Download Niche Inheritance

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts

Unilineal evolution wikipedia , lookup

Natural selection wikipedia , lookup

The Selfish Gene wikipedia , lookup

Incomplete Nature wikipedia , lookup

Sociocultural evolution wikipedia , lookup

Evolution of metal ions in biological systems wikipedia , lookup

Symbiogenesis wikipedia , lookup

Population genetics wikipedia , lookup

Ecology wikipedia , lookup

Koinophilia wikipedia , lookup

Evolutionary mismatch wikipedia , lookup

Adaptation wikipedia , lookup

Evolutionary history of life wikipedia , lookup

Theistic evolution wikipedia , lookup

Genetics and the Origin of Species wikipedia , lookup

Hologenome theory of evolution wikipedia , lookup

Paleontology wikipedia , lookup

Saltation (biology) wikipedia , lookup

Evolution wikipedia , lookup

Evolving digital ecological networks wikipedia , lookup

Introduction to evolution wikipedia , lookup

Transcript
Niche Inheritance: A Possible Basis for Classifying
Multiple Inheritance Systems in Evolution
John Odling-Smee
School of Anthropology
University of Oxford
[email protected]
Abstract
The theory of niche construction adds a second general inheritance system, ecological inheritance, to evolution (OdlingSmee et al. 2003). Ecological inheritance is the inheritance,
via an external environment, of one or more natural selection pressures previously modified by niche-constructing organisms. This addition means descendant organisms inherit
genes, and biotically transformed selection pressures in their
environments, from their ancestors. The combined inheritance
is called niche inheritance. Niche inheritance is used as a basis
for classifying the multiple genetic and non-genetic, inheritance systems currently being proposed as possibly significant
in evolution (e.g., Jablonka and Lamb 2005). Implications of
niche inheritance for the relationship between evolution and
development (EvoDevo) are discussed.
Keywords
cultural inheritance, development, evolution, ecological inheritance, epigenetic inheritance, niche construction, niche
inheritance
276
April 8, 2007; accepted September 30, 2007
c 2008 Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007, 276–289. John Odling-Smee
Organisms do not live very long. Because they don’t, the only
way they can affect evolution is by contributing to one or
more inheritance systems. In this connection standard evolutionary theory (SET henceforth) is restricting. It only recognizes a single general inheritance system, genetic inheritance
(Mameli 2004). It therefore implies there is only one way in
which organisms can contribute to evolution. In each generation, variant organisms survive and reproduce differentially
relative to natural selection and chance, thereby causing “fit”
organisms to transmit their genes to their descendents by genetic inheritance.
This restricted concept of inheritance constrains our understanding of how evolution works, and how it relates to
other processes in biology. For example, it has consistently
promoted the separation of developmental biology from evolutionary biology. At least since Morgan (1919), evolutionary
biologists have assumed that the between generation transmission of genes by organisms through genetic inheritance is
sufficient to explain how evolutionary changes occur in populations, regardless of the functions of those same genes within
generations during the development of individual organisms
(Amundson 2005).
A second consequence applies almost exclusively to humans. It has long been recognized that the expression of human
phenotypes depends on cultural inheritance as well as genetic
inheritance (Dawkins 1976; Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman 1981;
Boyd and Richerson 1985). However, if human evolution, like
the evolution of all other species, depends exclusively on genetic inheritance, then the only way in which cultural inheritance can affect human evolution must be by contributing
to human variation, and therefore to differential survival and
reproduction of diverse humans in each generation (Wilson
1975).
The assumption that genetic inheritance is the only inheritance system in evolution has recently been questioned, primarily because of new data stemming from molecular biology
(e.g., Schlichting and Pigliucci 1998; Oyama et al. 2001; WestEberhard 2003; Jablonka and Lamb 1995, 2005; Gilbert 2001,
2004; Pigliucci and Preston 2004; Mameli 2004). Jablonka
and Lamb (2005), for example, propose four distinct inheritance systems in evolution: genetic, epigenetic, behavioral,
and symbolic. Adopting a different approach, Odling-Smee
et al. (2003) propose that, minimally, two general inheritance
systems in evolution are necessary: genetic inheritance and
ecological inheritance.
This proliferation of putative inheritance systems introduces some dangers. It could eventually advance our understanding of evolution. It could even remove some longstanding “log-jams” that have prevented the achievement of
broader syntheses in biology, for instance, by making it easier to connect evolutionary biology to developmental biology
(West-Eberhard 2003), a possibility discussed here. Or it could
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
help fuse ecosystem level ecology with evolution (O’Neill et al.
1986; Jones and Lawton 1995; Holt 2005). However, it could
simultaneously make it harder to model evolution formally,
or to describe how each of the proposed inheritance systems
interacts with the others. One clear threat is that the coherence,
lucidity, and empirical potency of SET’s genetic inheritance
only approach could be lost in a “riot” of competing inheritance systems.
Can such a riot be avoided? Is it possible to make sense
of multiple evolutionary inheritance systems without a loss
of potency by evolutionary theory? A necessary first step is
to establish a taxonomy of inheritance systems that is both
simple and clarifying. I shall attempt that here. First, I will
use niche construction theory (Odling-Smee et al. 2003) as
a starting point, in an effort to establish a general theoretical
framework that is less hostile than SET to the idea that plural
inheritance systems exist in evolution. Second, I will use this
revised theoretical framework as a basis for classifying diverse
inheritance systems. Third, I will apply the resulting taxonomic
scheme to the exceptionally difficult case of human evolution.
The rationale for this last step is that the evolution of our own
species includes cultural inheritance, and probably involves
more distinct inheritance systems than the evolution of any
other species. Therefore, if the proposed taxonomic scheme
works for human evolution, it should also work for evolution
in general.
Niche Construction
The theory of niche construction was first introduced to evolutionary biology by Lewontin (1982, 1983). Recently it has
gathered momentum (Odling-Smee 1988; Odling-Smee et al.
1996, 2003; Laland et al. 1996, 1999, 2001; Lewontin 2000;
Oyama et al. 2001; Sterelny 2003; Boni and Feldman 2005;
Donohue 2005; Laland and Sterelny 2006). Figure 1 contrasts
SET, without niche construction, to an extended version of
evolutionary theory that includes it.
In SET (Figure 1a), natural selection pressures in environments (E) act on populations of diverse organisms (or phenotypes) to influence which individuals survive and reproduce,
and pass on their genes to the next generation via a single
inheritance system, genetic inheritance. The adaptations of organisms are treated as consequences of independent natural
selection pressures moulding organisms to fit pre-established
environmental templates. The templates are dynamic because
processes that are independent of organisms change the worlds
to which organisms have to adapt. However, the changes that
organisms bring about in their own worlds are seldom thought
to have evolutionary significance.
The main problem with this view is that it discourages consideration of the feedback in evolution caused by
the modification of environmental selection pressures by the
277
Niche Inheritance: A Possible Basis for Classifying Multiple Inheritance Systems in Evolution
Et
Natural selection
Gene pool
Populations
of Phenotypes
Next generation
Genetic inheritance
t
Et+1
t+1
Natural selection
Gene pool
Populations
of Phenotypes
Gene pool
Populations
of phenotypes
(a)
Natural selection
Et
Niche construction
Genetic inheritance
Next generation
Ecological inheritance
t
Natural selection
t+1
Et+1
Niche construction
Gene pool
Populations
of phenotypes
(b)
Figure 1.
a. Standard evolutionary theory. b. Extended evolutionary theory.
niche-constructing activities of organisms. All organisms,
through their metabolisms, movements, behaviors, and
choices, partly define, create, and destroy their selective environments, and in doing so, they transform some of the natural
selection pressures in their environments that subsequently
select them (Lewontin 1983; Odling-Smee et al. 2003). The
adaptations of organisms cannot therefore be exclusively consequences of organisms responding to autonomous selection
pressures in environments. Sometimes they must involve organisms responding to selection pressures that have previously
been transformed by their own, or their ancestors’, or each
other’s niche-constructing activities.
When niche construction is added, it extends evolutionary
theory as illustrated in Figure 1b. The evolution of organisms
now depends on both natural selection and niche construction. Genes are transmitted by ancestral organisms to their
descendents, as directed by the outcomes of natural selection
in the usual way. But selected habitats, modified habitats, and
modified sources of natural selection in those habitats are also
278
transmitted by the same organisms to their descendents, as a
consequence of their niche-constructing activities, through a
second general inheritance system in evolution, ecological inheritance. Ecological inheritance comprises the inheritance of
one or more natural selection pressures, previously modified
by the niche-constructing activities of organisms, in their external environments (Odling-Smee et al. 2003). The selective
environments encountered by organisms are therefore partly
determined by independent sources of natural selection, for
instance, by climate, or physical and chemical events. However, they are also partly determined by what organisms do,
or previously did to their own, and each other’s selective environments, by niche construction.
Innumerable examples of niche construction are known.
Animals manufacture nests, burrows, webs, and pupal cases;
plants modify fire regimes, levels of atmospheric gases, and
nutrient cycles; fungi decompose organic matter; and bacteria
fix nutrients (Turner 2000; Odling-Smee et al. 2003; Schwilk
2003; Hansell 2005; Meysman et al. 2006). There are also
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
John Odling-Smee
examples of social niche construction in insects (Frederickson
et al. 2005) and primates (Flack et al. 2006), and of cultural
niche construction in humans (Feldman and Cavalli-Sforza
1989; Durham 1991; Laland et al. 2000; Balter 2005; Smith
2007). For decades, ecologists have also realized that organisms can, and frequently do alter their environments in ecologically significant ways. Today these phenomena are referred
to by ecologists as ecosystem engineering (Jones et al. 1994,
1997; Wright and Jones 2006).
Many kinds of niche construction have already been modeled both by standard, and non-standard, population genetic
models. For example, niche construction is implicit in standard models of frequency- and density-dependent selection
(Futuyma 1998), habitat selection (Hanski and Singer 2001),
maternal inheritance (Kirkpatrick and Lande 1989), extended
phenotypes (Dawkins 1982), indirect genetic effects and epistasis (Wolf et al. 2000), and co-evolution (Thompson 1994).
Other models have explicitly investigated how niche construction and ecological inheritance change the dynamics of the
evolutionary process (Laland et al. 1996, 1999, 2001; OdlingSmee et al. 1996, 2003; Ihara and Feldman 2004; Hui and Yue
2004; Boni and Feldman 2005; Borenstein et al. 2006; Silver
and Di Paolo 2006). So far, all the latter models have found
niche construction to be evolutionarily consequential.
In spite of this work, the full significance of niche construction has been neglected. What has been missing, until
recently, was a body of theory that recognizes niche construction as a distinct causal process in evolution in its own right
(Waddington 1969; Lewontin 1983; Odling-Smee et al. 2003;
Laland and Sterelny 2006). Why has such a seemingly obvious
process been marginalized in evolutionary theory for so long?
The Limitations of Standard Evolutionary Theory
The answer probably lies hidden in a seldom re-considered
foundational assumption of SET concerning the role of environments in evolution. Odling-Smee (1988) called it a “reference device” problem. Lewontin (1983) originally described
the problem in terms of two pairs of coupled differential equations.
The first pair (1) summarizes SET:
dO
= f (O, E),
dt
dE
= g(E).
dt
(1a)
(1b)
In (1) evolutionary change in organisms, dO/dt, is assumed to
depend on both organisms’ states, O, and environmental states,
E (1a). In contrast, environmental change, dE/dt, is assumed to
depend exclusively on environmental states (1b). With many
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
caveats and complications, organisms are not generally regarded as causing any evolutionarily significant changes in
their environments.
But, said Lewontin, this is not how evolution works. His
second pair of equations (2) summarizes how he thinks it does
work:
dO
= f (O, E),
dt
dE
= g(O, E),
dt
(2a)
(2b)
Change in organisms, dO/dt, is assumed to depend on both
organisms’ states and environmental states as before (2a), but
environmental change, dE/dt, is now assumed to depend on
both environment states, and the environment-modifying activities of organisms (2b).
Philosopher Peter Godfrey-Smith (1996) drew attention
to the same problem when he described SET as an “externalist” theory, because it uses the external environment as its sole
explanatory reference device. The standard theory seeks to explain the internal properties of organisms, their adaptations,
exclusively in terms of properties of their external environments, natural selection pressures (Figure 1a).
The principal point the standard theory obscures is that
organisms are active, as well as reactive (Waddington 1969;
Lewontin 1983). To stay alive organisms must gain resources from their external environments by “informed,” “fuelconsuming” non-random “work” (Odling-Smee et al. 2003).
Organisms are therefore compelled to choose and perturb specific components of their environments. They are also compelled to change some of the selection pressures in their environments by doing so. This point is captured by Lewontin’s
equation 2b. In effect, this equation introduces a second “causal
arrow” in evolution in addition to Darwin’s “causal arrow” of
natural selection. Odling-Smee (1988) called Lewontin’s second causal arrow “niche construction.”
We can now pin down the “reference device problem”
more precisely. One of the causal arrows in equations 2, natural selection, is fully compatible with the externalist assumption of SET because it is pointing in the “right” direction, from
environments to organisms. Hence, it is conceptually straightforward to describe how external natural selection pressures
in environments cause adaptations in organisms. However, the
second causal arrow in 2, niche construction, is pointing in
the “wrong” direction, from organisms to environments. That
renders niche construction incompatible with the externalist
assumption of SET. It makes it difficult or impossible for evolutionary biologists to describe changes in natural selection
pressures, caused by prior niche-construction, as evolutionarily causal. Instead, SET is forced by its own explanatory
279
Niche Inheritance: A Possible Basis for Classifying Multiple Inheritance Systems in Evolution
reference device, the external environment, to “explain away”
all observed instances of niche construction as “nothing but”
phenotypic, or possibly extended phenotypic (Dawkins 1982,
2004) consequences of prior natural selection. SET can recognize niche construction as a consequence of evolution, but it
cannot recognize it as a cause.
The solution adopted by niche construction theory was to
change the explanatory reference device. Instead of describing
the evolution of organisms only relative to natural selection
pressures in external environments, as in (1), Odling-Smee
et al. (2003) describe evolution relative to their “niches.”
N (t) = h(O, E)
(3)
In (3), Nt represents the niche of a population of organisms O at time t, and the dynamics of Nt are driven by both
population-modifying natural selection pressures in E, and by
the environment-modifying niche-constructing activities of the
population of organisms, O. Everything here is evolving. The
population, O is evolving, as usual. O’s selective environment,
E, is in part coevolving as a consequence of O’s genetically
“informed”, or possibly “brain-informed” niche-constructing
activities. Finally, the niche relationship itself, N(t), is evolving
as a function of O’s and E’s interactions. Equation 3 subsumes
Lewontin’s equations, 2.
Because niches always include two-way interactions between organisms and their environments (Chase and Leibold
2003), this step is sufficient to allow an extended “interactionist” (Godfrey-Smith 1996) theory of evolution (Figure 1b) to
be substituted for the standard externalist theory (Figure 1a).
The solution works because the niche concept offers a “neutral” explanatory reference device. The (OE) niche relationship
does not impose an a priori bias either in favor of natural selection and against niche construction, or vice-versa. Instead
it allows both the “causal arrows” in (2), natural selection
and niche construction, to be modeled as reciprocal causes
in evolution (Laland and Sterelny 2006). Formal models can
now be built that capture (1) the modification of sources of
natural selection in environments by prior niche construction; (2) the subsequent selection of organisms by sources
of selection modified by prior niche construction; and (3)
changes in the adaptations, and hence in the subsequent nicheconstructing activities of organisms, caused by prior natural selection (Laland et al. 1996, 1999; Odling-Smee et al.
2003).
Conceptually and empirically, it is only necessary to
recognize that natural selection is not a property of autonomous external habitats, but a property of relativistic niches. On that basis, all the processes that modify
organism-environment niche relationships, including both natural selection and niche construction, become evolutionarily
causal.
280
Ecological Inheritance
Multiple consequences flow from this revision (Odling-Smee
et al. 2003). Here I will focus only on those that affect inheritance in evolution.
When niche construction is included as a co-directing
causal process in evolution, it not only contributes to the adaptations of organisms, but it also causes a second general inheritance system in evolution, ecological inheritance. This occurs
because some of the environmental consequences caused by
the repeated niche-constructing activities of multiple generations of organisms in their environments (e.g., the presence
of burrows, mounds, and dams or, on a larger scale, changed
atmospheric states, soil states, substrate states, or sea states;
Dietrich and Taylor Perron 2006; Meysman et al. 2006) accumulate or persist in environments across generations. When
they do, they transform some of the natural selection pressures
encountered by later generations of organisms (Odling-Smee
et al. 2003).
The way ecological inheritance works is substantially different from the way genetic inheritance works (Odling-Smee
1988). First, ecological inheritance is transmitted, in the form
of biotically modified sources of natural selection, through
the medium of an external environment. It is not transmitted
by reproduction. Second, unlike genetic inheritance, ecological inheritance does not depend on the transmission of discrete replicators between generations (Sterelny 2001, 2005;
Dawkins 2004). It depends only on organisms bequeathing altered selective environments to their offspring, either through
the physical perturbation of biological and non-biological
components of their environments, or by their choices of habitats. Third, in sexual populations genetic inheritance is transmitted by two parents only, during sexual reproduction, and
from the point of view of the offspring, on a single occasion only. In contrast, an ecological inheritance may be transmitted by multiple organisms, to multiple other organisms,
within and between generations, throughout the lifetimes of
the niche-constructing organisms. Last, ecological inheritance
is not exclusively transmitted by genetic relatives. It can also
be transmitted by other organisms, who share, or previously
shared, a common ecosystem. These other organisms must be
ecologically related, but they are not always genetically related
to the organisms receiving the inheritance.
The explicit inclusion of ecological inheritance in evolutionary theory replaces the single inheritance system in
Figure 1a by the dual inheritance system in Figure 1b. In
SET, Figure 1a, genes are transmitted between generations via
genetic inheritance, but nothing else is. In the extended version
of evolutionary theory, Figure 1b, organisms inherit genes, including naturally selected genes from their ancestors through
genetic inheritance. They also inherit some ancestrally modified natural selection pressures, in their environments, relative
to their genes, through ecological inheritance.
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
John Odling-Smee
Niche Inheritance
Ecological inheritance has important consequences for development as well as for evolution, and it could change the
perceived relationship between evolutionary biology and developmental biology. If, in each generation, each individual
offspring not only inherits genes, but also a previously chosen
or modified local selective environment relative to its genes,
then what each offspring must actually inherit is an initial
organism-environment relationship or “niche” from its ancestors.
Niche inheritance is summarized in equation 4.
N(to ) = h[Oi Ei ]
(4)
N(to ) represents the niche state at the moment of origin of a new
organism. It needs to be emphasized that each inherited niche is
now an individual organism’s “personal” developmental niche,
rather than a population’s evolutionary niche (Odling-Smee
1988).
This concept of niche inheritance differs from standard
ideas of inheritance in two ways. First, in SET the development of offspring organisms is assumed to begin with the
inheritance by each organism of a “start-up” kit of genes,
that subsequently “unfolds” in the context of an independent
environment, in the course of the organism’s development
(Lewontin 1983). In niche construction theory, however, the
development of an organism begins with the inheritance of a
“start-up” [OE] relationship, or niche, that combines both a
genetic and an ecological inheritance. Subsequently, these two
inheritance systems “interact,” and their interactions are in part
regulated by the phenotypically plastic, niche-constructing organisms themselves during their development (Oyama et al.
2001; West-Eberhard 2003; Pigliucci and Preston 2004).
Second, niche inheritance depends on two transmission
channels between generations, instead of one (Figure 1b). The
first channel is closely associated with reproduction and is reserved by SET for genetic inheritance only. The second channel is the external environment through which an ecological
inheritance is transmitted. Minimally, in addition to inherited
genes, each inherited niche, for each offspring, must include
the inheritance of an initial environmental “address” in space
and time, often influenced by parental choices. In many species
the parents also ensure that a “resource package” is present at
their offspring’s initial address. For instance, phytophagous insects not only supply their offspring with eggs, but they often
choose specific host plants on which to lay their eggs, the chosen plants subsequently serving as energy and matter resources
for their offspring. In addition to what its parents supply, an organism’s start-up niche may also include other environmental
resources, due to the niche-constructing activities of other, less
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
closely related organisms. For example, when termites build a
mound, they modify the mean, and reduce the range of temperature and humidity experienced by the developing larvae
by their collective niche-constructing activities (Hansell 2005;
Laland and Sterelny 2006).
Niche inheritance is therefore richer than SET’s geneticinheritance-only version of inheritance, and less restricting. It
may therefore provide a friendlier basis for incorporating and
classifying the multiple inheritance systems in evolution that
are currently being proposed (West-Eberhard 2003; Jablonka
and Lamb 2005). It is this idea that I want to explore in the
rest of this article.
The Dimensions of Niche Inheritance
In order to explore it, we must first describe the principal
sub-components of niche inheritance. For that, we need some
descriptive dimensions. We can derive two of them by further
unpacking the relativity of the [OE] niche relationship. One
dimension can be derived from the relationship between the
internal and external environments of organisms. This relationship demarcates the two transmission channels through which
the different components of niche inheritance are transmitted
(Figure 1b). A second dimension is derived from the relationship between whatever “semantic information” (Odling-Smee
et al. 2003) is inherited by organisms from their ancestors and
the diverse natural selection pressures in their environments
that selected that information. The latter must include selection
pressures previously modified by ancestral niche construction.
I will provisionally assume that these selection pressures are
themselves derived from energy and matter resources in the
environments of organisms. Let us start with the transmission
channels.
Channel 1 connects the internal environments of parent
organisms to the internal environments of offspring organisms, directly, via the mechanisms of reproduction. Ultimately
channel1 is reducible to cell division and cell fusion. Channel
1 was originally discovered by Schwann and Virchow in the
19th century, and it gave rise to cell theory. Any kind of inheritance that travels between organisms, from cell to cell, or
from O to O directly during reproduction will be treated as a
Channel 1 type inheritance.
Channel 2 connects possibly multiple, ancestral nicheconstructing organisms to descendent organisms indirectly,
through the modification of selection pressures in an external
environment. Any kind of inheritance that does not travel between organisms, from cell to cell directly, will be treated as
a Channel 2 type inheritance. Channel 2 works is the way that
ecological inheritance works, from O to E, and back to O.
These definitions assume it is easy to demarcate the internal and external environments of organisms in the context
of their [OE] niche relationships. However, the demarcation is
281
Niche Inheritance: A Possible Basis for Classifying Multiple Inheritance Systems in Evolution
not always easy. For example, it would seem straightforward
to define any individual organism, O, by whatever boundary
exists between the organism and its environment, E. Thus, in
the case of a single celled organism, the boundary is its cell
wall or membrane. O’s external environment E is then everything outside the same boundary. Depending on the focus of
interest, however, there can be complications. For example, in
a multi-celled organism the external environment of most cells
includes the other cells in the metazoan’s body. Hence, in somatic cell division inside a metazoan body, for example, when
a parent liver cell in an animal gives rise to two daughter liver
cells, the transmission of heritable resources is direct, from
cell to cell, and therefore through Channel 1. However, the external environment now becomes the rest of the liver, the rest
of the metazoan’s body, plus the metazoan organism’s external
environment. It follows that demarcating between an internal
and external environment depends on how “the organism,” or
part organism that is the current focus of interest, is defined.
Assuming “the organism,” O, can be defined sufficiently well,
then relative to O, an external environment, E, can also be
defined.
It may also be difficult to distinguish between heritable informational resources, versus the heritable energy and matter
resources that are the principal components of niche inheritance, and the primary sources of the natural selection pressures that select for semantic information in organisms. Here,
several points need clarifying.
First, the distinction between informational resources and
environmental energy and matter resources traces back to the
origin of life. To survive and reproduce, organisms must take
physical energy and matter from their environments. They
must also dump physical detritus back in their environments.
However, organisms cannot do either of these things unless
they are adapted to their environments. Moreover, organisms
cannot be adapted unless they are sufficiently informed a priori by adaptive semantic information. The “catch 22” is that
organisms cannot be informed a priori without also possessing
sufficient energy and material resources a priori to pay a fitness
cost for the acquisition, storage, and use of adaptive semantic information, including the “de novo” selection of “new”
adaptive information by natural selection (Odling-Smee et al.
2003; Bergstrom and Lachmann, 2004). So which came first,
physical resources or semantic information, metabolism or
replication? This is the classic origin of life problem and it is
still not fully resolved (Fry 2000). But it does illustrate how
fundamental and ancient is the distinction between semantic
information and energy and material resources in evolution.
It is also notoriously difficult to define semantic information. Here, I will only attempt a working definition: Semantic
information is anything that reduces uncertainty about selective environments, relative to the fitness goals of organisms.
Hence, the “meaningfulness” of whatever semantic informa282
tion is encoded in inherited genes ultimately derives from the
ability of those genes to “inform” organisms, relative to their
fitness goals and natural selection pressures, in such ways that
adapted organisms can tap into energy and matter resources in
their environments. This definition deliberately refrains from
specifying the physical carriers of semantic information. In
principle, the carriers could be genes, or other molecules, or
neurons, or in humans, cultural symbols. All that matters is
that the semantic information, carried by any carrier, can potentially influence the fitness of organisms.
I shall further assume that, in the case of genetic inheritance, natural selection causes semantic information to
be carried by heritable genes, simply through the persistence of selected genes. By persisting across generations, selected “fit” genes register “fit” outcomes of previous organismenvironment interactions and, in effect, become primitive
“memories” (Odling-Smee 1983, 1988; Odling-Smee et al.
2003). Semantic information is always relative because its
“meaning” is ultimately derived from a relationship between
the fitness needs of organism and selection pressures in their
environments, including selection pressures previously modified by niche construction. Conversely, environmental energy
and matter “resources” are also relative, because they are reciprocally defined by how they relate to whatever semantic information happens to be carried by specific organisms. Whether
they are positive or negative, harmful or beneficial, energy and
matter resources are only “resources” relative to those specific
organisms that carry the semantic information that makes them
so. Relative to other organisms that carry different semantic
information, and therefore different adaptations, exactly the
same resources may be completely irrelevant (Lewontin 1982,
1983; Odling-Smee et al. 2003).
A third problem relates to which transmission channel carries what kind of resource. By strongly identifying genes with
information, and by reserving Channel 1 for genetic inheritance only, SET encourages the idea that Channel 1 transmits
genetically encoded semantic information only. That idea is
misleading because some nongenetic components of “start-up
niches,” including some energy and matter resources, are also
transmitted by Channel 1, from cell to cell, during reproduction. For example, in insects and birds the eggs supplied by
“mothers” to their offspring carry some energy and matter resources in the form of cytoplasm and protein in egg yolks, as
well as semantic information (Sapp 1987; Amundson 2005).
Similarly, Channel 2 may appear to transmit physical energy and matter resources only, in the form of modified natural
selection pressures. However, this too is misleading, because it
is possible for ecological inheritance to transmit semantic information, as well as modified energy and matter resources, between generations. Semantic information is transmitted whenever an ecological inheritance includes other organisms that
are themselves inheritors and carriers of semantic information,
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
John Odling-Smee
and when the semantic information they carry is modified by
niche-constructing organisms. This point is complex and requires elaboration.
Previously, in our formal models of niche construction
(Laland et al. 1996, 1999, 2001), the resource transmitted between generations by ecological inheritance was notated by R,
where R symbolized any environmental resource that could be
modified by niche construction. R could therefore be an abiotic environmental component, for example a soil state, or a
water hole. Or it could be an artefact built by an organism,
for example, a termite nest, or a beaver dam. Or it could be
a biotic environmental component, for example another organism, from either the same or a different population as the
niche-constructing organism itself. All these initial models
were kept as simple as possible, partly by restricting R to energy and matter resources only. That restriction, however, is
neither necessary nor, in the longer term, desirable. Eventually, it is likely to be useful to distinguish between physical
resources, Rp , and informational resources, Ri .
Many other organisms in the environments of nicheconstructing organisms are likely to contain both Rp and
Ri resources relative to the adaptations of the focal organisms. Moreover, both the Rp and Ri contained by other organisms may be altered, or exploited, or defended against
by niche-constructing organisms. For instance, another organism may simply act as a physical resource, Rp , say a food
item, for a niche-constructing organism. Alternatively, a nicheconstructing organism may “manipulate” (e.g., the brood parasitism of cuckoos; Davies et al. 1998; Combes 2001) or more
or less efficiently “copy” (e.g., social learning in animals; Fragaszy and Perry 2003) the semantic information, Ri , carried
in either the genome or the brain of some other organism,
via some kind of communication. Similarly a parasite, say, a
virus, may insert its own parasite DNA into its host’s DNA
and by doing so manipulate the physiology or the behavior of
its host (Combes 2001). When this happens, the parasite does
not immediately gain any physical resource or Rp by its niche
construction. What it gains in the first instance is a degree of
control over its host’s phenotype by corrupting the semantic
information, Ri , in its host’s genome or brain. Subsequently,
the parasite may gain Rp as well by causing its host to supply
it with a physical resource. For instance, a gall produced by
a plant benefits the parasite, at some cost to its host (Combes
2001; West-Eberhard 2003).
Benign forms of communication are also possible, and in
many animals they are common. For example, it may “pay” a
parent animal to transmit some of the information it carries in
its brain to its offspring via social learning. It may also pay an
offspring to solicit and “copy” information held in the brains
of its parents, or its peers, or of other organisms in its social
group (Fragaszy and Perry 2003; Reader and Laland 2003;
Odling-Smee 2006).
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
It follows that when the source of a natural selection pressure comprises other organisms in the external environments
of niche-constructing organisms, the niche-constructing organisms can potentially modify either the Rp or the Ri that is
carried by other organisms, or both. Rp can be modified by the
conventional kinds of niche construction we have previously
modeled (Odling-Smee et al. 2003). Ri, however, is invariably
modified by some kind of between-organism communication,
henceforth “communicative niche construction.”
Unlike conventional niche construction, communicative
niche construction cannot modify a natural selection pressure
directly. It can only modify natural selection indirectly, in two
steps instead of one. The first step involves communicative
niche construction causing a change in the semantic information, Ri, carried either by the niche-constructing organisms
themselves, for instance by the niche-constructing organisms
copying some of the information carried by other organisms,
or by the niche-constructing organisms changing the semantic
information carried by other organisms. For instance, nicheconstructing organisms may corrupt the semantic information
carried by other organisms, as in the virus example. None
of this is sufficient to modify any selection pressure in any
organism’s environment.
A second step is also necessary as a consequence of the
first. If communicative niche construction modifies the semantic information, Ri, carried by either the niche-constructing
organisms or by the other organisms, and if the modified semantic information subsequently translates into a change of
phenotypic or extended phenotypic expression, including the
expression of different niche-constructing activities in any of
these organisms, then the resulting physical change in Rp
could eventually be sufficient to modify a natural selection
pressure in the environments of either the niche-constructing
organisms, or of the other organisms, or both. For example,
animals frequently change the behaviors of other animals in
their own or other species by communicating with them, for
instance, by giving alarm calls to conspecifics, or by sending “stotting” signals to “would-be” predators. Animals can
therefore modify biotic sources of natural selection in their
environments by communication (Maynard Smith and Harper
2003).
The same logic distinguishes between different kinds
of coevolution. If other organisms are utilized by nicheconstructing organisms exclusively as Rp, for instance food,
as in standard models of predator-prey coevolution, then the
two coevolving populations are likely to influence each others’ phenotypes directly, and their genes indirectly. However,
if other organisms are used by niche-constructing organisms
primarily as Ri, as often happens in host-parasite coevolution,
then a niche-constructing population may first influence the
genetics, or possibly the brains of the other organisms, and
then their expressed phenotypes. For example, in host-parasite
283
Niche Inheritance: A Possible Basis for Classifying Multiple Inheritance Systems in Evolution
Table 1. The components of niche inheritance.
Transmission
Channel
What is
transmitted
Type of inheritance
system
Processes affected by the
inheritance system
Channel 1
InternaI Environment
Semantic information
(1a) Genetic inheritance
Epigenetic inheritance
(e.g.) Chromatin marks
Methylation patterns
RNAi
Maternal effects
(1b)
(e.g.) Cytoplasmic inheritance
Other maternal effects
(2a) Inheritance of modified selective environments
(e.g.) Behavioral traditions
Communication systems
(2b) Inheritance of modified selective environments
(e.g.) Physically perturbed environments
Development/Welsmann/Evolution barrier
Energy/matter
Channel 2
ExternaI Environment
Semantic information
Energy/matter
coevolution, a parasite may change the semantic information
carried by its host directly, for instance, by inserting its DNA
in its host’s DNA. That may then alter its host’s subsequent
behavior (Combes 2001).
Classifying Inheritance Systems in Evolution
Equipped with these two dimensions of niche inheritance, internal versus external transmission channels, and heritable semantic information versus heritable physical resources, can the
concept of niche inheritance be used to classify multiple inheritance systems in evolution? Table 1 is an attempt to provide a
positive answer to this question.
Several authors have reviewed the plural inheritance systems that are now being proposed as evolutionarily significant
(e.g., West-Eberhard 2003; Jablonka and Lamb 2005). The
scheme I will use here is Jablonka and Lamb’s (J&L’s) set of
four inheritance systems, (1) genetic, (2) epigenetic, (3) behavioural, and (4) symbolic. The advantage of their scheme is
that it is sufficiently broad to subsume all kinds of non-genetic
as well as genetic inheritance systems in evolution. Table 1
classifies the first three of J&L’s systems. Their fourth system,
human symbolic inheritance, is discussed in a later section.
Table 1 uses both the two transmission channels, the internal versus the external environment, and the two principal
components of niche inheritance, semantic information versus
energy and matter, to generate a 2 × 2 table, with four cells, 1a,
1b, 2a and 2b. Each tabular cell (differentiated from biological
cells) is then assigned the type(s) of inheritance proposed to
belong to it. Some illustrative examples of non-genetic inheritance are also given in each cell.
Many of these assignments are straightforward. For example, if naturally selected genes encode semantic information
(Maynard Smith 2000; Odling-Smee et al. 2003), then genetic inheritance indisputably belongs to Cell 1a. Given that
284
Development → Evolution sometimes
Development → Evolution sometimes?
Development → Evolution
Development → Evolution
J&L (2005: 147) define epigenetic inheritance as the “transfer of information from cell to cell,” even though it might be
possible to define epigenetic inheritance more broadly, under their definition, epigenetic inheritance clearly belongs to
Cell 1a too. Examplar phenomena discussed by J&L under
the heading of epigenetic inheritance are also shown in Cell
1a. They include chromatin markings, methylation patterns,
RNAi (interference), and some maternal effects, for example
the inheritance of maternal mRNA (Davidson 2006).
Cell 1b includes cytoplasmic inheritance, and some other
physical resources that are transmitted by mothers to their
offspring during reproduction, primarily via eggs. These resources include proteins, and components of membranes
(Davidson 2006).
Cell 2a refers to J&L’s third inheritance system, behavioral
traditions, primarily in animals, and to the communication of
semantic information between animals through social learning (Fragaszy and Perry 2003). Since behavior is expressed in
external environments, the phenomena in Cell 2a frequently
involve both niche construction and ecological inheritance,
the latter in the form of modified natural selection pressures
in the external environments of descendent organisms. J&L
emphasize this themselves in their book (p. 236). Cell 2a also
includes one kind of niche construction (not shown), described
by Sterelny (2003: 153) as “epistemic engineering.” Epistemic
engineering refers to changes in “the informational character
of the next generation’s environment” caused by the nicheconstructing activities of prior generations. Sterelny is primarily referring to human epistemic engineering, but it occurs in
other animals too. Candidate examples include mammalian
scent marks and insect pheromone trails.
Cell 2b refers to more conventional kinds of ecological
inheritance, namely to the modification of natural selection
pressures in environments by niche construction by physical
perturbation or physical relocation (Odling-Smee et al. 2003).
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
John Odling-Smee
Table 1 demonstrates that it is not always easy to allocate
candidate non-genetic inheritance systems to single Cells. This
suggests there is either something wrong with Table 1, or that
some putative non-genetic inheritance systems may actually
include more than one kind of inheritance. A good example is
the inheritance of maternal effects. Mousseau (2006: 19) points
out that maternal effects are defined in a variety of ways, and
he himself defines them broadly as “all sources of offspring
phenotypic variance due to mothers above and beyond the
genes that she herself contributes.” Depending on how they are
defined, maternal effects, and possibly some paternal effects
too, could be assigned to all the cells in Table 1.
One particularly awkward example concerns the inheritance of bacterial communities from mothers. Gut bacteria
are critical for mammalian development (Hooper et al. 2001;
Xu and Gordon 2003), because bacteria induce gene expression in intestinal epithelia, the genes subsequently activating
pathways that allow intestinal capillaries to form and permit
lipids to be transported through the cells (Hooper et al. 2001;
Stappenbeck et al. 2002). Humans inherit their gut microbial
communities from their mothers’ vagina and the faeces at birth
(Ley et al. 2006). It might therefore seem natural to assign this
inheritance to reproduction and to Channel 1 in Table 1. However, bacteria are separate organisms from both human infants
and their mothers, so mothers are probably better described
as external environments for both the bacteria and their own
foetuses. If so, bacterial inheritance must be transmitted via
Channel 2, not Channel 1. This raises a further problem. In
mammals, bacteria potentially provide both a Ri and a Rp. Insofar as the development of a mammal’s gut depends on gene
expression regulated by bacterial genes, bacterial inheritance
belongs to Cell 2a. However, insofar as bacterial inheritance
aids subsequent mammalian digestive processes, it belongs to
Cell 2b.
The DevoEvo Consequences of Niche Inheritance
The final column on the right of Table 1 concerns whether any
of the component inheritance systems shown in the body of
the table might change our understanding of the relationship
between developmental biology (Devo), and evolutionary biology (Evo) in the EvoDevo relationship. One question that
has never gone away is whether any of the acquired characteristics, or any of the activities expressed by the phenotypes
of developing organisms during their lives, can subsequently
affect the evolution of their descendents in innovative or adaptive ways (Schlichting and Pigliucci 1998; Oyama et al. 2001;
West-Eberhard 2003; Pigliucci and Preston 2004; Jablonka
and Lamb 2005).
Niche inheritance is immediately followed by niche regulation. Niche regulation involves phenotypically plastic, nicheconstructing organisms, interacting with their local environBiological Theory 2(3) 2007
ments, in developmental [OE] niche relationships, throughout
their lives, on behalf of their fitness needs. Successful niche
regulation eventually leads to surviving and reproducing “fit”
organisms bequeathing niche inheritances in their turn to the
next generation. Niche regulation is provisionally described by
both Developmental Systems Theory (Oyama et al. 2001) and
the theory of phenotypic plasticity (Schlichting and Pigliucci
1998; Gilbert 2001; Pigliucci and Preston 2004). The question is whether any of the component inheritance systems in
niche inheritance can carry any kind of “acquired” variations
from parent organisms to their offspring, as a consequence
of the niche-regulating interactions of parent organisms with
their environments. (The arrows in the final column of Table
1 indicate candidate DevoEvo connections.) Let us consider
each of the inheritance systems in cells 1a, 1b, 2a and 2b in
turn.
According to SET, the first entry, genetic inheritance (Cell
1a), affects the development of individual organisms, but everything else that happens to, or is caused by the developing
phenotypes themselves during their development is evolutionarily irrelevant. This is because there is no capacity for soma
to translate back into DNA. That version of Lamarckism is
untrue (Jablonka and Lamb 2005). All that counts is the transmission of genes by “fit” organisms to the next generation. No
other connections between “Devo” and “Evo” are recognized
by SET. This point is symbolized by the two slashed lines in
Table 1. Amundson (2005) has shown how this disconnection
has historically been attributed to a series of putative “barriers”
between “Devo” and “Evo.” The best known barrier is the one
shown in Table 1, “Weismann’s,” derived from the early segregation of germ line from somatic cells during development
(see also Maynard Smith 2000).
Such disconnection between Devo and Evo is now thought
too severe, particularly by developmental biologists, and it is
being challenged by the non-genetic inheritance systems in
Table 1 (West- Eberhard 2003; Jablonka and Lamb 2005). The
second entry in Table 1, epigenetic inheritance, provides one
example. The notion that epigenetic variation, as well as genetic variation (Cell 1a), can be transmitted across generations
was controversial for decades, but there has recently been an
accumulation of empirical support for the idea (Bird 2002,
2007; Jablonka and Lamb 2005; Reik 2007). For instance, the
peloric form of the toadflax Linaria is caused by an epigenetically inherited methylation pattern, yet this phenotype has
been stably inherited for over 200 years (Jablonka and Lamb
2005; Bird 2007). Methylation differences in the gene for the
glucocorticoid receptor are apparently also transmitted from
generation to generation in rats. Methylation differences appear to be responsible for different abilities in rats to handle
stress (Weaver et al. 2004), enabling the gene to be transcribed
in the brains of some rats, where the gene is unmethylated, but
not in others.
285
Niche Inheritance: A Possible Basis for Classifying Multiple Inheritance Systems in Evolution
Provisional evidence also exists for some evolutionary
consequences of cytoplasmic inheritance and the inheritance
of some maternal effects. In the past, prominent evolutionary
biologists such as Morgan and Dobzhansky rejected cytoplasmic inheritance as being of any importance in evolution
(Amundson 2005). However, it is now established that a
mother’s experience of her environment sometimes leads to
variations in her growth, condition, and physiological state
that are subsequently transmitted to her offspring via cytoplasmic factors (e.g., via yolk amount or hormones (Mousseau
and Fox 1998a, 1998b). More generally, Mousseau (2006) has
summarized how and when transmitted maternal effects can
have evolutionary as well as developmental consequences.
All the remaining inheritance systems in Cells 2a and
2b in Table 1 depend on niche construction. Elsewhere, we
have shown, with examples, that: (1) Niche construction is expressed by individual organisms throughout their lives, and is
therefore itself a developmental process. (2) Niche construction can have subsequent evolutionary as well as developmental consequences. (3) Niche construction does have evolutionary consequences whenever prior niche construction causes the
subsequent modification of one or more natural selection pressures in the environments of populations, if the environmental
modification is sustained for sufficient generations (OdlingSmee et al. 2003; Laland and Sterelny 2006).
In this respect, there is a further general point. Table 1 introduces a second channel (Channel 2) via which the ecological
components of niche inheritance are transmitted. But Channel
2 is not affected by any of the “barriers” that apply to Channel 1. For example, there is nothing equivalent to Weismann’s
barrier in an external environment. Potentially, this point has
considerable consequences for the DevoEvo relationship. Insofar as (1) any of the inheritance systems in Table 1 affects
phenotypic variance and plasticity during development; (2)
any form of phenotypic variance and plasticity translates into
niche construction; and (3) the expressed niche construction
subsequently modifies one or more natural selection pressures
in the environments of later generations of a population via
Channel 2, then all the inheritance systems in Table 1 could
contribute to the evolution of populations, as well as to the
development of individual organisms.
Human Cultural Inheritance
J&L’s fourth system is human symbolic inheritance. Human
evolution depends on cultural inheritance as well as all the
other inheritance systems in Table 1, and the transmission of
cultural inheritance depends, to a considerable degree, on symbols and language (Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman 1981; Durham
1991; Deacon 1997; Richerson and Boyd 2005).
Human cultural inheritance has previously been modeled
in diverse ways by a variety of theories (Laland and Brown
286
2002). None is fully compatible with Table 1. For example,
one early approach, classical sociobiology (Wilson 1975), is
firmly based on SET. Accordingly, it assumes that the only
inheritance system in evolution is genetic inheritance. Hence
for sociobiology, the only way any culturally inherited trait can
affect human evolution is by biasing the contributions made
by culturally variant humans to genetic inheritance.
An alternative approach, advocated by gene-culture coevolutionary theorists, does recognize that cultural inheritance
can play a more significant role in human evolution (CavalliSforza and Feldman 1981; Boyd and Richerson 1985; Durham
1991; Richerson and Boyd 2005). This approach demonstrates
that inherited cultural behaviors, for example the dairy farming
of pastoralists (Enattah et al. 2002), can sometimes transform
human selective environments in ways that do select for different human genes. That led to “dual inheritance” models
of human evolution incorporating both genetic and cultural
inheritance. Laland et al. (2000, 2001) subsequently added
both cultural niche construction and ecological inheritance to
these dual inheritance models, thereby generating a “triple inheritance” model of human evolution incorporating genetic,
cultural, and ecological inheritance systems. But triple inheritance is also incompatible with Table 1, because it proposes
three instead of two transmission channels. However, because
it includes ecological inheritance, it does suggest a possible
further model that is compatible.
Originally, Laland et al. (2000) proposed three separate
inheritance systems in human evolution, only because the same
authors had previously modeled ecological inheritance exclusively in terms of Rp. Since human cultural inheritance is
primarily concerned with the transmission of semantic information in the form of cultural “knowledge,” it is obviously
not compatible with such an over-restricted version of ecological inheritance. It was for this reason that we previously
assigned human cultural inheritance a separate status. However, if ecological inheritance includes both Rp and Ri, as I
have been arguing here, then a separate status for cultural inheritance is not necesary. Instead, it becomes possible to treat
both the inheritance of cultural knowledge and the inheritance
of material culture as just different cultural components of an
inclusive human ecological inheritance system.
Doing so reduces Laland et al.’s triple inheritance model
to the new dual inheritance model of human gene-culture coevolution in Figure 2. Figure 2 is fully compatible with both
Figure 1b and Table 1. It indicates that both semantic information, inclusive of human cultural knowledge, and physical
resources, inclusive of human material culture, can be transmitted between generations by both Channels 1 and 2. Figure 2
therefore suggests that even though human cultural inheritance
is exceptionally interesting, because human knowledge can
generate exceptionally potent kinds of cultural niche construction in both human “epistemic engineering” (Sterelny 2003;
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
John Odling-Smee
Niche construction
t+1
Et+1
Natural selection
CHANNEL 2
Development
and maternal inheritance
Including “cultural knowledge ”
and material culture
Ecological inheritance
Next generation
t
Gene
pool
Genetic, epigenetic
Et
Culture
Populations
of diverse
humans
CHANNEL 1
Niche construction
Gene
pool
Natural selection
Development
Culture
Populations
of diverse
humans
Figure 2.
Dual inheritance in human gene-culture co-evolution via Channel 1 and Channel 2.
Tomasello et al. 2005) and human “ecosystem engineering”
(Boogert et al. 2006), it is not a special case requiring a separate
status. On the contrary, human cultural inheritance is just another component of human ecological inheritance. Like all the
other components of niche inheritance, it belongs in Table 1.
Conclusion
This still leaves some issues outstanding. I will signpost two
of them, but will make no attempt to do more here.
One issue concerns the relationship between informational resources (Ri ) and energy and matter resources (Rp )
again. It is a very difficult relationship to work out, partly
because relativistic systems are always difficult, and partly
because even though semantic information is always carried
by some kind of physical carrier, semantic information on the
one hand, versus energy and matter resources on the other, superficially appear to obey different thermodynamic rules. As
Sterelny (2003: 153) put it, “Information is unlike meat. After
passing on to you my stone-working technique I still have it.”
The true relationship between information versus energy
and matter is an ongoing problem for physicists and biologists
(Bekenstein 2003; Bergstrom and Lachmann 2004), and it is
unlikely to be resolved soon.
A second issue concerns fitness. In one respect, there is
no change. Niches are defined by their organisms, so it makes
little difference whether fitness is assigned to organisms, or to
their interactive niche relationships. Fitness is a relative concept anyway. But in a second respect, there may be a difference. Conventionally, fitness is measured by the contributions
organisms make to genetic inheritance only. So conventionally, there is only one “currency” in evolution, genetic fitness.
Niche inheritance, however, suggests that all the other inheritance systems in Table 1 may contribute to the fitness of
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
organisms too, and they may introduce other fitness currencies, for instance ecological or “economic” currencies, that
are not readily convertible to the base evolutionary currency
of genetic fitness.
A simple example is the selection of mates by females
in animal species. Females are usually expected to choose
males that signal they carry “fit” genes by advertising their
health, or their capacity to support a “handicap” (Zahavi 1975).
However, if an experimenter were to arrange a choice between
a genetic “wimp” (poor Ri resources), artificially assigned
control over extremely rich physical (Rp) resources, versus
a genetic “Adonis” (good Ri resources), artificially assigned
extremely poor (Rp) resources, who would she choose? The
answer is by no means a foregone conclusion. (Charmantier
and Sheldon 2006).
A more complicated example arises from the tensions that
exist between genetic and cultural processes in human geneculture coevolution (Figure 2). Cultural niche construction is
not always adaptive (Laland, et al. 2001). The Fore’s cannibalism, for instance, increased their vulnerability to kuru disease
(Durham 1991). Similarly, both the Easter Island and Greenland Norse communities probably contributed to their own
downfall through culturally “acquired,” maladaptive, “nichedestructing” practices (Diamond 2005).
This raises a novel question. Do humans inherit two kinds
of semantic information carrying different, and sometimes incompatible “meanings? “Cultural meaning” is the apparent
product of cultural selection and decision processes (CavalliSforza and Feldman 1981; Durham 1991; Richerson and Boyd
2005). “Genetic meaning” is established by natural selection.
Both kinds of “meaning” occur in the context of interactive
human niches, where both natural and cultural selection processes are constantly being modified by both cultural and noncultural human niche construction. Are they compatible? It is
287
Niche Inheritance: A Possible Basis for Classifying Multiple Inheritance Systems in Evolution
a question that goes beyond traditional nature versus nurture
type questions and it indicates another reason why a more
comprehensive approach to inheritance in evolution is probably necessary. The concept of niche inheritance could supply it.
Acknowledgment
I should like to thank Doug Erwin, Marc Feldman, Kevin Laland, Kim
Sterelny, Pete Richerson, and two anonymous referees for their valuable criticisms of an earlier draft of this paper.
References
Amundson R (2005) The Changing Role of the Embryo in Evolutionary
Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Balter M (2005) Are humans still evolving? Science 309: 234–237.
Bekenstein JD (2003) Information in the holographic universe. Scientific
American (August): 59–65.
Bergstrom CT, Lachmann M (2004) Shannon information and biological fitness. Information Theory Workshop. IEEE. 50–54.
Bird A (2002) DNA methylation patterns and epigenetic memory. Genes and
Development 16: 6–21.
Bird A (2007) Perceptions of epigenetics. Nature 447: 396–398.
Boni MF, Feldman MW (2005) Evolution of antibiotic resistance by human
and bacterial niche construction. Evolution 59: 477–491.
Boogert NJ, Paterson DM, Laland KN (2006) The implications of niche construction and ecosystem engineering for conservation biology. BioScience
56: 570–578.
Borenstein E, Kendal J, Feldman M (2006) Cultural niche construction in a
metapopulation. Theoretical Population Biology 14: 92–104.
Boyd R, Richerson PJ (1985) Culture and the Evolutionary Process. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Cavalli-Sforza LL, Feldman MW (1981) Cultural Transmission and Evolution:
A Quantitative Approach. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Charmantier A, Sheldon BC (2006) Testing genetic models of mate choice
evolution in the wild. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 21: 417–419.
Chase JM, Leibold MA (2003) Ecological Niches: Linking Classical and
Contemporary Approaches. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Combes C (2001) Parasitism: The Ecology and Evolution of Intimate Interactions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Davidson EH (2006) The Regulatory Genome: Gene Regulatory Networks in
Development and Evolution. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Davies NB, Kilner RM, Noble DG (1998) Nestling cuckoos, cuculus canorus,
exploit hosts with begging calls that mimic a brood. Proceedings of the
Royal Society London B 265: 673–678.
Dawkins R (1976) The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dawkins R (1982) The Extended Phenotype. Oxford: Freeman.
Dawkins R (2004) Extended phenotype–but not too extended. A reply to
Laland, Turner and Jablonka. Biology and Philosophy 19: 377–396.
Deacon TW (1997) The Symbolic Species: The Co-evolution of Language
and the Brain. New York: Norton.
Diamond J (2005) Collapse: How Societies Choose to Fail or Survive. London:
Penguin/Allen Lane.
Dietrich WE, Taylor Perron J (2006) The search for a topographic signature
of life. Nature 439: 411–418.
Donohue K (2005) Niche construction through phonological plasticity: Life
history dynamics and ecological consequences. New Phytologist 166: 83–
92.
Durham WH (1991) Coevolution: Genes, Culture and Human Diversity. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
288
Enattah NS, Sahi T, Savilhati E, Terwilliger JD, Peltonen L, Jarvela I (2002)
Identification of a variant associated with adult-type hypolactasia. Nature
Genetics 30: 233–237.
Feldman MW, Cavalli-Sforza LL (1989) On the theory of evolution under
genetic and cultural transmission, with application to the lactose absorption problem. In: Mathematical Evolutionary Theory (Feldman MW, ed).
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Flack JC, Girvan M, de Waal FBM, Krakauer DC (2006) Policing stabilizes
construction of social niches in primates. Nature 439: 426–429.
Fragaszy DM, Perry S (2003) The Biology of Traditions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Frederickson ME, Greene MJ, Gordon DM (2005) “Devil’s gardens” bedevilled by ants. Nature 437: 495–496.
Fry I (2000) The Emergence of Life on Earth: A Historical and Scientific
Overview. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Futuyma DJ (1998) Evolutionary biology. 3rd ed. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.
Gilbert SF (2001) Ecological developmental biology: Developmental biology
meets the real world. Developmental Biology 233: 1–12.
Gilbert SF (2004) Mechanisms for the environmental regulation of gene expression. Birth Defects Research (Part C) 72: 291–299.
Godfrey-Smith P (1996) Complexity and the Function of Mind in Nature.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hansell MH (2005) Animal Architecture. Oxford Animal Biology Series.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hanski I, Singer MC (2001) Extinction-colonization and host-plant choice in
butterfly metapopulations. American Naturalist 158: 341–353.
Holt RD (2005) On the integration of community ecology and evolutionary
biology: Historical perspectives, and current prospects. In: Ecological
Paradigms Lost: Routes of Theory Change (Cuddington K, Beisner B,
eds), 235–271. New York: Academic Press.
Hooper LV, Wong MH, Thelin A, Hansson L, Falk PG, Gordon JI (2001)
Molecular analysis of commensal host-microbial relationships in the intestine. Science 291: 881–884.
Hui C, Li Z, Yu D (2004) Metapopulation dynamics and distribution and
environmental heterogeneity induced by niche construction. Ecological
Modelling 177: 107–118.
Ihara Y, Feldman MW (2004) Cultural niche construction and the evolution
of small family size. Theoretical Population Biology 65: 105–111.
Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (1995) Epigenetic Inheritance and Evolution. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2005) Evolution in Four Dimensions. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Jones CG, Lawton JH, Shachak M (1994) Organisms as ecosystem engineers.
Oikos 69: 373–386.
Jones CG, Lawton JH, eds (1995) Linking Species and Ecosystems. New
York: Chapman and Hall.
Jones CG, Lawton JH, Shachak M (1997) Positive and negative effects of
organisms as physical ecosystem engineers. Ecology 78: 1946–1957.
Kirkpatrick M, Lande R (1989) The evolution of maternal characters. Evolution 43: 485–503.
Laland KN, Brown GR (2002) Sense and Nonsense: Evolutionary Perspectives
on Human Behaviour. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Laland KN, Odling-Smee FJ, Feldman MW (1996) On the evolutionary
consequences of niche construction. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 9:
293–316.
Laland KN, Odling-Smee FJ, Feldman MW (1999) Evolutionary consequences of niche construction and their implications for ecology. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 96: 10242–10247.
Laland KN, Odling-Smee FJ, Feldman MW (2000) Niche construction, biological evolution, and cultural change. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23:
131–175.
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
John Odling-Smee
Laland KN, Odling-Smee FJ, Feldman MW (2001) Cultural niche construction
and human evolution. Evolutionary Biology 14: 22–23.
Laland KN, Sterelny K (2006) Seven reasons (not) to neglect niche construction. Evolution 60: 1751–1762.
Lewontin, RC (1982) Organism and environment. In: Learning, Development
and Culture (Plotkin HC, ed), 151–170. New York: Wiley.
Lewontin RC (1983) Gene, organism, and environment. In: Evolution from
Molecules to Men (Bendall DS, ed), 273–285. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lewontin R (2000) The Triple Helix: Gene, Organism, and Environment.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Ley RE, Peterson DA, Gordon JI (2006) Ecological and evolutionary forces
shaping microbial diversity in the human intestine. Cell 124: 837–848.
Mameli M (2004) Nongenetic selection and nongenetic inheritance. British
Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55: 35–71.
Maynard Smith J (2000) The concept of information in biology. Philosophy
of Science 67: 177–194.
Maynard Smith J, Harper D (2003) Animal Signals. Oxford Series in Ecology
and Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Meysman FJR, Middleburg JJ, Heip CHR (2006) Bioturbation: A fresh look
at Darwin’s last idea. Trends in Ecology abd Evolution 21: 688–695.
Morgan TH (1919) The Physical Basis of Heredity. Philadelphia: Lippincott.
Mousseau TA (2006) Maternal effects. In: Evolutionary Genetics: Concepts
and Case Studies (Fox W, Wolf JB, eds), 19–21. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Mousseau TA, Fox CW, eds (1998a) Maternal Effects as Adaptations. Oxford
University Press.
Mousseau TA, Fox CW (1998b) The adaptive significance of maternal effects:
Moms do more than make babies. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 13:
403–406.
Odling-Smee FJ (1983) Multiple levels in evolution: An approach to the
nature-nurture issue via applied epistemology. In: Animal Models of Human Behaviour (Davey G, ed), 135–158. Chichester: Wiley.
Odling-Smee FJ (1988) Niche constructing phenotypes. In: The Role of Behavior in Evolution (Plotkin HC, ed), 73–132. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Odling-Smee FJ (2006) How niche construction contributes to human geneculture coevolution. In: Social Information Transmission and Human Biology (Wells JCK, Strickland S, Laland K, eds), 39–57. Boca Raton, FL:
Taylor and Francis.
Odling-Smee FJ, Laland KN, Feldman MW (1996) Niche construction. American Naturalist 147: 641–648.
Odling-Smee FJ, Laland KN, Feldman MW (2003) Niche Construction: The
Neglected Process in Evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
O’Neill RV, DeAngelis DL, Waide JB, Allen TFH (1986) A Hierarchical
Concept of Ecosystems. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Oyama S, Griffiths PE, Gray RD, eds (2001) Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Pigliucci M, Preston K, eds (2004) Phenotypic Integration: Studying the Ecology and Evolution of Complex Phenotypes. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Reader SM, Laland KN (2003) Animal Innovation. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Biological Theory 2(3) 2007
Reik W (2007) Stability and flexibility of epigenetic gene regulation in mammalian development. Nature 447: 425–432.
Richerson PJ, Boyd R (2005) Not By Genes Alone: How Culture Transformed
Human Evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Sapp J (1987) Beyond the Gene: Cytoplasmic Inheritance and the Struggle
for Authority in Genetics. New York: Oxford University Press.
Schlichting CD, Pigliucci M (1998) Phenotypic Evolution: A Reaction Norm
Perspective. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.
Schwilk DW (2003) Flammability is a niche construction trait: Canopy architecture affects fire intensity. American Naturalist 162: 725–733.
Silver M, Di Paolo E (2006) Spatial effects favour the evolution of niche
construction. Theoretical Population Biology 70: 387–400.
Smith BD (2007) The ultimate ecosystem engineers. Science 315: 1797–
1798.
Stappenbeck TS, Hooper LV, Gordon JI (2002) Developmental regulation of
intestinal angiogenesis by indigenous microbes via Paneth cells. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 99: 15451–15455.
Sterelny K (2001) Niche construction, developmental systems, and the extended replicator. In: Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and
Evolution (Oyama S, Griffiths PE, Gray RD, eds), 333–349. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Sterelny K (2003) Thought in a Hostile World: The Evolution of Human
Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.
Sterelny K (2005) Made by each other: Organisms and their environment.
Biology and Philosophy 20: 21–36.
Tomasello M, Carpenter M, Call J, Behne T, Moll H (2005) Understanding
and sharing intentions: The origins of cultural cognition. Behavioral and
Brain Sciences 28: 675–735.
Thompson JN (1994) The Coevolutionary Process. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Turner JS (2000) The Extended Organism: The Physiology of Animal-built
Structures. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Waddington CH (1969) Paradigm for an evolutionary process. In: Towards
a Theoretical Biology (Waddington CH, ed), Vol. 2: Sketches, 106–128.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Weaver CG, Cervoni N, Champagne FA, D’Alessio AC, Sharma S, Seckl
JR, Dymov S, Szyf M, Meany MJ (2004) Epigenetic programming by
maternal behavior. Nature Neuroscience 7: 847–854.
West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental Plasticity and Evolution. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Williams GC (1992) Gaia, nature worship, and biocentric fallacies. Quarterly
Review of Biology 67: 479–486.
Wilson EO (1975) Sociobiology: The New synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Wolf JB (2000) Indirect genetic effects and gene interactions. In: Epistasis
and the Evolutionary Process (Wolf JB, Brodie III, ED, Wade MJ, eds),
158–176. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wright JP, Jones CG (2006) The concept of organisms as ecosystem engineers
ten years on: Progress, limitations and challenges. BioScience 3: 203–209.
Xu J, Gordon JI (2003) Honor thy symbionts. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences USA 100: 10452–10459.
Zahavi A (1975) Mate selection: A selection for handicap. Journal of Theoretical Biology 53: 205–214.
289