Download Changing the Rules? Leaving the Game? Nullification, Secession

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Battle of Wilson's Creek wikipedia , lookup

Union (American Civil War) wikipedia , lookup

Alabama in the American Civil War wikipedia , lookup

Virginia in the American Civil War wikipedia , lookup

United States presidential election, 1860 wikipedia , lookup

Tennessee in the American Civil War wikipedia , lookup

Mississippi in the American Civil War wikipedia , lookup

Baltimore riot of 1861 wikipedia , lookup

Georgia in the American Civil War wikipedia , lookup

Border states (American Civil War) wikipedia , lookup

Missouri secession wikipedia , lookup

South Carolina in the American Civil War wikipedia , lookup

Secession in the United States wikipedia , lookup

Issues of the American Civil War wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Changing the Rules? Leaving the Game?
Nullification, Secession, and the American
Future
James H. Read ∗
I. INTRODUCTION
I would like to thank Professor Mark Killenbeck for
inviting me to participate in this Symposium and Professor
Sanford Levinson for his thought-provoking keynote
address. I also want to thank the other scholars on this panel
and the participants on the Arkansas panel for their
observations on the ground-level politics of the issues we are
examining today.
In his keynote, Professor Levinson asked whether the
recent revival of nullification and secession rhetoric
represents “frivolousness” or “serious arguments.” 1 He
rejects the claim that American states may constitutionally
nullify federal law and remain in the Union. 2 But secession,
he argues, must be taken more seriously. 3 Levinson observes
that everyone can think of secessions worth defending. 4
I agree with Levinson’s criticism of nullification. I also
agree that one can more readily make a serious case for
secession than for nullification. Stating, “We are staying in
the game but playing by different rules” is different than
saying, “We are exiting the game.” But politically, in the
United States, nullification is the more immediate issue, as
∗ Professor of Political Science, College of St. Benedict and St. John’s University;
A.B., University of Chicago, 1980; M.A., Harvard University, 1983; Ph.D., 1988.
1. Sanford Levinson, The Twenty-First Century Rediscovery of Nullification and
Secession in American Political Rhetoric: Frivolousness Incarnate or Serious
Arguments to Be Wrestled With? 67 ARK. L. REV. 17, 17 (2014).
2. See id.; see also Sanford Levinson, Commentary, States Can’t Nullify Federal
Law,
STATESMAN.COM
(Feb.
6,
2010,
10:08
AM),
http://www.statesman.com/news/news/opinion/commentary-states-cant-nullifyfederal-law-1/nRkSG [hereinafter States Can’t Nullify Federal Law].
3. Id.
4. See Levinson, supra note 1, at 78.
104
ARKANSAS LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 67:103
shown by several recent measures: the Missouri bill
Levinson mentioned (H.B. 436), which sought to nullify
federal gun-control laws; 5 the Arkansas bill discussed in the
previous panel (H.B. 1752), which sought to prevent federal
officers from enforcing a federal law in Arkansas that
regulated firearms; 6 and many other current nullification
initiatives. First, I will address nullification; second, I will
turn to secession.
II. NULLIFICATION
First, states have many options other than nullification
to resist overreaching federal policies and to demand
changes. Nullification legislation is neither the only way, nor
the most effective way, for states to signal their opposition to
overreaching federal policies. 7 Nullification does not occur
when a state publicly expresses its view that the federal
government has acted unconstitutionally, nor does it occur
when a state challenges the federal government in court.8
Furthermore, one should not confuse nullification with civil
disobedience, whereby individual citizens break laws they
consider unconstitutional or unjust and accept the legal
consequences. 9 I will define nullification narrowly: It is the
doctrine that each individual state, claiming to be fully
sovereign, has the right—without exiting the Union—to be
the final judge of its own constitutional rights and
obligations, and the legal authority to act on that judgment
by obstructing federal law within the state’s boundaries.10
5. Id. at 17-18 (discussing vetoed Missouri legislation purporting to protect a
citizen’s Second Amendment Rights); see H.B. 436, 97th Gen. Assemb., First Reg.
Sess. (Mo. 2013). The Missouri bill is discussed below, along with Governor Jay
Nixon’s veto message. See infra note 24 and accompanying text.
6. H.B. 1752, 89th Gen. Assemb., Reg. Sess. (Ark. 2013), available at
http://www.arkleg.state.ar.us/assembly/2013/2013R/Bills/HB1752.pdf; Where the
Rubber Meets the Road: A Dialogue, 67 ARK. L. REV. 113, 116, 120-21 (2014).
7. See John Dinan, Contemporary Assertions of State Sovereignty and the
Safeguards of American Federalism, 74 ALB. L. REV. 1637, 1638 (2011)
(“[N]ullification . . . [is] inconsistent with the Supremacy Clause of the United States
Constitution and [has] no place or effect in the United States federal system.”).
8. See James H. Read & Neal Allen, Living, Dead, and Undead: Nullification
Past and Present, 1 AM. POL. THOUGHT 263, 268 (2012).
9. See id.
10. Id.
2014]
THE AMERICAN FUTURE
105
Levinson and I agree in rejecting this constitutional
argument. 11
Second,
the
constitutional
argument
against
nullification does not depend on whether one accepts the
strong version of judicial supremacy announced by the
United States Supreme Court in Cooper v. Aaron—that the
Supreme Court is the ultimate interpreter of the
Constitution. 12 In short, nullification is not constitutionally
and politically wrong because the Supreme Court said so.
On this point, Levinson and I also agree.
Neither James Madison nor Abraham Lincoln would
have accepted the Court’s assertion of judicial supremacy in
Cooper v. Aaron. Madison and Lincoln both regarded the
people of the United States, collectively, as the ultimate
author and interpreter of the Constitution through the
democratic process over time. 13 For both Madison and
Lincoln, nullification was wrong because it enabled a
minority to dominate the majority on matters that affected
everyone. 14 In that respect, as Madison stated in an 1830
letter, nullification would “overturn the first principle of a
free Government.” 15
If “We the People” are the “ultimate interpreter” of the
Constitution, then one might ask how those constitutional
judgments are rendered. The Court is an institutional
decision-maker; “We the People” are not. I would argue,
however, that for better or worse, all of us interpret the
Constitution all the time in our decisions as citizens, voters,
elected officeholders, and so on.
Our constitutional
judgments may be well-informed or badly informed. They
may be careful or sloppy. But in any event, these judgments
11. See supra note 2.
12. 358 U.S. 1, 18 (1958).
13. Abraham Lincoln, First Inaugural Address (Mar. 4, 1861), in ABRAHAM
LINCOLN: POLITICAL WRITINGS AND SPEECHES 120 (Terrence Ball ed., 2013)
[hereinafter LINCOLN: POLITICAL WRITINGS AND SPEECHES]; see Letter from James
Madison to Edward Everett (Aug. 28, 1830), in 9 THE WRITINGS OF JAMES MADISON
383 n.2 (Gaillard Hunt ed., 1910) (explaining Madison’s views on the “nullifying
doctrine”).
14. See supra note 13.
15. See Letter from James Madison to Edward Everett, supra note 13, at 392
n.2.
106
ARKANSAS LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 67:103
shape our political opinions and decisions in ways that the
Court will never be able to control.
One example is the recent Missouri bill (H.B. 436)
purporting to nullify a federal firearms law, 16 together with
Missouri Governor Jay Nixon’s veto message. 17 The first
question one might ask is whether the Supreme Court would
have declared this measure unconstitutional had the
Governor signed the bill into law. Undoubtedly, the Court
would, at minimum, have struck down the bill’s imposition
of criminal penalties for federal officials enforcing federal
law.
But as we know from the civil-rights era, courts alone
cannot enforce their decisions on deeply contested matters. 18
Enforcing racial equality required the actions of three
presidents, 19 the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 20 the Voting Rights
Act of 1965, 21 and the courage of thousands of civil-rights
activists. 22 Thus, although the Supreme Court had already
spoken a decade earlier in Brown v. Board of Education,23
the ultimate jury here was the people of the United States,
through a contentious, but ultimately decisive, process.
Likewise, I suggest that we view contemporary
nullification claims and counterclaims as constitutional
arguments presented not only to federal judges but also to
us, as citizens. Both the text of H.B. 436 and Governor
Nixon’s veto message make constitutional arguments. 24 The
16. H.B. 436, 97th Gen. Assemb., First Reg. Sess. (Mo. 2013); see Levinson,
supra note 1.
17. See infra note 24.
18. See, e.g., THE CIVIL RIGHTS ACT OF 1964: THE PASSAGE OF THE LAW
THAT ENDED RACIAL SEGREGATION 18, 32 (Robert D. Loevy ed., 1997) (explaining
that President Eisenhower had to use U.S. Marshals to enforce court-ordered school
integration).
19. Id. at 32, 39, 333 (Dwight D. Eisenhower, John F. Kennedy, and Lyndon B.
Johnson).
20. Civil Rights Act of 1964, Pub. L. No. 88-352, 78 Stat. 241 (codified as
amended at 42 U.S.C. § 2000a–h (2006)).
21. Voting Rights Act of 1965, Pub. L. No. 89-110, 79 Stat. 437 (codified as
amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 1971, 1973 to 1973bb-1 (2006)).
22. See generally PETER B. LEVY, THE CIVIL RIGHTS MOVEMENT (1998)
(providing biographies of several civil-rights activists).
23. Brown v. Bd. of Educ. of Topeka, Shawnee Cnty., Kan., 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
24. H.B. 436, 97th Gen. Assemb., First Reg. Sess. (Mo. 2013); Letter from Jay
Nixon, Governor of Mo., to the Sec’y of State of the State of Mo. (July 5, 2013)
[hereinafter
Letter
from
Jay
Nixon],
available
at
2014]
THE AMERICAN FUTURE
107
constitutional argument of H.B. 436 briefly paraphrases the
Tenth Amendment,25 followed immediately by a long,
unattributed allusion to Thomas Jefferson’s draft of the
Kentucky Resolutions—as though it were text from the
Constitution. 26
Governor Nixon’s veto message quotes, in full, the
Supremacy Clause in Article VI, Clause 2, of the U.S.
Constitution. 27 He also argues that H.B. 436 violates the
First Amendment “by making it a crime to publish the name
or other information of someone who owns a firearm.” 28
One does not need to be a Supreme Court Justice to decide
whether the bill or the veto message makes a better
constitutional argument.
Finally, the nullification doctrine can only work within
a functioning federal union if each state extends “full faith
and credit” to the nullification acts of other states—even
when different states, guided by opposing constitutional
judgments, nullify federal law in opposite directions on
matters that affect all states and regions. If, for example,
Arizona were to nullify federal immigration law to seal its
borders more effectively and California were to nullify
federal immigration law to open its borders, would each state
honor one another’s nullifications while remaining in a
functioning federal union?
Probably not. Instead, Arizona and California would
immediately begin nullifying one another’s nullifications.
Such conflicting nullifications occurred in the 1850s on
matters related to slavery, and the equivalent would happen
today. 29 If a state nullifies a federal law because it believes
its own constitutional judgment is right, that state is unlikely
http://www.house.mo.gov/billtracking/bills131/rpt/hb436vl.pdf (arguing that H.B. 436
violates the Supremacy Clause and infringes on an individual’s freedom of speech).
25. H.B. 436, 97th Gen. Assemb., First Reg. Sess. (Mo. 2013).
26. H.B. 436, 97th Gen. Assemb., First Reg. Sess. (Mo. 2013); see Thomas
Jefferson, The Kentucky Resolutions of 1798: Jefferson’s Draft, in THE PAPERS OF
THOMAS JEFFERSON 536 (Barbara B. Oberg et al. eds., 2003).
27. See Letter from Jay Nixon, supra note 24, at 1-2.
28. Id.
29. See Read & Allen, supra note 8, at 281-83 (noting disagreement between
state political figures commenting on the nullification-like actions of other states in
relation to federal laws).
108
ARKANSAS LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 67:103
to respect the nullifications of other states whose
constitutional judgments it considers wrong. 30
III. SECESSION
Professor Levinson is correct that the argument for
secession is more serious than the argument for
nullification. 31 Levinson and I agree that, in the United
States, secession is not a constitutional right and, therefore,
it would need justification on other grounds. 32 However,
secession can sometimes be justifiable. But I disagree with
Levinson on what criteria would justify secession. Further, I
am also much more pessimistic that secession, in most cases,
could be accomplished peacefully—in a way that safeguards
the rights of all or resolves the conflicts that triggered the
secession in the first place.
The argument for secession is strong in two types of
cases. One is a clear case of oppression by the existing
government, where secession is the most readily available
remedy. 33 The Declaration of Independence—borrowing
from John Locke—asserts that dissolution of government is
justified by “a long train of abuses and usurpations,” but not
for “light and transient causes.” 34 These phrases are fairly
general, but the Declaration’s specific list of grievances gives
them content. 35 Of particular importance is the King’s
dissolution of legislative bodies and resort to military rule,
both of which deprived Americans of the normal, peaceful
means of securing redress for their grievances. 36 Nothing
similar has occurred in any of the contemporary American
secession movements Levinson mentioned. 37
30. See id. at 281-82.
31. See Levinson, supra note 1, at 58-59, 77-78; States Can’t Nullify Federal Law,
supra note 2.
32. Sanford Levinson, “Perpetual Union,” “Free Love,” and Secession: On the
Limits to the “Consent of the Governed”, 39 TULSA L. REV. 457, 459-60 (2004)
[hereinafter “Perpetual Union”].
33. See THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 2 (U.S. 1776).
34. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 2.
35. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE paras. 3-30.
36. See THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE paras. 14, 24, 30.
37. See Levinson, supra note 1, at 28-29, 52-54 (noting several contemporary
secessionist movements scattered throughout the United States, none of which have
either dissolved a legislative body or subjected the civilian population to military
rule).
2014]
THE AMERICAN FUTURE
109
Furthermore, in the case of the Confederate secession
of 1860–1861, the slave states were not only represented in
Congress and other branches of federal government, they
were overrepresented because of the Senate’s composition
and the three-fifths clause. 38 The slave states seceded
because they were not overrepresented enough to ensure the
policy result they wanted—a guarantee that Congress would
not prohibit slavery in the western territories.39
In addition to an oppressive government, another
justification for secession is where the parties mutually agree
to part ways peacefully, with some agreed-upon process to
settle claims and to protect the rights of internal minorities.
The peaceful partition of Czechoslovakia into Slovakia and
Czech Republic is perhaps the clearest example. 40 Such
cases, however, are the exception. The Yugoslavian
scenario, whereby secession leads to secession-withinsecession ad infinitum—of the kind Abraham Lincoln spoke
about in his First Inaugural Address 41—may be more likely
in many parts of the world today.42
The Yugoslavian secessions of 1991–1992 resolved
nothing; all the worst instances of ethnic cleansing and
genocide occurred after the secession, not before. 43 Bosnian
Muslims and Kosovars might have remained safe in a united
Yugoslavia, but they too had to secede in self-defense after
the secessions began.44
The Confederate secession of 1860–1861 would also
have resolved nothing. Professor Levinson closed his
keynote address with a quote from President Buchanan, who
opposed secession but wanted to spare Americans a bloody
38. See Paul Finkelman, How the Proslavery Constitution Led to the Civil War,
43 RUTGERS L.J. 405, 407, 419, 424 (2013).
39. See id. at 424-26.
40. Jaroslav Tir, Keeping the Peace After Secession: Territorial Conflicts Between
Rump and Secessionist States, 49 J. CONFLICT RESOL. 713, 736 (2005).
41. LINCOLN: POLITICAL WRITINGS AND SPEECHES, supra note 13.
42. See Milica Z. Bookman, War and Peace: The Divergent Breakups of
Yugoslavia and Czechoslovakia, 31 J. PEACE RES. 175, 175-76 (1994) (detailing the
domino-like stream of secessions arising in Yugoslavia).
43. See id. at 176-77.
44. See JELENA OBRADOVIĆ-WOCHNIK, ETHNIC CONFLICT AND WAR
CRIMES IN THE BALKANS: THE NARRATIVES OF DENIAL IN POST-CONFLICT
SERBIA 50-51, 56 (2013) (noting the incredible violence unfolding in Yugoslavia that
motivated multiple local ethnic groups to secede as a means of self-defense).
110
ARKANSAS LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 67:103
war. 45 I can sympathize with Buchanan’s agony, but letting
the South go in peace would not have spared Americans a
bloody war. This strategy would have only shifted the war
westward and changed the label. The slave states, having
seceded from the Union to ensure that slavery would not be
shut out of the western territories, would certainly not have
turned around and peacefully relinquished those same
territories to the Union.46 Nor would the Union have
conceded these territories to the newly independent
Confederacy. The war would have become an “international
conflict,” not a “civil war,” but it would have occurred
nonetheless.
Further, if the slave states could justify secession based
on an inherent right of self-determination,47 then surely the
slaves themselves would have had an equal or greater right
to “secede” from their slave owners and to call in any power
on Earth—including the Union army—to support them in
their effort. Levinson would likely agree on this point. He
appears, however, to treat the Confederate secession as an
outlier because of the centrality of slavery. 48 Instead, I see
significant parallels between the Confederate secession and
many others that do not involve slavery.
Professor Levinson asks whether the United States has
now become too large to function as a democracy. 49 I hope
this is not true because the alternatives are not good. If it is
true, and if the United States would ultimately function
better separated into smaller states and confederacies, then
secession is a decision that affects everyone. The decision to
secede would have to be made by all of us—not just by some
states or regions unilaterally forcing the result upon the rest.
45. See Levinson, supra note 1, at 78-79.
46. The Confederacy also cherished hopes of securing California, or at least half
of it. See J. M. Guinn, How California Escaped State Division, 6 ANN. PUBLICATION
HIST. SOC’Y S. CAL. 223, 225-26 (1905).
47. See “Perpetual Union”, supra note 32, at 472-77 (noting that the heart of the
South’s secessionist argument was self-determination).
48. See Levinson, supra note 1, at 60-62.
49. Id. at 76-77.
2014]
THE AMERICAN FUTURE
111
In conclusion, I certainly agree that some secessions can
be justified.50 Secession, however, is a high-stakes decision,
not an ordinary act of political opposition. It carries
enormous consequences for many people besides those who
decide to initiate it. For that reason, secession demands a
high level of justification—one that I do not perceive in any
of the American cases before us now.
50. See, e.g., OBRADOVIĆ-WOCHNIK, supra note 44, at 48-52 (discussing various
atrocities and war crimes that occurred during the Yugoslav Wars, resulting in several
“secessions”).