* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Theoretical foundation of Educational Administration and Policy
Political economy in anthropology wikipedia , lookup
Unilineal evolution wikipedia , lookup
Social theory wikipedia , lookup
Political philosophy wikipedia , lookup
Social contract wikipedia , lookup
Philosophy of history wikipedia , lookup
History of the social sciences wikipedia , lookup
Neohumanism wikipedia , lookup
Sociological theory wikipedia , lookup
Other (philosophy) wikipedia , lookup
Public choice wikipedia , lookup
Community development wikipedia , lookup
Postdevelopment theory wikipedia , lookup
Development theory wikipedia , lookup
East China Normal University Department of Educational Management Workshop on Practical Foundations of Educational Management & Educational Governance Lecture 7 and 8 Public Reason: The Practical Foundation of Educational Management to Governance (III) A. The Possibility of Social Choice: From Rationality to Public Reason 1. Amartya Sen, the Nobel laureate in economics in 1998, in his Nobel Prize Lecture entitled The Possibility of Social Choice, defines social choice as “the choice ‘of the people, by the people, for the people’.” (Sen, 2002, P. 66) 2. The impossibility of social choice: The conventional view in economics about social choice has been dominated by the Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Kenneth Arrow, another Nobel Laureate in economics in 1972, indicates that it is practically impossible to arrive at a unanimous consensus on social-preference ordering among a human aggregate in rational, autonomous and democratic fashion. (Arrow, 1950) Therefore, he stipulates that “If we exclude the possibility of interpersonal comparisons of utility, then the only methods of passing from individual tastes to social preferences which will be defined for a wide range of sets of individual orderings are either imposed or dictatorial.” (1950, P. 342) 3. The possibility of social choice: In his Nobel Prize Lecture, Sen reviews his career-long stance of taking issue with the Arrow impossible theorem. That is, he asserts that social choice is possible. He defines his enquiry of social choice in three related questions (Sen, 2002, P. 66) a. “How can it be possible to arrive at cogent aggregative judgments about the society (for example, about ‘social welfare,’ or ‘the public interest,’ or aggregate poverty’), given the diversity of preferences, concerns, and predicaments of the different individuals within the society?” b. “How can we find any rational basis for making such aggregative judgment as ‘the society prefers this to that,’ or ‘the society should choose this over that,’ or ‘this is socially right’? c. “Is reasonable social choice at all possible, especially since…there are ‘as many preferences as there are people’?” B. Distinction between Rational and Reasonable Persons 1. John Rawls’s distinction between reasonable persons and rational persons a. “Persons are reasonable in one basic aspect when, among equals say, they are ready to propose principles and standards as fair terms of cooperation and to abide by them willingly, given the assurance that others will likewise do so. ….The reasonable is an element of the idea of society as a system of fair cooperation and that its fair terms be reasonable for all to accept is part of its idea of reciprocity.” (1993, 49-50) b. “The rational is, however, a distinct idea from the reasonable and applied to a single, unified agent (either an individual or corporate person) with the powers of judgment and deliberation in seeking ends and interests peculiarly its own. The ration applies to how these ends and interests are adopted and affirmed, as well as to how they are given priority. It also applies to the choice of means, 1 1 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance in which case it is guided by such familiar principles as: to adopt the most effective means to ends, or to select the most probable alternative, other things equal.” (1993, p. 50) More specifically, “what rational agents lack is the particular form of moral sensibility that underlies the desire to engage in fair cooperation. …Rational agents approach being psychopathic when their interests are solely in benefits to themselves.” (1993, p. 51) As in everyday speech, we may characterize rational agents that “their proposal was perfectly rational given their strong bargaining position, but it was nevertheless highly unreasonable.” (1993, 48) c. In light of Rawls’ distinction, practical reason can then be construed as reasons that reasoning agents attributed to their actions. It goes beyond the principle of t rationality and means-end calculation. It conforms to the principle of reciprocity and fairness, which members of a given community mutually accepted. Accordingly, practical reason can be defined as human capacity to attribute their actions to i. The principle of rationality, ii. The principle of reciprocity, and/or even iii. The principle of fairness 2. Amartya Sen’s distinction between rationality and reason a. From economics point of view, Amartya Sen has made a more specific distinction between the rational person and reasonable persons. He underlines that in mainstream economics, rational persons is “characterized by intelligent pursuit of self-interest”. More specifically, “it has … been assumed that they must also be the detached from others, so that they are completely unaffected by the well-being or achievement of others.” (Sen, 2009, P. 188) b. In his article entitled “Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory”, (1977) he stipulates that human can make choice and action not in accordance with the self-interest pursuant rationality. He suggests that human may choice and act on the bases of “sympathy” or “commitment”. i. By sympathy, It “refers to one person’s welfare being affected by the position of others’ (for example, a person can feel depressed at the sight of misery of others)” (Sen, 2009, P. 188) ii. By commitment, it is “concerned with breaking the tight link between individual welfare and the choice of action”. That is doing what can be done to remove the misery of others without considering one’s own welfare, …”that is a clear departure from self-interest behavious.” (Sen, 2009, P. 188-89) c. Furthermore, Sen underlines that “Adam Smith, the father of modern economics…is often wrongly thought to be a proponent of the assumption of the exclusive pursuit of self-interest, in the form of the so-called ‘economic man’.” (Sen, 2009, P. 185) Sen points out that it is only in explaining “the motivation for economic exchange in the market” that Smith underscored human’s predisposition of self-interest pursuit. In fact, Smith has distinguished clearly reasons other than egoistic self-interest pursuit in explaining human’s choice and action, for example, sympathy, generosity and public spirit. (Sen, 2009, P. 185) d. In contrast to narrow-minded self-interest pursuant rationality, Sen agrees with Rawls that humans are capable of reasoning in wider context and with variety 2 2 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance of criteria (not confine to egoistic self-interest), to scrutinize one’s thoughts and action as objectively and impartially as possible, and ready to submit one’s erroneous decision or act to stronger evidence and/or better arguments. In his own words, he characterizes “reasonable persons as “capable of being reasonable through being open-minded about welcoming information and through reflecting on argument coming from different quarters, along with undertaking interactive deliberations and debates on how the underlying issues should be seen.” (Sen, 2009, P. 43) 3. Elinor Ostrom, Nobel Laureate in economics in 2009, also examines the behavioral base of rational choice and collective action from a different methodological and theoretical perspective. a. In her presidential address, American Political Science Association, 1997, entitled “A Behavioral Approach to the Rational Choice Theory of Collective Action’” (2014/1997), Ostrom presents her evidences accumulated from decades of laboratory experiments on game theory. And to up with the conclusion that in social dilemmas, such as the prisoners’ dilemma, reasonable persons may find the solution to escape from the loss-loss situation and arrive at mutual beneficial solution. b. Ostrom categorizes her theory as the second-generation models of rationality: i. She indicates that in the first-generation model of rational choice, theorists simply accept as given the fact that “individual are boundedly rational, they do not calculate a complete set of strategies for every situation they face.” It is because they cannot have obtained complete information on all potential actions, all outcomes, and all strategies of their partners. (Strom, 2014, P. 136) ii. Learnt heuristics: Ostrom underlines that “in field situations (such as laboratory experiments), individuals tend to use heuristics─rules of thumb ─that they have learned over time regarding responses that tend to give them good outcomes in particular kinds of situation.” (Ostrom, 2014, P. 136) In short, individuals will reason out and “learn heuristics that approach best-response strategies.” (P. 137) iii. Internalized norms: Furthermore, these learnt instrumental heuristics may sediment into norms and values in repeated situations over time. Ostrom suggests that “by norm I mean that the individual attaches an internal valuation─positive or negative─to taking particular types of action.” (Ostrom, 2014, P. 137) Within a particular societal and physical milieu, a set of prominent norms and values will sediment into culture and they will be socialized and internalized from generations to generations. iv. Institutionalized rules: “By rule I mean that a group of individuals has developed shared understandings that certain actions in particular situations must , must not, or may be undertaken and that sanction will be taken against those who do not conform.” (P. 137) As a result, strategic situations of social dilemma will be institutionalized into typified course of actions and routines, which expected outcomes can be taken granted. v. Reciprocity: With refers to human’s capability to learn heuristics, to internalize norms and to institutionalize rules, human beings can maintain a state of reciprocity with their fellow humans. By reciprocity, Ostrom refers to “a family of strategies that can be used in social dilemmasinvolving (1) an effort to identify who else is involved, (2) an assessment of the 3 3 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance likelihood that others are conditional cooperators, (3) a decision to cooperate initially with others if others are trusted to be conditional cooperators, (4) a refusal to cooperate with those who do not reciprocate, and punishment of those who betray trust.” (Ostrom, 2014, P. 138) Taken together, Ostrom has built a model of core relationship in collective action as follow (Source: Ostrom, 2014, P.144) To incorporate some of the exogenous variables into the core-relationship model, the model can be elaborated as follows (Source: Ostrom, 2014, P. 148) 4 4 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance C. Substantive Theories of Practical Reason and Public Reason 1. In the previous section we have explicated some main theses explaining “how” social choice of preferences and rational choice of collective action are possible. In this section, we will explicate the substantive choices and actions actually taken by human aggregate or societies. That is to review some prominent theses which attempt to vindicate what should be the preferable, desirable, morally right and/or political legitimate “choices” that a society should choose in a particular public-policy domain. 2. Levels of evaluation: The substantive contents of social choice, especially choice among different value stances i.e. evaluation, may be differentiated into three levels of evaluation. Ronal Dworkin has made a distinction between three levels of value. He suggests that “ethnics studies how people best manage their responsibility to live well, and personal morality what each as an individual owes other people. Political morality, in contrast, studies what we all together owe others as individuals when we act in and on behalf of that artificial collective person.” (Dworkin, 2011, Pp. 327-8) Accordingly, evaluation may be categorized into a. Ethical evaluation: It refers to desirable traits and features attributed to human behaviors, actions, and conducts at individual level. It concerns questions such as, What is a righteous character? What is a virtuous person? What is the worth in life? What is an ethical conduct? … b. Moral evaluation: It refers to desirable traits and features attributed to human interactions and relationships among fellows humans. It concerns questions such as, What is a fair deal? What is worth in friendship? What is good husband and/or wife? What is good teacher and/or student? c. Political values: It refers to the ethical and moral values taken by a given society as of prominent importance that they should be imposed onto all members of that society coercively. Accordingly, discourse of political value entails the legitimacy of a public authority (the modern state) in substantiating those prominent values onto the civil society which falls under its sovereignty. More specifically, it relates to sound and legitimate public policies in various public domains, such as education, social welfare, health care, etc. 2. In the field of moral and political philosophy, there are varieties of perspectives trying to vindicate the substantive content of “good” at individual ethnical level, social moral level, and public political level. For examples, a. Emotivism or libertarianism b. Consequentialism or utilitarianism c. Deontological perspective d. Perspective of virtue ethics d. Perspective of historical institutionalism e. Perspective of realization-focused comparison D. John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice 1. The backgrounds and significance of Rawls’ theory of justice: a. John Rawls’s book A Theory of Justice has been characterized as a deontological perspective of practical reasoning. More specifically, his formulations have been categorized as a Kantian approach to the question of what is good society. b. Kant’s concept of categorical imperative i. Kant stipulates that in a course of action, “I ought never to act except in such a way that I could also will that my maxim should become a universal law.” 5 5 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance (Kant, 1996, p. 57) ii. ‘Universal’ here means “an action is morally permissible if you would be willing to have everyone act as you are proposing to act. An action is morally wrong if you are not willing to have everyone act as you are proposing to act.” (Rogerson, 1991, p. 108) c. G.A. Cohen, one of the outright critics of Rawls’ theory of justice, underlines that “The publication of John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice in 1971 was a watershed. …Before A Theory of Justice appeared, political philosophy was dominant by utilitarianism, the theory that sound social policy aims at the maximization of welfare. Rawls found two features of utilitarianism repugnant. He objected, first, to its aggregative character, its unconcern about the pattern of distribution of welfare, which means that inequality in its distribution calls for no justification. But, more pertinently… Rawls also objected to the utilitarian assumption that welfare is the aspect of a person’s condition which commands normative attention. He recommended normative evaluation with new arguments (goods instead of welfare quanta) and new function (equality instead of aggregation) from those arguments to values.” (Cohen, 2011, P. 44; see also, Cohen, 2008, Pp. 11-14) 2. Conception of Justice as Fairness : John Rawls formulate his theory of justice from the idea of “Justice as Fairness”, which was published in the form of a journal article in Philosophical Review, vol. 64, no. 1, Pp. 164-194 in 1958. He wrote in the paper that a. “It might seem at the first sight that the concepts of justice and fairness are the same, and that there is no reason to distinguish them, or to say that one is fundamental than the other. I think that this impression is mistaken. In this paper I wish to show that fundamental idea in the concept of justice is fairness; and I wish to offer an analysis of the concept of justice from this point of view.” (Rawls, 1999[1958], p. 42) b. The meaning of fairness: “Fundamental to justice is the concept of fairness which relates to right dealing between persons who are cooperating with or competing against one another, as when one speak of fair games, fair competition, and fair bargains. The question of fairness arises when free persons, who have no authority over one another, are engaging in a joint activity and among themselves settling or acknowledging the rules which define it and which determine the respective shares in its benefits and burdens. A practice will strike the parties as fair if none feels that, by participating in it, they or any of the others are taken advantage of, or forced to give in to claims which they do not regard as legitimate. This implies that each has a conception of legitimate claims which he thinks it reasonable for others as well as himself to acknowledge. …A practice is just or fair, then, when it satisfies the principles which those who participate in it could propose to one another for mutual acceptance under aforementioned circumstances.” (Rawls, 1999[1958], p. 59) 3. The idea of original position a. In reality, most of the situations in which humans enter into cooperation or competition are not in fair terms. That is they are not in equal footings when engage in a bargain and one of the parties may has an upper hand over their partners. The worst scenario the parties found themselves in a situation where they have to strike a balance not in the most favorable terms of both parties. In other words, “the best that each can do for himself may be a condition of lesser justice rather than of greater good. …It is at this point that the conception of the 6 6 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance original position embodies features peculiar to moral theory.” (Rawls, 1971, p. 120) b. Accordingly, the conception of original position is a conceptual device initiated by Rawls to “insure that fundamental agreement reach in it are fair” and yield the name of “justice as fairness”. (Rawls, p. 17) “The original position is defined in such a way that it is a status quo in which agreements reach are fair. It is a state of affairs in which the partners are equally represented as moral persons and the outcome is not conditioned by arbitrary contingencies or the relative balances of social forces. Thus justice as fairness is able to use the idea of pure procedural justice from the beginning.” (Rawls, 1971, p. 120) 4. The conception of the veil of ignorance a. “The idea of the original position is to set up a fair procedure so that any principles agreed to will be just. The aim is to use the notion of pure procedural justice as a basis of theory. Somehow we must nullify the effects of specific contingencies which put men at odd and tempt them to exploit social and natural circumstances to their own advantage. Now in order to do this I assume that the parties are situated behind a veil of ignorance.” (Rawls, 1971, p. 136) b. “It is assumed, then, that the parties do not know certain kinds of particular facts. i. First of all, no one knows his place in society, his class position or social status; nor does he know his fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence and strength, and the like. Nor, again, does anyone know his conception of the good, the particulars of his rational plan of life, or even the special features of his psychology such as aversion to risk or liability to optimism or pessimism. ii. More than this, I assume that the parties do not know the particular circumstances of their own society. That is, they do not know its economic or political situation, or the level of civilization and culture it has been able to achieve. The persons in the original position have no information as to which generation they belong.” (Rawls 1971, p. 137) 5. Two Principles of Justice: Based on the idea of justice as fairness, Rawls stipulates right at the beginning of his book A Theory of Justice that “justice is the first virtue of social institution” (P.3) and “the primacy of justice” over other social values. Hence, he assets that the basic structure of a just society is to be constituted in accordance with “the two principles of justice”. a. “First Principle: Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with similar system of liberty for all. b. “Second Principle: Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both i. to the greatest benefits of the least advantaged, …and ii. attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunities.” (Rawls, 1971, p. 302) 6. Applications of the principles: “These principles primarily apply …to the basic structure of society. They are to govern the assignment of rights and duties and to regulate the distribution of social and economic advantages….These principles presuppose that the social structure can be divided into two more or less distinct parts.” (Rawls, 1871, p. 61), a. The First Principle applies to those distinct “aspects of the social system that 7 7 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance define and secure the equal liberties of citizenship. …The basic liberties of citizens are, roughly speaking, political liberty (rihght to vote and to be eligible for public office) together with freedom of speech and assembly; liberty of conscience and freedom of thought; freedom of person along with right to hold (personal) property; freedom from arbitrary arrest and seizure as defined by the concept of the rule of law. These liberties are all required to be equal…, since citizens of just society are to have the same basic rights.” (p.61) b. The Second Principle applies to those aspects of social system “that specify and establish social and economic inequalities.” More specifically, it “applies…to the distribution of income and wealth and to the design of organizations that make use of differences in authority and responsibility, or chains of command.” (p. 61) 7. Interpretation of the second principle a. Rawls qualifies that the two constituent phrases in the Second Principle, namely to “everyone’s advantage” and “equally open to all” need further interpretation. b. Rawls interprets the two phrases as follows (Rawls, 1971, p. 65) “Everyone’s advantage” “Equally open” Principle of efficiency Difference principle Equality as careers open to talent System of Natural Liberty Natural Aristocracy Equality as equality of fair opportunity Liberty Equality Democratic Equality 8. Priority and lexical orders between principles of justice a. The priority of liberty: The First Principle, namely the principle of liberty) has lexical priority over the Second Principle: This ordering means that a departure from the institutions of equal liberty require by the first principle cannot be justified by, or compensated for, by greater social and economic advantages.” (p. 61) b. The priority of democratic equality over the other three systems, in other words, the priority of difference principle and equality as equality of fair opportunity over principle of efficiency and equality as careers open to talent. E. Criticism on Rawls’ A Theory of Justice Since its publication in 1971, John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice has received numerous criticisms. These criticisms and discussions have waged on for more than forty years. As a result, the idea of justice or more general the field of practical reason and public reason have been proliferated substantially, both in terms of theory and method. These criticisms and discussions will be sketchily explored in three aspects: 1. Criticism on the original position and its deontological-liberal stance 2. Criticism on its transcendental-institutional approach 3. Criticism on the materials of justice: Equality of what? F. Criticism on the original position and its deontological-liberal stance 8 8 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance 1. Critiques on the liberal assumptions underlying Rawls’ concept of original position theory of justice ((Mulhall and Swift, 1996, P. 1-33) a. The misconception of the conception of person qua person: In Rawls’ original position a person is but a chooser of no conception of ends and good of life; of no identity, lived experiences and lifeworld; and of no origins, history and tradition. b. Misconception of asocial individualism: In Rawls’ original position, person but a chooser located in a game situation, in which she is totally independent of any social affiliations, social roles, social responsibilities, social identity, and conceptions of common goods. c. Misconception of ahistorical universalism: The decision emerged from the original position, i.e. principles of justice, is assumed to be universally applicable across human cultures and social institutions. d. Misconception of aempirical subjectivism: The decision arrived at by rational choosers in original position is assumed be based purely on their subjective preferences, totally in disregard of the empirical grounds, in which this decisions are supposed to unfold and to be implemented. 2. Michael Sandel’s Critique on Rawls’ Deontological Liberalism a. Michael Sandel published a book entitled Liberalism and the Limits of Justice in 1982. The book is a direct critique on Rawls’ work A Theory of Justice. The focus of Sandel’s critique is on Rawls’ building his theory of justice on the assumption which Sandel characterizes as deontological liberalism. b. By deontological liberalism, according to Sandel’s interpretation, it refers to Rawls’ stance of assigning liberalism such a deontological and prominent status that it becomes the Categorical Imperative of all ethical concerns. This can be evident in the following three theses stipulated by Rawls. c. Priority of justice: “Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of system of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be rejected or revised if it is untrue; likewise laws and institutions no matter how efficient and well-arranged must be reformed or abolished if they are unjust. …Being first virtue of human actives, truth and justice are uncompromising.” (Rawls, 1971, Pp. 3-4) d. Right prior to good: i. “We should therefore reverse the relation between the right and the good proposed by the teleological doctrines and view the right as prior.” (Rawls, 1971, p. 560) ii. Two capacities of moral personality: “Moral personality is characterized by two capacities: one for a conception of the good, the other for a sense of justice. When realized, the first is expressed by a rational plan of life, the second by a regulative desire to act upon certain principle of right. Thus a moral person is a subject with ends he has chosen, and his fundamental preference is for conditions that enable him to frame a mode of life that expresses his nature as a free and equal rational being as fully as circumstances permit. Now the unity of the person is manifest in the coherent of his plan, this unity being founded in the higher order desire to follow, in ways consistent with his sense of right and justice, the principles of rational choice. (P. 561) iii. Inability to settle pluralism in conceptions of good: As each moral person is to make his rational plans of life separately, a plurality of life plans and conceptions of good is bound to emerge. To Rawls, 9 9 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance it is practically impossible as well as undesirable to impose a dominant conception of good (dominant-end) on a group of free-willing agents. iv. As a result, the common aim of moral persons “in the original position is to establish just and favorable conditions for each to fashion his own unity. Their fundamental interest in liberty and in the means to make fair use of it is the expression of their seeing themselves as primarily moral persons with an equal right to choose their mode of life. Thus they acknowledge the two principles of justice to be ranked in serial order as circumstances permit. …The main idea is that given the priority of right, the choice of our conception of the good is framed within definite limits. The principles of justice and their realization in social forms define the bounds within which our deliberations take place.” (P. 563) e. The priority of individual autonomy: i. Immanuel Kant’s conception of autonomy “Everything in nature works in accordance with laws. Only a rational being has the power to act in accordance with his ideas of laws ― that is, in accordance with principles ― and only so has he a will. Since reason is required in order to derive actions from laws, the will is nothing but practical reason. If reason infallibly determines the will, then in a being of this kind the actions which are recognized to be objectively necessary are also subjectively necessary ― that is to say, the will is then a power to choose only that which reason independently of inclination recognizes to be practically necessary, that is, to be good.” (Kant, 2008[1785], P.5) ii. “Following the Kantian interpretation of justice as fairness, we can say that by acting from these principles persons are acting autonomously: they are acting from principles that would acknowledge under conditions that best express their nature as free and equal rational beings. To be sure, these conditions also reflect the situation of individuals in the world and that their being subject to the circumstances of justice. But this simply means that the conception of autonomy is that fitting for human beings. …The moral education is education for autonomy. In due course everyone will know why he would adopt the principles of justice and how they are derived from the conditions that characterize his being an equal in a society of moral persons.” (Rawls, 1971, P. 516) 3. Sandel’s communitarian critiques on Rawls’ deontological liberalism a. Rawls’ flaws on the conception of the person i. Voluntaristic connection between a person’s plans of life and the self: On Rawls’ conception of the person, one can always voluntaristically make choices among plans of life and conceptions of good. However, to the communitarians, “establishing one’s own end is not a matter of choosing from a menu of available possibilities, but one of discovering what one’s end really are or ought to be.” (Mulhall and Swift, 1996, P. 50) And this discovery process is deeply embedded in the sociocultural milieu which one is born with and/or has to live with. ii. Disconnection between a person’s plans of life and identity: In connection to Rawls’ voluntaristic conception of choices of one’s end and/or plan of life, such choices can hardly be a constitutive part of one identity, that is, these ends and plans of life could not have been owned permanently and continuously by oneself because they are subject to changes in accordance with one’s preferences or desires. However, to Sandel or communitarians in 10 10 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance general, the process of personal identification is in essence a social interacting process. It is a balance, negotiation or even conflict between one’s self-aspirations and the social obligation to family, tribe, social class, nation, or any social bondage to which one belong. iii. Disconnection between personal identity and sense of community and common good: Accordingly, “Rawls’ conception of the self commits him to an impoverished understanding of political community. …On Rawls’ view a sense of community describe a possible aim of antecedently individuated selves, not an ingredient of their identity. Essentially communal goods thereby find their place only as one type of contender amongst many.” (Mulhall and Swift, 1996, P. 52) To the communitarians, a community can be conceived as a home in which one can attach one’s sense of belonging, attribute one’s vocation for life and one’s meaning of existence. b. Rawls’ flaws on the conception of community i. A society is but a field of cooperation between antecedently individuated rational choosers of ends based primarily on their independent preferences and personal desires. ii. The value of society is defined simply by its capacity to guarantee individual freedom in realization of personal preferences and desires iii. Apart from the fulfillment of individual freedom, a society is excluded from any possibility of constituting any forms of common good, such as fraternity, trust and care. G. Criticism on the Transcendental-Institutional (or Deontological) Approach 1. Amartya Sen, in his book The Idea of Justice (2009), suggests in the introductory chapter of the book that “there are two basic, and divergent, lines of reasoning about justice among leading philosophy.” (P.5) “The distance between the two approaches, transcendental institutionalism, on the one hand, and realization-focused comparison, on the other, is quite momentous.” (P. 7) 2. Transcendental institutionalism: By Transcendental institutionalism, it refers to the approach in political philosophy “led by the work of Thomas Hobbes in the seventeenth century, and followed in different ways by such outstanding thinkers as Jean-Jacques Rousseau, concentrated on identifying just institutional arrangements for society. This approach…has two distinct features.” (Sen, 2009, P. 5) a. “First, it concentrates its attention on what it identifies as perfect justice, rather than on relative comparisons of justice and injustice. …The inquiry is aimed at identifying the nature of ‘the just’, rather than finding some criteria for an alternative being ‘less unjust’ than another.” (PP. 5-6) b. “Second, in searching for perfection, transcendental institutionalism concentrate primary on getting the institutions right, and it is not directly focused on actual societies that would ultimately emerge. …It is important …to note here that transcendental institutionalists in search of perfectly just institutions have sometime also presented deeply illuminating analyses of moral and political imperative regarding socially appropriate behavior. This applies particularly to Immanuel Kant and John Rawls, both of whom have participated in transcendental institutional investigation, but have also provide far-reaching analyses of requirements of behavioural norms.” (P. 6-7) According to Sen’s characterization, John Rawls is one of the recent exemplar figure of the transcendental institutionalist approach to the studies of justice. (Sen, 11 11 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance P. 6-7; and also Pp. 52-74) 3. Realization-focused comparison: a. By Realization-focused comparison, it refer to “comparative approaches that were concerned with social realization (resulting from actual institutions, actual behavior and other influences). …They were all involved in comparisons of societies that already existed or could feasibly emerge, rather than confining their analyses on transcendental searches for a perfectly just society. Those focusing on realization-focused comparisons were often interested primarily in the removal of manifest injustice from the world that they saw.” (Sen, 2009, P. 7) b. Sen has categorically alleged his work with the perspective of realization-based comparison. In his own words, “this book (i.e. The Idea of Justice) is an attempt to investigate realization-based comparisons that focus on the advancement or retreat of justice. It is, in this respect, not in line with the strong and more philosophically celeborated tradition of transcendental institutionalism that emerged in the Enlightenment period (led by Hobbes and developed by Locke, Rousseau and Kant, among others), but more the ‘other’ tradition that also took shape in about the same period or just after (pursued in various way by Smith, Condorcet, Wollstonecraft, Bentham, Marx, Mill, among others) (Sen, 2009, P. 8-9) c. Sen specifically underlines the reasons why he prefers realization-focused comparative approach to transcendental institutionalist approach. It is because opting for the realization-focused comparative approach has “dual effect, first, of taking the comparative rather than transcendental route, and second, of focusing on actual realizations in the societies involved, rather than only on institutions and rules.” (Sen, 2009, P. 9) d. More specifically, Sen underlines there are two endogenous flaws in the transcendental institutionalist approach: i. Transcendentalism: Sen suggests that taking the transcendentalist stance entails two problems. - Problem of feasibility: “There may be no reasoned agreement at all, even under strict conditions of impartiality and open-minded scrutiny (for example, as identified by Rawls in his ‘original position’) on the nature of the ‘just society’: this is the issue of the feasibility of finding an agreed transcendental solution.” (Sen, 2009, P. 9) - Problem of redundancy: “An exercise of practical reason that involve an actual choice demands a framework for comparison of justice for choosing among feasible alternatives and not an identification of a available perfect situation that could not be transcended: this is the issue of redundancy of the search for a transcendental solution.” (Sen, 2009, P.9) ii. Institutionalism: Sen queries whether we should focus “only on the establishment of what are identified as the right institutions and rule”. Instead, he ask, “should we not also have to examine what emerges in the society, including the kind of lives that people can actually lead, given the institutions and rules, but also other influences, including actual behaviour, that would inescapably affect human lives?” (Sen, 2009, P. 10) H. Criticism on the Materials of Justice: Equality of What? 12 12 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance 1. Criticism on good-based distributive justice: Sen begins his critique on Rawls’ theory of justice by taking issue with Rawls’ focusing his two principles of justice solely on fair distributions of primary goods. In a lecture delivered in 1979 entitled “Equality of What?” Sen argues that “there is, in fact, an element of ‘fetishism’ in the Rawlsian framework. Rawls takes primary goods as the embodiment of advantage.” Sen underlines that “judging advantage purely in terms of primary goods leads to a partially blind morality.” (Sen, 1980, P. 216) a. In relation to Rawls’ first principle of justice, which sets priority to the fair distribution of basic liberty, Sen writes recently that “it has argue that the total priority of liberty is too extreme. Why should we regard hunger, starvation and medical neglect to be invariably less important that the violation of any kind of personal liberty? …It is indeed possible to accept that liberty must have some kind of priority, but total unrestrained priority is almost certainly an overkill. There are, for example, many different types of weighting schemes that can give partial priority to one concern over another.” (Sen, 2009, P. 65) b. As in connection with the second principle of justice and more specifically difference principle, Rawls’ problem of focusing mainly on the fair distribution outcomes of primary goods for the benefits of the least advantaged is much more evident. Sen suggests that “in the difference principle, Rawls judges the opportunities that people have through the means they possess, without taking into account the wide variations they have in being able to convert primary goods into good living. For example, a disable person can do far less with the same level of income and other primary goods than can an able bodied human being. A pregnant woman needs, among other things, more nutritional support than another person who is not bearing a child. The conversion of primary goods into the capacity to do various things that a person may value doing can vary enormously with differing inborn characteristics (for example, propensities to suffer from some inherited diseases), as well as disparate acquired features or the divergent effects of varying environmental surroundings (for example, living in a neighbourhood with endemic presence, or frequent outbreaks, of infectious diseases). There is, thus, a strong case for moving from focusing on primary goods to actual assessment of freedoms and capabilities.” (Sen, 2009, P. 65-66) 2. Conceptualization of capability: a. A shift of the informational focus of studies of justice: Sen begins his construction of the capability approach to justice with his conception of “informational focus”. He suggests that “ Any substantive theory of ethics and political philosophy, particularly any theory of justice, has to choose an informational focus, that is, it has to decide which features of the world we should concentrate on in judging a society and in assessing justice and in justice.” (Sen, 2009, P. 231) Sen points out that there have been various informational focuses at work in the studies of justice, for examples utilitarianism focuses on utility and its entailed satisfaction, Rawls focuses on the holdings of primary goods, and Dworkin focuses on resource holdings with reference to “liberal equality”, etc. (Sen, 1993, p. 30) Instead, Sen bases his theory of justice on the informational focus of capabilities and freedoms. b. The conception of “functioning”: Sen underlines that the most primitive notion in the capability approach is the idea of “functionings”. He conceptualizes that “functionings represent parts of the state of a person─in particular the various 13 13 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance things that he or she manages to do or be in leading a life. …Some functionings are very elementary, such as being adequately nourished, being in good health, etc., and may be strongly valued by all, for obvious reasons. Others may be more complex, but still widely valued, such as achieving self or being socially integrated. Individual may, however, differ a good deal from each other in the weights they attach to these different functionings.” (Sen, 1993, P. 31) c. The conception of capability: Accordingly, “the capability of a person reflects the alternative combinations of fuctionings the person can achieve, and from which he or she choose one collection.” (Sen, 1993, P. 31) In short, “capability is our ability to achieve various combinations of functionings that we can compare and judge against each other in terms of what we have reason to value.” (Sen, 2009, P. 233) d. Distinction between well-being and agency: …. Accordingly, the idea of capability can be conceptualized into capability of “agency achievement” and capability of “well-being achievement” (Sen, 1993, P. 37) Sen has specifically given priority to the former over the latter. It is because “overall agency goals” would usually include promotion of one’s well-being. Moreover, in some critical situations, human agents may choose the achievement of their agency goals at the expanses of their well-beings. For example, under foreign invasion, civil soldiers may willing to risk their lives in defending their country. Hence, to provide the freedom and capability for a person to achieve his or her agency goal is more fundamental than providing him or her the capability of maintaining his or her well-being. f. Distinction between achievement and freedom to achieve: Sen has further conceptualized the idea of capability with another conceptual distinction, that is, the distinction between the capability of actually attain something and the capability of being free to attain the thing valued. (Sen 2009, P. 235-238) Once again has assigned the priority to the latter over the former. Sen underlines that such a distinction and prioritization is important to the capability approach because “it is oriented towards freedom and opportunities, that is, the actual ability of people to chose to live different kinds of lives within their reach, rather than confining attention only to what may be described as the culmination─or aftermath─of choice.” (Sen, 2009, P. 237) g. In summary, the conceptualization of the idea of capability in Sen capability approach to justice can be presented in the follow table. Well-being Achievement Agency Achievement Actual Achievement Well-being Achievement Agency Achievement Freedom to achieve Well-being Freedom Agency Freedom (Adopted from Sen, 1993, P. 35) Obviously, within Sen’s capability approach to justice the concept of capability is focused on primarily “agency-freedom” conceptualization rather than the other three alternatives. 3. Capability-based Justice in Communitarian vs. Liberal Debate 14 14 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance a. Capability, society and public reasoning: Having rested the concept of capability on the “agency-freedom” footing, Sen further points out the dilemma between the individualism and communitarianism built in his concept of capability. That is, within the “agency-freedom” based concept of capability, we have to decide whether the capability should rest primarily on individual or on community. To resolve this dilemma, Sen has provided the following two additional qualifications to his capability approach to justice. b. Capability and society: Sen has specifically underlines that “identifying the capability approach as methodological individualism would be significant mistake.” (Sen, 2009, P. 244) He goes on indicating that “It is hard…to envision cogently how persons in society can think, choose or act without being influenced in one way or another by the nature and working of the world around them. …To note the role of ‘thinking, choosing and doing’ by individuals is just the beginning of recognizing what actually does happen, …but we cannot end there without an appreciation of the deep and pervasive influence of society on our ‘thinking, choosing and doing’. When someone thinks and chooses and does something, it is, for sure, that person─and not someone else─who is doing these things. But it would be hard to understand why and how he or she undertakes these activities without some comprehension of his or her societal relations.” (Sen, 2009, P. 245) Hence, Sen has explicated at length how the concept of capability should be construed in correspondence with the concept of identity, which in Sen’s conceptualization is pluralistic, multiple and diverse in nature. (Sen, 2009, P. 247; Sen, 2006) c. Capability and public reasoning: Having located the concept capacity at the social rather than individual level, Sen are facing yet another problem. That is can a consensus be researched by a society at a given point in time the conception of capabilities and their ranking? Though Sen has categorically refuted to work out “some fixed list of relevant capabilities,” (Sen, 2009, P. 242) yet he does compromise that “the approach of capability is entirely consistent with a reliance on partial rankings and on limited agreements. …The main task is to get things right on the comparative judgments that can be reached through personal and public reasoning, rather than to feel compelled to opine on every possible comparison that could be considered.” (Sen, 2009, P. 243) Hence, Sen believes that it is only through what he called “interactive public reasoning” that we may be able to obtain “a better understanding of the role, reach, and significance of particular functionings and their combination.” (Sen, 2009, P. 242) 4. Objectivity and impartiality in public reasoning: Having substantiated the capability-based concept of justice in communitarian perspective, Sen has come to one of the most difficult topic in substantive theory of practical reasoning, how to arbitrary a specific ethical, moral and/or political choice, preference or even action is correct? What is the criterion for the judgment? Amartya Sen renders the thesis of impartiality a. Three concepts of objectivity: The concept of objectivity can imply different meanings between theoretical and practical science, espeically between natural sciences and practical sciences. i. Objectivity of things: It refers to the state of existence of a physical object independent of human mind. In enquiries in natural science, a proposition can be verified by means of seeking corresponding state of existence in respective things, objects or phenomena. Based on this so-called 15 15 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance correspondence principle, a scientific proposition can claim its objectivity by referring to the existence of the respective things or affairs. Furthermore, the repeatability of the occurrence the phenomena under study could increase the objectivity of the proposition and its verification. ii. Objectivity of meanings: It refers to the state existence of shared meanings among a group of interpreters. Conventionally, it is claimed that human believes, utterance, expression, written texts, work of art etc. all bear subjectivity of the speakers or authors. However, as these expressions of subjectivity have been objectivated into written text, historical accounts and/or work of art. They will obtain their own existence alienated from its makers. As the texts, accounts and work are read and interpreted by large numbers of humans. They may generate shared meanings, feelings, believes or even convictions. As a result, the meanings embedded in the texts, accounts and work will have obtained their objectivity. Sen has characterized this type of objectivity as objectivity of comprehension and communication (Sen, 2009, P. 118) iii. Objectivity of practical reasoning: Sen argues that in ethical, moral and public reasoning, in short practical reasoning, objectivity can be generated by means of constant and critical scrutiny among a group of reasonable persons. He approvingly quoted Rawls argument that “The first essential is that a conception of objectivity must establish a public framework of thought sufficient for the concept of judgement to apply and for conclusions to be reached on the basis of reasons and evidence after discussion and due reflection. ….To say that a political conviction is objective is to say that there are reasons, specified by a reasonable and mutually recognizable political conception, sufficient to convince all reasonable persons that it is reasonable.” (Rawls, 1993, Quoted in Sen, 2009, P. 42) b. The concept of impartiality: Based on the objectivity of practical objectivity, Sen further proposes the concept of impartiality as the most fundamental base for realization of the idea of justice. Sen points out that the concept of impartiality has been commonly applied by several philosophers as the building block of the idea of justice. For examples i. In Immanuel Kant oft-quoted “categorical imperative” in practical reason, he specifies “Act always on such a maxim as thou canst at the same time will to be a universal law” (Kant, 1907; Quoted in Sen, 2009, P. 117-8) ii. Henry Sidgwick in his book The Method of Ethnics paraphrases Kant’s maxim in the following words, “That whatever is right for me must be right for all persons in similar circumstances ─ which as the form in which I accept the Kantian maxim ─ seemed to me to be certainly fundamental, certainly true, and not without practical importance.” (Sidgwick, 1966; Quoted in Sen, 2009, P. 118) iii. John Rawls in his book Political Liberalism in 1993 has replaced his thesis of original position with the thesis that “reasonable” and impartial persons” can arrive at reciprocal and mutual beneficial conclusion on the principles of justice in political domain. (Rawls, 1993) iv. Finally, Adam Smith invokes the idea of the ‘impartial spectator’. He proposes in The Theory of Moral Sentiments that “when judging one’s own conduct, to examine it as we imagine an impartial spectator would examine it’, or as he elaborate in a later edition of the same book: ‘to 16 16 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance examine out own conduct as we imagine any other fair and impartial spectator would examine it’.” (Sen, 2009, P. 124) With references to these perspectives, Sen concludes that “The place of impartiality in the evaluation of social justice and societal arrangements is central to the understanding of justice.” (Sen, 2009, P. 223) c. Two domains of impartiality: Sen suggests that “there is …a basic distinction between two quite different ways of invoking impartiality. …I shall calls respectively ‘open’ and ‘closed’ impartiality.” (P. 123) i. Closed impartiality: “With, ‘closed impartiality’ the procedure of making impartial judgements invokes only the members of a given society or nation (or what John Rawls calls a given ‘people’) to whom the judgements are made.” (Sen, 2009, P. 123) ii. Open impartiality: “In the case of ‘open impartiality’, the procedure of making impartial assessments can (and in some cases, must) invoke judgements , among others, from outside the focal group, to avoid parochial bias. In Adam Smith’s famous use of the device of the ‘impartial spectator’, the requirement of impartiality requires…the invoking of disinterested judgement of ‘any fair and impartial spectator’, not necessarily (indeed sometimes ideally not) belonging to the focal group.’” (Sen, 2009, P. 123) I. In Search of the Just Educational Governance Model: From the excursion of the discourse on justice in the past fifty year, we may not yet obtain an encompassing framework of justice. However, we are at least bettter equipped then before with some essential conceptual tools and analytical instruments that may illuminate our trail in searching for a just educational governance model for mainland for the 21st century. 1. The approach to justice: Between the transcendental institutionalism and realization-based comparison approach, I would suggest we should adopt the more realistic and pragmatic approach of realization-based comparison approach in reviewing and designing educational policy and educational governance models. Within a modern society, attaining global equality and justice among all educational sectors across all children from diversity backgrounds is simply impossible. As James S. Coleman once say in reviewing his life-long strive for equality of educational opportunities for the US schooling system, he specifies that he has not been working for attaining equality in the US schooling system, and instead what he has been striving is to lessen the inequality existing in the system. Coleman’s view echoes exactly Sen’s conception of realization-based comparison approach to justice. 2. The materials of justice: One of most contested domains within the perspective of distributive justice has been on the issue of what is to be distributed justly. From utilitarian’s total utility, Rawls’ good-based justice, Dworkin’s resource-based justice to Sen’s capability-based justice, students of distributive justice have been wrestling with these conflicting perspectives for more than a century. As we apply the debates to the designing educational policy and administrative measures, my choice will be for Sen’s capability-based justice, more specifically, the “agency-freedom” capability-based justice. The assumption behind this choice is a simple believe that all humans are born with a particular potentials, which should be given genuine opportunities to develop to the full, according to their own free will, reasons and choice. 17 17 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance 3. The players in the distributive game: Another focus of contention in the field of justice is the characterization of the participants in the distributive games. We have witnessed a line of characters, ranging from egoistic individuals rationally pursuing one’s own self-interest to the maximum, reasonable persons, trusting and trustworthy commons, to deliberative, reflective, impartial spectators. However, as this spectrum of characterizations are applied to the context of education system, it seems unrealistic as well as impossible to homogenize all participants into one typification. For example, parents will strive hard to get the best for their children (especially simple child); school teachers may treat the students in her class equally or even impartially, but it is common findings in teacher career adjustment study that teachers will seek satisfactory working environments in terms of student ability, ethnicity, social classes and varieties of other backgrounds; School administrators, especially school-heads may be idealized as openly impartial educators, who would admit whatever children, who happen to appear at the school door step. But in reality, under the perfromative pressure of school-league-table ranking, quality-assurance inspection, and failing-school label and shut-down, school administers could easily fall into the egoistic trap of adopting administrative measures of self-interest for the school. Even governmental officials, who are responsible for designing and implementation of educational policy for the who nation, may face hard choices or even social dilemma in allocating limited supply of resources and/or personnel and have to abandon the global-impartial ideal in educating the future citizens of the nations. 4. The optimal mechanism: Last but less, when it comes to the design (not to mention passage and implementation) of the substantive policy and/or measures in concrete educational domains, we are once again back to the choice Elinor Ostrom advocates in her Nobel Prize Lecture that there is only quick-fix solution (such as market or hierarchy) by to fall back to polycentric governance. Nevertheless, we may begin the complex and polycentric discourse of distributive justice of education via Sen’s conceptions of impartiality and ethical objectivity. To summarize, to constitute a just governance of education policy, the sensitizing framework to begin with is as follows. Approach to Justice Material of Justice Players in the Distributive Game The Optimal Mechanism Transcendental institutionalism; Realization-based comparison approach Gross-Total Utility; Good-based Justice; Resource-based Justice; Capability-based Justice Egoistic self-interest maximizes; Reasonable, fair, & reciprocal persons; Trusting & Trustworthy persons; Deliberative, Reflective & Impartial Spectators Polycentric Discourse of Complexity by Ethical Objectivity & Impartiality 18 18 W.K. Tsang CENU-Workshop on Practical Foundations of Ed Management & Governance