usedto enlist participantsa group that shares common goals. Who would adopt Metcalfe's Law as a creed worth fighting for? Self-professedNetizens (Internet citizens) are potential candidates,but their presenceis small, focusedaroundthe monthly magazineWired as well as a few libertarianand Left-leaning Web sites. Their currentbehaviorresembles an unruly debatingsociety more than a political movement.Still, even if the rights and dutiesassociatedwith Netizenshipare informal, vague,and unknown beyonda small circle of adherents,the notion of using the global telecommunications infrastructureto createalternativeforms of political associationbears watching. The "Web lifestyle" anticipatedby Gatesis a considerablymore potentand immediatelyrelevantdeclaration.When askedhow he makessuchpredictions, he answered,"I'm trying to draw a map thatconnectsthe presentto the future" (l997b). For him to say the Web lifestyle will soon exist is to suggestit exists now, since"getting ahead"requiresthat we preparefor it. The predictionstands as an instruction that future humanbehaviorwill increasinglyrequire interaction acrossthe Internet, or a relatedmedium. Announcingan instructive claim of such import standsas a hegemonicassertionpertinentto anyonewho feels he or she belongsto modemsociety. Beyond his confirmed businessacumen, Gates'spreeminentstatuswithin global industry gives his opinionsthe aura of objective knowledge. For those seeking initiation into the world of wealth creation,Gates'srank as the world's richest self-mademan gives him a priori authority, akin to the traditional authority commonthroughoutpretechnological 158 CRAIG SIMON cultures."[MJaternal unclesdo not transmit [aJ particularstock of knowledge becausethey know it, but they know it (that is, are defined as knowers), becausethey are maternaluncles" (Bergerand Luckmann1966, 70-71). In this sense,by pronouncingan is, Gatesurges an ought. That samepronouncementcorrespondsto a set of directives given to Microsoft employees and subcontractors,marshalingthe organization'sresourcestoward the goalof completing specific projects. And it also servesas a commitmentwithin the marketplace,declaringthat Microsoft's resourceshave beenput at risk in the expectationthat consumersand other enterpriseswill commit their own resourcesto the sameproject. By predicting a Web lifestyle, Gatesconstructsit. Those who may eventually adopt that lifestyle will also play a role in its construction,so that the institution and the person'sidentification with it are simultaneouslyco-constituted.We can think of a phenomenonand its practitioners separately,but they are not separable.One cannot exist without the other. A path cannotbe called a path without the peoplewho walk it. This is no subtle point; the notion of co-constitutionis at the heart of constructivism's critique of both positivismandthe post-modernmovement. Arguably, the only reality social beings can know is socially constructed, since even the most rigorously scientific disciplines of knowing are mediated by a languagethat explainsthings in terms of persistent,humanly manageable tools like logic or the study of causeand effect. To break from positivism and "postism" is to acknowledgeone's consciousparticipation in the act of construction, while simultaneouslyrecognizing that, without attention to social structure, there can be no meaningful way to ground identity. The issue is whetherwe believe we are collectively subjectto a universalfate, individually mastersof a uniquely private reality, or pragmaticallyadaptive to the world aroundus. It is not unusualfor many peopleto jumble these attitudestogether as it suitsthem on different issues,with little concernfor their own discipline of thinking. The samedistinctionsplay out in attitudestoward the social significanceof the growth of telecommunications.The digerati agendaexploits this confusion,promotingthe modernistimpulse to heraldthe adventof the "New World Information Order," while celebratingpost-moderndesiresto fabricate multi-userdungeonsin virtual reality. I intend to show that a particularvirtue of the constructivistapproachis its ability to explain how the claims of universalismand equality inherent in an instruction-rulelike Metcalfe'sLaw disguisethe conditions of inequality that emergefrom successivewaves of technologicalinnovation. Such inequalities can privilege certain innovatorsor stakeholders,therebycreatingor perpetuating monopoly power. Another virtue of the theory is its strengthin explaining how the design and implementationof seeminglyarcaneelectronic standards are facilitating the worldwide triumph of an institutionalizedethos in which market-stylebehaviorsreign supreme.In other words, summoningan earlier INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 159 metaphor,the freshestknots in the golden straitjacketsworn by nation states havebeentied by computerexperts. Of course, it is not unusual for contemporaryanalysts to discuss the challengesthat modemforms of electronicallymediatedcommercepresentto nation-states.Legal scholarMichael Froornkin usesthe term regulatory arbitrage to describe the ease in with which Internet-savvytraders can exploit differencesin national laws to their own advantage.Yet he is optimistic about this, predicting the effect will "probably be to promote liberal democraticvalues of opennessand freedomand not to detractfrom modemstates'legitimate regulatorypowers" (1997, 155). On the other hand, economistStephenKobrin worries that new technologieswhich enablethe use of digital money (e-cash) are a "sovereignty killer." "[T]he advent of e-cash raises serious questions aboutthe very idea of 'domestic'and 'international'as meaningfuland distinct topics" (1997, 71). Constructivismallows us to take such analysisa step further, however, beyond discussionsof a weakenedsovereignty,toward an understandingof its co-constitutedsuccessororder. Consequently,we need to understandwhat sort of rules arebecomingmore importantin people'slives. It is appropriatehere to considerthe definition of the word standard.In the English languageit derives from "stand hard," the rallying point in a battle at which a heraldic bannerwas raised so that field commanderscould locate the sourceof their orders. The word now has multiple meanings,including "flag" and "a rule set up by an establishedauthority." Every standardworks literally and figuratively as a social arrangement.Cultural symbolsare easyto recognize as such when people are physically assembledaround a common focal point. Sharedbehaviorsmanifest such assembliesas well, the more so when people acknowledge theircommonpractices,reflect upon them, and makethemformal. When peoplelook to a standardfor instruction, they are simultaneouslyconstituting an arrangementof peoplewho are "pointing" to that standard.New arrivals at the scenemay learn what a standardis just by pointing in the same direction as others. In that sense,the standardhas regulatorypower as well as constitutive effect. We organize ourselvesaccording to the standardswe acknowledge.We make standardsby following them. They re-presentwhat we do and sayaboutthem. To shuna pervasivestandardis to fall out of stepwith one'speers,proving one'sdisloyalty to a group'snorms(Fletcher1993).This investsstandardswith an ethical power. By stipulatingwhat is, standardsoperationalize"oughts." We may refer to standardsas self-enforcingor self-surveilling,but, as adherentsto the various "post" movementsrecognize,our willing participation in a social arrangementis essentialto it. Thus we may say that a rule is drawn from the consentof the people who practiceit, and that every rule, to qualifY as such, must incorporateone or more standards.An intriguing and practical line of questioning,then, is how peopleenlist supportfor new standards.Let us now 160 CRAIG SIMON tum to an aspectof standardsmaking by a group of digerati that combines practicalandsymbolic importance,and the effectsof which will be felt within a few years,ratherthan in many decades. Internet Ownership and the Public Trust The Internethas a root, technically called a root zone (often written as "." and pronounced"dot"), which servesas the authoritativedirectory to all locations properly registered withinthe system(for an exhaustiveexplanation,seeKahin and Keller 1997,Rony and Rony 1998). At the time of this writing in 1997,the primary root of the Internet sits on serverA, a machinein Herndon,Virginia, which containsa databaselisting many of the namesand addressesof the tips of the Internet'sbranches,properly referredto as hosts,of which thereare now well over 20 million (nw.com). Hosts constitutethe end points on which data reside, and the devicesthrough which peopleaccessthe system.Though host computersmust be uniquely numbered,peopleprefer using memorablewords and acronyms.Consequently,an important function of the root is linking domain namesto host numberswhile ensuringthat no two hostsare assignedthe samename. Day-to-dayresponsibility for managingserverA's databaseis currently in the handsof Network Solutions,Inc. (NSI). Additions and revisionsto the host addressdata on serverA immediatelypropagateto serversB through M, and then on throughout the Internet, cached(stored) in name serversaround the world. Those name servers, run by Internet service providers (ISPs), from giantslike America On Line down to the humblestentrepreneur,all userouting software,which serveroperatorsvoluntarily point backup the chainto serverA for instructions on how to direct traffic around the system. Therefore,when individuals sende-mail through the Internet or "surf' the Web, their transmissions are routed aroundthe systemon the basisof the contentsof the root and reproducedin compliantnameservers. Responsibilityfor operatingInternet'sroot is expectedto changehandsin 1998, either in April when NSI's five-year contractwith the National Science Foundationexpires,or six months later if necessary,after an optional "rampdown" period, during which new operatorswill take over. But it is not yet clear who thosenew operatorswill be. A battle has beenbrewing for severalyears over how to expandthe top level of the domain namesystem(DNS), and who will be in chargeof adding new top-level genericsuffixes, like firm, web, arts, and info. The existing generic names,edu, org, net, and especiallycom, are filling quickly, and are primarily an Americanpreserve.Many digerati seethe upcomingtransition as an opportunity to acceleratethe Internet'sgrowth as a platform for global telecommunications convergence.Fulfillment of Metcalfe's Law requiresbuilding a systembig enoughto encompassworld society,result- INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 161 ing in somethingfar lessAmericanin characterthanat present.U.S. politicians, not surprisingly, have pledged to maintain control. Upon learning that the Internet's designerswere planning to move the root oversight functions to Geneva,RepresentativeCharlesPickering (R-Mississippi), head of the House Science Subcommitteeon Basic Research,declared, "This is something uniquely American. That part of the [plan] is not going to sell very well--not here,not on Main Street." To investigatethis controversyis to plunge into an acronym soup of standards-makingbodies, intergovernmentalagencies,and other organizations which built the Internetand which claim a stakein its future. To abbreviatethe story, we may begin with two groupswhoseleaderstestified before Congressman Pickering's committee: The Internet Society (ISOC), headedby Don Heath (previously employedby MCI and British Telecom), and the Internet AssignedNumbersAuthority (lANA), headedby Jon Postel(a veteranhandof Internet engineering,currently basedat the University of SouthernCalifornia's Information ScienceInstitute [lSI]). ISOC and lANA are key forces behind the effort to constitute a policy oversightcommittee(POC), which would take over authority of DNS management whenNSI's contractexpires.NSI would still be allowed to provide domain name registration services, a lucrative business,but NSI's monopoly would end, to be replacedby a globally competitive framework of registrars. Thesewould, in tum, participatein a council of registrars(CORE), incorporated in Geneva.POC activities would be reviewedby a public advisory body (PAB), representingthe interestsof Internet stakeholders.The details of this plan were initially presentedon February2, 1997, by the InternationalAd Hoc Committee(IAHC), a group directedby Heath. The IARC plan was formally establishedthrough an instrumentknown as the Generic Top Level Domains Memorandumof Understanding(gTLD-MoU, or simply MoU). Unfortunately for MoU supporters,the signing ceremonyhostedby the International TelecommunicationsUnion (lTV) in Genevaon April 29, 1997 did not go as they might havehoped. Private industry'S responsewas lukewarm. The MoU neededa more resounding endorsementfrom telecommunicationscompanies,service providers, and other Internet businessesas an indication of legitimacy among Internet stakeholders.PSINet, an important early supporterof the IAHC, denouncedthe MoU and called for a global Internetconventionwith Vice President Al Gore as moderator. The following week, in responseto mounting criticism, substantialchangeswere announced,removing provisionsfor a lottery that would have limited the number of total registrarsto twenty-eight, coveringsevenglobal regions. The public sector'sinitial responsewas also cold. Days before the ceremony, the U.S. StateDepartmentleakeda memo from Madeline Albright ex- 162 CRAIG SIMON pressing"concerns"about the ITU secretariat'sacting "without authorization of membergovernments"to hold "a global meetinginvolving an unauthorized expenditureof resourcesand concludingwith a quote internationalagreement unquote" (Sernovitz 1997; Wylie 1997). The EuropeanCommissionalso expressedconcerns.In July the U.S. Departmentof Commerceinitiated a notice of inquiry (Nor), soliciting public commenton the expirationofNSI's monopoly. The controversy continued to escalate,prompting hearings before the Pickering'ssubcommitteein late September. Americancritics of the MoU complainthat authority for resolvingdisputesover contendeddomain names would move beyond the jurisdiction of U.S. courts. Disputeswould insteadbe settledby administrativechallengepanels(ACPs) under the administrationof the Arbitration and Mediation Centerof the World Intellectual PropertyOrganization(WIPO). MoU supportersarguethat clearer,more evenhanded proceduresare necessaryto reduce the likelihood of arbitrary and inconsistentdecisions.UnderNSI's guardianship,registrationand hostingof existing brandnameslike mcdonalds.comby third partieswasallowedunlessthe brand owner took stepsto demonstrateprior rights. NSI transferreda nameto the proven owner only when the initial registrantagreed,or after litigation (InterNIC 1996), and in confusing situations,would put contendednames"on hold." One notable exampleinvolvedpeta.org, a nameclaimedby Peoplefor the Ethical Treatmentof Animals (PETA) but initially registeredto the promoter of PeopleEating Tasty Animals (Doughney1996). An evenmore vexing disputearoseoverprince.com, a properly registeredtrademarkof distinct companiesin different countries,serving as a lessonin the challengesof regulatinga global infrastructurethrougha patchwork of nationalcourts(OppedahlI997).MoU supportershopethat expandingthe rangeof generictop-level nameswill reducethe cachetof namesending in com, abating explosive demandsfor that suffix. But the MoU's successwill hinge in large part on the ability of the POCIPAB/COREIACP institutional structure to resolve disputesover contendedresources.Thus POC choseas its first president David Maher,an attorneywhosespecialityis internationaltrademarksand intellectual property. Let us now considerthe DNS transitionfrom the perspectiveof constructivist categories. With regard to instruction-rule, further commercializationof the Internet would both follow and reinforce the pro-businessnorms that permeatemodem industrial states.Adam Smith'sguiding handwould becomean even freer one. There are competingproposalsto establishroot serverconfederations(RSCs) that take a far less centralized,even cowboyish, approachto the question of DNS management.RSC supportersthus claim a more faithful allegianceto the free market principle. Advocatesof the MoU, in tum, are likely to wave the bannersof the Internet'sfounding mothersand fathers, assertingtheir legacy and statusas reveredauthorities. INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 163 With regard to commitment-rule,breakingNSI's monopoly and creating a global marketfor domainregistrationwould augmentcompetitionon the Internet, where consumerscan already choose from many sourcesfor hardware, software,and contentvendors,as well as, to a lesserdegree,Internet connection services.This casedemonstratesthe intentionality inherentin markets.To eliminate a monopoly, somethingmust be createdin its space.Moreover, students of IR who are concernedwith the constructionof internationalrelations should pay close attentionto the new forms of judicial associationestablished through the MoD. Switching domain name dispute resolution venues from nationalcourtsto Geneva-based ACPs would constitutean expresslynew form of commitment-rulewhich could eventuallyinfluenceglobal trademarklaw. With regardto directive-rule,the ability to coordinatecompliantdeviceson the Internetis of fundamentalimportancefor stabilizing the day-to-dayoperationsof a "Web lifestyle." Ensuring that Internet service providers all point to a common authority like CORE for domainnameinformation promotesthat goal. Replanting the standardof the Internet'sroot may appearto be an obscuretechnicalexercise, but it would havea pivotal impact,perhapssimilar to thoserarehistoricalmoments when new calendarsor systemsfor calibrating time are instituted. Whetherthis transitionwill be smoothor traumaticremainsto be seen. Extending the Internet Domain This disputeover ownershipof the DNS root raisesthe recurringquestion"Who 'owns' the Internet?" Resolving the immediatebattle will decide, for the time being, not only who gets to collect the Internet'sequivalentof rent or tax on domain names,but, more significantly, whetherthe Internet'sdesignerswill be able to proliferate the use of generic nameswhile globalizing (or at least deAmericanizing)systemadministration,creatinga world marketout of a national monopoly. The use of generictop-level nameshas not beenwidespreadbeyond the United Statesand Canada.From elsewherein the world, NSI's distance, inconvenientbusinesshours,and English-languageorientationare often prohibitive. For anyone outside North America seekingto establishan Internet presence, registration under a national suffix usually provided an acceptable alternative.Openingnew CORE-certifiedregistriesin other countrieswill thus make generic suffixes more appealing,especiallysince the new top-level domains will not be so heavily dominatedby Americans. Also, the decision to incorporateCORE in Genevaaffords the symbolismof a neutral,"international" city, and enhancesthe practical accessto the root's administrativeregime by Europeans,Africans, Asians, and others. If theseplans succeed,worldwide investmentsin Internet serviceswill continueto accelerate,and its generic spaces will take on a different, less"American" look. Defending the MoU under pressurebefore Pickering'S committee, Heath 164 CRAIG SIMON statedthat the DNS must be treatedas "an internationalresourcesubjectto the public trust." Its management"must allow for true self-governancein order for the Internet to reach its fullest potential." "If one nation tries to rule it," he predicted, "others will overrule it" (Heath 1997b). Such words provide insights into the philosophyof digerati leaders.Commentsrelatedto Internet self-governance, Global InternetGovernance(GIG), and global civil societyall "raise flags" that indicatedirectionsin which their thinking is headed.Heathhassubmittedother statementsto the U.S. governmentregardingISOC'sglobal agenda. We believe that it is important that governmentsof the world should be involved in the self-governanceprocessesthat will evolve; but, they should do so in a mannerso as not to control or otherwisecreateeffective control and, thus, thwart the processof true Internet self-governance.The Internet communicationsmedium; it must not be used must remainan unencumbered as a tool for censorship,or of controlling the free flow of information. The architectureof the Internet is basedon an end-to-endphilosophy.Any "controlling" activity should only be done at the end points: where content is introduced,or where it is takenoff. It is with thesethoughtsin mind that we say governmentshould be involved, but not in such a way to take control. (1 997a) The claim that the Internet'sarchitectureis basedon an "end-to-endphilosophy" is frequently repeatedamong the system'sdesigners.By declaring their intent to draw and uphold a borderseparatingthe Internet'swires and switches from the world without, the architectshave becomegatekeepers,pledging to maintain systemsecurity while advancingthe interestsof the system'susers. However, in distinction to the narrow gatesoperatedby the club of sovereign statessincethe inception of the Westphaliansystemin the seventeenthcentury (bsterud 1997), the Internet's gates are wide and beckoning to all comers. While most seriouspublishersrequire novice authorsto overcomea seriesof rigorous hurdles,the Internet allows anyoneto publish any inanities he or she wishes, instantly, without review. While entry into a professionalelite is normally grantedafter a processthat reinforcesthe group'sstandardsand reputation, the Internet'sstructureis intentionally openand inclusive. Therefore,it is noteworthywhen the digerati targeta group they wish to exclude,as they have doneby seekingto deny governmentsa placeat the Internet'sheadtable. Building trust in the securityof Internettransactionswill foster ever greater activity over that medium, increasingdemandfor the wiring and switchesthat carry its signals. The supplying industriesare extremelyvolatile in character, though quite profitable when successful.This environmentservesto reinforce the politically proactiveapproachesof leading playerslike MCI, whosecorporate personalitieswere forged in the deregulatoryheyday of the ReaganThatcher years and fortified by the explosive gigantism of the 1990s. Tremendouseconomiesof scale and rapid developmentcycles have brought INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 165 about remarkableimprovementsin the quality of goods, coupled with steady reductionsin price. It is not unreasonableto forecastthat hundredsof millions if not billions of peoplewill be able to afford accessto the systemwithin the first decadesof the next century. Under thesecircumstances,private industry is more likely to continuefunding digerati activities than to supportany effort that might threatenInternetexpansion. Many of the Internet's gatekeepersbelieve that new structuresof social organizationwill form, respondingto new kinds of needs,which cannotbe met by the nation-state.Glenn Kowack, prior to his appointmentas lANA's representativeto POC, wrote a piece in the normally staid engineeringjournal IEEE Communicationswhich laudedthe Internet'sengineersfor deployingthe "costimplosive" economicmodel of the information technologyindustries.He echoes Peter Drucker in welcoming the rise of "societies of organizations," believing this heraldsa shift of global importance.This growth will lead, however, to a "vacuum" in the "administrativeenvironment"which cannoteffectively be filled by traditional governments: The generaldirection of the Internet and the activities of its global community of users,consistentwith [Thomas]Paine'sconceptof "natural individual propensityfor society," are both philosophicallylegitimate and arguablysuperior to jurisdictionalclaimsby nation-states.(Kowack 1997,55) The MoU's promotersand their adversariesboth recognizethat the ability to commandor deny the flow of information measurestheir power. For rapid system growth to continue, sendersand receiversmust be assuredthat their transmissionsare private and trustworthy.The digerati agendais thereforefuriously engagedin developingmechanismsto secureInternettransmissionsfrom interference,especiallyin relation to issueslike cryptography,free speech,and protectionof intellectual property. This coincidentally provokesconfrontation with stateswhose traditional businessis also to provide security within their domain. The MoU disputeis just one of the battlegroundsbut is symbolically important,becauseof the communicativepowerof namesand addresses. These are constructedinstruments,part of an indispensable,imperfect tool we call language. They are tags on reality which we use to mediate our contacts through a similarly constructed,mappedspace.To control the domain name systemin a world that rises each day greeting a Web lifestyle is to name the streetsand boulevardsthat feed the "Information Superhighway."Thosewho exercisethis control will acquirea tremendouspower to fashion our memories of place,and to reblendour comingsand goingsin an entirely new way. Today'sInternet has a significant design limitation that inhibits the fulfillment of Metcalfe's Law. The current addressingscheme(Internet Protocol Version 4-IPv4) allows a theoretical maximum of 232, or 4,294,967,296 nodeson the system,well short of the populationprojectedfor the world in the 166 CRAIG SIMON next century. The practical numberof addressesis far less becauseof inefficienciesin the allocation scheme,but an upgradepresentlyunder development (IPv6) will createroom for 2128, or over 3.4*1038 addresses,a truly mind-stretchingquantity, presumablyenoughfor everyoneborn in the next few centuries,plus vast numbersof interconnecteddevicesper person.The project to expandthe addressspaceis called InternetProtocolNext Generation (IPNG), and hasbeenproceedingundera level of reasonablybusinesslike and effective technical cooperationunder the aegis of the Internet EngineeringTask Force (IETF), the organizationthat spawnedlANA and ISOC. Other IPNG priorities include adding security featuresthat support commercial transactions, technicalimprovementsto facilitate smooth streamingtransmissionsof sound and video, and managementfeatures to regulatetraffic-congestion.Thesewill all be essentialelementsof the Web lifestyle, regardlessof the MoU's fortunes. Postscript Though this work refers to a digerati agenda, there is no conspiratorial Protocols of the Elders of Cyberspaceor philosophical Digerati Papers which allows us to plumb their thinking. Yes, one can point to screedslike "A Magna Carta for the Information Age" (Gidari 1995), "A Cyberspace IndependenceDeclaration" (Barlow 1996), and "Crypto-Anarchist Manifesto" (May 1992), but thesestandas individual works. They presentinteresting insights into the culture, but they are self-consciouslygrandiose,and are unrepresentativeof the leadersat the core. I invented the term digerati agendato amplify my conclusionthat the creatorsof global telecommunications standardsare self-consciouslychallenging the rules and the rule of sovereignstates,offering new mechanismsfor coordinatingeconomictransactionsand enlisting humanloyalties, and experimentingwith prototypesof global government.I confessthat by positing its existenceI playapart in its construction.As Lao Tzu wrote in the openingof the Tao te Ching, "Naming is the origin of all particular things." By bringing the conceptto a new audience,or by presentingnew ways of thinking about it to those who are already interestedin such ideas,I may augmentit and changeit. Ironically, the open-mindedreaderparticipateswith me in that construction.Our effort to understandthe digerati agendareproducesit, and impartssignificanceto something that may soonbe forgotten. Time will tell if it shouldhavebeen,but there is enough intriguing evidenceto warrant a continuing look. My conjectures may appearto be as grandioseas any screed,but dismissingthis phenomenon out of hand risks overlooking a developmentof great potential consequence. Peopleare subject to the standardsand structuresthat they themselveshave made.Thus constructivisminvites its own methodof analysis. INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 167 Note Thanks go to Vendulka KubaIkovli, Nicholas Onuf, Michael Froomkin, Phil Agre, and Ken Goodmanfor their helpful comments. Bibliography Internetlinks may be accessed directly through:http://www.flywheel.comlircw/igg.html. Anonymous.1994. "Magna Cartafor the KnowledgeAge. Release1.2." http:// crirnson.comlcis/Magna-Carta.htmlhttp://www.pff.org/pff/position.htrnl. Akirnaru, Haruo, Marion R. Finley, Jr., and Zhiseng Niu. 1997. "Elements of the Emerging Broadband Information Highway." IEEE CommunicationsMagazine (June):84-91. Ashley, Richard K. 1983. "The Eye of Power: Politics of World Modeling." International Organization37:3. Barlow, John Perry. 1996. "A CyberspaceIndependence Declaration."February 9. http://eff.org/pub/publications/John_Perry_Barlowlbarlow_0296.declaration. http://www.vrx.netldeclaration.html. Barry, Andrew. 1996. "Lines of Communicationand Spacesof Rule." In Foucault and Political Reason:Liberalism, Neo-liberalism and Rationalities of Government,ed. Andrew Barry et al. Chicago:University of ChicagoPress. Berger, PeterL., and ThomasLuckmann. 1966. The Social Constructionof Reality: A Treatiseon the SociologyofKnowledge.New York: Anchor Books. Berners-Lee,Tim. 1992. "Summary of the World Wide Web Initiative." http://www.w3.org/summary.html Boyle, James. 1997. "Foucault in Cyberspace:Surveillance,Sovereignity, and HardWiredCensors.''http://www.wcl.american.eduipub/facultylboyle/foucault.html Brockman,John. 1996. Digerati: Encounterswith the CyberElite. New Y 0Ik: Hardwired. Cook, Gordon. CookReport.http://www.cookreport.com. Cowhey, PeterF. 1990. "The InternationalTelecommunicationsRegime: The Political Rootsfor Regimesof High Technology."International Organization,44 (2) 158--76. Doughney, Mike. 1996. "peta.org Domain Name Placed on Hold." May 12, 1996. http://www.mtd.comltasty/editoria13.html Fletcher, George P. 1993. Loyalty, An Essay on the Morality of Relationships.New York: Oxford. Friedman,ThomasL. 1997. "France'sNew Jacket."New York Times.June5: A21. Froomkin, Michael. 1997. "The Internetas a Sourceof RegulatoryArbitrage." In Borders in Cyberspace,ed. Kahin andNelson, 129-63. Cambridge:MIT Press. Gandy, OscarH., Jr. 1993. The Panoptic Sort: A Political EconomyofPersonalInformation. Boulder: WestviewPress. Gates,William. 1997a. "Banking on a Web Lifestyle." New York Times Special Features.July 15, 1997. http://nytsyn.comllive/Gates2/21O_072997_132203_9368.html - - - . 1997b. "Q&A: Where Do Your Ideas About the Future Come From?" New York Times, Syndicate. September23, 1997. http://www.nytsyn.comllive/gates2/ 266_092397 _134025_24271.html Gidari, AI. 1995. "A MagnaCartafor the Information Age." SeattleTimes.October30, 1995. Giddens,Anthony. 1990. The Consequences of Modernity. Stanford: StanfordUniversity Press. 168 CRAIG SIMON Heath, Donald M. 1997a."In the Matter of Registrationand Administration ofIntemet Domain Names." U.S. Departmentof Commerce,Docket Number 9706131377137-01. http://www.isoc.org/whatsnewINTIAcomments.html - - - . 1997bTestimonyto the HouseScienceSubcommitteeon Basic Research.September30, 1997. http://www.isoc.orglwhatsnew/huestimony_oral_970930.htrnl Helmers,Sabine,Ute Hoffman, and JeanetteHofman. 1996. StandardDevelopmentas TechnosocialOrdering: The Case of the Next Generationof the Internet Protocol. Social ScienceResearchCenterBerlin. http://duplox.wz-berlin.de/docs/ipng.htrnl Hills, Jill. 1994. "DependencyTheoryand Its RelevanceToday: InternationalInstitutions in Telecommunicationsand Structural Power." Reviewof International Studies20: 169-86. InterNIC on-line documents. 1996. "Domain Name Policy Dispute." ftp://rs. internic.netipolicy/internic.domain.policy James,William. (1891) 1972a."The Moral Philosopherand the Moral Life." Essaysin Pragmatism. In Pragmatismand Other Essays,ed. JosephBlau pp. 214-35. New York: WashingtonSquarePress. - - - . (1910) 1972b. "The Moral Equivalentof War" in Pragmatismand Other Essays,ed. JoesephBlau, 289-301.New York: WashingtonSquarePress. Kahin, Brian, and JamesKeller. 1997. Coordinating the Internet. Publication of the HarvardInfrastructureProject.Cambridge,MA: MIT Press. Kahin, Brian, and Charles Nesson,eds. 1997. Borders in Cyberspace:Information Policy andthe Global Information Infrastructure. Cambridge:MIT Press. Kobrin, StephenJ. 1997. "Electronic Cashand the End of National Markets." Foreign Policy (Summer,107): 71. Kowack, Glenn. 1997. "Internet Governanceand the Emergenceof Global Civil Society." IEEE CommunicationsMagazine(May): 52-57. Landauer,Thomas K. 1995. The Trouble with Computers: Usefulness,Usability and Productivity. Cambridge:MIT Press. Lanier, Jaron. 1997. Lecture deliveredat the New Media Minds Forum Centerfor the Arts, San Francisco. September11, 1997. http://www.hotwired.com/ synapse/nmm/97/37/IanierOa.htrnl Low, Colin. 1997. "IntegratingCommunicationServices."IEEE CommunicationsMagazine(June): 164-69. May, Timothy. (1988) 1992. "Crypto-Anarchist Manifesto." http://calweb.coml mdtatel3rypto.htrnl Metcalfe,Bob. 1996. "ThereOughtaBe a Law." New York Times.July 15, 1996,C5. Mills, Mike. 1997. "Orbit Wars." WashingtonPost. August 3,1997,W08 Murphy, Craig N. 1994. International Organization and Industrial Change: Global Governancesince1850. Cambridge:Polity Press. Negroponte,Nicholas. 1995. BeingDigital. Hotwired. Noll, A. Michael. 1997. Highway of Dreams: A Critical View Along the Information Superhighway.Mahwah,NJ: LawrenceErlbaumAssociates. NW.COM (Network Wizards). 1997. "Internet Domain Survey." http://www.nw. cornlzonelWWWIreport.html Nye, JosephS., and William A. Owens. 1996. "America'sInformation Edge." Foreign Affairs 75 (2): 20-36. Onuf, Nicholas Greenwood. 1989. World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social TheoryandInternationalRelations.Columbia:University of SouthCarolinaPress. Oppedahl,Carl. "NSI Flawed Domain Name Policy Information Page." http://www. patents.comlnsi.sht INTERNET GOVERNANCE GOES GLOBAL 169 Osterud, Oyvind. 1997. "The Narrow Gate: Entry to the Club of SovereignStates." Reviewo/InternationalStudies23: 167-84. Peirce, Charles S. (1877) 1955. "The Fixation of Belief." Reprintedin Philosophical Writings 0/Peirce, ed. JustusBuchler.New York: Dover. Re/onnin DePetrazzini,Ben A. 1995. The Political Economyo/Telecommunications veloping Countries: Privatization and Liberalization in ComparativePerspective. Westport:PraegerPress. Rony Ellen and Peter Rony. 1998. The Domain Name Handbook: High Stakesand Strategiesin Cyberspace.Lawrence:R&D Books. Ruthowski,Anthony. World InternetAssociation.http://www.wia.org Sernovitz, Andy. 1997. "The US Govt. Is *not* Supportiveof gTLD-MoU." July 27, 1997. http://www.old.gtld-rnou.orglgtld-discusslmail-archive/ 4682.html Sichel, Daniel E. 1997. ComputerRevolution:An EconomicPerspective.Washington, DC: Brookings. Thurm, Scot. 1997. "The Productivity Puzzle."San JoseMercury News. September14. http://www.sjrnercury.comibusiness/product091497.htm Uncapher,Willard. 1994. "BetweenLocal and Global: Placing the Mediascapein the TransnationalCultural Flow." http://www.eff.orglnet.culture. globalvillage Wendt, Alexander. 1992. "Anarchy Is What StatesMake ofIt: The Social Construction of PowerPolitics." International Organization46 (2): 391-425 Wylie, Margie. 1997. "U.S. Concernedby ITU meeting." News.com. April 29, http://www.news.comiNews/lternlO.4.10198.OO.html Zurawski, Nils. 1997. Beyondthe Global Infonnation Frontiers: What Global Concepts ("Weltbilder") Are There on the Internet and Why? Paperpresentedat the Internet Society conference,INET97. http://www.isoc.org/isoc/whatis/conferences/inet/ 97/proceedings/G4/G4_2.HTM. This page intentionally left blank ________ Part IV Construction in the Academy This page intentionally left blank 8 Remodeling International Relations: New Tools from New Science? Henry L. Hamman The inclusion of a chapteron the applicationof scienceand mathematicsin internationalrelations(IR) in this set of essaysmay appearcontradictory,in no small part becausethe constructivistapproachto international relations is often seenas a subsetof antipositivistor post-positivisttheory, as a genre that rejects empiricism, as one of the pillars that upholds the edifice of science,and as applicableto the study of social phenomena.That this view is widely held is due to a misapprehension of the natureof constructivism, sinceconstructivistsdo not follow antipositivistsin rejectionof empiricism. In fact, constructivist thinkers--at least those who work with Nicholas Onufs approach-havederived their theoreticalconstructs preciselyfrom the observationand analysisof the empirical. Unlike the antipositivist or post-positivist position, which rejects the whole notion of application of the tools of scienceto the study of human behavior,constructivismendorsesthe scientific notion of formulating theory on the basisof empirical knowledgeas well as the scientific view that knowledgeis tentative,subjectto revision, andincomplete. A numberof reasonsfor the rejectionof scienceby "post" social scientists have beendiscussedin earlier chapters.However, anotherfactor adding to the difficulty of discussingthe possible contributions of natural scienceand mathematicsto the understandingof the social world is the social sciencecommunity'slack of awarenessof developmentsin twentieth-centuryscience.(To be fair, natural scientists,as a group, are hardly au courant with the state of the art in sociology or anthropology,either.) My 173 174 HENRY L. HAMMAN conjectureis that-for social scientistsat the centerof their fields (men and women in their forties and fifties)--scienceeducationgenerally stopped with high school chemistry, or perhaps asingle required natural science coursein their undergraduate years.One would further suspectthat most of thesecourseswere taughtby individuals who had themselvesreceivedtheir scientific training in the 1920sor 1930s,just as the implicationsof quantum physicsand the specialand generaltheoriesof relativity were beginningto be assimilatedinto the naturalsciencecanon. Further, the researchtopics of international relations may well appear incompatible with the methods and data analysis techniquesapplied in many natural scienceresearchefforts. Natural scientistsoften conduct researchin which observedoutcomesfall not preciselyon targetbut within a range, and they draw conclusionsbasedupon averagesof events.On the other hand, international relations tends to be eoncernedwith specific events,and the measureof efficacy is the ability to predict a specifie outcome.Given the small numberof entitiesavailablefor observation,the lack of appropriateexperimentalvenues,and the inherentdesire of human beings not to be shown up as wrong, it is hardly surprising that in recent decadesinternationalrelationsscholarshiphasturnedaway from the intractable problemsof dealing with the real world and toward linguistic gamesmanshipand wordplay. The argumentadvancedhere is that internationalrelationsscholarsmay find it useful to reconsidertheir attitudestoward the natural sciencesand mathematics.First somebasicconsiderationsconcerningsystemsandmodels will be summarized,and then a numberof developmentsin the natural sciencesand mathematicsthat appearto be of partieularsalieneefor international relationswill be discussed.Additionally, the outline of a possible schemafor the integrationof constructivistontologyandmodernmathematics and naturalsciencewill be presented. Systemsand Models Scientific and mathematicalthought is largely systematic,and the goal of much of this thought is the developmentof theoriesthat can be represented as modelsof the subjectunderstudy. Unfortunately,becaueof the remembrance of attemptspast to apply general systemstheory to the study of politieal behavior,any suggestionthat somesort of "systemstheory" could advancethe study of internationalrelations is distastefulto many international relationstheorists. As Mario Bunge (1979) points out, however,we really have no choice but to study systemsand their componentsif we wish to comprehendthe REMODELING fNTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 175 workings of our world. As Bunge observes,studyingcomponentsin isolation is akin to studying sawdustto understandtrees--boringand of limited utility. Conversely,studying the externalsof the trees without referenceto their compositionleavesthe observerwith only generalities.The difficulty with a systems-oriented approachis that it requiresboth breadthand depth; scholarsmust be both generalistsand specialists.Nonetheless,whetherthe subjectis treesor the socio-economico-politicalworld in which we live, we cannotescapethe requirementfor systemicthought. At its simplest,a systemis a group of elementsthat are linked togetherin some fashion. This definition is implicit in such uses of the term as "a systemof laws" and "a systemof philosophy."A taxonomy--thesimplest form of systematization---isan exampleof this usage.As with any other form of systematization,one of the major goals of taxonomicalsystemsis to enableenhancedprediction(SeeCasti 1990,43). Systemsmay be classified as either static or dynamic. Static systems expressa relationship among componentparts that remains unchanged. Dynamic systemschangeovertime. A dynamic systemis a systemin which somesort of input is receivedby componentsthat are in some form interconnectedand which, in turn produce some sort of output. (See Howard 1991 for a clear discussionof the basic formal definition of a dynamic system.)If both input and output are containedwithin the system,the systemis a closedsystem.To the extent that the systemreceivesinput from outsideor deliversoutputto the outside, the systemis an open system.An open systemmay have recursivecharacteristics.In sucha system,outputis releasedinto the largerenvironmentbut may also feed back into the system as an input. A systemthat receives recursive inputs and inputs from the larger environmentis a cybernetic system.This type of system is what we are interestedin in international relations,sinceit is a generaldescriptionof the internationalsystemand its relationshipto the largerenvironmentin which it operates. Another important distinction is betweendiscrete and continuoussystems. In a discretesystem,inputs arrive in packets,outputsare producedin the sameform, and the systemchangesin finite increments.In continuous systems,inputsand outputsare streams. Two other divisions amongsystemsare important: the division between systemsthat treat time as an explicit variableand thosethat do not, and the division betweensystemsthat exhibit entropyand thosethat do not. While time is a factor in all dynamic systems,not all systemsrequire that the interval of time be specified.Systemsthat do not specify time are referred to as systemsin which time is an implicit variable,while systemsin which time is specifiedare referredto as systemsin which time is an explicit variable. 176 HENRY L. HAMMAN The division of systemsinto entropic and nonentropicsystemsalso relates to the question of time. A general thermodynamicdefinition of the term entropy is "a measureof the capacity of an isolated macroscopic systemfor change"(Covenyand Highfield 1990,362).Left unchecked,an entropicsystemwill eventuallymove to a stateof equilibrium. This may be viewed as a form of decay,a temporalprocess.In the mathematicalsense, entropy is consideredas a loss of information over time. As such, entropy may be considereda measureof the disorganizationpresentin a system. The presenceof entropy signifies that for the system,time is a one-way street: the systemcannotbe made to run backward.Entropie systemsare also known as dissipativesystems.Human beings are a good exampleof dissipativesystems,sinceno matterhow hard we try to stemthe onslaught of old age, no one has yet managednot to get old. Even Dorian Gray eventuallydisintegrated. For nonentropicsystems,to the contrary, time is viewed as reversible. Newtonianphysicsand classicalastronomytreat the systemsthey study as nonentropic. Becausethey do not decay, nonentropic systemsare also known as conservativesystems. Since in the real world entropy is a constant,all real-world systemsare time-dependent. Having declaredentropya constant,one is alsoaskedto consideranother idea that seemsdiametrically opposed-evolution.Entropy arguesfor the decay of systems.Evolution posits the developmentof increasinglycomplex systems.Canthesetwo conceptscoexist? There is a body of theory and experimentthat seemsto supporta view that in certain conditions,systemscan exhibit both evolution and entropy. Ilya Prigogine(1984), who developedthe theory of dissipativestructures, arguesthat dissipativestructuresdevelopin systemsthat are operatingfar from equilibrium. It is within thesedissipativestructuresthat evolutionary processesare thoughtto takeplace. A final important division betweentypes of systemsis that between linear and nonlinearsystems.In essenceit is the division betweensystems in which there is a constantproportionalrelationshipbetweenthe variables in the system(linear) and systemsin which changesin the valuesof variablesare not necessarilyproportional(nonlinear).Until recently,mathematics has lacked the tools to study nonlinearsystemssatisfactorily, so there hasbeena markedtendencyto attemptto producelinearmodelsof systems, evenwhen thesehavebeeninappropriate. Having acceptedthe idea of the system,one immediatelyfacesa problem: to portray the system completely requires that the system itself be studied. However, in all but the simplest systems,this is impossible: for REMODELING INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 177 example,the solar systemis not accessibleto direct observation.Additionally, if the goal of studyingthe systemis to understandcertainaspectsof it, thereis considerableeconomy of effort to be producedby limiting the study of the systemto thoseaspectsthat areof particularimportanceby creatingmodels. Bunge(1973) offers this taxonomyof models: • The modelas objectmay be definedas a hypotheticallyreal but possibly fictitious sketchof something.The model as object may be pictorial or conceptual (e.g., a mathematicalformula), but it is always partial; if it is not partial, the model is identical with the object of study. Thus, the model as object is a meansof selectingthe essential and ignoring the nonessential. • The model as theory is a specific theory of a concreteor reportedly concrete(that is, nonreified) object. The relation betweentheory and model here is that a generaltheory that lacks the particulars supplied by the model cannotbe tested;only when the theory is convertedto a model is it available for empirical testing. The model as theory may be consideredas a hypothetico-deductivesystemconcerninga model object. The goal of this type of modeling is to insert the specific theory derived from the model into a comprehensivetheoretical scheme. • The modelin the (Estheticsenseis a pictorial representation. • The model in the heuristic senseis an analog of a familiar object, a metaphor. • The model in the model-theoreticsenseis a true interpretationof a formal system. The type of model of most immediateconcernto internationalrelations is the model as object. The hope is that through the developmentof enough specific model objects, it will be possibleto intuit or otherwise develop the morecomprehensivetheoreticalschemeassociatedwith the modelastheory. In trying to producemodelsto serveas a test bed for theory, the sciences search for analogons. An analogon is something more than a simile or metaphor,somethinglessthan equivalence.An analogonis a set of parallel cases.Systemsof different designthat are functionally similar are consideredanalogous. Formal modeling may be consideredthe construction of formal anThis view can be justified bealogons for natural-;-eal-world-systems. cause the successfulformal model, while without meaningful content, nonethelessproduces outcomes that show a subjective similarity to the naturalreality. 178 HENRY L. HAMMAN At this point, it may be worth a moment'sdigressionto note that not all operationsinvolving quantitativemethodsare actuallymodeling. A formal mathematicalmodel consists of a set of symbols, a set of transformationrules statedas well-formed formulae, and a set of inference rules that permit the constructionof otherwell-formed formulae; when a set of axioms is allowed to operateon these elements,the result is a formal system.If it is allegedthat this systemis an analogonof anotherphenomenon, the systemis said to be a formal model. Statisticalanalysisis the analysisof numericaldata,either descriptiveor inferential. Inferential statisticalanalysisis a form of analysisthat relies on probability theory for determiningboth the reliability of data and the reliability of inferencesdrawn from that data. Simulation is a form of modeling in that it is an explicit attempt to producea simulacrumof somereal processin anotherform. The game of Monopoly is a simulationof the capitalisteconomicsystem.While a simulation may be basedon a formal model, many simulationsare developed heuristically. Formal modelsare basedon threekey assumptions; • That quantitationof datais possibleand that thesedataare not reified but representsomesort of reality. • That it is possibleto expressmathematicallythe relationshipbetween variablesrepresentedby the datathat havebeengathered. • That solving equationsthat expressthis relationshipbetweenvariables shedslight upon reality. Modeling in International Relations A numberof criticisms of modelingin internationalrelationshaveemerged. Without exhaustingthe subject, a summaryof thesecriticisms would include the following lines of attack: • The genericcriticism of the assumptionsof Newtoniandeterminism. Even probabilisticmodels-modelsthat introducerandomor stochastic effects-arereally only Newton plus an uncertaintyterm, sincethe stochastic effect is introduced on heuristic rather than theoretical grounds. • The criticism that internationalrelationsmodelsare basedon concepts that are anarchicallydefined(seeFergusonandMansbach1988). • The criticism that internationalrelationsmodelshave often beenproduced for normative rather than scientific reasonsand may well exhibit their creators'normativebiases. REMODELING INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 179 • The criticism that many modelsin internationalrelationsare particularistic. • The criticism that becauseof their heuristic nature, most models in internationalrelationsremainunsubjectedto the rigor of phasespace analysisfor validation, thus leaving openwhethertheir variable space is coterminouswith that of their real world analogons. • The criticism that methodsof scientific analysisdrawn from the physical sciencesare inappropriateto the studyof humanbehaviorbecause consciousness is not currently accessibleto scientific analysis (Penrose 1989, 1994). Thc basicproblemwith internationalrelationsmodelsderived from classical scicntific methodology is, however, one that is generally unstated:most international relations models are basedon the intellectual assumptionsof Newtonian physics: the clockwork, totally determineduniverse. Newton's physicsare an attemptto explain the regular aspectsof life. In international relations,though, what we are interestedin is not regularity but irregularity. Thus, clockwork models are inappropriatebecausethey do not allow for irregularities,andwhen irregularitiesappear,the modelsaredeemedfailures. The inability of classicalscienceand mathematicsto provide tools for the significant advancementof knowledgein international relationsappears to many theoriststo have foreclosedadvancementsalong these lines. But the core problem is somewhatmore tractable: it is not that sciencehas failed, but that we have emulatedthe wrong science,the scienceof the eighteenthand nineteenthcenturies,ratherthan the scienceof the end of the twentiethcentury. Emergent Scienceand Mathematics While the term still has not beenuniversally adoptednor comprehensively defined,one ofthe key aspectsof currentscientific thoughtis the notion of emergentproperties.In shorthandterms,the notion of emergenceis tied up with the questionof behavior.Scientistsare generallynot contentsimply to observeand note the structureof the object of their study; they want to know what the object will do under given conditions and, if possible,the reasonfor that particularaction. In otherwords, they want to know not just what "it" is, but why "it" doesthe things it does. One of the ways scientistsdo this is by paring down the "its" they study. They try to pick out the significant featureor featuresof the object of their interestandto limit the variablesthey consider.This activity hasbeengiven the vaguely pejorative name of reduction, pejorative becauseit has been 180 HENRY L. HAMMAN arguedthat reductionmakesthe complexoverly simplistic and substitutesa pencil sketchof a tree for the reality of the forest. That line of attack was successfulin raising serious doubts about the entire scientific enterprise amongmany who heard it, both inside and outside the scientific community. But research,discoveries,and observationsover the past century, building to a crescendoin the 1960s, 1970s,and 1980s, have led to the finding that astonishinglycomplexand unpredictedbehavioroften emerges from simple----:reduced:----systems. This new scienceis a scienceof emergence-theunfolding of the system to reveal levels of complexity and structurethat are not apparenton the surface.Emergencemeansthat there are some propertiesof matter and being that emerge(or appear)only as matterand/orbeingdevelopscomplexity. Marjorie Greneaddressesthe questionof whetherliving systemsare govemed by the laws of physics-areductionistproposition.She points out that this syllogism seemsto suggestthat living systemsareexplainedby the laws of physicsand that no other laws apply. She notesthat such a position doesnot follow "unless we know ... that the laws of physics are the only laws we know." This not being the case,sheproposesas a valid syllogism: "All living systemsindeedobey the laws of physics,but without contraveningthe laws of physicsthey may well obeyotherlaws aswell" (Grene1971,21). Today, even the most diligent defendersof the reductionistcanon concedethat there are propertiesof complex structuresthat do not have counterpartsat lower levels. StevenWeinberg(1992) notesthat there is nothing like intelligenceon the level of individual living cells and nothing like life on the level of atoms and molecules.He arguesthat while emergenceis most obvious in the biological and behavioralsciences,it also appearsin physics.He cites as examplesthe emergentpropertiesof thermodynamics, suchas entropyand temperature,propertiesthat are without meaningin the discussionof individual particlesof matter. Weinberg'sis essentiallya reductionistview of emergence.Others,like Roger Penrose(1989, 1994), have made a much broaderclaim, that there systemsthat are not exists a set of rules goveming--especially--human evenaccessiblethroughreduction. Despitethe contestationover the scopeof the conceptof emergentproperties,even thosewho find the conceptoversoldagreethat someaspectsof reality only becomevisible (apparent)at certainlevels of systemicdevelopment. A simple exampleof an emergentproperty might be that of color. Considerthe level at which this propertyemergesin the elementcarbon: • What color is a quark? We don't know, and evenif we did, it would tell us nothing aboutthe color of carbon. REMODELING INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 181 • What color is an electron?The sameanswerapplies. • What color is the nucleusof a carbon atom? Again, the questionis irrelevantto the color of carbon. • What color is coal?Black. We may know the componentsof a carbonatom, but the propertyof color emergesfrom the way thosecomponentsinteract and only abovea certain level. Other examplesof emergentpropertiesin the natural world include intelligence, photosynthesis,various forms of systemic self-organization, and language.Theseand other emergentpropertieshave in common that they appearonly in systemsthat haveattaineda certainlevel of complexity. Emergenceis itself a featureof the emergentscience. For intemationalrelations,what is important about the notion of emergenceis that those who are studying complex systembehaviorare beginning to generalizeaboutemergentproperties. One exampleof the generalizationsthat are appearingcomesfrom the field of artificial world modeling,a computationalfield that usesthe power of the computerto test out algorithms for the creation of virtual environments. The underlying hypothesisthat legitimates the study of artificial worlds is a strangecombinationof reduction (in that artificial worlds are much simpler than their real counterpart)and holism (in that the entire world is the universeof study, not just a small cornerof it). Among those who have used the idea of the artificial world are economists and statisticiansseekingto understandeconomicbehaviorin the real world by creating an artificial world and observing the developmentof economicstructuresin it. It is out of this work that the processof emergent hierarchical organization has appeared.For the current purpose,two observedcharacteristicsare important.The first is that this emergentorganization is hierarchical(seeLane 1992 for a good discussionof the implications of hierarchy). The secondimportant observationis that systemsexhibiting emergent hierarchical organizationseemto produceorder from within themselves. This propertyis noted in physical,chemical,biological, and social systems andis often calledself-organization. GregoireNicolis and nya Prigogine(1989) point out that self-organization, though first observedin biological systems,is not a function of biology but is much more deeplyrooted. They cite as examplesof self-organizationthe order that emergesin thermal convection(a phenomenonstudiedin physics) and the chemical phenomenonknown as autocatalysis,in which the presenceof a product of a chemicalreactionstimulatesfurther production of that product. 182 HENRY L. HAMMAN The ideathat propertieslike self-organizationemergeas systemsbecome more complex is interestingin itself, but more interestingis the question: What purposedo emergentproperties,suchas self~organization, recognizably serve?The answerto this question,offered by emergentscience,is that emergent prop~ recognizably ertiesare the meansby which complexsystemsadaptto their environment. Proponentsof the view of emergenceas an adaptivemechanismseethis as a crucial dividing point betweentheir view of scienceand the more traditional position. Drawing on ideasand computermodels developedby JohnHolland, Murray Gell-Mannstatedthe institutionalpositionthis way: • Thereare basicrules that all systemsof a given type follow. • Historical accidentis the sourceof othersystemicparameters. • Those featuresof systemsthat are not determinedby basic rules or historical accidentare the result of emergentadaptationof the system to its environment. The trick, of course,is sorting out what is a basic rule, what is the result of historical accident,and what is the productof emergentadaptation. Emergence's Antecedent-Uncertainty Emergentsciencehas beena long time in blossoming:the bud was formed in the fecund thirty-year period that startedwith Max Planck'sproposalof the quantumtheory in 1900, advancedwith Albert Einstein'sspecial and general theories of relativity (1905 and 1915), and culminated with the unification of thesetwo theoriesby P.A.M. Dirac in 1929. The notion of the quantumis perplexing:while it resolvescontradictions betweenprediction and observationin the behaviorof particles, it defies intuition and our everydayperceptionof reality. And yet, it is sucha simple idea: the quantumis the smallestamountof energyby which a systemcan change.Inherentin the definition is the notion that the quantumis discrete, not continuous.The idea of the quantumis importantin physicsbecauseit redefineswhat atomic structureis. In classicalphysics,the atom resemblesthe solar system,withneutrons. the elec~ trons orbiting aroundthe central atomic core of protonsand neutrons.The electronscanhaveany orbit diameterand can, in theory,be trackedwith the sameprecisionas astronomerscan track Mars. This comfortablepicture is disturbedby the quantumtheory, which holds that there are only certain energylevels at which the electrons(or any other particles)can exist. This feature means that when the energy level of a particle changes,it shifts immediatelyfrom one orbit to anotherand that unlessone knowsprecisely REMODELING INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 183 what the energylevel of the particle is at a given time (somethingthat is impossibleto determine),one can only give probabilitiesfor the position of a particle. As if this were not complicatedcnough,researchersin quantum mechanicshave shown both theoretically and experimentally that the particles appearas wavesand waves as particles,dependingon the conditions under which they are observed.Odd as it may seem, the results of studyof the physicaluniverseover the pastninety yearshaveremovedfrom physical sciencethe matter-of-factand the pragmatic and have elevated uncertaintyto the statusof a first principle. Mathematicshas added its own confirmation of ultimate unknowableness. GOdel's 1931 publication of his incompletenesstheorem has made clear that no matter how hard we try, we can never produceunity of truth and proof. GOdel showedthat for any given logical framework, there is at leastonepropositionthat canbe provedonly by referenceto a meta(logical) framework,and so on to infinity. As informally statedby JohnCasti (1990), GOdel's Theoremis that arithmetic is not completely formalizable. Stated even more informally, it is impossible to write down all the rules to a mathematicalsystem.GOdcl's Theoremmeans,for those who work with formal systems,that no matterhow hard they try, someaspectof the system will escapethem. The importanceof GOdel's discovery is predicatedon the assumption that what is true for formal systemsis also true for real, that is, nonmathematical, analogons.In Godel's Theorem, the question is not whether the formal system mirrors the real system, but whether the formal system (which has an independentexistence)provides us with information about .the structureof real systems. On a trivial level, we seethe notion of incompletenessin ancientexplanations of how the Earth fitted into the cosmos.In one variant, the Earth (which was thoughtof as a flat disk, like a tray) was said to be balancedon the backsof two turtles. The turtles, in tum, were said to standon the backs of two birds. This systemofferedno explanationof wherethe birds perched when they becametired of flying. If GodeJ'sTheoremis correct (and we have no reasonto assumethe contrary), then we are always obliged to accepton faith someelementof any systemof thought. It is, of course,one thing to acknowledgethe limits of knowledgeand quite anotherto build a scientific structureupon thoselimits. The former is nothing more than a negationof determinism.The latter would be a considerably greater achievement,since it would provide a means of moving forward, a meansof surmountingthe obstacleposed by the removal of determinismfrom the calculusof existence. No doubt, few practicingscientistsor mathematicianslie awakeat night 184 HENRY L. HAMMAN worrying about suchissues.They haveresearchproblemsto solve, articles to write, and careersto advance,just as we all do. Fortunately,though, the researchthey have undertakenhas generated a structurethat adaptsto both deterministicand indeterminatephenomena.In addition, this structureaccommodatesnotions of change,choice, and nonrationality,for which classical Newtoniandeterminismhad beenunableto accountin an acceptable way. In the popularliterature dealingwith aspectsof this new appreciationof natural sciencesand mathematics,this structureis often given the appellation "the scienceof complexity." This may be a misnomer, since a new understandingof complex systemsis an aspect(but not the whole substance)of the new structure.It is for that reasonthat I have chosenthe phrase"emergentscience"to describethis thought structure.In the following sections,I shall touch briefly on someof the other conceptsthat help to delineateemergentsciencefrom the classicalmodel. Nonlinearity We find it easyto incorporateinto our thoughtssuch ideas as, "For every action, there is an equal and opposite reaction." This sort of statement appealsto us as it tracesa direct path from A to B, a relationshipthat can be expressedas A --+ B. This statementsaysthat A (whateverA may be) mapsinto B. But we can say much more aboutthe relationshipof A and B, drawing on our intuition. We can say that, for the statementabove,it is also true that A =kB. While the valuesassignedto A, B, and k (some constant)may change, the relationship among these three values is straightforwardand directly proportional. Relationshipsthat do not respondproportionally (and systemsthat exhibit this property) are called nonlinear. For nonlinearsystems,it is possible for two variables to be in a relationship that varies under different conditions. Nonlinearity is an aspectof emergentsciencethat mathematiciansand scientistshaveonly begunto explore.Therearetwo relatedreasonsfor this. The first is the relative difficulty of solving nonlinearproblems.Because they do not exhibit the regularity of responseof linear problems,nonlinear problemsare not susceptibleto simple mathematicalmanipulation.Nonlinear equationsare so difficult to solve that, until recently, the approachof scientistsand mathematicianswhen confrontedby nonlinearterms was to toss them out, to linearize the equation. Sometimesthe equationswere deliberately written to avoid nonlinear terms. For instance,the classical REMODELING INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 185 equation for heat flow is linear, but heat flow is nonlinear. The result of approachingnonlinearproblemsas if they were linear is the Hobson'schoice that results: problemsthat are seento be nonlineareither are left unattacked or areconvertedto linear problemsand solvedwith the wrong answers. The secondreasonfor the recentemergenceof nonlinearityin mathematics and sciencehas to do with the relatively recentarrival on the sceneof the computer, more particularly the proliferation of small but powerful individual computerworkstations.As noted above, the beauty of a linear problemis that once two solutionsfor it are found, the path of all solutions is known. This meansthat, for the most part, linear problemscan be solved without referenceto equationsbecauseformulae are sufficient. To get the answerto a nonlinearproblem, however,one must find the stateof all the variablesand parametersfor eachpoint at which a solution is sought.When this had to be done by hand,or evenwith a mechanicalcalculator,nonlinearity resembledthe south face of the Eiger-fascinatingbut apparently unchallengeable. Indeterminacy Another block in the structureof emergentscienceis the notion of indeterminacy, or, more accurately,the notion of "apparentindeterminacy."The starting point for understandingthe importance of indeterminacyis, as usual, the Newtonian worldview and, more particularly, what Gerald Holton refers to as "the delayedtriumph of the purely mechanisticview in the completionof Newton's work by Laplace"(1988,3). Laplaceis best known for his notion that a universalintelligence,aware of the position and velocity of all matter at a given moment, could accurately predictoutcomesto the infinite future. Sucha notion appearsamusing,naive, or arroganttoday, but much of the substanceof our daily lives we live as if Laplaceandeterminismwere fact, even while bridling at the figurative straitjacketsinto which our free wills have beenencased.It is no wonderthat humanistswith only limited exposureto the notionsof physicsrail againstdeterminism. Of course, as David Ruelle observes,Laplace's cosmic view is less restrictive than we are generally taught to believe. Ruelle points out that there is nothing inherently contradictorybetweendeterminismand chance, for if the stateof a systemat its start time is not preciselyfixed but random, then the systemwill remainrandom(1991). Despitethis small comfort, the clockwork world of Laplacecontinuedto trouble philosophers.It was only with the developmentof quantummechanicsin the early part of this centurythat relief of a sort appeared. 186 HENRY L. HAMMAN Two points are speciallyimportantfor emergentscience.The first is the introduction of the notion of probability into a field that had previously beencharacterizedby the questfor precision.The secondis the introduction of the notion of the subjectiverole ofthe observerinto a field that had been characterizedby an objectiviststance. This profoundly unsettlingview of the natureof the fundamentalstructure of the physical world has beencited as one of the intellectual roots of the relativistic philosophical movementsthat have assumedsuch importance in the intellectual tenor of contemporaryWesternthought. If the nature of fundamentalphysical reality is dependentupon the observer,then what can be determined?From another perspective,since we observers make the choiceof what to look for, are we not ourselvesproducingdeterministic results?Ifwe cannotassertlocation as more than a statementof the odds,what, then, can be certain?Ifwe can determineaccuratelywhat those odds are, is this not a form of true certainty?Paradoxessuch as thesehave becomea stapleof the philosophyof science. Conditionality,Complexity,and Chaos As the spreadof computingpowerfocusedattentionon nonlinear problems, conditionality appearedas an answerto the puzzling fact that eventsthat seemedalike often producedvastly different outcomes.Quantummechanics gave impetus to the notion of indeterminacy.These ideas, which all share the property of "fuzziness," found unity in the rubric of chaos and complexity. Conditionality is really nothing more than a willingness to say, "It all depends."In other words, emergentsciencemakesexplicit the well-known but too-often-ignoredreality that ceterisparibus seldomapplies. The best examplesof the importanceof conditionsto outcomesare drawn from the subfield of emergentscienceknown as chaostheory, but the idea is one that goesbackcenturies.The verseaboutthe causalchain in which for want of a nail, the horse'sshoewas lost, which causeda knight to be withdrawn from battle, which causedthe tide of the battle to turn, which led to the fall of a kingdom is a clear illustration of the idea behind conditionality. Had a blacksmithtappedjust a bit harderon the nail, perhapsthe horsemight not have lost its shoe,and so forth. Or maybe,there was a flaw in the nail or a weaknessin the structureof the hoof. Suchspeculationcan go on ad infinitum (not to mentionad nauseam). The problem that chaos theory is most closely associatedwith in the physical sciencesis an ancient one: turbulence. Turbulence is a specific caseof a problem--tbebreakdownof order in deterministicsystems.What REMODELING INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 187 makesturbulenceso difficult to deal with is the unpredictabilityof its onset. Not only has physical sciencefailed to devise rules for predicting the appearanceof turbulence,it alsohasfailed to developan adequateexplanation for its appearancewithin otherwiseorderedsystems.Lacking requisitetheoretical tools, engineersand scientistsgenerallydeal with turbulenceeither by ignoring it when possibleor by treatingit as a problemto be approached heuristically. Turbulent phenomenahave been encounterednot only in engineering, but also in a rangeof systemsin which, despitetheir manifestlydeterministic nature,the randomand the inexplicablecould appearsuddenlyandwithout warning. Since the problem of turbulence appearedincapable of solution within the scopeof existing knowledge,the responsewas, for the mostpart, to ignore the issuesraised,concentratinginsteadon the regularities, with the view that theseanomalieseventuallywould be resolved.There is nothing shamefulin this; it is the meansby which the physical sciences have progresseddespite the continued existenceof problems that they lacked the ability to solve. The danger,of course,is that what is ignored may be treated as if it did not exist. The problem of indeterminacyin determinatesystems,however,proveddifficult to ignore, particularly after the arrival of the computer,when even the most deterministic scienceof all--mathematics--was increasinglytroubled by stochasticintrusions.The intrusion of the random-seeminginto the determinatewas the cause of intellectual disquiet, as it appearedto be in contradictionto the Newtonian vision of a universe in which, when initial values were known, outcomes wereassumedto be predictable. Complexity, like chaosand like the quantum,is one of those concepts that both defies intuition and appealsto intuition. Essentially,the idea be~ hind complexityis that the location of interestingbehavioris in a region far from stability, where order is just on the verge of breaking down, at the edge of chaos. Scholarswho write about complexity often refer to what they call criticality. When they do so, they often cite a sandpile as an exampleof what they aretalking about. The sandpileis a system:it consistsof componentgrains of sand.The systemreceivesinput as more sanddribbling from above.New grains of sandorganizethemselves(without volition) on the top of the pile, so that the structuregrows higher and higher until it can no longer remain stable. At that point, the sand slides unpredictably(chaotically) down the sides of the pile, and the system attains a new, self-organizedstate of criticality. The behavior of the sandpile system is an example of how systems operateon the edgeof chaos,the areaof the system'sphasespace thatis of 188 HENRY L. HAMMAN particular interest to researchersin complex systemsbehavior. There are severalreasonsto suspectthat this region is of particularinterest. First, the system is seekingto maintain itself in an organizedfashion, without any outsideintervention.This conceptof self-organizationis a core conceptof theoriesthat embracecomplexity. Self-organizationis the mechanism by which insect colonies arrange themselves,the mechanismby which convectioncurrentsappearin liquids and gasesthat have previously exhibited only Brownian motion, and (very possibly) the mechanismthat underliesthe creationof humansocieties,including states. Second,the systemat the edgeof chaosis interestingbecauseit exhibits the dynamic tension betweenorder (self-organization)and stochasticbehavior (chaos). Since the system has not slipped over the dividing line betweenstability and chaos,its behavioris perfectly predictable.When the boundaryis crossed,it becomesimpossibleto say with any certainty what will happento the structure.One cannoteven say just when the boundary will be crossed,since there is exquisitesensitivity to changesin conditions at this boundary. Who can know which grain of sand, falling at which precisespot, will be the trigger for a slide?Even if the grain of sandand the precisespotwereto be detennined(one could figure out which grain caused the slide by simply dropping sanda grain at a time), that knowledgewould not enablethe observerto predict the condition of either that grain or the systemwhen it emergesfrom the chaoticregion. Third, the systemis interestingbecausethe excursionsinto chaotic behavior vary. At sometimes, the slides that the falling sandtriggers will be small, and only minor changesin the systemwill result. At other times, the excursionsinto chaotic realmswill producemajor restructuringof the system. A mathematicalfunction called apowerlaw enablesan observerof the system to speakprobabilistically about the chancefor a major or minor restructuringto take place,althoughnot to predict with any precisioneither when a given excursioninto chaoswill occur or how severethe excursion will be. The Problem of Learning Researchershave long beenpuzzledby questionsabout how complex systems seemto learn--to changetheir structures,their behaviors,and even their appearances--without the presenceof a central directing sentient power. Of particular interestis the genetic algorithm, a set of instructions that modifies itself and in so doing may bring improvementsto the system in which it operates. Algorithms are nothingmore than a setof rules for achievinga particular REMODELING INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 189 task. The benefit of an algorithm is that, once it has beendeveloped,those who use it do not have to think about its derivation. In fact, they have no knowledgeof the algorithm'spresenceor operation.Humanbeingsare not awareof the embeddedalgorithmsthat govern much of their behavior.For instance,there is the algorithm that determineswhat happenswhen food reachesthe stomachand the algorithm that controls what happenswhen a speckof dust approachesthe eye. Thesealgorithms are hardwiredinto our individual systems. One would imagine that algorithms, once installed, would remain the same,rote formulas, producing the sameresults repeatedly, ad infinitum. Yet we know that systemsevolve, that new behavioral responsesappear.If algorithms are rules and rules are deterministic,how cantherebe any change? John Von Neumannaddressedthis problem. He first discussedsystems, which he called automata,that follow algorithmsto produceoutputsunlike themselves,such as computers,which follow instructionsbut do not reproducethemselvesby thoseinstructions,and McCulloch-Pittsneurons,which produce pulses that are different from the automaton.Then he turned to automata,"which can have outputssomethinglike themselves."Von Neumannthen definedwhat he was interestedin. Von Neumannarguedthat this passageis "an axiomatically shortened and simplified description of what an organism does." He notes that the resultsreachedby such an operationwould be heavily dependentupon the way the elementaryparts had beendefined, their number,and so on. However, having acknowledgedtheselimitations, he arguedthat it is legitimate to consider a system of self-reproducingautomata"which will stand up undercommonsensecriteria" (1966, 77). Von Neumannmadea telling point when he observedthat, in considering self-reproducingorganisms,one would expect to find that the organism could not produce any new organism more complicated than itself. One would expect to see a reproductionfalling short of the original, so that the processwould be a degenerativeone. However, this is not necessarilythe case, Von Neumann noted. The key to this nonintuitive result he called "complication," and the level of complicationwas the determinantfactor for whetherthe processof reproductiveactivity would be degenerativeor otherwise. The level of complicationwas, in tum, determinedby the number of parts. Von Neumannsaid he did not know precisely where the break point was, but he proposedthe level at betweenone dozenand two dozen.Then he madethe following observation,which is the crucial one for this discussion: There is thus this completely decisive property of complexity, that there existsa critical size below which the processof synthesisis degenerative,but 190 HENRY L. HAMMAN abovewhich the phenomenonof synthesis,if properly arranged,can become explosive,in otherwords,wheresynthesesof automatacan proceedin sucha manner that each automatonwill produce other automatawhich are more complexand of higherpotentialitiesthan itself. (1966, 80) The meansfor this productionof more complexautomataproposedby Von Neumann is the introduction into the system of random changesin the descriptive code that the automatause for reproduction. Some of these randomchangeswill causethe reproductivecycle to break,and thesemutations will be lethal. Others will lead to the production of more complex machinesthat can reproducethemselvesat the new level of complexity. This is, at a basic level, preciselyhow genetic algorithms behave.This is also a much simplified presentationof the way in which DNA operatesin the reproductivecodingofliving organisms. Holland's creationof genetic algorithms is the outcomeof nearly forty years of efforts to simulate evolution in a computer.His insight was that while mutations play a role in evolution, the primary engine of genetic evolution is mating, with the resultantrecombinationof genetic material. Holland'smodel for this processrelies on what he calls a classifiersystem, consistingof a set of rules, eachof which performsparticularactionsevery time its conditions are satisfied by some piece of information (Holland 1992, 66). If certain parts of the output of a classifier systemare tied to behaviors,thenthe operationof the systemcan trigger actions. While the geneticalgorithm clearly appliesto biological systems,it can also be applied to other systems.For instance,corporatemanagementsystems evolve as managersdevelopnew classifiersystemsthat rate fitness in termsof corporateprofit. A Do-It-Yourself Kit for Constructivists The picture of scientific or mathematicalthought outlined above is (1 suspect) considerablydifferent from the picture held in the minds of many internationalrelationstheorists.However,this picture is remarkablyconsistent with constructivistontology, enoughso that it is possible,without too much imagination,to suggesta possibleisomorphismbetweenconstructivism and emergentscience'selaborationof complexdynamic systems.This observationmay be demonstratedby the act of constructingwhat computer programmerscall a look-up table, or a table of correspondences, suchas the one presentedin Table 8.1. This exerciseis presentednot as definitive or complete, but simply as an example of just how easily one can locate correspondences betweenconstructivismand current scientific or mathe- REMODEUNG INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS 191 Table 8.1 Potential Isomorphisms Between Emergent Science and Constructivism Social arrangement/structure Agent Rule Institution/regime Social arrangement/structure Social construction Unintended consequence Social arrangement/structure automaton Complex automaton Genetic algorithm Classifier system Interconnection matrix Emergent hierarchical organization Emergent property matical thinking. While the table as it now standsis no more than a hypothesis,the relationshipssuggestedby it are subjectto experimentalconfirmation or rejection. Onufs definition of agentsis at least consistentwith the propertiesof complexautomata,especiallyif thoseautomataare seenas both constructing andbeing constructedby rules (which changeover time), alsoknown as "genetic algorithms." And just as agent-constructedand agent-governing rules generateand are generatedby institutions, so too can autornataevolved setsof geneticalgorithmsbe seenas classifiersystemsthat generate the further evolution of the automataand the systemof which they are components.A systemthat evolvesitself (as doesthe internationalsystem) is by definition an emergentorganization.As Onuf points out, that system, despiteclaims of sovereignty,doesexhibit hierarchicalcharacteristics,thus suggestingthat this social constructionis isomorphicwith emergenthierarchical organization.Clearly, there is an isomorphismbetweenOnufs "unintendedconsequences" and emergentproperties,both by definition being productsof the complex interplay among the elementsof the systembut generatedfrom the systemitself. Of course,pointing out potentialisomorphismsis considerablylessdifficult than building a formal theoreticalmodel, but the apparentgoodnessof fit betweenemergentscienceand constructivismis surely enoughto suggest that it may be too soon for internationalrelationstheory to give up on the methods(andepistemology)of the sciencesandmathematics. If the isomorphismssuggestedhold up under appropriatetests, the advancefor international relationstheory would be significant, since intemational relationswould finally have in hand the tools neededto commence the constructionof a model-theoreticapproachto the discipline. And that would be no small achievement. 192 HENRY L. HAMMAN Note Someof the material in this chapteroriginally appearedin a different form in my "The EmergentScientific Epistemologya."1d International Relations" (unpublisheddoctoral dissertation,Coral Gables,Fla.: University of Miami, 1993), while additional material flows from researchundertakenat Sociocybernetics,Inc. I am grateful to my colleagues at Sociocybernetics,Inc., especiallyBernardE. Howard, for their patienceand lucidity in discussingand explainingmany of the mathematicalconstructsusedherein. I should also like to thank Vendulka Kubalkova and Nicholas Onuf for many constructivesuggestions.Obviously, misunderstandingsor misrepresentations that remain are my responsibilityalone. Bibliography Bunge,Mario. 1973. Method,Model. andMatter. Dordrecht:D. Reidel. - - - . 1979. CausalityandModern Science,3d rev. ed. New York: Dover. Casti John. 1990. Searching/orCertainty: What ScientistsCan KnowAboutthe Future. New York: William Morrow. Coveny, Peter, and Roger Highfield. 1990. The Arrow 0/ Time: A Voyage Through Scienceto SolveTime'sGreatestMystery.New York: FawcettColumbine. Ferguson,Yale H., and Richard W. Mansbach.1988. The Elusive Quest: Theory and InternationalPolitics. Columbia:University of SouthCarolinaPress. Gell-Mann, Murray. 1990. "The SantaFe Institute." SantaFe: The SantaFe Institute. Photocopy. Grene, Marjorie. 1971. "Reducibility: Another Side Issue?"In Interpretations0/ Life andMind: EssaysAroundthe Problem0/Reduction,ed. MaIjorie Grene.New York: Humanities. Holland, JohnH. 1992. "GeneticAlgorithms." ScientificAmerican267 (1): 66-72. Holton, Gerald. 1988. The ThematicOrigins 0/ Scientific Thought: Kepler to Einstein, rev. ed. Cambridge:HarvardUniversity Press. Howard, Bernard E. 1991. "Dynamic Systems." Coral Gables, Fla: University of Miami. Photocopy. Lane, David A. 1992. "Artificial Worlds and Economics." Santa Fe: The Santa Fe Institute.Photocopy. Nicolis, Gregorie, and Ilya Prigogine. 1989. Exploring Complexity: An Introduction. New York: W.H. Freeman. Penrose,Roger. 1989. The Emperor'sNew Mind: ConcerningComputers,Minds, and the Laws0/Physics.Oxford: Oxford University Press. - - - . 1994. Shadowso/the Mind: A Search/orthe Missing Scienceo/Consciousness.Oxford: Oxford University Press. Prigogine,Ilya. 1984. Order out 0/Chaos: Man's NewDialogue with Nature. Toronto: BantamBooks. Ruelle, David. 1991. Changeand Chaos.Princeton:PrincetonUniversity Press. Von Neumann,John. 1966. Theory of Self-ReproducingAutomata, edited and completedby Arthur W. Burks. Urbana:University of Illinois Press. Weinberg,Steven.1992. Dreams0/Final Theory. New York: Pantheon. 9 Reconstructing the Discipline: Scholars as Agents Vendulka Kubtilkovti SinceNicholasOnuf introducedthe approachin 1989,"constructivism"has spreadlike a forest fire. Unfortunately most scholarstook only the label. They attachedit to many things and rarely definedit. Worse still, it became a vacuouscliche: as the post-Cold War order is being reconfigured,the term constructivismhasan air of being appropriatefor the occasion. This book was not written to reclaim rights to a particularword. If in the world of academeit were possibleto registera trademarkfor any "original" term or concept,the legal professionwould have to move to campusesand the flood of academicpublicationswould be reducedto a trickle. We want to reattachthe term to the meaning its author originally intended for an entirely different reason. Constructivismas Onuf conceivedit was designedto convey a distinct message.If someonecries that there is a fire when there is no fire, then eventually the word will no longer convey alarm when it would be warranted. When people falsely cry "fire," the word loses its meaning and association.As this book shows,constructivismdoesnot refer to instances of statessigning internationalagreements, joining an internationalorganization, or observingrules of a particularinternationalregime. Constructivism, in this book, refers to a universal human experienceof living in both smallerand larger social contexts.Expandedontological guidelinesto how the world is put togetherdo not necessarilyexcludeor diminish the centrality, in the presentworld, of statesand interstaterelations.Yet the redescription of the world leadsto a very different understandingof statesand states' 193 194 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A relations.Reclaimingthe word constructivismsavesit from being drowned in so manyparallel meaningsthat the original messageis not heard. Addressingthe issue raisedby the title of this chapterwith constructivism in mind provides ample justification for moving beyond endlessesoteric debatesinto something more constructive. How do scholars in IR function as agents?How does the discipline as an institution constitute agency?How, in short, can constructivismbe turned to an analysisof this discipline itself? Answering thesequestionsfrom a constructivistperspective revealsthe multiple agenciesand their often conflicting rules that the academicdiscipline, and individual scholars,mustreconcile. Agents are participantsin the social process,individuals whoseactsmaterially affect the world. Not all individuals can intervenein every kind of world-making,social arrangement-constituting process.Rulesconstitutinga societydefine the conditionsunderwhich individuals, institutions, or associationscan intervenein the affairs of society. Each of us, in our professionas scholars,is an agent. Indeed,we can be in manysortsof agentsat once,andwe arepart of multiple socialarrangements which, by defmition, we could or should be intervening in the world. In this chapter,I count five suchsocial arrangementsin which we can, as a profession and/or as individuals, make a difference: in the culture of society broadly construed,in the culture of internationalpolitics, in the foreign policy of the United Statesin particular,in the discipline ofIR, and in the classroom.To put it differently, how IR as an institution in the United Statesfunctionsas an agent dependson the intersectionof a numberof social processes,all of which affect or are affected by academicIR: society, its foreign policy, the international societyand its agents,the IR discipline itself, andthe teachingthat trains future agents.The requirementsof theseagenciesare intertwined, sometimesmutually reinforcing, often conflicting. In the following discussionsI will try to addressthemas if they were isolatedfrom eachother. 1. Guardians of Western Culture in Academic Disciplines Societydeterminesthe guardiansof its culture. For that purpose,the educational systemis establishedand chargedwith the analysisand codification of rules and norms, and with their legitimization,justification, elucidation, and explication. Educationprovidesknowledgeboth of theserules and of overt and covert sanctionsfor noncompliance.Universitieseducatethe future public elites, educators,journalists and other media specialists,and future policy makers. According to establishedpracticein the Westernuniversities,rules keep the guardiansof educationaway from agentsin "real life." Until recently, RECONSTRUCTING THE DISCIPLINE 195 the questionof whetherIR could become"an agent"in internationalpolitics would have been beyond the bounds of reasonabledebate,and one who raisedthe questionwould be dismissedas a disciple of Noam Chomsky,Joe McCarthy, or of Soviet Marxist-Leninist propaganda.In the liberal tradition, academicsand practitionershavebeenregardedas two distinct ethnic groups with only limited intermingling, as with the exception of few Kissingersdefectingto diplomacy and lapseddiplomatsseekingcareersin academe.The prevailing view, as Stanley Hoffmann put it, was that you cannotexpect"a cherry tree to grow applesany more than an appletree can grow cherries."Academicsas guardiansof knowledgewere to be protected from political interferencein their relentlesssearchfor the truth. This positivist separationof scholarand subjectmatter was reinforced by the more sophisticatedpositivism of behavioralism:in their pursuit of objectivetruth and value-free knowledge, the academicdiscoverersof knowledge were isolated(Alker 1982) to preservetheir questfrom the contaminatinginfluenceof "outside" interests.The separationhasdevelopedinto a big "gap" in needof bridging. AlexanderGeorge(1994) reportsthat policy makersconcedethe usefulnessof putting things in a larger context.Georgeconcluded, however, that the academicversion of knowledge is perceived as very different from "policy relevant knowledge" (the more heuristic wisdom soughtby policy makers).Can the distinction betweenacademicsand poliey makersbe defendedin the information age, in an era of unprecedented democratizationof accessto datarequiring interpretation?If the universities do not help to makesenseof the world, whereelsedo policy makerstum? Other custodiansof Westernculture, of which the discipline of IR is a part, are scattered:they are in the media, the publishing world, different governmentagencies,and think tanks. The circumstancesunderwhich they are eligible to become"agents"dependalso on the internal normsandrules establishedin the intellectualcommunityof a country. In principle, university professors,as both scholarsand teachers,have been called upon to rationalize and legitimize the assumptionsof their culture. As such they can serveas prime agentsof social construction.But often it is the unintendedeffects of their primary activities that become more important. For example,the IR discipline hasbeenconstructedas a discipline with the mandateto study war and conflict in international relationsso that future wars may be avoided.Nobody would dismantlea discipline for failing to fulfill that mission, which is no doubt harderthan finding a cure for cancer. If IR has failed in its main mission, then inadvertentlyit has performed to perfection a much easierrole, namely the reaffirmation of the mainstreamrealistunderstandingof internationalrelations. 196 VENDULKA KUBALKOV A Statesas social arrangementsrequireand receiveconstantremindersand confirmations,constantdisplaysof symbolsand rituals reinforcing the social processcalled stateor nation. The understandingof the world as taught in international relations coursesassistedthese processes.A state-centric view and an understandingof "anarchy" on the "outside" contrastedwith the safetyof the "inside" reinforce personalallegiancesto the state.As has frequently beenpointedout, the internationalor global awarenessof young studentsand citizens generally is low, and the blind acceptanceof norms and rules for national behavioron the world stageis incredibly high. Citizens question internal policies in minute detail but accept the image of internationalrelationsas received.Thus they acceptpassivelythe existence of and needfor immigration regulations,carry passports,and subjectthemselvesto visa controls. The state'sflags fly proudly, and soldiersare celebrated and honored for dying or killing for their country, the most incredibly powerful of social constructions. 2. Guardiansof tbe Cultureof tbe International Societyof States The public elites of other countriesare similarly engagedin shapingthe rules and normsof their societies.IR scholarshaveactedon the assumption that becausethe theory and practice of IR are supposedto be universally valid, the practice of IR and the codifications of norms and rules of IR publishedby Americanpresseswill be universallyaccepted.The worldwide use of the English languagehas reinforcedthis myth. This approachdenies a role to local circumstancesin different countries and to local "agents" who areinevitably engagedin the processof co-construction. Reactingto this flawed assumptionof universality, many perceivecultural imperialism,hegemony,and parochialismin the practiceof American intellectuals. American scholarsof IR reassurethemselvesthat they are doing a good job in teaching a realist view of the world, in an effort to representthe "truth," since the statessystem is so well institutionalized acrossthe planet.Thereis no meaningfulway to live outsidestates(except in ratherinhospitableareason the oceanand underwateror in the air). How was this arrangementconstructed?Who setthe rules andnorms? Anglo-AmericantextbooksportrayacademicIR and its understandingof this processas part of a universal humanexperience.This contrastssharply with perceptionsof the processelsewhere.IR does not exist as a separate academicareaof study in most partsof the world. Yet in the Anglo-American context, it has beenportrayedas being on a par with natural sciences suchas biology or physics,of universalrelevance. RECONSTRUCTING THE DISCIPLINE 197 Onuf's analytical schememakesit easierto recognize-indeed,it leads us to expect--thatthe rules and norms of IR are not uniform acrossthe world. The practiceof diplomacy originating in the West appearsto have gained universal currency. Yet not all rules and norms related to IR are sharedor universalized.Statesaccept international law and international organizations,and in their international intercourse behave in a similar manner(Hedley Bull thought this constitutedwhat he called international society). Onuf's constructivism acknowledgesthat there are multiple sourcesof rules and norms constructingthe world's social structure.Both local identity and culture are crucial influenceson the interpretationand creationof rules by agents.The analysisof norms and rules in world politics revealsthat they reflect national,ethnic, religious, and other identities, broughtto bearon socialprocessesby particularcultures. The conductof internationalrelationsmakessenseonly within a cultural context. Unfortunately,becauseof the assumptionof universality, the cultural contexthas beena blind spot (or indeeda consciouslyexcludedsubject) in the discipline of IR. And yet, membersof Western societiesdo assumethat ideascount,that rules guide conduct,that peoplecanmakereal choices,and that differencescan be reconciled.By contrast,in the former Soviet bloc (in which culture retainsa stronglegacyof the communistway of thinking and understandingthe world), new rules have not always replacedthe old. The culture of the former Soviet bloc still assignsa primary positionto materialfactorsandtreatsrules in a strictly instrumentalfashion. It may appearto offer meaningful choices,but the rule has not yet been establishedthat choicescan be made. It is indeedpossiblethat rules will continueunchangedon one level and will changeon another,as happened whenthe SovietUnion fell apart. IR scholarsseldom appreciatethat the majority of the world does not speakor think in the languageof modernity. IR expertsthereforeconfront an insurmountableproblem with the currentdebateabout "de-Westernization," "desecularization,"or "Islamization" of the world; "religious wars"; or revanchedu Dieu. The missingcommondenominatoris a needto recognize that frighteningly complex world affairs require an understandingof many systemsof thought, whetherreligious or secular.Each of thesesystems carries its own attitudes and values about good and bad, right and wrong, the world and God, individual, family, society,state,nation, wealth, authority,equality,justice,conflict, violence,andwar. The causeof the problem can be found in Westernculture. Most postEnlightenmentWesternthinkers,in the spirit espousedby many academics to this day, assumethat religions are superstitionsto be phasedout in the age of "modernity" and "progress"by a "secular humanism"and by sci- 198 VENDULKA KUBA.LKOVA. ence.Exposedby a diminishedpreoccupationwith the Cold War, the error of this assumptionis being revealed.Stimulatedby migration, social mobility, trade, and the electronicand print media, religion has expandedexplosively within many societiesand has reemergedas an internationalforce. Religions are increasinglyrecognizedas one of the most significant forms of social organizationand ideology, the codifications of norms and rules. Religiously inspired people are agents too. The world is disrupted with increasingfrequencyin the nameof religion, at both the domesticand the internationallevel. Indeed,somereligions do not include amongtheir values a territorial principle that respectsstateboundariesand nonintervention acrossthem.. Religions define valuesand strugglesover values,in addition to strugglesfor securityand wealth, and will very likely playa central role in the next century. Many observersnow view religion as an important predictorof peaceand war, just as ideology was during the Cold War. Yet the study of religions is totally absentfrom IR studies.In the most recent book heraldingthe return of the identity and culture to internationalrelations, there is no index entry referring to religion per se and there are only severalpagesdealingwith Islam (Lapid and Kratochwil 1996). 3. Advisors to ForeignPolicy Makers IR neednot be irrelevantto foreign policy making. The lack of relevanceis expressedin the deepeningdisdain with which policy makers approach researchand advice proffered by academics.For policy makers,the readymade substitute for scholarly advice is at hand in the Information Age: accessthroughinformationsuperhighwaysto "knowledge"without the benefit of formal training in IR. If academicIR does not perform this role, if the debatesbecometoo esotericor impossibleto understand,then sanctions (often too subtle to be regardedas such) will come into play: funding for professorsandjob opportunitiesfor graduateswill flow elsewhere,and the statusand the profile of the professionwill be lowered. The franchisewill be taken over by whoeverelse is capableof performing the relevanttasks: print media,televisioncommentators,andjournalists. Academicsmay consolethemselvesthat theseare peoplewhom we prepared to be agents and whose role we constructed.But did we? If we examinethe rendition of the world as we find it in the media, the conclusions are disturbing: awarenessof the "outside" has not beenenhancedand internationalaffairs take a distant secondplaceto national and particularly local events. Reporting and editorials in public affairs journals reflect a strong degreeof statecentrismbut none of the increasinglyarcaneconceptual apparatusthat IR scholarsuse to make senseof the world. We do hear RECONSTRUCTINGTHE DISCIPLINE 199 voices that speakin the languageof constructivism,without knowing what it is, like Moliere's M. Jourdain,who neverknew that he spokein prose. 4. Membersof AcademicDisciplines Certain rules and norms govern the American academiccommunity as it engagesin the social processesdiscussedso far. Crucial in this regardis the hierarchy of the American IR community, the internal rules it abides by, and its ability to regenerate,evaluateitself, and adjust. Also important are the rules and norms that establishqualificationsand seniority in the field, define scholarship,and identify the "mainstream,"marking the rest as outsidethe mainstream. The distinction betweenmainstreamand nonmainstreamdoes not have an obvious parallel in the British Commonwealthcountries or Europe. There, terminal degreesare awardedwith the participation of a diverse academiccommunity.Doctoral examinersare selected(and their identity is kept secretfrom the candidate)from any other university in the same(or evenanother)country. Thus a standardis maintainedthat doesnot necessitate the tremendouslystrict pecking order in the American academy, whereby degreesare judged and awardedinternally by each institution. Academein the United Statesis thereforevery hierarchical,with very limited "upward mobility." Perhapsthe reasonis the tremendoussize of the U.S. educationalsystem.IR is taughtin most of the 3,200degree-awarding institutions, which would make it difficult to follow the British and Continental model. The consequence of the U.s. systemis that only the elite in the IR field, a handful of "experts" located in the most respectedU.S. universities,are "agents."What is publishedin the main scholarlyjournals (with editorial boards"manned"by the samegroup) and by the main publishing housesis controlled by these experts. The rest of the field is left simply to instructstudentsin mainstreamwisdom. 5. Teachersof Studentsin a Relationas Individuals Most scholarsare teachers.Teachingremainsthe most pedestrianform of agencyfor most of us, but the main or the only one in which we are not anonymous.We devisesyllabi that reflect our professionalopinions about knowledge,and we standin front of classesto conveyit. It is from thesepedagogicalconcernsand ambitionsthat this volume has grown. On one hand, IR is one of the most importantsubjectstaught in the social sciences.On the otherhand,we worry aboutwhetherour pronouncements qualify as knowledgeto impart to students.We have two choices. 200 VENDULKA KusALKOV A One is to presentthe studentwith a smorgasbordof approachesand debates encouragedby the notion that IR is multi paradigmatic.Thus graduatestudentsare left with the problemof decidingto what paradigmtheir research should be attached,and undergraduatestudentsare left with xenophobic ideas about the increasinginhospitability of the world "outside." Professional students,combining IR with preparationfor work in businessor otherprofessionswith a "global" component,will be left without muchhelp andwith little ideaaboutwhat to expectwhen confrontingthe globe. The secondchoice is to pick and teach an approachthat each of us regardsas the most sensibleone, playing down or ignoring all the others. This is easyfor scholarswho teachthe resultsof their own research.Yet the sharp distinction between mainstreamand nonmainstreammakes it irresponsiblefor nonmainstreamscholarsto pursuethis path since their students would be seriouslydisadvantagedby ignoranceof mainstreamtexts shouldthey proceedto otherinstitutionsfor otherdegrees.Neitheroption is attractive to the teacher who is disenchantedwith current debates.Not everyonefinds it easyto teach tenfold classificationsand increasinglyincestuousdelusionary"debates"over "schoolsof thought" (of often one or two people)explaining an imaginary world populatedby abstractand nonhmnanbut often reified creaturessuch as states,anarchies,structures,levels, units, and balances.The creaturesare accordedtheir own logic that peoplecannothopeto influence. A reorientationis obviously overdue.A glanceat a handbookfor teachers (LaBarr and Singer 1977) publishedtwenty years ago reveals thatwe are adding without cmnulatingand repeatingwithout deepening.Most of the texts this handbooklists still appearin footnotes.The list could now be augmentedby including youngerscholars,but newer books are more and more polemical and assmnea broader and broader range of shallower knowledgediffused within a larger and larger body of literature. Nothing ever seemsto be pruned out. Amazingly not even the "hurricane" of the Cold War's endmanagedto do the pruningjob. However, it is the accumulationof irrelevancies,in all five social processesdiscussedabove,that gives hope that changeis possible.Pressures for changecome also from outside the discipline. Many academicfields, social sciencesas well as natural sciences,are now adding global concerns to their agenda.Interest in the global context is obvious not only among economists(who populatea subfield of IR) but also in sociology,historical sociology, sociology of religion, anthropology,demography,and geography. It seemsto follow logically that as the world becomesincreasingly global, the subject matter of thesedisciplines will spill acrosstraditional boundaries.The natural sciencesalso work with the global perspectivein RECONSTRUCTING THE DISCIPLINE 201 mind, particularly thosesciencesthat addressenvironmentaldegradationor the Information Age-by definition global in scope.It is too late to stop them from encroachingon our turf What then doesthe future of IR hold? What will happennext? Reconstructing IR? Nothing. Certainly not soon.Thereare only two processes,both social, that might interveneto bring abouta changein due course.First, the discipline of IR might ceaseto be an agent in any of the sensesdiscussedabove. Before that happens,however,a secondprocessmight intervene:IR might well take on ideasand conceptsfrom other fields. This processof absorption would be at the sametime a processof dissolution.IR would not cease to exist but would assumea new role--a role pioneeredin the study of the environment.IR would coordinatean influx of social and natural sciences into global studieswithout insisting on its own distinct turf. Justas ecology has becomean organizerand integratorof many disciplines(indeed,ecology is derived from the Greek oikos, for "house"), so too IR might house the "social ecologyof global society." Unlike realism,constructivismis not threatenedby such potentialdevelopments.On the contrary,it can provide valuableassistancein reconstructing the discipline. Thosewho are awareof theseprocessesare more likely to take stepsforward aheadof the mainstream. Note Paul Kowert has very kindly helpedme to rewrite this chapter.My thanksgo to him for this assistance,as well as to both Paul Kowert and Nicholas Onuffor their comments.I take responsibilityfor the chapter'sconclusions. Bibliography Alker, Hayward R. 1982. "Logic, Dialectics, Politics: Some RecentControversies."In Dialectical Logic for (he Political Sciences,ed. H.R. Alker, PoznanStudies in the Philosophyof the Sciencesof Humanities,vol. 7,65-93. Amsterdam:Rodopi. George,AlexanderL. 1994. Bridging the Gap: Theoryand Practice in Foreign Policy. Washington,DC: United StatesInstituteof Peace. LaBarr, Dorothy F., and 1. David Singer. J977. The Studyof International Politics: A Guide to the Sourcesfor the Student, Teacher, and Researcher.SantaBarbara,CA: Clio Books. Lapid, Y osef, and Friedrich KratochwiI, eds. 1996. The Return of Culture and Identity in InternationalRelationsTheory. Boulder,co: Lynne Rienner. Pettrnan,Ralph. 1994. "What We Think About World Politics, What We Don't Think, and Why?" Paperpresentedat the U.S. InternationalStudiesAssociationConference, March. This page intentionally left blank Index Adorno, Max, 45 Adler, Emmanuel,8 academicdisciplines.Seedisciplines academicsand practitioners,195 act, acting.Seedeed action-structure.SeeCarlsnaes; morphogenesis actions, classof. Seerules administrativechallengepanels (ACPs), 162, 163 agency,59-61,64-77 co-constitutionof, 128 theory of, 128 agent(s),5, 6, 7 as institutions,72-73 as observers,61-62, 64, 71, 73 autonomy,independence of, 65, 77 control over, 63, 74-5 defined,80-81 individual as, 83 InternationalRelationsas, 195 imputing structure,83 scholarsas, 194-201 singular,collective, 64, 66 stateas, 83 Seealso rule agent-structureproblem/debate,62, 79-99,62,79,82,83,89 and levels of analysis,88-89 ontologicaland methodological natureof, 83 Albright, Madelaine,161 algorithm, genetic,188-90 Alker, Hayward,31,195 Seealso Alker, H. and Biersteker,T. Alker, H. and Biersteker,T., 30, 31, 36,48 Allen, Roger, 111 Allport, Gordon, 107 Alperovitz, Gar, 44 Althusser,Luis, 6, 45 Seealso Marxism, structural analytic dualism,91-92 anarchy,196 in structuralrealism,90 interactionswithin, 90 condition of. Seerule Anderson,Perry,41, 44 anthropology,9 anti-epistemology.SeeFoucault,Michel anti-positivist, 173 approachiparadigm,48 discourse,39 archaeologyof knowledge.See Foucault,Michel Archer, Margaret,91-92 Aristotle, 30 arrangements. See structure artificial world, 181 Ashley, Richard, 35, 36, 37,41,48,49 associations,as institutions,72-76 Aswan High Dam, 113, 114, 116,118 attribution error, 107, 110, 114,116 Austin, lL., 45 authority. Seecontrol legitimate; hegemony autonomy.Seeagents,autonomyof BaghdadPact, 110, III balanceof power, 20 as institution, 70-71 global,153 Seealso consequences, unintended Banks,Michael, 36 203 204 INDEX Baran,Paul, 44 Barry, Andrew, 154 behavior,regularities.Seebehavioralism behavioralism,84 benefits,74 Benjamin,Walter, 45 Berners-Lee,Tim, 149 Bhaskar,Roy, 86, 88, 89 Seealso realism,scientific Biersteker,Thomas.SeeAlker H. and BierstekerT. binary thesis-antithesis. Seedialectics, dialecticalrules biological determinism,125 Booth, Kenneth,27 Bourdieu,Pierre,44, 48 Britain, 110-20 Brown, Chris, 29 Brucan,Sylviu, 46 Bull, Hedley, 26, 41, 197 Bunge,~ario, Bunge,~ario, 174-5, 177 Buraimi, 112 Byroade,Henry, 111 Campbell,John, 104, 105 capitalism,global, 154 Carisnaes,Walter, 90, 91-92 Carr, E. H., 25-57, 28, 29, 36, 53-54 Carter,Jimmy, 104 castes,75 Casti,John,175, 183 categorization,106 Chan,Stephen,90 change,30 18~ chaos,7,53-54 as absenceof rule, 62 choices,60-63,65,67,70, 74, 77 Seealso rules Churchill, Winston, 110, 115 citizens,manufactureof, 126 citizenship,104 civil society,38, 48 classstruggle,29 clockworld model, 185 co-constitution,80 patternof, 82, 155 Seealso structures,phenomenal propertiesof coercion,37 cognitivepsychology.Seepsychology Cold War, 198 collective action, 101 collective identities,93 Seealso identity command,chain of, 71, 76 Seealso organizations commissive-rule,158, 162-3 commitment-rules,68, 72 Seealso rules commongood, 39 computers,148, 149, 150, 151, 159 communications,digital, 152 communicativeaction,theory of, 129 and constructivism,129 complexinstitutions.Seeinternational relations complexity,186-188 Comte,Auguste,8 conditionality,186-188 conflict. Seedialectics,dialectial rules conjecture,historical, 45, 52n.2 consensus,37-38 consequences, intended,unintended, 20,59-64,68-69,71,73-74, 76-77,83,97 conservative,7 construction,of knowledge,of reality, purposeof, 38 social, 37, 38 distortionsof, 37 constructivism,4-5,8, 14, 19,20, 147, 199 an overview of, 103-6, 12&-30, 155-7 and critical theory, 19 andDNS, 162-3 andemergentscience,190-1 and empirical research,20 and epistemology,19 and feminism, 125-46 and historical materialism,20 and InformationAge, 156-66 and liberal theory, 19 and post-positivism,129 andpost-structuralism,19 12&-9 INDEX constructivism(continued) andscience,and mathematics, 173-92 and theory of communicativeaction, 129 and third debate,19, 128 as manipulationof states,126 intellectualsourcesof, 19-20,25 "proto", 25 versionsof, 193 ofCarlsnaes,Walter 91-92 ofDessler,David, 8t'Hl8 offeminist, 126-46 ofWitworth, Sandra(Coxean), 126-7,ofSylvester, Christine(post-structural) 127-8 of Jabri, Vivienne and Chan, Stephen,93 ofOnuf, Nicholas,58-78 overviewsof, 80-84, 79-82 Seealso Onuf, Nicholas.See constructivism of post-movement,5, 52 of Wendt, Alexander,84-86, 88-89,90-91,102 Seealso Wendt, Alexander consumersof knowledge.See knowledge contradiction,dialectical.See dialectics,dialecticalrule control, legitimate,as authority, 76 conventionon homework, 141-3 conventions,66-67 convergence,152, 160 Council of Registrars(CORE), 161, 163 counterhegemony, 38 countriesas constructions.See societies Cowhey,Peter,154 Cox, R.W., 27, 33, 36, 37, 41, 48, 49, 54n.l and2, 126, 127 critical, 7, 20, 28, 48 approach,theory, 19,26,37,48,49, 52, 53, 54n.l sociology,37, 45 criticality, 187 205 culture,Western,195 of internationalsociety, 196-7 local, 197 cyberspace,153, 166 debatein IR, 200 on levels of analysis.Seelevels of analysis on agent-structure.Seeagent structureproblem Seealso debates,"great" deconstruction,4,8, 17,40, 125 deed,81, 155, 156 dependencytheory, 11,38 Der Derian, James,49 Derrida, Jacques,40, 125 Deschamps,Jean-Claude,107 Dessler,David, 8t'Hl8, 89 determinism economic,44 in agent-structure,80 Newtonian,178 development;unilinear,dynamic, multi causal,and multidirectional. Seedialectics,dialecticalrules dialectics,27, 29, 30-32, 37 as ontology, 31 Seealso ontology as epistemology,31 Seealso epistemology as method31 Seealso methodology dialectical interplay, 92 logic, 27 materialism,31 relation,29 rules, 30-32 synthesis,of agentand structure.See structurationtheory dialectical,radical, approach.See Alker H. and Biersteker,T. dialects,disciplinary 6 difference,93 digerati, 148, 150, 151, 165 Dirac, P.A.M., 182 directive-rules,67, 71, 158, 163.See rules 206 INDEX disciplines,disciplinaryboundaries,5, 200-1 discourse,7 distorted communication,theory of, 39 ideologies,39 social construction,38 DomainNameSystem(DNS) 102-3, 148 andconstructivism,162-3 domination,37 Doty, Roxanne,94 DNS. SeeDomainNameSystem Drucker, Peter,165 Dulles, JohnFostergood; 112, 114 Durkheim, Emile, 46 dynamic,30 economicdeterminist.See determinism Eden,Anthony, 110, 111, 112,1l3, 117 Egypt, 109-20 Eisenhowever,Dwight, 112 Elster, Jon, 89 emancipation,19,38,39,52 politics of, 128 emergentproperties,91 hierarchicalorganization,181 empirical,4 research,andconstructivism,20, 21 empiricism,84, 173 endogeneous. Seeendogeneous, exogeneousdichotomy Engels,F., 28, 31 English School,ofIR 4, 1 Enlightenment,8, 15 Enloe, Cynthia, 104, 125 entropy, 175, 176 epistemiccommunities,154 epistemology,12-21,89,93-94, 104 Ethernet,148-9 equilibrium, 10 Seealso Waltz ethics,ethical issuesin IR, l3 Eurocommunism,38 exogeneous,endogeneous dichotomy, 53, 154 facts, independentexistenceof, 38 falsificationism,46 feminism, 51, 125--46 main schoolsof, 125 humanist,127 post-structural,127---8 standpoint,127 foreign policy making, and IR discipline, 198 formality. Seerule, legal Foucault,Michel, 28, 36, 37,44,48, 125 France,110-20 Frankfurt School,28, 45, 54n.1 free will, in agent-structure,80 Freud,Sigmund,49 Friedman,Thomas,153 Froornkin,Michael, 159 functions. Seespeechacts fundamentalattribution error, 107, 110 Seealso attribution error Gadamer,Hans,39 Galtung,Johan,46, 104 Gates,Bill, 150, 157, 158 Gell-Mann, Murray, 182 gender as a constellationof rules, 130 as social construct,125, 129 in IR, 125 in political economy,4 genderedrules, 124 of home-basedwork, l30-1 GenericTop Level Domains Memorandumof Understanding (gTLD-MoU), 161, 163 Seealso Memorandumof Understanding(MoU) George,Alexander,195 George,Jim, 105 Giddens,Anthony, 46,52,80,81,85, 88,89,93,104,147,152,156 Gilder, George,148 Gingrich, Newt, 150 INDEX global, 6 capitalism,124 context,200 governance,neo-Gramscian approach,154 telecommunications,147 globalism,globalist, 11,38,41,44 Global InternetGovernance(GIG), 164 Glubb, JohnBogot "Pasha,"112 goals,60, 64--65, 71, 73, 77 Goedel' stheorem,183 "goldenstraitjacket,"153 Gorbachev,M.S., 38 Gore, AI, 161 government,60, 76 Gramsci,Antonio, 11,28,36,37,38, 45,48,126 "great" debatesin IR, 4, 13, 79 first. Seerealismand idealism second,(behaviouralistsvs systemicists),84 third, 20 and agent-structure debate,83 Grene,Marjorie, 180 Habermas,Jurgen,19,26,28,36,37, 39,48,52,54n.l, 129 Halliday, Fred, 49 Harding, Sandra,125 harmonyof interests,20 Seealso unintendedconsequences Hart, H.A.L., 45 Heath,Don, 161, 163, 164 Hegel, G.W. F., 30 HegelianMarxism, 44 hegemony different meaningsof, 10, 11 Gramscion, 37, 38 of Americanculture, 196 Seealso form of rule hegemonic,156 assertion,157 consensus,49 hegemony,156 Hempel,c., 46 Heraclitus,30 hermeneuticconcepts,in structuration theory. Seestructurationtheory 207 hermeneutics,18 heteronomy.Seeform of rule heteronomous,156 hierarchy.Seerule, conditionof, form of Hills, Jill, 153 historical bloc, 48 materialism,49 history, 30 Hitler, Adolph, 113, 115 Hobbes'sstateof nature,10 Hobsbawm,Erick, 44 Hoffmann, Stanley,40,195 holistic, 84 holistic. Seedialectics Holland, John, 182, 190 Hollis and Smith, 80, 86, 88,89-90, 91,92-93,96 Hollis, Martin. SeeHollis and Smith Holsti, K. J., 12,36 Holton, Gerald, 185 home-basedwork, 123-4 HomeNetInternational,136--8, 140 homeworkermovement,124 homeworkers,l23 Horkheimer,Max, 45, 54n.l household,rules of, 131-3 humanism,secular,197 Hume, David, 84 idealism,idealist, 26, 29,30, 31, 32 Seealso debates,"great," first; realism identity, 64, 152 and categorization,106 and cognitivepsychology,106 and exogeneous,endogeneous influences,90 and interests,collective,national, 101, 109 and language,105 as belonging,104 changing,124 defined,75 feministson, 104 formation on, 125 in neoliberaland neorealisttheories, 101-3 208 INDEX influenceon world politics, 197 national,4 of self and other, 105 of state,102, 108 political, 102 ideologies manipulationby in social construction,126 Seealso distorted imperialism, 11 cultural, 196 incompleteness theorem.SeeGoedel's theorem Seeagents, independence. independenceof indeterminacy,185-6 individual, as agent,83 individualism methodological83 ontological,80, 84, 89 and structuralism,85 information, 62, 66-fJ7 InformationaAge, 4, 153 Information Revolution, 153-5 Information Superhighway,165 "institutional tum," 97 institutionalizationof structure,62 institutions,61, 70-77, 82 defining features:status,office, types of, networks,organizations, associations,71-72 and rules 83 changesthroughchangesof rules, 143 instruction-rules,67, 71, 158, 162 integrationtheory, 102 intellectual intentions.Seeconsequences interconnected.Seedialectics, dialecticalrules interdependence, interdependent,40 interests,64, 71, 77 andconstructivism,103-9 and psychology,103-9 exogeneousorendogeneous,102 formation of, 101 structuralconstraintsand incentives, 103 InternationalAd Roc Committee (IARC),161 internationalinequality, 11 InternationalLabor Organization(lLO), 123, 133, 136, 137, 138, 141-3 internationallaw, sourcesof, 71 InternationalPolitical Economy,33 internationalrelations, and constructivism,58-59, 62, 70, 77 InternationalRelations(lR), 156, 163 American, 196, 199 and mathematics,173-92 and science,173-92 Anglo-American,196 approachesto, 11 as a discipline, 3, 5, 36 as a social science,10 evolution of, 9 hierarchical,156 knowledgein, 34 state-centric,9, 196 teachingof, 21, 199 uniquenessof subject-matter,9 Seealso disciplines,academic internationalsociety, 197. Seesociety, international InternationalStudiesAssociation,18 InternationalTelecommunication Union (lTU), 148, 161 InternationalTelephoneandTelegraph ConsultativeCommittee (CCITT),154 InternetAssigned Authority (lANA), 161, 165, 166 InternetEngineeringTaskForce, 166 InternetProtocol, 149, 165, 166 InternetServiceProviders(lSPs), 160 InternetSociety(ISOC), 161, 164, 166 Internet, 147-fJ6 interparadigmatic,36 interpretative,interpretivist, 18 interpretivism,93, 94, 102 Islam, in InternationalRelations, 197-8 Israel, 109, III Jabri, Vivienne, 90, 93 James,William, 156, 157 INDEX Jones,Charles,27 Kant, Immanuel,7 Keohane,R.O., 18,40,41 andNye, J., 18,40 Kirkpatrick,Ivone, 115, 116 knowledge academicandpolicy relevant,195 creationof, 34 cumulative,8 productionanddissemination,3, 6, 83 progressiveaccumulationof, 84 purposeof, 33, 34 uncertain,36 knowledgeconstitutiveinterests,37 Kolko, Gabriel, 44 Korbin, Stephen,159 Korsch, Karl, 28 Kowack, Glenn, 165 Kratochwil, Friedrich, 7, 18, 104 Kratochwil F. and Ruggie,J., 41 Krippendorf, E., 46 Kuhn Thomas,35, 36 Lakatos,Imre, 46 Landauer,Thomas,151, 152 language,4,8,17, 19,39,81 imperfectionsand inadequacies,46 manipulationof, 105 by peopleand nations, 105 of modernity, 197 scholarly,3-4 Seealso rules Lanier, Jaron,149 Lapid, Y osef, 19 26,41, 105 Laplace,Pierre-Simon,85 Left, 11,35 and Right, 33 leftist, 7 Lenin, V.I., 28, 29,30, 48, 49 levels of analysis,9, 79, 84, 95-96 and agentstructureproblem,88-89 andMGP,109 as imputeddemarcations,95 attributesof, propertiesof, definition by rules, 96 209 Levi-Strauss,Claude,6 liberal institutionalism,10 liberal, liberalism, 9, 20, 30 linear, 30 linguistic philosophy,45 linguistic tum, 17, 18, 19,6 emancipatorynatureof, 105 in IR, 105 Linklater, Andrew, 27, 28,33, 49 Lloyd, Selwyn, 112 logical empiricism,32, 46 logical positivism, 32, 46 logoentrism,127 Lucky Break, 112, 113 Lukacs,Georg,28 MacLellan, David, 44 Macmillan, Harold, 115 Maher,David, 162 manand nature,separationof, 33 Mandel, Ernst,44 manipulation,38 of minds,of states,126 Seealso ideologies;distorted Marcuse,Herbert,45 market,62, 72, 76--77 Marx, Karl, 28, 29, 31, 37,41, 48, 52 Marxism, 7, 11,30 Continental28, 29, 38 European,11 Hegelian,44, 49 Western28 non-determinist,44 and feminism, 1-24, 125 Marxism-Leninism,Soviet,28, 29 materialcircumstances,60, 64,69 material resources,59, 64 mathematics,7 in InternationalRelations,173-92 McCaw, Craig, 150 McLean, John,48 mechanics,quantum,185 Memorandumof Understanding (MoU), 161, 163, 165, 166 Mercer, Jonathan,108 Merlau-Ponty,Maurice,28 metaphysics,8, 13 210 INDEX Metcalfe'sLaw, 148-9, 157, 158, 160, 165 meteorology,7 methodology,13,89,94 methods,of naturalsciences,84 Seealso debates,great,second Microsoft, 150, 158 minimal group paradigm(MGP), 106, 108-9 models,174-78 clockwork, 179 probabilistic, 178 stochastic,178 typesof, 177 modeling formal, 177 in InternationalRelations, 178-9 modernism,155 modernity,40 languageof, 197 logocentrismof, 127 monocausal,30 Morgenthau,Hans,26, 40, 48 morphogenesis and structuration, 91-92 MoU. SeeMemorandumof Understanding(MoU) multi causal,30 Murphy, Craig, 154 Mussolini, Benito, 113 Nasser,GamalAbdel, 109, 110 nationalidentity. Seeidentity National ScienceFoundation,160 nationalinterest,9 naturalism,8 natureand society,unity of, 20 Seealso global, governance, neo-Gramscianapproach, 154 neoliberalism,101 neorealism,34, 48, 52, 101 Seealso structuralrealism Netizens,157 network externalities,149 Network Solutions,Inc. (NSI), 152, 153,160 networksof rules,as institutions,71-72 Neufeld, Mark, 105 "new thinking," 38 New World InformationOrder', 158 Nexus, 152 Nicolis, Gregoire, 181 Nietzsche,Friedrich,44 non-deterministic Marxism, 44 Seealso Marxism nonlinearity, 184 norm, normative.Seerules normative,19 normsas context, 129 norms,study of, 129 notice of inquiry, (NOI), 162 Nutting, Anthony, 118 Nye, Josephand William Owens,153 objectivity, 34, 39, 46, 52 observer,subjectiverole of, in physicalsciences,186 offices, 72-76 Oilman, Bertell, 30 ontological individualism, 80 structuralism,80 ontology, 13-19,20,89,94,104 positional,87 transformational,87 Onuf, Nicholas,G., 4,19-21,42-43, 52-53,79,88,95-97,104-6, 147-49,156,173 Seealso constructivism,versionsof Oppendahl,Carl, 162 oppression37, 38 organizations,as institutions,71-72 other,the, 7 others,127 outside- inside, 196, 198 paradigm,35, 36 the usein IR, 35 paradigmatic discipline, 36 parochialism,48 Seealso Alker and Biersteker parochialism,40 paradigmatic,48 INDEX participants.Seeagents partsand wholes.Seelevel of analysis patterns,of rules, practices, institutions,61-64, 67, 73-75, 81 Peirce,Charles,156 Penrose,Roger, 180 perception,III Seealso cognitivepsychology perestroika,105 perspectivism,19 Seealso Lapid, Y osef Peterson,Spike, Y., 104, 125 Pettman,Jan,Jindy, 125 philosophy,separationfrom science,8 physics,7 Pickering,Charles,161, 163-64 Planck,Max, 182 pluralism,methodological,19 pluralist, 11,41 policy makers,195, 198 Policy OversightCommittee(POC), 161, 162, 165 policy relevance,33 policy relevantknowledge,195 political economy,separationinto economicsand political science,8 political identity. Seeidentity politics of emancipation,128 politics, emancipatory,critical, 4 Popper,Karl, 46 positive sumgame,International Relationsas, 101 positivism, 4, 7, 8, 33, 34, 36, 37,45, 81,84,95,155, 195 science,4, 16, 17 Postel,Jon, 161 "post" movement,11, 17, 18, 19,20, 25,27,28,29,33,34,35,37,41, 52, 154, 159 and science,173 post-Marxist,45, 49 post-modem,4, 5,19,2039,49,155, 158 skepticism,127 post-positivism,173 post-positivistandpositivist, 19 Seealso third debate post-Soviet,5 211 post-structural,19,44,45,48 feminist, 127-8 Poulantzas,Nicos, 45 powerover opinion, 33, 36, 37, 38, 39, 52 power, 125, 143 power-knowledge,39 power-relations,39 powers,67, 76 practice,7, 31 Seealso theory and practice.See rules, institutions pragmatism,93, 157 praxis, 7 Prigogine,Iiya, 176 principle, 67, 70, 73, 76 probability, 186 problem-solving,7 problematique,7,45,54n.2 productivity, 151 project, 7 promises,67-68 properties,emergent,179-80 Public Advisory Board(pAB), 161, 162 public good, 101 public goodstheory, 149 purpose,39 purposes.Seegoals quannuntheory,182 radical dialecticalapproach.SeeAlker andBiersteker raisond'etat,9 rational choicetheory, 11 rational conduct,60-61, 65, 69, 74 rationalistepistemologicaltradition, 84 rationalist,20. Seereflective and rationalist realismin IR, 5, 7, 8, 9, 11,25,36,37, 29,30,31,32,36,41 and idealism,29, 30, 31, 53-54 in philosophy,7 pluralist, globalist,41 scientific, 7 structural,10 reality,34 212 INDEX Realpolitk, 9 reason.SeeEnlightenment Reagan-Thatcher era, 153-54 reciprocalcausalities.Seedialectics recursive,175 reductionism,in IR, 83 reflectiveandrationalistapproaches,18 regimes,70, 102, 154 regulatoryarbitrage,159 religions, ofthe world, 197-8 and IR studies,198 resources,64, 72-73,154,162,163 control over, 74-75 revolution, 29, 37 Bolshevik,37 rhetoric, 17 Richardson.L.F., 9 right-wing, 7 rights andduties,68-72 role, 72, 76 root serverconfederations(RSCs) 162 Rosenau,James,N., 36 Ruelle,David, 185 Ruggie,John, 18 rule, 20, stablepatternof relations,62-63 condition of, anarchy,77 form of, 156 hegemony,hierarchy,heteronomy, 62-63, 75--77 rules, 19,20,80,83,129 andactivism, 130 and resources.SeeDessler,David as heuristictool, 129 as materialproperty(Onu!), 81 as propertyof structure(Giddens),81 as support,72 at the nexusof biology, psychology and sociology, 104 categoriesof, instruction,directive, commitment,67-68, 70-73,129, 104-6 codifying, 124 commitment-rules WOlX, 142 changingandhome-based constitutiveand regulative,68-69, 81,87, 129 definition, 59-60,66-67 directive-rules, changingand home-basedwork, 140-2 division of private and public spheres,133 families of, 6~70 instruction-rules, changingand home-basedwork, 13~0 legal, 69, 75--76 making,following, breaking,69, 74-75 of academicdisciplines,194 of household,131-3 oflabor market, 135-6 of state,133-5 of Westernculture, 194 ontologicalstatus,82 Seealso institutions uniformity acrossthe world, 197 Runyan,Anne, S., 125 Russia,37, 38 science,16 credibility of, 10 emergent,179-84 in InternationalRelations,173-92 natural,physical,8, 33, 83-84 social, 4, 8, 20, 204 philosophyof, 21 separationfrom philosophy,8 scientific realism,81-82,83, 85, 87,94 Scott, Joan,125 Self-EmployedWomen'sAssociation (SEWA), 123, 137, 138, 140, 142 self-organization,181-2 Seeidentity self-consciousness. Sherif, Muzafer, 106 Shuckburgh,Evelyn, 111, 112 simulation, 178 Singer,David, 12,79,84 Smith, Adam, 162 Smith, Steve.SeeHollis and Smith social arrangements,58, 63, 73 Seealso structure social beings,59 social constructions, as manipulation,126 INDEX 213 social constructions,(continued) structure(continued) Seealso constructions dissipative,176 social identity theory(SIT) functionsof, 82 and stereotyping,108 in Waltz, 84 intersubjective,in identity formation, social movement,124, 151 103 and changeof rules, 130 of society,82 social,relations,59 phenomenalpropertiesof, 82, 83 theory, 19,52 world,59 Seealso social arrangements; societies,59, 73-76 institutions subject-object,33 society SuezCrisis, 109--18 international,59, 69, 74-75 surveillance,social, 152 distinctivecharacter.Seestructure sociology,8, 30 Sweezy,Paul, 44 Sylvester,Christine, 104-5, 125, historical,49 127-8 sovereignty,9, 62, 67, 69, 73, 159, symbolic interactionism,93 164, 166 synthesis.Seedialectics,dialecticalrules SovietUnion 28, 37, 109, system,systems,174--8 110, 197 complex, 184 and 'new thinking', 105 conservative.Seenonentropic speechacts, 81, 156 cybernetic,175 functions,68-69 discreteand continuous,175 typesof, assertive,directive, dissipative,176 commissive,66 entropicand non entropic, 176 spheresof influence,as institutions, 70-71 linear and nonlinear,176 standards,154, 155, 159,166 openandclose, 175 static, dynamic, 175 standards-making process,147 time dependence,175 stateidentity. Seeidentity systemicists,84 state,62, 72-73,76, 150, 151, 153,154, 156, 165 as agent,83 Tajfel, Henri, 106 positionaldefinition, 86 taxonomy,175 statecraft,9 TCP/IP, 149, 151 technology,150, 153, 154 status,71 Stienstra,Deborah,126 telecommunications,147, 148, 151, Strange,Susan,153 152, 154, 160, 165 structural Teledesicventure,149--50 liberalism, 10 temporalprocess.SeeCarlsnaes, Marxism, 6, 35 Walter realism,5, 10,34,35,41,48,52,83,88 text, 17,39 structuralisttheoriesof linguistics,44 theories,purposeof, 39 structuration,46, 80 theoryandpractice,31, 33 theory of, 80, 83, 89 third debate,19 Seealso debates,great structure,5 and constructivism,128 definition, 62--63, 82 Thompson,E.P., 35 determinismof, 80, 82, 88 Seealso Wendt,Alexander Thucydides,36 214 INDEX Tickner, A., 104-5 time and space,40 spatialand temporalstructures,86 Seealso structuration transactioncosts,102 transfonnationalontology.See ontology treaties,as institutions,70-71 Trevor-Roper,Hugh, 26 Trotsky, Leon, 28. SeeMarxism, Western trotskyist, tradition, 44 Tucker, Robert,41 turbulence,7, 186 Turner,John, 106 uncertainty,182-4 unilinear. Seelinear United States,109, Ill, 117 unity of natureand society,20 university, university professors,195 unobservablephenomena,81, 85 Seealso scientific realism utopianism.Seeidealism value-freenatureof knowledge,52 Vico Giambattista,156 Vienna Circle, 45 Vietnam, 11 virtual reality, 149 voluntarism.Seedetenninism Von Neumann,John, 189 Walker, R.B.J.,49 Wallerstein,Immanuel,44,84-85 Waltz, Kenneth,7,10,34,35,41,83, 84,85,87,90 war, studyof, 9 web lifestyle, 152, 157 Weber,Max, 44,45,46 Weinberg,Steven,180 Wendt, Alexander,79, 82, 84-86, 88-89,9~91, 90-91 101, 150 on agent-structure,82, 84, 85 on stateidentity, 102 WesternMarxism. SeeMarxism Westphaliansystem,164 Whitworth, Sandra,126 wholesand parts.Seelevels of analysis Williams, W. A., 44 Winch, Peter,46 Wittgenstein,Ludwig, 44 World IntellectualProperty Organization(WIPO), 161 world social,physical,differencebetween, 16 making of, 59 material,64 social, cleavageinto selfand other, 106 World systemstheory, 11,83,84 World Wide Web, 149