
CHAPTER 5 SOME EXTENSIONAL SEMANTICS
... If T is the only designated value, the third value ⊥ corresponds to some notion of incomplete information, like undefined or unknown and is often denoted by the symbol U or I. If, on the other hand, ⊥ corresponds to inconsistent information, i.e. its meaning is something like known to be both true a ...
... If T is the only designated value, the third value ⊥ corresponds to some notion of incomplete information, like undefined or unknown and is often denoted by the symbol U or I. If, on the other hand, ⊥ corresponds to inconsistent information, i.e. its meaning is something like known to be both true a ...
The First Incompleteness Theorem
... is effectively decidable whether a purported proof is indeed a correctly constructed T -proof which starts from T -axioms and proceeds via correct moves in T ’s built-in deductive system. Moreover, without loss of generality, we can take the effective procedure for checking proofs for a properly set ...
... is effectively decidable whether a purported proof is indeed a correctly constructed T -proof which starts from T -axioms and proceeds via correct moves in T ’s built-in deductive system. Moreover, without loss of generality, we can take the effective procedure for checking proofs for a properly set ...
SCIENTIFIC NOTATION
... positive if you moved it left (a large number) and negative if you moved it right (a small number). For example, 299,792,458 Æ 2.99792458 x 108 decimal moved 8 places to the left 0.000 000 000 000 000 000 1602 Æ 1.602 x 10–19 decimal moved 19 places to the right To convert scientific notation back t ...
... positive if you moved it left (a large number) and negative if you moved it right (a small number). For example, 299,792,458 Æ 2.99792458 x 108 decimal moved 8 places to the left 0.000 000 000 000 000 000 1602 Æ 1.602 x 10–19 decimal moved 19 places to the right To convert scientific notation back t ...
Principia Mathematica

The Principia Mathematica is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics, written by Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1913. In 1927, it appeared in a second edition with an important Introduction To the Second Edition, an Appendix A that replaced ✸9 and an all-new Appendix C.PM, as it is often abbreviated, was an attempt to describe a set of axioms and inference rules in symbolic logic from which all mathematical truths could in principle be proven. As such, this ambitious project is of great importance in the history of mathematics and philosophy, being one of the foremost products of the belief that such an undertaking may be achievable. However, in 1931, Gödel's incompleteness theorem proved definitively that PM, and in fact any other attempt, could never achieve this lofty goal; that is, for any set of axioms and inference rules proposed to encapsulate mathematics, either the system must be inconsistent, or there must in fact be some truths of mathematics which could not be deduced from them.One of the main inspirations and motivations for PM was the earlier work of Gottlob Frege on logic, which Russell discovered allowed for the construction of paradoxical sets. PM sought to avoid this problem by ruling out the unrestricted creation of arbitrary sets. This was achieved by replacing the notion of a general set with the notion of a hierarchy of sets of different 'types', a set of a certain type only allowed to contain sets of strictly lower types. Contemporary mathematics, however, avoids paradoxes such as Russell's in less unwieldy ways, such as the system of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.PM is not to be confused with Russell's 1903 Principles of Mathematics. PM states: ""The present work was originally intended by us to be comprised in a second volume of Principles of Mathematics... But as we advanced, it became increasingly evident that the subject is a very much larger one than we had supposed; moreover on many fundamental questions which had been left obscure and doubtful in the former work, we have now arrived at what we believe to be satisfactory solutions.""The Modern Library placed it 23rd in a list of the top 100 English-language nonfiction books of the twentieth century.