Download Kant`s Ethical Theory

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Utilitarianism wikipedia , lookup

Cosmopolitanism wikipedia , lookup

Divine command theory wikipedia , lookup

Alasdair MacIntyre wikipedia , lookup

Emotivism wikipedia , lookup

School of Salamanca wikipedia , lookup

Ethical intuitionism wikipedia , lookup

Moral development wikipedia , lookup

Moral disengagement wikipedia , lookup

Lawrence Kohlberg's stages of moral development wikipedia , lookup

Consequentialism wikipedia , lookup

Ethics of artificial intelligence wikipedia , lookup

Morality and religion wikipedia , lookup

Moral relativism wikipedia , lookup

Speciesism wikipedia , lookup

Neohumanism wikipedia , lookup

Kantian ethics wikipedia , lookup

Morality throughout the Life Span wikipedia , lookup

Moral responsibility wikipedia , lookup

Thomas Hill Green wikipedia , lookup

Morality wikipedia , lookup

Secular morality wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Kant’s Ethical Theory
The Good Will
 Morality cannot be based on happiness or on any other type of consequences of
our actions. Otherwise, morality would be based on circumstances that are, in
part, beyond our control. Also, since we often cannot predict the consequences of
our actions, we would often not know whether our actions are right or wrong.
 The only thing that is good “without qualification” is a good will.
 One has a good will if and only if he/she acts from the motive of respect for the
moral law.
 Whether one’s act has moral worth depends on the motive from which he/she acts.
The only motive that confers moral worth on one’s actions is respect for the moral
law.
 A morally good action is not the same thing as a morally right action. Even if one
does the morally right thing, he/she does not deserve moral credit unless he/she
acts from a good will.
Rationality and Morality
 Morality applies to human beings—not animals.
 Animals pursue pleasure. Therefore, the pursuit of pleasure cannot be the basis for
morality.
 The reason that morality applies to human beings but not to animals is that human
beings are rational beings (though imperfectly so).
 Human beings are rational because they are capable of following rules, reasoning
to conclusions, generalizing, and making free choices.
 Rationality is not necessarily limited to human beings. God, angels, and
extraterrestrial beings are other possible rational beings.
 Perfectly rational beings would naturally always act rationally. However, since
human beings are imperfectly rational, they are often inclined to act irrationally.
 Morality requires of human beings that they act as perfectly rational beings would
act.
 Since human beings are often inclined to act irrationally, the moral requirement to
act as a perfectly rational being would act is in the form of an imperative
(command)
Imperatives—2 Classifications
1. Objective vs. Subjective
A. Objective—expresses “how a fully rational being would act given certain aims
or desires” (e.g., “A fully rational being who wants to be a great violinist will
practice every day.”)
B. Subjective (Maxim)—a rule of action that specifies the actions of imperfectly
rational beings. (e.g., “If I want to be a great violinist, I shall practice every
day.”)
2. Hypothetical vs. Categorical
A. Hypothetical—prescription (“ought”) is conditional on the existence of certain
desires (e.g., “If an individual wants to get rich, he/she will invest in the stock
market.”)
B. Categorical—prescription (“ought”) is not conditional on the existence of
certain desires (e.g., “Always tell the truth”)
Kant’s Theory of Right and Wrong
Necessary Conditions for Right Action
 Morality applies to all imperfectly rational beings.
 Since morality would apply to non-human imperfectly rational beings, it does not
depend on human nature or the particular circumstances of human life.
 Every voluntary human action commits the agent to a particular subjective rule of
action (maxim). (e.g., If I go out to a restaurant for dinner, I am committing
myself to some rule like “If I am hungry and don’t want to cook, I shall go out to
eat.”)
 Morality must be unconditional. Therefore, all proper moral principles must be
categorical imperatives.
 Moral rules must be universalizable—i.e., it must be conceivable for all rational
beings to follow those rules, and the agents must be willing for that to happen.
Kant’s Fundamental Principle of Moral Obligation—the Categorical Imperative
First Formulation (CI1)
Act only according to that maxim by which you can at the same time will that it
should become a universal law.
Interpretation of “can at the same time will that it should become a universal law”—
 It must be possible for the maxim of one’s action to be a universal law—i.e.,
there must be no inconsistency in conceiving of everyone’s (all rational
beings’) always following that maxim. (cf., deceitful promise example)
 It must be possible for the agent to will that his/her maxim to become a
universal law—i.e., there must be no inconsistency between the agent’s aims
and objectives in life and the prospect of everyone’s always following that
maxim. (cf., wasting talents example)
Second Formulation (CI2)
Act so that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of another,
always as an end and never as a means only.
Interpretation of “always as an end and never as a means only”—
 To treat someone as an end is to recognize him/her as a rational being
deserving of the same respect as yourself and to treat him/her accordingly.
 Although we should not “use” others by deceiving or manipulating them, it is
permissible to enter into social arrangements with them in which they
knowingly and willingly perform services for us. (e.g., the waiter who brings
us our food in a restaurant). This is the significance of the word “only” in the
second formulation.
Third Formulation (CI3)
Act only so that the will through its maxims could regard itself at the same time as
universally lawgiving.
Interpretation of “universally lawgiving”—
 Since we are choosing the maxims for our actions, we are giving ourselves the
moral rules rather than following the dictates of some authority or other—e.g.,
government, society, or even God.
 Since our maxims must be universalizable, in giving ourselves those moral
rules, we are, in effect, legislating for everyone else as well.
Objections to Kant’s Ethical Theory
1. It is doubtful that there is a single maxim associated with each action. For many
actions, there appear to be multiple maxims on which the action could be based.
2. Kant’s assumption that we have a moral obligation to act as perfectly rational beings
would act is not supported.
3. The claim that the consequences of actions have no effect on whether they are
morally right or wrong is implausible. (e.g., lying to save the life of an innocent
person)