Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Top Down or Bottom Up? The Spread of Systemic Corruption in the Third World Feisal Khan Department of Economics Hobart and William Smith Colleges Geneva, NY 14456 [email protected] Abstract: Recent pronouncements by the World Bank and the IMF have focussed new attention on systemic corruption in the Third World and its negative effect on economic development. The traditional approach to modelling corruption in the social sciences has been to see it as a classic principal-agent problem. While excellent for analyzing individual actions, the principal-agent approach cannot explain the spread of corruption when society is characterized by a norm of 'non-arm's-length' dealings, or how a superior's corruption affects subordinates' behavior, i.e., it cannot incorporate social interactions. This paper presents a threshold model of corruption that shows how, in economies characterized by relatively under-developed formal institutional checks and balances, 'non-arm's-length' dealings and leadership corruption can rapidly lead to systemic corruption. The model accommodates the differences seen in corruption levels in the Third World. Also addressed are some implications of this model for reforming systemically corrupt countries. The model can be readily adapted to other situations where the attitudes and inclinations of the leadership are important in determining the final outcome. December 2001 As this is a work-in-progress, any comments would be greatly appreciated. 1 All models are wrong but some are useful. George Box Introduction to the Problem1 In 1997 the fall of Mobutu Sese Seko, for thirty-two years the strongman of Zaire and the undisputed King of the Kleptocrats, served to underline the importance of corruption as a key explanatory factor in understanding why some Third World countries' track record on economic development has not been better. According to the Los Angeles Times, Zaire's already low per capita income of $213 in 1986 had fallen to $148 by the end of 1996. In contrast to the poverty of his country, Mobutu was estimated to have a personal fortune worth five billion dollars, the result of "ruthless repression and unbridled corruption." One estimate of the almost unimaginable level of official corruption in Zaire in the 1970s put the amount of the annual government operating budget that was "lost or diverted" at 60 percent (Callaghy 1984, 189). More recently, "presidential appropriations" from the national budget were conservatively estimated at a minimum of 15-20 percent annually. This figure, of course, excludes non-presidential "appropriations." One newspaper report has Mobutu telling a convention of Zairian public officials to steal but not too much, since then they would be punished. After thirty-two years of Mobutu, the people of Zaire, potentially among the richest countries in Sub-Saharan Africa, are among the poorest in Africa. With the economy near collapse and suffering from "endemic lawlessness and rampant corruption," and Mobutu ousted by a rebel movement, the Times went on to warn that "such chaos is hardly unique in Central Africa."2 The extent to which widespread and systematic governmental corruption had become a problem for economic development in the Third World, and for Western policy makers deciding on development assistance to it, was made apparent by the President of the World Bank, James Wolfensohn. At the 1996 annual meeting of the International Monetary Fund (IMF) and the World Bank, Wolfensohn stated that corruption was one of the greatest barriers to economic progress in developing nations and that the Bank would no longer view it with a Nelsonian eye. This statement was seconded by the Managing Director of the IMF, Michel Camdessus. The magnitude of the problem, and the limits to which the World Bank was willing to go to ameliorate the situation, was indicated by Wolfensohn’s statement that if "we [the Bank] find evidence of corruption we will cancel the project." (See the Los Angeles Times, 4 October 1996, for more details.) The corruption troubling the Bank and the Monetary Fund was what the coiner of the term "kleptocracy," Stanislav Andreski, defined as being indistinguishable from "venality." "Corruption," he wrote, "is... the practice of using the power of office for making private gains in breach of laws and regulations nominally in force" (Andreski 1968, 92, emphasis added). This definition nicely captures the full flavor of the problem since the "regulations nominally in force" may be observed only in the breach. There is considerable evidence to believe that high levels of corruption reduce both economic growth and reduce overall social welfare: in short, systemic corruption is (rightly) seen as an obstacle to overall economic and social development (Wei 1999, 1997; Ades and Di Tella 1996; Khan 1996; Mauro 1995; Alam1989; Myrdal [1968] 1989; Andreski 1968; among many others). As such, both the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund, among other international aid donors, are taking steps to combat it. I 1 I wish to thank Laurie Brand, Tim Cason, Nora Hamilton, Tolga Koker, Timur Kuran, Vai-Lam Mui, Murat Somer, and Jennifer Tessendorf for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. All deficiencies in the text are my sole responsibility. 2 Preceding data, unless otherwise cited, is from the Los Angeles Times, March 21, 1997, and May 17, 1997; see also other news reports from early 1997 for further details. See Callaghy (1984) or Gould (1980) for dated yet still comprehensive analyses of corruption in Zaire and Mbaku (1996), Fatton (1992), Ekpo (1979) for corruption in Africa in general. 2 This is in contrast to the earlier academic views of corruption being either relatively harmless (Leys [1965] 1989) or possibly even beneficial if it helps to overcome structural bottlenecks in the economy (Huntington 19793, 1968; Nye [1967] 1989; Leff [1964] 1989).4 Part of the reason for the change in how academics view corruption could be due to the realization of how easily petty, or even efficient, corruption could reach systemic levels in many, especially Third World, countries as the institutional structure decays over time (see, e.g., Shleifer and Vishny 1993) and how many bureaucrats deliberately increased the level of regulation complexity in order to increase their level of bribes (Kaufman and Wei 1999). While now recognizing the negative effects of corruption, the literature lacks a clear enunciation of a mechanism by which a government becomes systemically corrupt. In short, we do not have a clear enunciation of the process how an inefficient-predatory outcome could result. The literature also lacks a model that incorporates the effects of "non-arm's length transactions" being the dominant pattern in the economy. The objective of this paper is to lay out a simple and intuitively obvious threshold model that shows how a systemically corrupt system of government, i.e., a true kleptocracy, can come about in a society characterized by non-arm's length transactions. In addition, some implications of the model regarding the potential outcomes of reform efforts will also be considered. II The Basic Principal Agent Model of Corruption So why do bureaucrats and politicians become corrupt? Accept bribes? Sell off public property for personal gain? Or act in any of the myriad other ways that fall under the catch-all rubric of corruption? I contend that choosing corruption over honesty is the optimal choice for a boundedly rational utility maximizer if the benefits from being corrupt outweigh those from staying honest. Consider an individual, either a civil servant or a politician, faced with the choice of either behaving in a corrupt manner or not. The individual contemplating the corrupt act has to weigh the possible costs and benefits of his actions accruing to him. This is a very important point to keep in mind: the individual considers only his costs and benefits, not those of society. Following Becker's (1968) seminal work, the usual treatment of corruption in the social sciences has been to see it as a classic principal-agent (PA) problem (e.g., Bac 1996; Johnston 1996; Mookherjee and Png 1995; Huang and Wu 1994; Basu et al 1992; Chander and Wilde 1992; Kiser and Tong 1992; Klitgaard 1991b, 1988; Rose-Ackerman 1978; Banfield 1975; and many others). Some models of corruption combine aspects of a PA problem with game-theoretic approaches (e.g., Manion 1996; Besley and McLaren 1993; Rasmusen and Ramseyer 1993; and Macrae 1982), or with dynamic modelling approaches (e.g., Dawid and Feichtinger 1996; Bicchieri and Rovelli 1995; Feichtinger and Wirl 1994; Andvig and Moene 1990; Lui 1986), but "the standard institutional context is a two-person hierarchy consisting of a principal and an agent (Bac 1996, 277).5 In the PA approach to modelling corruption, the principal (the supervisor) employs an agent (the subordinate) to carry out some assigned task. The principal does not know whether or not the agent will perform the task satisfactorily--in this case the satisfactory performance of the task is that there is no corruption involved. Thus incomplete information on the principal's part about the agent's intentions may lead to suboptimal outcomes. In 3 Consider this succinct statement of the pro-corruption argument from Huntington (1979, 321), "In terms of economic growth the only thing worse than a society with a rigid, over centralized, dishonest bureaucracy is one with a rigid, over centralized, honest bureaucracy." 4 Andreski (1968) is an early exception to this. However, in all fairness to these authors, they were referring to individual corrupt acts and not to systemic corruption. Paddling against current research, Olsen and Torsvik (1998) argue that, under very specific circumstances, individual acts of corruption can lead to overall societal gain. However, this is again referring to individual, i.e., non-systemic, corruption. 5 Sometimes (e.g., Johnston 1996; Klitgaard 1991b) this is described as a principal-agent-client (PAC) problem to denote the fact that the principal (the department head) employs an agent (the individual bureaucrat) to deal with the client (the private individual). There is no significant difference between the PA and the PAC approach. 3 addition, the possibility of corruption may also lead to an adverse selection problem as corrupt agents apply for the government post. Principals may also be voters who elect a politician (their agent) to govern them. Accordingly, the principal may employ some other agents to monitor the first agent's work (e.g. external auditors or the General Accounting Office of the US government), but these may also turn out to be less-than-reliable.... The process of hiring workers to monitor other workers can go on, in theory at least, indefinitely. A possible solution to the problem outlined here is to give the external monitors an incentive contract to promote continued diligence, with severe penalty clauses in case of collusion with corrupt agents. However, this really does not solve the recursive failure problem since collusion between the corrupt agents and the external monitors is always possible (Besley and McLaren 1993; Basu et al 1992; Andvig and Moene 1990; Klitgaard 1988; Lui 1986; and many others). From the perspective of the original agent, the PA model gives a very straightforward analysis of the decision facing him. The potential payoff can be depicted using a standard economic expected utility model in which the individual weighs the benefit from corruption against the (net) benefit if he is caught. The expected utility (EU) to an individual of being corrupt is as follows: EUC = pBC + (1-p)BP where p is the probability of not being caught, BC is the utility from being corrupt, and BP is the (net) utility after being caught and punished. (1) I assume that BC is greater than BP, otherwise it would be irrational to be corrupt unless one knew that he would never be caught (i.e., p = 1). If BH is the utility from remaining honest (received with a probability of one), then the individual chooses corruption if his expected utility from that is greater than the utility from honesty: honest iff BH > EUC. Klitgaard (1988, 71) puts a slight twist in this standard model by incorporating "the moral satisfaction [the individual] takes from not being corrupt" into the individual's utility calculations.6 The inclusion of a moral element in the EU function is a notable refinement since individual utility in this context has at least two distinct components: that from material benefits and that from knowing that you have done the right thing. 7 This is very important since a major limitation of the standard PA model is that, although probabilities and payoffs may be the same, different individuals do not necessarily behave in an identical manner. While one will greedily accept the bribe, the other will refuse. Some attempts at modelling corruption using the PA form assume a uniform attitude to corruption in order to keep the model fairly tractable. For example, Mookherjee and Png (1996, 158) voiced a fairly common theme in the literature when they said that, "Our analysis implicitly assumed that all officials are equally prone to graft." Other authors realize the excessive oversimplification of this assumption since those officials that have an "ethical conception of public office and strong moral values may not even reach the point of making a cost-benefit comparison" (Berkman 1992, 1349). Besley and McLaren (1992, 122) also put great emphasis on the fact that "an honest person regards his integrity as priceless and thus will not take a bribe." So the explanation for why two individuals faced with exactly the same payoffs and punishments may act differently lies in the moral character of the two. We must distinguish between total utility and material utility. Individuals act to maximize their total utility, which includes both material utility and moral utility. Thus differences in how strongly moral beliefs are held affect 6 Andvig and Moene (1990, 65) agree that "moral costs" may be important to the corrupt agent but do not include a separate moral cost term in their model. 7 Klitgaard's (1988, 71) expected utility of corruption model is: EU = U[R(x) + p(x-f) +(1-p)x] where EU is the expected utility of corruption, x is the payoff from corruption, R(x) is the moral cost to the agent of corruption, p is the probability of being caught and punished, and f is the size of the penalty for corruption. If the utility from being honest is less than that from being corrupt, the agent will choose corruption. 4 the level of disutility (cognitive dissonance) from contravening them. That is why there is a distribution of corruption proclivity and why there will always be some (a very small) number of individuals that are absolutely incorruptible. Hence the observation of both Ostrom et al (1993, 148) and Klitgaard (1988, 52-55) that there do exist honest officials in completely (systemically) corrupt organizations.8 Since the prevalent morality in a systemically corrupt society is not conducive towards ethical behavior, most individuals, taking their behavioral cues from their superiors and peers, act accordingly.9 Indeed, Huther and Shah (2000) argue that in a systemically corrupt society, "anti-corruption agencies, ethics offices, and ombudsmen" simply serve to perpetuate the status-quo since they themselves have been completely corrupted. Klitgaard's model of expected utility from being corrupt can be modified, the notation made slightly simpler, and the moral element included, as follows: EUC Honesty payoff and pBC + (1-p)BP - MC (2) BH + MH (3) C P B > B MC < MH. EUC is the expected utility from corruption, p is the probability of not being caught and punished,10 BC is the material utility from being corrupt when C is the payoff from corruption, BP is the net material utility after being caught and punished for corruption when P is the punishment, MC is the moral cost of being corrupt, possibly the discomfort of having a guilty conscience, MC=0 is equal to MH, the moral benefit from honesty, which decreases in C,11 BH is the material utility from honesty when H is the payoff from honesty (i.e., wages). = = Naturally, the utility from corruption, BC, has to exceed the (net) utility from being caught and punished, BP. Furthermore, I assume that the moral satisfaction from honesty, MH, is greater than (i.e., worth more to the individual) the moral discomfort from being corrupt, MC.12 I argue that the value of MC, the moral cost of corruption, would be extremely important in determining the EU of corruption for any given individual. And it is also likely that different individuals would have different levels of moral disutility from corruption. There is no comprehensive explanation for why people have differing degrees of moral sentiments but, as stated earlier, there does seem to be some common basis for ethical behavior.13 8 Wilson (1993, 103) cites studies indicating that people who exhibited great moral courage (e.g., saving Jews from the concentration camps in WWII) had parents that stressed the importance of principled behavior and, for want of a better description, 'doing the right thing.' Similarly, Frank (1988, 248-253) underscored the importance of both parents and societal institutions in laying down the basic underlying foundations of adult moral behavior; Stretton and Orchard (1994, 174) concur. In any case, it is an indisputable fact that people have differing degrees of moral sentiments and that societal institutions pay a large role in determining what individuals will consider "acceptable" behavior (Wilson 1993, 46-48 & 121-122 and Frank 1988, 152). The exact process by which this is done is certainly deserving of study but it is beyond the purview of this work. 9 The preceding refers to the de facto morality, not the de jure one. For example, the news media in Pakistan is full of government exhortations to behave honestly, to act as a good Muslim should, to report the corrupt, and so on. However, these entreaties are so far removed from the reality of life in Pakistan that they might as well be in Greek for all the impact they have. 10 Subsumed within p is the probability that if he is caught, he can bribe his way out of punishment. 11 That is, there is a positive moral benefit to not taking a bribe; it decreases with the size of the bribe. I assume that C=0 means that the individual is acting honestly, not that he is acting corruptly without accepting a payoff. 12 Consider the case when the expected material utility from honesty is exactly the same as the expected material utility from corruption. It seems reasonable to assume that in this case most people would choose to behave honestly. Hence, MH, must be greater than MC. 13 Van Rijckeghem and Weder (1997) carried out a detailed econometric analysis of whether low wages in civil services caused corruption. Their results indicate that low wages are not a major source of corruption since the near eradication of corruption would require wages of anywhere between 2.81 to 7.08 times (depending upon the country) the manufacturing sector wage. The onus for the cause of corruption, again, falls back on personal morality and the prevailing institutional culture. 5 The individual will choose corruption if his expected utility from corruption (after accounting for a guilty conscience) is greater than his utility from honesty (after augmenting it for the moral satisfaction from not being corrupt). Changes in p, the probability of detection and punishment, ceteris paribus, will determine whether the individual will act corruptly. This is because, at the margin, the individual is indifferent between honesty and corruption, i.e., the total utility from honesty equals that from corruption, when: BH + MH = pBC + (1-p)BP - MC (4) Solving for p*, the value of p that equates both sides of the equation, gives us: p* = BH + MH - BP + MC BC - BP An analysis of the comparative statics of Equation 5 yields the following results: i) dp* = 1 ; dBH BC - BP ii) dp* dMH = 1 ; BC - BP iii) dp* dMC = 1 ; BC - BP iv) dp* dBP = BH + MH + MC - BC ; (BC - BP)2 v) dp* dBC = - (BH + MH + MC - BP); (BC - BP)2 (5) The comparative statics lead to some interesting conclusions.14 While these are not necessarily counter-intuitive, neither are they immediately obvious. In the first three results the size of the effect of a marginal change in any of the first three variables is dependent upon the value of (BC - BP), i.e., on the difference between the material utility from corruption and the (net) utility if one is corrupt and caught and punished. When looking at the remedies for corruption, a seemingly reasonable assumption would be that the effects on an individual's p* of changes in BH, MH, MC--the material and moral benefits from honest behavior and the moral cost of corruption--would be entirely separate from the benefits of corruption, BC, or his net utility if he is caught and punished, BP. The comparative statics of equation 5 show that this is not so. What the first three results tell us is of course intuitively obvious to all observers: in the absence of a strong punishment deterrence for corruption, moral and material costs and benefits become extremely important in determining when a hitherto honest official acts corruptly. The significance of marginal changes in BH, MH and MC come into their own only if the value of (BC - BP) is extremely low. However, a minimal value of (BC - BP) is not socially desirable since this would mean that the punishment for corruption is extremely light and, thus, probably has only a minimal deterrent effect. Maximizing the value of (BC - BP) would appear to indicate that punishment is more important than moral and material costs and benefits. This is not necessarily so since we do not know the actual values, in terms of utility, 14 The results here are qualitatively similar to Becker's (1968) seminal paper on the economic approach to crime, except that he did not include a moral cost term and was more explicitly concerned with the effects upon expected utility of marginal changes in his variables. Here I am more concerned with how the individual's corruption threshold is affected by marginal changes in other variables. 6 H H C H H C C P of B , M and M , or of their partials. Different values of the variables B , M , M , B and B would lead to differing answers as to which variable is more important. The fourth comparative static result, again, underlines the importance of strong punishment as a deterrent for corruption. The effect of changing the punishment, BP, is of course dependent upon the value of the expression (BH + MH + MC - BC) but the crucial factor here is the value of the term (BC - BP)2. The interpretation is that, if the punishment for corruption is already severe (i.e., BC - BP is large), then making punishment more severe will have a smaller effect than might otherwise be thought. This also indicates that there are declining marginal returns to progressive increases in the severity of punishment. The final comparative static result is the most interesting. Again, the key point here is the value of the term C P 2 (B - B ) . The counter-intuitive result here is that, as the benefit of corruption increases, the associated drop in p* is less than might be expected since an increase in the benefit of corruption also increases the value of (BC - BP)2, thereby reducing the overall size of the effect. This result is counter-intuitive in that we do not expect to see diminishing decreases in p* as the benefits of corruption increase. We expect to see the opposite.15 It can be safely assumed that most non-systemically corrupt governments would wish to raise p* to the highest level possible to ensure that hitherto honest officials would require an extremely high (perhaps near unity?) probability of not being caught before they would act corruptly.16 When corruption is punished relatively leniently, the role of non-punishment factors becomes more important. Making non-punishment factors more important would involve actions such as raising the material benefits of honesty (i.e., official salary) and raising the moral cost of corruption and the moral benefit of honesty. The former is a monetarily expensive proposition while the latter are likely to be expensive more in terms of time and official commitment than in money. As result five of the comparative statics shows, the most effective action would seem to be raising the corruption penalties. In any case, none of these remedies is necessarily cheap or easily implemented. Some of the most effective remedies (raising the moral cost of corruption) require the longest time to be effective and some of the easiest to implement (raising the penalties for corruption) may run into political complications (an unwilling legislature or strong civil service unions). Finally, higher penalties for corruption may have unforeseen consequences as increased penalties lead to higher bribes being demanded, which in turn may raise the benefits of corruption enough to tempt hitherto honest officials. III Moving Beyond the PA Model If we consider (1-p) to reflect the degree of honesty to be found in the sub-population that is government bureaucracies rather than in the population at large, then the probability of corruption being punished is likely to be quite high for any of the industrialized Western countries. Societal norms of honesty, the punishment for official corruption, the strength of the media and the independence of the judiciary are strong enough to ensure that the prevailing bureaucratic culture is predominantly honest. Corruption, while it certainly exists, is usually of the isolated variety and is often confined to a few minor departments or individuals. The PA model of corruption, extremely useful in looking at environments where most corruption is of the isolated kind, has some shortcomings that reduce its explanatory power when it comes to corruption in Third World 15 While the PA model is concerned with individual behavior, an extension to the behavior of the group is possible here. Ever increasing benefits from being corrupt will result in comparatively few hitherto honest individuals acting dishonestly since the majority of the officials will already be corrupt, i.e. their p* has already been reached. 16 There is certainly a cost-benefit tradeoff regarding monitoring and enforcement costs on the one hand and reduction in corruption on the other. Klitgaard (1988) has an extensive discussion of this issue. This aspect of the corruption issue is, however, beyond the scope of the model presented here. 7 economies. It lends valuable insight into the actions of any given actor but it cannot show--since it was never meant to--how corruption spreads or how the actions of one individual affect the actions of others.17 The dynamic corruption models mentioned earlier (Dawid and Feichtinger 1996; Feichtinger and Wirl 1994; Andvig and Moene 1990; Lui 1986) consider cases where the equilibrium changes from one of low corruption to one of high corruption or vice-versa (Bicchieri and Rovelli 1995). They also consider a situation exhibiting multiple equilibria with intermediate (but usually unstable) levels of corruption. However, their analysis does not look at the change in the behavior of individual agents. Furthermore, these dynamic models suffer from an additional drawback: they do not explicitly consider the effects of leadership behavior on subordinates. This drawback is one shared by other PA models as well, although Basu et al (1992, 354) do acknowledge the importance of leadership as the presence of an "incorruptible" elite civil service at the head of the government leads to the norm of honesty. Klitgaard (1988) and Rose-Ackerman (1978, especially Ch. 9) have the only extensive discussion of the effects of a supervisor's corruption proclivities on the behavior of subordinates but these do not incorporate threshold effects in their analysis. Several of the PA models (including the game-theoretic ones and the dynamic ones) incorporate various forms of threshold effects but of a type somewhat different from the ones in this paper. Some PA models incorporate greater degrees of institutional refinement and realism than others. For example, Basu et al (1992) and Andvig and Moene (1990) model the possibility of recursive corruption--the official who catches the corrupt official may himself be bribable. Dawid and Feichtinger (1996) incorporate the corrupt official's desire to maintain a "good" reputation in their model. Tirole (1996) allows for the fact that a group's reputation for corruption may affect how individual members choose to behave. However, what the literature lacks is a model of how a superior's corrupt behavior affects that of the whole organization and of how the behavior of individual agents change over time. Why is leadership behavior important? In the real world, who is already corrupt will greatly affect the decision of the other administrators as to whether or not they will opt for honesty or corruption. Assume, for the sake of argument, that 10% of the population is corrupt. If this is the bottom 10%, the 1st decile, in terms of power or influence in society, then this corrupt element is not going to influence significantly large proportions of society since this is not the reference group on which people are going to pattern their behavior. However, if this is the top 10% of the population, the 10th decile, in terms of power or influence in society and they are seen to escape punishment, this will obviously affect large portions of society since many people, at least the next 20 to 30% of society, will use the top 10% as its reference group. This is a weakness of the PA model since it cannot accommodate disproportionate changes of this sort. From the PA perspective, marginal changes in p give only marginal changes in outcome. In another context, the dynamics of revolutions, Kuran (1989, 46) shows the importance of an asymmetric demonstration effect on individuals and how it can change the situation drastically.18 Similarly, even if individuals are personally disinclined either to be corrupt or, ceteris paribus, to facilitate corrupt behavior in others, they may well be forced to act corruptly. In addition, honest individuals may also face persecution by their corrupt colleagues. If their superiors are corrupt, then non-corrupt individuals may be ordered to facilitate corruption in others. Not complying with a superior’s request may damage their own careers. It is also possible that after being forced to act corruptly on the behalf of others, the hitherto uncorrupt individual may decide to act corruptly on his own behalf. In the land of the blind the one-eyed man may be king; in the land of the corrupt, the honest man is often perceived as merely stupid for not taking advantage of the available opportunities--even if he may be a highly moral person attempting to set an example for his fellow citizens. What is needed is a model that can offer some understanding of how systemic corruption occurs within a society. The level of corruption within a society is usually endogenous to it and thus a model that helps in better understanding this process is needed. Observers of Third World societies will attest to the fact that the situation vis-a-vis corruption can change for the worse in the space of a few years. For instance, both 17 The absence of social linkages in the standard PA model led Tanzi (1995, 167) to assert that the Beckerian model is "of limited applicability" to much of the Third World. This is probably too strong a statement to put forth but it does bring up the crucial weakness of these type of models. 18 See Section V in this work for a more complete exposition of this. 8 Theobald (1990) and Klitgaard (1988) detail how rapidly, within a generation, systemic corruption replaced isolated corruption in Nigeria and the Phillippines, respectively. As stated before, there are two possible time paths for a transition to systemic corruption: relatively rapid and comparatively slow. A rapid transformation of the societal norm from isolated corruption (with the isolated incident of high-level corruption) to systemic corruption lies at the crux of my argument that the transmission mechanism must be from the top-down. The alternative time path is the comparatively slow one when an entire society's norm gradually changes from one of honesty to one of corruption. Thus, in the normal course of events, a completely corrupt leadership would arise "naturally." However, when the transformation takes place within the space of a few years, there must be some sort of a catalyst at work. This catalyst is, perforce, the inclination of the leadership. So how, exactly, would these two mechanisms work? IV A Threshold Model of Corruption A heuristically richer model can be built by allowing the criteria for choosing corruption or honesty to be endogenous to that society. It is obvious that a better approximation of reality would be to have the level of corruption in a society determined by interactions among the preferences of the individual actors themselves. What is needed here is a threshold mechanism for changing the prevailing societal norm--honesty or corruption--within the model. Several of the dynamic PA models described earlier (Dawid and Feichtinger 1996; Bicchieri and Rovelli 1995; Feichtinger and Wirl 1994; Andvig and Moene 1990; Lui 1986) have such a mechanism but they do not consider the importance of the leadership in setting the norm of the institutional culture. The PA model of corruption gives us, for every individual in any given population, the value of p--the probability that he will not be caught if he behaves corruptly--at which he is indifferent between honesty or corruption. In the same way, the threshold values of p of the entire population can be arranged in ascending order. It is not necessary to know the threshold of every individual in this society. It is enough for our purposes to know that (i) every individual has a threshold and (ii) that they are distributed across a range of zero to one. This allows the use of the important insights gained from the principal-agent model--the concept of an individual's p*--and endogenize the incentives faced by each individual actor. Once this is done, a more realistic model of corruption, one that incorporates the importance of social linkages, can be developed.19 Threshold models, also known as bandwagon-effect models, critical-mass models, tipping models, and cascade models, have a long history in the social sciences. Granovetter's (1978; 1973) and Schelling's (1978) works are classics in this area and, arguably, the inspiration for an entire generation of models that show how seemingly "minor" factors can result in "major" results. For example, Schelling (1978) analyzed how separate individual decisions determined societal outcomes and could lead to overall inefficiencies. Some of the more recent contributions to the literature have been Hong and Conrad (1998), Corneo and Jeanne (1997), Kuran (1995), Bikchandani et al (1992), and Witt (1989). While the exact details of these models of social behavior differ, they are all similar to the threshold model detailed below. The threshold corruption model developed here draws heavily from Kuran's earlier works (1991; 1989; 1987) and, especially, on chapters three, four and six of his 1995 book, Private Truths, Public Lies: The Social Consequences of Preference Falsification. The work done here adapts and extends a great deal of his analytical framework, initially developed to explain "unexpected" revolutions such as the collapse of Communism in Eastern Europe, to corruption. 19 There is a problem here in that the assumption is that all people are corruptible. But what about the truly incorruptible ones? We know that there are at least some people that cannot be bought. The importance of personal morality can resolve this dilemma. Even if no one else can ever detect your corruption, you yourself know what you have done. Hence the corruption is, in a way, detected. Therefore, if your personal corruption p is one, this means that you will never be corrupt since your conscience will know what you have done. For a truly religious person, this knowledge might take the form that God will know your actions, even if no human does. 9 In general, the threshold corruption model developed here will use the same basic premise: seemingly minor changes in individual behavior lead through a cumulative causation mechanism to major changes in societal outcomes. Like other such models, the threshold corruption model will show just how the proverbial straw broke the camel's back. This model adds to the literature in both fields, corruption and threshold models, in several different ways. It extends the reach of threshold models to the analysis of societal corruption, a field where such models have been comparatively little used. In the threshold corruption model, the individual's decision whether or not to act corruptly is endogenized. That is, the incentives for the individual to act corruptly depend upon the societal value of p, the probability that corruption will not be detected and punished, and this value is now determined within the model itself. At the extremes, such incentives do not matter. People who are truly incorruptible or truly corrupt will behave predictably no matter what the incentives might be. However, the vast majority of the population will fall somewhere between these two extremes and for them the prevailing societal incentives--the value of p-- will determine their behavior. Furthermore, the threshold corruption model also accounts for the societal interaction aspect of corruption since it incorporates the cumulative effects of corrupt behavior by others into its analysis. Moreover, the threshold model will also show the asymmetric demonstration effect of leadership corruption on subordinates. Finally, the model will explicitly incorporate socio-cultural effects by showing how prevailing cultural norms that are conducive to corrupt behavior may reduce each individual's corruption threshold. Thus the threshold corruption model brings society and culture into the analysis since the actions of the individuals involved change the incentives they face and, hence, affect their future actions. In addition, the threshold corruption model will also illustrate the path-dependent nature of the transition to systemic corruption--it matters who acts corruptly and when. The model will also highlight the imperfect predictability aspect of the systemic corruption transition--ex ante, we cannot predict, since we lack perfect information and foresight, who will act corruptly and when. However, the model will allow us to predict, in general, under what circumstances we can expect to see an increase or a decrease in corruption. So what is the threshold corruption model? Assume for the sake of simplicity that the total population of a society consists of 10 persons. These are denoted by the letters a1 through j1 and each individual has to chose between behaving honestly or behaving corruptly. Each individual faces an infinite number of decision rounds and all individual decisions are made simultaneously at the start of each round. In order to keep the model tractable, I assume that, once having made this choice, he cannot change it in that same round. At the start of the next round, the individual can see the individual decisions of the other members and may then make a new decision. Whether or not the individual behaves corruptly is determined by his "corruption threshold," the proportion of the population (or relevant reference group) that has to act corruptly before the individual will. Realizing that corruption is usually an activity that carries strong societal (and professional) sanctions against it, most people will act corruptly only if they feel that decision is one that has been made by a sufficiently large number of their peers--safety in numbers. This is because, as in the principal-agent model, all persons carry out a cost-benefit analysis that determines at what level of overall societal corruption does the benefit to him of becoming corrupt outweigh the costs of detection and punishment. Different individuals arrive at different cost-benefit valuations and, hence, may have differing thresholds. I assume that p, the probability of corruption remaining undetected and unpunished, is not exogenous to a society. It seems reasonable to assume that the probability of being caught and punished would tend to decline as the number of corrupt individuals increases (Lui 1986) since, if the opposite were true, corruption would never increase. However, this decreasing probability of punishment need not be a linear function of, or directly proportional to, the number of corrupt individuals. The individual characteristics of different governments and social systems would determine the value of p at any given moment in time. In general, I shall make the simplifying assumption that the probability of corruption remaining undetected is a non-decreasing function of the share of corrupt individuals in that society. In particular, the value of p in this model will be equal to the proportion of corrupt people in the society. 10 With this simplifying assumption, it is now possible to expand from the PA model of individuals to a threshold model of societal corruption.20 If an individual's personal corruption threshold is 0.20, at least 20% of the people in this society must be corrupt before he will behave in a corrupt manner (i.e., for him, p = 1 - 0.2 or 0.8). Similarly, a person with a threshold of 1.0 is incorruptible since all of society must be corrupt before he will be, but this cannot occur since all of society cannot be corrupt if he is not. The corruption thresholds of all 10 members of society, arranged in ascending order of their thresholds, are given in Table I. According to the table, person a1 will always be corrupt, while j1 will never be corrupt. This is because, with a threshold of 0, person a1 will be the first to be corrupt, even if no other individual in society would ==================================================================== Table I Individuals a1 b1 c1 d1 e1 f1 g1 h1 i1 j1 Threshold 0.0 0.2 0.2 0.25 0.35 0.45 0.55 0.65 0.75 1.0 ==================================================================== act in a corrupt manner. This may be because a1 is an extreme risk taker, may feel that he will never be caught, has no moral qualms about violating corruption taboos, and so on. Similarly, person j1 might be extremely risk averse, or have very high moral standards, or simply place too high a value on his moral comfort to ever be tempted by the possible corruption payoffs. The overall proportion of corrupt individuals in this society is 0.10 and so p is also 0.1. This distribution of corruption thresholds is not enough to trigger corrupt behavior in either b1 or c1 since they require a corrupt proportion of 0.20. In a situation such as the threshold distribution in Table I, the prevailing norm here is honesty (the number of honest persons, N, equals 9). However, our individual a1 is still prepared to behave corruptly. But this equilibrium is vulnerable to a shock since the probability of corruption being detected and punished is less than one. In particular, any of a number of events can change individual thresholds and certain individual threshold changes can rapidly change the population equilibrium from “mostly honest” to “mostly corrupt.” What could such a shock, an exogenous trigger, be in this case? Perhaps a governmental budget crisis means that fewer resources are being spent on monitoring. Perhaps an individual has unexpected major medical expenses. Perhaps he is passed over for promotion and so decides to augment his pension by other means. For our purposes, assume that the shock here is individual b1's daughter’s upcoming wedding.21 All that actually matters here is that he is now prepared to act corruptly. What possible effect might this have on other individual’s in the same group? The behavior of any given individual is usually contextual. By this I mean that most individuals do not have an infallible moral compass to guide their daily actions and, hence, take many of their behavioral cues from the actions of others around them. Corruptibility, like other forms of human behavior, is dependent upon the relative corruption of others in society. Individual b1's corrupt behavior now also changes the behavior of persons c1 through h1 since the higher levels of corruption affect them as well. If a1 and b1 are corrupt, then c1 will be as well since his threshold is 0.2 and this has been achieved. This in turn will affect d1, e1, f1, g1, h1 and i1. As shown in Table II, the prevailing norm in this society has now changed to 20 There are several possible reasons for this. First, it is possible that corrupt individuals would not report other individuals who are observed to act corruptly. Second, collusion is possible in that, for a consideration, monitors do not report corrupt behavior. Third, it is possible that self selection would ensure that more corrupt individuals are likely to gravitate to the monitoring branch of the government. However, explicitly incorporating these into the model would make it much less tractable without adding greatly to its explanatory power. 21 This is, of course, just one of many possible changes. This shock is not as facetious as it may appear. See Wade (1989) for just such an example. 11 ==================================================================== Table II Individuals a1 b1 c1 d1 e1 f1 g1 h1 i1 j1 Old Threshold 0 0.2 0.2 0.25 0.35 0.45 0.55 0.65 0.75 1.0 New Threshold 0 0.1 0.2 0.25 0.35 0.45 0.55 0.65 0.75 1.0 ==================================================================== to corruption since nine out of ten members are no longer honest.22 Thus N, the proportion of honest individuals in this society is now 0.1 and there is a bandwagon effect that changes the societal norm from honesty to corruption. Ordinarily, this bandwagon effect will be slow: the process will not run its course overnight or even in a few weeks. This is because it may take repeated corrupt acts by a small minority to affect the others23, opportunities for safely acting corruptly may be relatively limited, or it may even require the induction of new personnel, ones with lower corruption thresholds, to change effectively the prevailing norm. I have purposely allowed a1's behavior to affect immediately only b1's behavior (perhaps a1 and b1 are colleagues that share an office). While an artificial constraint, it is necessary to show the sequential nature of the spread of systemic corruption. It is entirely possible for one person's corruption to have an immediate effect on two (or more) colleagues if their corruption thresholds are identical. The change in the prevailing societal norm will also affect the calculations for determining the expected benefits of corrupt behavior. Consider Equation 5 discussed earlier: p* = BH + MH - BP + MC BC - BP (5) The threshold value of p, p*, is the probability of corruption remaining undetected and unpunished at which a hitherto honest official is indifferent between corruption and honesty. This transition from honesty to corruption is determined by the value of p, ceteris paribus. So for the population distribution in Table I, with a 90% honest population, the relevant value of p is 0.1. Thus, for all individuals except a1, BH + MH > 0.1BC + 0.9BP - MC. (6) and for all individuals except j1, BH + MH < 0.9BC + 0.1BP - MC. (7) Equation 7 represents the situation in Table II. For all individuals except j1, the prevailing p* of 0.9, once the bandwagon effect of systemic corruption has taken place, is more than the threshold value for any corrupt individual in the population. The expected payoff from corruption has greatly increased for the average or representative individual in this society even if the actual values of BC, BP and MC do not change. Corruption, in terms of its 22 This is just one of an infinite number of possible threshold distributions possible. Under different distributions, there may be no bandwagon effect after a threshold change. Or there may be minor effects such as only one or two more people acting corruptly. Or the initial distribution may have all members already acting corruptly. I chose a distribution which allows me to illustrate the specific bandwagon effect I have in mind. 23 The availability heuristic would require that there usually be more than one occurrence before the average observer decides that the probability of detection is low enough for him to take a chance. See Kuran (1995) for a full exposition of the effects of heuristics on human behavior. 12 expected utility, is now more profitable than ever since the probability of being caught and punished for corruption, p, is directly dependent upon the proportion of honest people in society. We can see how a simple increase in the number of corrupt individuals in society can greatly increase the payoff for corruption and tempt even those who have a relatively high corruption threshold. Of course if, when he first acted corruptly, a1 was caught and given exemplary punishment, it is entirely possible that b1's corruption threshold might have been raised from 0.2 to 0.3 instead of being lowered. Then there would be no need to worry about the effects of corruption on society since the dominant societal norm would continue to be honesty. So it follows then that strict enforcement of anti-corruption laws and ruthless prosecution of the corrupt can hold the threshold sequence constant and prevent the vicious corruption bandwagon from starting. A successful example of just such a strategy is Singapore (Quah 1989), one of the least corrupt countries in the Transparency International surveys.24 It also then follows that lax enforcement of the anti-corruption laws and/or an inefficient legal system that cannot swiftly prosecute the corrupt could easily change the existing threshold distribution. This would occur when hitherto honest officials reevaluate their decision to stay honest in light of the knowledge that the legal system cannot (will not) easily punish the corrupt. V The Importance of Asymmetric Demonstration Effects So far the assumption has been that every individual's decision carries equal weight in society. This is not a realistic assumption. The current decisions of some individuals are more important in influencing future decisions than the decisions of others. I contend that the attitudes of the leadership of society are extremely influential in determining the behavior of subordinates, particularly with regards to corruption (Basu et al 1992; Whitehead [1983] 1989; Wade 1989; Klitgaard 1988; Rose-Ackerman 1978; and many others). Within the context of a threshold model, this can be shown by assigning each individual's decision a weight consonant with "his importance and influence in society" (Kuran 1989, 46). The model then captures the fact that a hierarchical social structure, or even a non-hierarchical one in which individuals have asymmetrical levels of influence, is very important in bandwagon effects. Following Kuran (1989, 46), the effects of a separate weight being assigned to different individuals can be gauged thus: n CT = wc i i (7) i 1 where CT is the (weighted) proportion of society that is corrupt; n is the number of individuals in society; wi is the weight assigned to each corrupt individual i; ci is 1 if individual i is corrupt and zero if honest. All the weights of all the individuals in society sum to 1. Thus if everyone in society is honest then CT equals zero. Similarly, if only individual i is corrupt but he is of minimal importance in society, then CT is near zero and the society is still basically honest. 24 The relative accuracy of Transparency International surveys (see, e.g., http://www.gwdg.de/~uwvw/icr.htm) of comparative international corruption levels have been used questioned by some but their use by agencies such as, e.g., the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund in their official publications, attest to their general acceptance. 13 ==================================================================== Table III Individuals a1 b1 c1 d1 e1 f1 g1 h1 i1 j1 CT Threshold1 0 0.1 0.2 0.25 0.35 0.45 0.55 0.65 0.75 1.0 0.05 Threshold2 0 0.05 0.2 0.25 0.35 0.45 0.55 0.65 0.75 1.0 0.15 Threshold3 0 0.05 0.1 0.25 0.35 0.45 0.55 0.65 0.75 1.0 0.80 Threshold4 0 0.1 0.2 0.25 0.35 0.45 0.55 0.65 0.75 0.0 1.00 Weight 0.05 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.15 0.20 ==================================================================== Consider the population in Table III. This is the same population as in Table II and it has the same (new) threshold distribution, Threshold1. Ignoring the weights gives us the same end result as in Table II. Now consider the actual weights assigned to our individuals. When a1 behaves corruptly here, the value of CT is 0.05, not enough to prompt corrupt behavior in individual b1 or, subsequently, any one else. This society is still honest as its CT (i.e., weighted corruption level) is only 0.05.25 Suppose that there is a change in individual b1's threshold (for the same reasons as before) and it is lowered to 0.05, i.e., Threshold2 is now in effect. Individual b1 will now also act corruptly and so we have two corrupt individuals and eight honest ones. However, b1's weight is still 0.1 which, combined with a1's weight of 0.05, gives us a CT of 0.15--not enough to trigger corrupt behavior in any one else. This is in direct contrast to the situation in Table II where, given that all individual actions carried equal weight, the change in one individual's threshold was enough to trigger corrupt behavior in others. The end result here is that we simply have a slightly more corrupt society but one where the prevailing norm is still essentially honesty (n = 0.8). Now, if individual c3's threshold changes to 0.1, i.e., Threshold3 is now in effect, the new CT of 0.25 is enough to trigger corrupt behavior in d3 and every other individual except for j3. We can thus see the importance of weights in determining whether the eventual outcome is honesty or corruption. The final example is Threshold4, which replicates the threshold distribution of Threshold1 except that the corruption threshold of individual i3,, the single most influential individual in the population declines from 1.0 to 0.0. This, admittedly extreme, change now raises the CT to 0.25, enough to trigger a corruption bandwagon in the rest of the population. The final CT is now 1.0--complete corruption. The point of this extreme change is to show that the greater is the individual's weight in society, the more likely his or her action is to change the status quo. Once again, enforcement of the existing anti-corruption laws and an efficient legal system is more likely to prevent an undesirable change in the threshold distribution and, hence, prevent a norm change from honesty to corruption. VI Systemic Corruption: Bottom-up and Top-down Paths All the preceding examples (Tables I, II and III) had a norm of honesty as an initial starting point. But is it accurate to presume that most non-Western countries started their post-colonial history more honest than they were corrupt? Based upon what we know about their current corruption levels, very low according to Transparency International surveys, why presume a relatively honest initial point? It is my contention that the preceding examples with weights that are skewed towards honesty reflect the situation in most post-colonial states at the time of independence. Most of these states inherited a bureaucratic structure that was fundamentally honest--at least as far as the personal enrichment of the ruling colonial elite went 25 There is no objective criteria for assigning these particular weights to these particular individuals. This weight distribution serves to illustrate the point being made here. A different weight distribution could well give very different results. 14 26 (Hope 1996, 130; Andreski 1968, 103 & 110-115; Myrdal [1968] 1989b, 410). Myrdal buttresses his claims of an honest British colonial administration by extensively quoting from the post-independence Indian Government's official Report of the Committee on Prevention of Corruption in 1964, the Santhanam Report. This report grudgingly admitted that "the higher ranks [of the colonial administration] were comparatively free from this evil [of corruption]" (Myrdal [1968] 1989b, 418) and that, for the post-independence period, the consensus of testimony to the Commission was that: corruption had increased to such an extent that people have started losing faith in the integrity of public administration. ...corruption has, in recent years, spread even to those levels of administration from which it was conspicuously absent in the past. (Quoted in Myrdal [1968] 1989b, 417) It is inconceivable to me that any post-colonial government would have an incentive to paint the colonial rulers as being more honest than they actually were. Naturally, this contention of an honest colonial administration holds most strongly for ex-British and then for ex-French colonies (the bulk of the post-WWII ex-colonial states). Hallet (1965) contends that the much-reviled Belgian colonial administration in the Congo (later renamed Zaire and now again the Congo) was also extremely competent and honest. The ex-Portuguese colonies and the remnants of the once vast Spanish colonial empire are a somewhat different matter but they were numerically fewer than the British and French ones.27 The above statements should not be taken to imply that the source of all corruption is within the Third World itself. Lambsdorff (1997), after an extensive econometric analysis, compiled an indicator of the bribery potential of leading exporting countries, i.e., how likely is an exporter to bribe his importing counterpart and how much of an exporting country's sales abroad are due to bribery. Naturally, Western countries are heavily over-represented in his "bribery propensity rankings." Similarly, others, e.g., LeVine (1989) and Ali (1985), have remarked upon the role of multinational (i.e., mainly Western) firms in encouraging corruption in the Third World. In this context, Lambsdorff (1997) further points out that bribes paid to foreigners by businessmen are tax deductible in Germany and Belgium, and that the US is the only advanced Western country to currently specifically prohibit bribing foreign customers--although an OECD internal agreement is supposed to extend this practice to all member countries by the end of 1998.28 A true chicken-or-the-egg type of question is whether, in the first instance, a bribe was offered to an official or whether it was demanded by him. However, in either case, the basic point remains that it is an internal decision (whether to demand or accept a bribe) that starts the rot in the government apparatus, not the decision to offer it. Ali takes issue with the assertion of an honest British colonial administration in India. However, his examples of "corruption" are not convincing and, in a work that has a general anti-colonial tone and includes a scathing denunciation of neo-imperialism by multinational corporations, even he admits that, while "Colonial rule was not free 26 However, Ali (1985, 194-195), while agreeing with the above contention of an honest British colonial administration, argues that this honesty in administering "government money" did not extend to their personal dealings with the natives: accepting "gifts" (e.g., free vacations) was commonplace, as was the custom of officials on the verge of retiring from government service allowing their wives to accept going-away "presents" from influential natives. Since even these "corrupt" officials are described as being "scrupulously careful and honest about government money," Ali's implicit argument has to be extortion: natives who did not give gifts would be punished. However, nowhere does Ali actually state that uncooperative natives were punished. Corruption in the British administrators, in so far as it existed, would have been of the isolated kind. Collins and Lapierre (1980 [1975]) also remark on the propensity of the wives of some extremely high-ranking British colonial officials in India to solicit gifts of expensive jewelry, though they make it clear that this was rare and certainly not the norm in the last hundred years or so of British rule. In any case, Ali's allegations are flatly contradicted by the post-colonial Indian Government's own report on corruption. 27 The differences in European colonial policies and administration, and why they existed, is a fascinating dissertation topic in itself. I have no concise answer for why the differences existed except to say that it probably reflected the metropole government's own relative honesty levels and attitudes to their people. 28 The actual enforcement of these anti-bribery laws, if the US example of complete laxity after a brief initial enforcement spurt is anything to go by, will be problematical at best. 15 from its share of corruption, but since independence the shocking increase in graft and bribery has bewildered nearly every observer (Ali 1985, 157)." So why and how did this "shocking increase" take place? As Hope (1996), Tanzi (1995), Alexander (1994), Dewey (1991), Ali (1985), Caiden and Caiden (1977), Jabbra (1976), Wilson (1967), and Banfield (1958), and many others, have argued, much of traditional society (now found mainly in non-Western countries) is characterized by the belief that objective criteria in public dealings should not apply to friends and relatives. Thus Tanzi's (1995) norm of "arm's length dealings" does not apply in transactions involving relatives, clan/tribe members and friends, who are given preferential treatment while non-associates are discriminated against. The argument I make here is that the colonial administrators were much less susceptible to pressure from their family and friends for favorable treatment, if for no other reason than the fact that their families were not in the colonies and most of their friends were other colonial officials. After decolonization, the natives who assumed full political power were susceptible to this pressure for favorable treatment and, without the presences of Basu et al's (1992) "incorruptible civil service elite" to keep them on the straight and narrow, did their duty to their family and friends rather than to their profession. Given the fact that most of the newly independent states were scarcity economies, i.e., marked by a relative shortage of modern goods, it would be extremely difficult for government administrators, who often enjoy considerable discretionary power, to resist the demand of family, friends, and even perhaps co-ethnics, for favorable treatment in the allocation of scarce resources (Bates 1974). Even if they did not want to favor friends and relatives, after independence, the administrators no longer have the excuse of saying that the colonial authorities would not allow them to bypass normal administrative procedures. Thus we see a gradual decay in administrative standards and a rise in corruption as friends and relatives benefit from their association with those in power. From this, it is a comparatively easy step to favor complete strangers in exchange for monetary consideration (Tanzi 1995). Within the context of the threshold corruption model, this process would work as detailed below. Consider the new group of government administrators in Table IV at Thresholdt=0 (i.e., the threshold distribution at time t=0). Assume that this is the situation in a former European colony (e.g., India or Pakistan) immediately after independence. Corruption is found only at the lowest levels of the administration and the upper ranks are fairly honest. The only openly corrupt individual here is a2 and society is extremely honest (n=0.9 and CT=0.05). The result of the removal of an upper echelon not responsive to local pressures is a continual erosion of individual corruption thresholds--shown here by a 0.03 decrease in each time period. As a result of this continual erosion, at t=2, individual b2's corruption threshold is reached and the government's weighted corruption level, CT, reaches 0.10. This is not enough to set a bandwagon effect in motion. We simply have a slightly more corrupt government. At t=4, the continued erosion in corruption thresholds causes c2 and d2 to behave corruptly as well and the government's CT reaches 0.30. We still see no bandwagon effect since the erosion in thresholds has not yet reached the critical point. At t=5, individual e2's personal corruption threshold is reached and he behaves corruptly as well, raising the CT to 0.40. Finally at t=7, the steady decline in individual corruption thresholds reaches the critical point and a bandwagon effect is triggered--corruption is now complete as the government's CT reaches 1. 16 ==================================================================== Table IV Individuals a2 b2 c2 d2 e2 f2 g2 h2 i2 j2 CT Thresholdt=0 0 0.10 0.20 0.25 0.45 0.60 0.65 0.65 0.90 0.95 0.05 Thresholdt=1 0 0.07 0.17 0.22 0.42 0.57 0.62 0.62 0.87 0.92 0.05 Thresholdt=2 0 0.04 0.14 0.19 0.39 0.54 0.59 0.59 0.84 0.89 0.10 Thresholdt=3 0 0.01 0.11 0.16 0.36 0.51 0.56 0.56 0.81 0.86 0.10 Thresholdt=4 0 0.00 0.08 0.13 0.33 0.48 0.53 0.53 0.78 0.83 0.30 Thresholdt=5 0 0.00 0.05 0.10 0.30 0.45 0.50 0.50 0.75 0.80 0.40 Thresholdt=6 0 0.00 0.02 0.07 0.27 0.42 0.47 0.47 0.72 0.77 0.40 Thresholdt=7 0 0.00 0.00 0.04 0.24 0.39 0.44 0.44 0.69 0.74 1.00 Weight 0.05 0.05 0.10 0.10 0.10 0.10 0.10 0.10 0.10 0.20 ==================================================================== Table IV illustrates quite nicely how a gradual decay in administrative standards--as shown by the eroding corruption thresholds29--could lead to a systemically corrupt society. This gradual transition, fueled by a general societal preference for non-arm's-length transactions, is an inevitable outcome insofar as the rulers of the new state are unable or unwilling to prevent themselves or their subordinates from using non-arm's-length criteria in their official dealings. Leadership determined to maintain high societal honesty levels would, of course, obviate the need for analyses such as this.30 Similarly, an inefficient or non-independent legal system would also help hasten this transition to systemic corruption if it provided inadequate recourse to those elements of the population who wish to prevent a non-arm's-length criteria in decision making. So far the implicit statement in the previous models has been that corruption spreads from the bottom up. This belief is correct insofar as the stated impetus for corruption came from outside the administrative structure and first affected the lower ranking members of the government--whose corruption thresholds were lower than those of their superiors. But, in general, would these corruption thresholds actually be lower for lower-ranking officials? I would argue, initially at least, yes. This is because natives in the upper ranks of the colonial administration were held to a higher standard of morality than natives in the lower ranks. Thus, having served in that environment, high-rank natives who moved into the highest strata of government would, initially at least, retain a comparatively higher corruption threshold.31 Huntington (1968, 68) is in accord with this belief. This is, however, clearly at odds with the historical record of rulers such as, for example, Mobutu, Marcos or Duvalier. In these cases, it is not easy to argue that corruption was a bottom-up phenomenon. The expansion of the threshold corruption model in the next section shows explicitly how high-level corruption can rapidly change the entire institutional culture from relative honesty to systemic corruption. The threshold corruption model shows how the societal norm could gradually change from honest to corrupt. The model can also easily accommodate cases of very rapid transition. Consider Table V below. This society has the 29 Within the context of the original PA model, the process by which corruption thresholds are lowered would work thus: continued pressure by family and friends on government administrators marginally lowers their corruption thresholds as their willingness to accept a slightly higher risk level increases. Some hitherto honest individuals now act corruptly. This has two effects: (i) some individuals may reevaluate their own assessment of the situation in light of others' successful corruption; and (ii), family pressure on these still honest individuals increases--"Why can't you do for your family what X did for his?" This causes a further fall in individual corruption thresholds and more corrupt acts. More corruption leads to a further drop in corruption thresholds, which, in turn, leads to.... 30 See Quah (1989) for an account of how, in Singapore, determined leadership actually raised the societal honesty level to a point higher than that under the colonial regime. 31 See, for example, Philip Mason's highly readable memoir, A Shaft of Sunlight: Memories of a Varied Life (NY: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1978), for an account of life in the elite pre-independence Indian Civil Service (ICS) and, especially, the pronounced differences between native members of the ICS and lower ranking administrative/support staff. 17 same threshold distribution as in Table IV but the weight distribution is changed to reflect its more hierarchical nature and the greater power of its leadership. Now suppose that there is a change of leadership and individual j3, the most influential person in this distribution is replaced by k3, the result of, say, a military coup, at the start of time period 1. Individual k3 has a corruption threshold of 0 and this results in a bandwagon effect which causes the system's norm to change from honest to corrupt--the new CT is now 1. With such a drastic change in leadership corruption thresholds, the process which took seven time periods in Table IV is here accomplished in one, thus underscoring the extreme importance of leadership in determining the speed of the transition. ==================================================================== Table V Individuals a3 b3 c3 d3 e3 f3 g3 h3 i3 j3 CT Thresholdt=0 0 0.10 0.20 0.25 0.45 0.60 0.65 0.65 0.90 0.95 0.05 Thresholdt=1 a3 0 b3 c3 d3 e3 f3 g3 h3 i3 k3 CT 0.10 0.20 0.25 0.45 0.60 0.65 0.65 0.90 0.00 1.00 Weight 0.00 0.00 0.00 0.05 0.05 0.05 0.10 0.15 0.20 0.40 ==================================================================== We could add further refinements to the basic model and move closer to the real world. For example, the size of the population could be increased, enabling the creation of different layers of hierarchy, arranging the population into peer groups and giving the peer's actions greater weight, and so on. Thus we could show the existence of (relatively more) honest sub-groups in a (relatively more) dishonest society and vice-versa.32 VII Incorporating Cross-Peer Linkages into the Slippery Slope of the Culture of Corruption Several authors have remarked upon the seeming ability of the South Korean and Japanese governments to keep their economic bureaucracies relatively honest while the political establishment was not (Kong 1996; Khan 1996; Dutt and Kim 1994). How is such an insulation possible? And can the threshold corruption model accommodate such real-world variations? The answer to the first question is, "Through cross-peer linkages," and the answer to the second question is, "Yes." But why are cross-peer linkages important? Such linkages are, of course, common in the real world in that people in a government department are not hermetically sealed from outside influence. They are aware of what their peers or near peers in other departments are doing or, what is more important for our purpose, what they are getting away with. Furthermore, individuals are often transferred across government departments and an individual who behaves corruptly in one department is not likely to automatically become honest if he is transferred to another: it depends upon the relative Cs of each department and the individual's own corruption threshold. Individuals thus respond not only to their leaders' actions but to their peers as well. They take their cross-departmental peers' behavior 32 All societies are sub-divided into myriad sub-groups and, of course, individuals may belong to more than one sub-group. For example, one sub-group may be individuals working for a particular corporation. Another may be alumni of a particular university. A third may be members of a particular religious denomination. Any given individual may belong to all three (or more) of these sub-groups. Many of these sub-groups influence the behavior of members of different sub-groups but this may not always be so; the issue is one of salience. Your boss' behavior may influence your own but it is unlikely that the behavior of the boss of a fellow member of the church choir is going to affect materially your own behavior. Sub-groups that are seen as criminal entities often do not affect persons outside their sub-group. For instance, in the U.S. there exist urban gangs which carry out a variety of criminal activities but the behavior of these criminal gangs do not (usually) cause individuals in significantly different sub-urban areas to pattern their behavior after gang members. The behavior of gang members is simply not salient. On the other hand, gang members' behavior is likely to affect the attitudes and behavior of non-members who live in the same neighborhood--non-members may wish to emulate them. 18 into account when they decide how to act. It is necessary to acknowledge this important demonstration and replication aspect of the spread of corruption. Successful corruption by members of one government department acts in the same way that a bacterial infection in one organ of the body does: if left untreated it can quickly spread to other organs and then rapidly reach systemic levels. My model can incorporate this quite easily by making just such a linkage.33 Cross-peer linkages are connections between individuals in different departments, usually but not exclusively between those who are near or at the same level: for example between c4 and l4 or d4 and n4, in Table 3.6, which depicts a very simple form of government that has two separate departments, a finance department (FD) and a public works (project implementation) department (PD). Both departments ultimately report to one man, the Director General (DG). Each department is composed of nine individuals, excluding the DG, and every individual in the government has a corruption threshold and a weight. The two-departmental situation can be represented as in Table VI.34 Both departments have the same DG and he has a corruption threshold of 0.65. Although not incorruptible, he has the highest corruption threshold in the government. For the sake of preserving the hierarchical nature of the relationship between individuals, their weights and corruption thresholds are now arranged in descending order. The separate corruption thresholds and weights of each individual in the two departments give us two different C (corruption) values (CF and CP, the weighted proportion of corrupt individuals in each department) as an indicator of their relative degree of corruption. Thus we see that the DG has two honest departments. That is, the (weighted) norm for each department could not be described as "corrupt." Taking each individual department as a separate entity (and including the DG as the head of each), their departmental Cs are relatively low (CF and CP of 0.30 and 0.10 respectively). While the corruption thresholds of the DG and the senior-staff of each department are considerably higher than that of their subordinates, the former are not incorruptible. Under the right conditions, a systemically corrupt outcome is certainly possible. 33 Granovetter (1973) discusses how "weak ties" between individuals can affect decision-making, I am considering weak ties between departments here in that individual's do not consider just a peer's behavior but that of the peer's department as a whole.. 34 This type of analysis can be applied equally well to a society that has two ethnic groups or comprises of two regions. It can also be easily extended to more than two groups or regions. 19 ================================================================== Table VI Corruption Director General Threshold Weight x4 0.65 0.20 Finance Dept. Public Works Dept. Corruption Corruption Individual Threshold Weight Individual Threshold Weight a4 0.60 0.15 j4 0.60 0.15 b4 0.50 0.15 k4 0.50 0.15 c4 0.40 0.10 l4 0.40 0.10 d4 0.35 0.10 m4 0.30 0.10 e4 0.20 0.10 n4 0.25 0.10 f4 0.10 0.10 o4 0.25 0.05 g4 0.05 0.05 p4 0.15 0.05 h4 0.00 0.05 q4 0.00 0.05 i4 0.00 0.00 r4 0.00 0.05 Sum of weights 0.80 Sum of weights 0.80 CF = 0.30 CP = 0.10 ================================================================= The behavior of people in each department determines its C, the level of corruption to be found in it. It follows then that the individual contemplating corruption would want to know about the overall level of corruption in government when making his cost-benefit evaluation. So in considering whether the overall governmental C meets his corruption threshold, the individual uses a weighted average of his department's C and that of the rest of the government. Using a weighted average is justified because, while a shared corporate culture does shape individual expectations (Tirole 1996, 3; Huang and Wu 1994, 400), the influence of those individuals with whom one has the most daily contact is likely to be stronger than that of the entity as a whole. However, the corporate culture of the entity as a whole cannot be neglected entirely since it has an influence, if not on the rank and file, then at least on the sub-group's leadership. So the weight assigned by any individual i to the C of the home department must be at least equal to, if not greater than, the weight assigned by that individual to any other department's C. Equation 8 below shows such a weighted average, assigning equal weights to both departments. CT = (0.5CF + 0.5 CP) (8) Now consider individual p4 in the PD. His corruption threshold is 0.15 but the departmental weighted corruption level, CP, is only 0.10. His threshold has not been reached, but this would hold true only if the PD is indeed hermetic. However, this is not likely. So, in making his corruption decision, p4 uses a cross-departmental weighted average, CT, in determining whether or not his individual corruption threshold has been reached: CT = (0.5*0.30 + 0.5*0.10) = 0.20 (versus a CP of 0.10). (9) Thus p4 corruption threshold has been reached and he acts corruptly at time t=0. The new CP is now 0.15 and the CT has increased to 0.225. This is still not enough to trigger a systemic corruption bandwagon. However, consider what would happen if individual o4's corruption threshold drops to 0.20 at time t=1. Using just the departmental CP of 0.15 is not enough for him to behave corruptly. However, the cross-departmental weighted CT of 0.225 is high enough to meet his corruption threshold. He behaves corruptly. In turn, the resulting higher weighted 20 corruption average is enough to reach n4's corruption threshold of 0.25 at time t=2. This now raises the weighted corruption level enough to reach m4's threshold of 0.30 at time t=3. This in turn causes d4's threshold to be reached at time t=4, which in turn.... The final result is systemic corruption as both departmental Cs reach 1.00. The same results could be obtained in a much shorter time period if a change in government leadership, e.g., a military coup or successful revolution at time t=1, replaces individual x4 with someone whose corruption threshold is, say, 0.2. This would set off an immediate corruption bandwagon effect at time t=2 that would convert the entire CT to 1.00. Leadership corruption greatly speeds up the transition mechanism. Thus, under the right circumstances, systemic corruption can come about in either a top-down or bottom-up manner. Now assume that we start from a systemically corrupt government, CT of 1.00, with the same individual corruption thresholds as in Table 3.6. What happens if a new leader whose corruption threshold is 1.00 (the proverbial incorruptible leader) somehow comes to power? Nothing. The new governmental CT, 0.80, is lower than before but it is not enough to make any corrupt official change his behavior. Every one other than the leader is still corrupt and there is no real change in how business is done.35 If the new leader, with his weight still at 0.20, could also replace the top three individuals in each department with individuals with corruption thresholds above 0.80, then the resultant change in leadership would swing the pendulum in the other direction--towards honesty. In this case we are then talking about a wholesale purge of the entire leadership of the government. Of course, if the new leader has a weight of more than, say, 0.40, then the current threshold distribution would result in a swing back towards a norm of honesty fairly effortlessly. Unfortunately, the history of much of the developing world does not lend itself to either proposal. We have seen neither a coup replacing the corrupt by the honest nor have we seen the rise of an honest Leviathan determined to embark upon the Herculean task of cleaning the Augean stables of government.36 There is nothing sacrosanct about the 0.5 weight assigned to each department. It is simply a convenient number to use given that the weight assigned to the individual's home department must be at least equal to that assigned to the rest of the government. It is also a convenient one to use given the individual weights and thresholds used in Table 3.6. Changing this parameter may, under some circumstances give different, either good or bad, results. That is also acceptable. For example, the British colonial tradition was to isolate the armed forces from the rest of colonial society as much as possible. Thus a would-be corrupt army officer (at least in the immediate post-colonial era) would assign a much greater weight to the army's C than to that of any other department. The normal weight assignment would be to give a substantially higher weight to one's own department than to that of one's peers. Thus, for example, in the Japanese and South Korean (under General Park) traditions, the economic bureaucracy was kept isolated and shielded from the political sphere (Kong 1996; Dutt and Kim 1994) while in the Indian case, the once insulated and highly capable Indian Administrative Service was turned into the civil service wing of the ruling Congress Party (Dutt and Kim 1994). So for the Japanese and the South Korean economic bureaucracy, the weights assigned by a would-be corrupt official to the departmental C would be much higher than the weight assigned to the C of the politicians. Some spillover of corruption is of course likely to occur in even these tightly insulated cases, as shown by recent reports of corruption in the top bureaucrats of the Japanese Finance Ministry (Efron 1998). The threshold effect in Table 3.6 did not have a specific time element attached to it. The usual expectation would be that an overnight change in most governments is not likely. Even in Zaire, Mobutu's reign did not convert the entire national government into a kleptocracy overnight. We are likely to see a more gradual erosion over time (as in Table IV), with the rate of corruption spread being determined by several factors (pervasiveness of 35 As an example of this, consider Klitgaard's (1988, 173-175) analysis of the efforts to root out corruption in a government department in "Ruritania" (actually Pakistan) by a newly appointed "Mr. Clean" that were unsuccessful because he did not have the full support of his superiors and corrupt departmental officials were able to stymie his efforts. Feichtinger and Wirl (1994, 116-117) argue that this is essentially what happened to Gorbachev's reforms in the Former Soviet Union. 36 Lee Kwan Yew, first Prime Minister of Singapore, could conceivably be cast in the role of an anti-corruption Hercules but he was not dealing with a systemically corrupt system (see Quah 1989 for more on Yew's anti-corruption strategy). 21 non-arm's-length dealings, the corruption inclinations of the higher leadership, the efficacy of the judicial system, and so on). VIII Some Implications of the Threshold Corruption Model Many, if not all, of the following results are not surprising to any well informed observer of the corruption scene, whether in the Third World or the First. For example, the importance of leadership is intuitively obvious since "Do as I say, not as I do" is a notoriously ineffective leadership principle, and the lack of institutional constraints on the leadership in the Third World has been remarked upon by many (among others, Ades and Di Tella 1996; Diamond 1995; Ostrom 1993; Leff [1964] 1989; Klitgaard 1988; Andreski 1968). However, the threshold model of corruption described here contributes to the literature on corruption since it provides a mechanism that can actually generate these results. Since these results can be generated, it is also possible to see under what circumstances these consequences can be avoided. The principal-agent model (PA) has no readily generalizable stylized facts for the analysis of systemic corruption since, as I have noted, it assumes that the leaders--the principals--are honest. By definition, systemic corruption is the result of a completely corrupt leadership. The basic PA model is also not readily applicable to other situations which involve system-wide consequences, although it is invaluable for analyzing individual actions in a wide variety of circumstances. The basic PA model has, as shown in section II earlier and as is apparent from the model itself, definite implications for the effect on individual behavior of changes in corruption due to changes in the level of punishment or the probability of detection. The model described here, building upon the PA model, has more to say about the likely effects of different circumstances on systemic corruption. i Variability of the Demonstration Effect Given the importance of role models (the actions of influential people in society), frames of reference (the actions of one's own leadership versus the actions of all other individuals in society) and in-group versus out-group behavior (the actions of people in one's own department versus the actions of others) in determining an individual's own actions, corrupt leadership is more likely to lead to systemic corruption due to the variability of the demonstration effect. In plain English, you are more likely to be corrupt if your superior is, since his actions carry greater salience for you. This fact is captured by the weights assigned to each individual. This, of course, underscores the importance of leadership behavior in determining the outcome: corruption or honesty. ii Centralization of Power A clear implication of this model is that countries with a highly centralized system of government will be more vulnerable to systemic corruption. This is because the inclinations of the leadership have a direct effect on a larger number of civil servants at all levels of government. In short, the network of interactions among individuals in a centralized system of government allows for the more rapid transmission of corruption. In more decentralized systems, in a best-case scenario, corrupt leadership in one part of the administrative apparatus may have no spillover effects since (i) it would not serve as a reference group for many civil servants and (ii) the effects of corrupt leadership may be countered by other non-corrupt leaders at different levels of government who have independent power bases. Alternatively, as my interdepartmental weighted corruption model shows, the spread of corruption may simply be slowed down at best. iii Institutional Constraints An indirect implication of this model is that countries that do not have independent institutions with countervailing power against the executive, i.e., no formal system of checks and balances based on a separation of powers system such as that of the US, will be more susceptible to systemic corruption than countries that do. This is because such a system raises the likelihood that corruption, especially high-level corruption, will be detected and 22 punished (i.e., p is lowered). Furthermore, it also creates independent power bases that the executive has, by definition, very little control over. iv Culture Culture, i.e., the accepted norms and practices of a society, matters greatly in determining whether the final outcome is systemic corruption or relative honesty. This is because it is exactly this culture--the environment that the individual concerned has to live with and in on a daily basis--that provides him with his behavioral and attitudinal cues. So it is the dominant cultural norms and not some abstract, Weberian ideal of the perfect bureaucrat, that guides the actions of the vast majority of the decision-makers in any government entity. It stands to reason that societies that have a norm of "non-arm's-length" dealings, i.e., which are characterized by a relatively strong "traditional " socio-economic structure, are much more likely to be corrupt than societies that have a relatively weak "traditional" component to their social fabric. As detailed earlier, the latter tend to have a stronger social safety net and weaker interpersonal ties between individuals. In this context, the development of strong formal institutions that can substitute for traditional ones becomes very important if corruption is to be reduced. v Predictability The final state of the system can be only, at best, imperfectly predicted. Imperfect predictability means that, ex ante, we cannot make authoritative pronouncements about the final outcome no matter how ‘obvious’ it may seem ex post. This is because so many "small events," many of which are unpredictable and whose importance for the future cannot be known now, determine the final outcome that seemingly minor changes may have major consequences down the road.37 In addition, the likelihood of a corruption bandwagon taking place is extremely sensitive to the distribution of corruption thresholds in any given population or subgroup. Thus a seemingly minor difference may give us very different results. For example, consider Table 3.6. Here it is individual o4 that sets the corruption bandwagon in motion when his threshold dropped to 0.20 from 0.25. This minor change was enough to initiate a sequence that changed the entire status quo. If this change had not taken place, there would be no bandwagon effect. vi The Possibility of Reform The final, and most dispiriting, stylized fact emerging from this model is that minor reforms are generally useless in a systemically corrupt society. Once the CT of the entire system is close to one, small changes cannot reverse the status quo. Successful reforms would then have to include a major transformation of the entire governing apparatus. Simply inducting honest leadership at the very top of the administrative structure will not necessarily give us an honest outcome--unless the systemic corruption equilibrium is unstable, i.e., sensitive to small changes in threshold distribution. For example, in Table II, if individual c1's corruption threshold had been 0.25 instead of 0.2, a relatively minor difference given the population threshold distribution range of 0 to 1, the effect of the drop in b1's corruption threshold from 0.2 to 0.1 would have been negligible. No bandwagon effect would have taken place. Unfortunately, given the history of increasing corruption in the developing world, the norm appears to be more corruption and not less. Successful reform will most likely require a complete reconstruction of the existing administrative structure--probably the induction of new people with a new threshold distribution. The PA model holds that corruption reform is relatively simple: raising the probability of detection and punishment or increasing the severity of punishment will reduce corruption. Such an undertaking, for reasons already explained, is not likely to be successful. However, as history of the West shows, it is possible to move from a low-honesty equilibrium to a high-honesty one eventually. The disheartening aspect of this transition in the West, from the standpoint of today’s Third World countries, was that it took several generations to achieve. 37 Before independence, Joseph Mobutu was a clerk-sergeant in the Belgian Congo's Force Publique. He was selected for commissioning as an officer by the colonial authorities, an event that paved the way for his eventual coup d'etat. This could in no way have been foreseen by the board that approved his selection. 23 IX Conclusions Corruption is stigmatized by virtually all societies at all times (Ali 1985; Noonan 1984) because, in addition to the ethical and moral damage it does, it misallocates resources, reduces economic surplus and consequently economic growth, and degrades the all important link between effort and reward. A corruption free society is as likely as a crime free one, but there are certainly great benefits from reducing corruption, at least until the point where the marginal benefit of reduced corruption is equal to its cost. There are essentially two ways by which a society can become thoroughly corrupted. The first is that, as Table III showed, for a gradual erosion of corruption thresholds to give us a systemically corrupt outcome. This is a relatively slow process but, given a societal norm of non-arm's-length dealings and the absence of truly exemplary leadership determined to prevent it, there is a certain inexorable inevitability to it. The second is through a much more rapid transformation of existing societal mores due to the rise to power of a thoroughly corrupt leadership. This is the model laid out in Table V of this work. I would argue that the presence of both a non-arm's-length dealings norm and leadership corruption, acting as a mutually reinforcing relationship, is responsible for the speed of the transition to systemic corruption in the developing world. However, as has been shown, corruption has been universally condemned by all societies. If the entire societal norm is one of non-arm's-length dealings and the leadership is no different than the population, then why condemn them? Because it is clear that systemic corruption has many of the characteristics of a Prisoner's Dilemma game. If everyone is honest, then we all gain. If all are honest save I, then my corruption has a much larger reward accruing to it than my honesty. However, if all are corrupt, then we all lose. Thus a universal condemnation of corruption serves an important societal function. Its aim is to prevent, at the systemic level, self-interested (i.e., profit-seeking) behavior from taking the next step and turning into opportunistic (i.e., corrupt) behavior. The latter, of course, serves no good societal purpose. More effective corruption reduction is possible only if we can better understand its spread. The complete eradication of isolated corruption is probably neither feasible nor desirable from a cost-benefit perspective. The removal of systemic corruption is both feasible and desirable, though neither easy nor inexpensive. The traditional approach to modelling corruption in the social sciences has been to view it as a principal-agent problem. While invaluable in understanding the individual's decision to act corruptly or not (i.e., what is the individual's corruption threshold), the PA model does not increase our understanding of how corruption spreads in a society where there are few effective institutions to temper the power of the executive. In the atomistic PA model, the individual changes only his own behavior, without reference to that of any other person. My threshold model underscores the importance of feedback effects on the spread of corruption. Specifically, it incorporates the effects of high level corruption on the overall corruption level in society, an important social dynamic that many other theories of corruption miss. Thus this model includes important sociological effects that a simple PA model cannot adequately handle: the importance of role models, particular frames of reference and in-group versus out-group behavior in determining an individual's own actions. Finally, as Tanzi (1995) and others have argued (persuasively) that societies without a norm of non-arm's-length dealings are much more likely to be corrupt than societies that do have this norm (as shown in Table IV). In such a situation, the character of the leadership assumes even greater importance. When the natural predilection of the vast majority of the bureaucracy is to favor their own friends or relatives, it requires an iron-willed executive indeed to enforce the rules. A corrupt leadership is far less likely to exhibit such resolve than an honest one. If for no other reason than the fact that a dishonest leadership has already demonstrated that its strength of character is lacking. Historical data from India appears to support this contention. The norm in Indian/South Asian society is non-arm's-length dealings (Tanzi 1995; Alexander 1994; Dewey 1991; Bhatia 1967). The Indian government's own Santhanam Report indicated that, seventeen years after independence, leadership corruption was now widespread (Myrdal [1968] 1989b, 417). More recent reports from India indicated that the country was rapidly reaching systemic 24 levels of corruption (Tharoor 1997; Economist March 2 1996, 36; Dahlburg 1996; Los Angeles Times, 31 October 1996, pA3). The falsification of at least a part of the model would be if corruption among the leadership did not cause increased (overall) administrative corruption. South Korea and Japan, two post-WWII economic success stories, have had extremely high levels of leadership corruption. However, many analysts (e.g., Khan 1996; Kong 1996) argue that these countries were unique in their ability to keep the administrative bureaucracy separate from the political leadership. Unlike most Third World states, the administrative bureaucracy was not turned into a de facto extension of the ruling party apparatus, one whose purpose was not policy implementation but to ensure the continuation in power of the ruling establishment. Thus, using the analysis from equation 8 of the model, the weight assigned by a Japanese or South Korean bureaucrat to the corruption of the political establishment would have been very low. There would then be minimal spillover corruption effects. Unfortunately, this kind of compartmentalization of the administrative (i.e., policy implementation) apparatus is very rare in the Third World.38 Dutt and Kim (1994, 196) describe how the Indian Administrative Service, "virtually unparalleled in the Third World" in its professional competence, was turned into a de facto extension of the ruling political party. Finally, what does the threshold corruption model add to the methodological literature on corruption? While neither the concept of using a Principal-Agent (PA) approach to model criminal behavior nor that of using a bandwagon/threshold approach to model social situations is new, what is an original contribution to the literature is to combine both of these methodological approaches into a cohesive whole that increases our understanding of how systemic corruption can come about. The PA model gives invaluable insight into individual decision-making by examining the incentives faced by each individual as he or she is trying to decide whether to act corruptly or not. The threshold model brings the social interaction aspect of the corruption decision to the fore since corruption is a social act and no analysis of systemic corruption can ignore this aspect of it. The threshold corruption model utilizes both of these methodological approaches to help explain systemic corruption. The model's major innovation is in endogenizing individual corruption thresholds, and hence individual incentives, and then showing how systemic corruption can come about. Furthermore, the threshold corruption model can account for cultural effects in the systemic corruption phenomenon. This is done by specifically incorporating the effects of a norm of "non-arm's-length" transactions into the analysis of how the transition to systemic corruption occurs. Finally, the assigning of a weight, consonant with his standing in society, to each individual incorporates the asymmetric demonstration effect, i.e., the importance, of leadership behavior into the analysis of both how a systemically corrupt society comes about and of any efforts to reform it. These three main points, I contend, make the threshold corruption model a valuable addition to both the corruption and threshold literatures. This threshold corruption model, of course, would not have been possible without the work of Becker (1968; 1974), Granovetter (1973; 1978), Schelling (1978) or Kuran (1995; 1991; 1989; 1987). It takes its basic threshold sequence and general representation format from Kuran and its underlying logic from Granovetter and Schelling. It is thus a logical extension of these works as well as an original contribution/extension of their societal analysis. In conclusion, let me reiterate that the model is useful in understanding how corruption spreads and achieves systemic levels. The model gives a more formal exposition of the old Chinese adage that fish (and nations) rot from the head down. Well over two millennia ago, a Chinese sage wrote lines that indicate that there is truly nothing new under the sun. The key to success or failure in government lies in the ruler. If the inkling line is properly set above, 38 However, reports (e.g., Efron 1998) seem to indicate that corruption has spread to the civil service mandarins of the Japanese finance ministry. Thus in the long run, even in Japan, successful compartmentalization is not necessarily possible. 25 the wood will be straightened beneath it. It is not that the inkling line does anything in particular to the wood, but rather that the disciplining of the wood in following the inkling line makes it so. Thus if the ruler is truly upright, honest officials will be commissioned and villainous persons will hide themselves; but if the ruler is not upright, the wicked will get on in the world and loyal subjects will withdraw into retirement. (Translation of section 7 of The Hua Nan Tzu, Book Nine: The Art of Rulership from Ames 1983, 182-183, in Huang and Wu 1994, 390.) In accord with The Hua Nan Tzu, the model suggests that the single most important determinant of whether isolated corruption becomes systemic is the honesty level and determination of the leadership to prevent systemic corruption from becoming the norm. From this, it is a natural conclusion that higher level corruption should be punished more severely than lower level corruption. This is because especially severe sanctions against higher level officials will carry a much greater demonstration effect, as well as reduce the public perception that corruption punishments are suffered only by the unimportant and unconnected. This is unfortunately, easier said than done. As von Klausewitz said, winning a war is actually a very simple matter but, in war, it is the simplest things that are the most difficult. Even more unfortunate is the end result of systemic corruption: states like Pakistan, India, Zaire, Kenya, and virtually any other Fourth World and many Third World countries that one cares to name. The state becomes incapable of meeting any of its people's needs or of sustaining economic development. The end of the Cold War has made it possible for international aid donors (both Western governments and international organizations) to insist on higher ethical standards in recipient countries. During the height of the Cold War, "national security considerations" caused them to overlook, and at times actively assist in, the looting and impoverishment of Third World countries. Many of the most corrupt countries are either large aid recipients (e.g., India, Pakistan and Kenya) or are extremely dependent on Western markets for their products (e.g., Nigeria). If international aid donors are interested in improving the living standards of the poor of the world, the best first step is to insist on some level of accountability for the rulers of the Third World. 26 BIBLIOGRAPHY Ades, Alberto, and Rafael Di Tella. 1996. "The Causes and Consequences of Corruption: A Review of Recent Empirical Contributions. Institute of Development Studies Bulletin 27 (April):6-11. Alam, M. Shahid. 1995. "A Theory of Limits on Corruption and Some Applications." Kyklos 48(3):419-435. ---. 1989. "Anatomy of Corruption: An Approach to the Political Economy of Underdevelopment." American Journal of Economics and Sociology 48 (October):441-456. Alexander, K. C. 1994. The Process of Development of Societies. New Delhi: Sage Publications. Ames, Roger T. 1983. The Art of Rulership: A Study in Ancient Chinese Political Thought. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. Anderson, Annelise. 1995. "The Red Mafia: A Legacy of Communism." In Lazear 1995. Andreski, Stanislav. 1968. The African Predicament: A Study in the Pathology of Modernisation. NY: The Atherton Press. ---. 1966. Parasitism and Subversion: The Case of Latin America. NY: Pantheon Books. Andvig, Jens Christian, and Karl Ove Moene. 1990. "How Corruption May Corrupt." Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 13 (January):63-76. Bac, Mehmet. 1996. "Corruption, Supervision, and the Structure of Hierarchies." Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 10 (October):277-298. Bandow, Doug, and Ian Vasquez. 1994. Perpetuating Poverty: The World Bank, the IMF, and the Developing World. Washington, D. C.: The Cato Institute. Banfield, Edward C. 1958. The Moral Basis of a Backward Society. New York: The Free Press. Barkow, Jerome H., Leda Cosimides, and John Tooby, editors. 1992. The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture. New York: Oxford University Press. Basu, Kaushik, Sudipto Bhattacharya, and Ajit Mishra. 1992. "Notes on Bribery and the Control of Corruption. Journal of Public Economics 48 (August):349-359. Bates, Robert H. 1974. "Ethnic Competition and Modernization in Contemporary Africa." Comparative Political Studies 6 (January):457-484. Baumol, William J., and Kyu Sik Lee. 1991. "Contestable Markets, Trade, and Development." World Bank Research Observer 6(January) :1-18. Becker, Gary. 1968. "Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach." Journal of Political Economy 76 (March/April):169-217. Becker, Gary, and George Stigler. 1974. "Law Enforcement, Malfeasance, and Compensation of Enforcers." Journal of Legal Studies 3 (January):1-19. Berkman, Umit. 1992. "Bureaucracy and Bribery: A Conceptual Framework. International Journal of Public Administration, 15(6):1345-1368. Besley, Timothy, and John McLaren. 1993. "Taxes and Bribery: The Role of Wage Incentives." The Economic Journal 103 (January):119-141. Bicchieri, Cristina, and Carlo Rovelli. 1995. "Evolution and Revolution: The Dynamics of Corruption." Rationality and Society 7(April):201-224. Bhatia, Krishan. 1967. The Ordeal of Nationhood: A Social Study of India Since Independence. New York: Atheneum. Bikchandani, Sushil, David Hirshleifer; and Ivo Welsh. 1992. "A Theory of Fads, Fashions, Custom, and Cultural Change as Informational Cascades." Journal of Political Economy 100 (October):992-1026. Bok, Sissela. 1978. Lying: Moral Choice in Public and Private Life. New York : Pantheon Books. 27 Buchanan, James. 1975. The Limits of Liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Caiden, Gerald E., and Naomi Caiden. 1977. "Administrative Corruption." Public Administration Review 37(May-June): 302-309. Callaghy, Thomas. 1984. The State Society Struggle: Zaire in Comparative Perspective. New York: Columbia University Press. Chander, Prakash, and Louis Wilde. 1992. "Corruption in Tax Administration." Journal of Public Economics 49 (December):333-349. Cheung, Steven N. S. 1996. "A Simplistic General Equilibrium Theory of Corruption." Contemporary Economic Policy 14 (July): 1-5. Clarke, Michael, editor. 1983. Corruption, Causes, Consequences and Control. London: Pinter. Corneo, G., and O. Jeanne. 1997. "Snobs, Bandwagons, and the Origins of Social Customs in Consumer Behavior." Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 32 (March):333-347. Dahlburg, John-Thor. “India’s Diary of Corruption.” Los Angeles Times, 1 March 1996, p.A1. Dawid, Herbert, and Gustav Feichtinger. 1996. "On the Persistence of Corruption." Journal of Economics 64(2):177-193. de Leon, Peter. 1993. Thinking About Political Corruption. Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe. de Soto, Hernando. 1989. The Other Path: The Invisible Revolution in the Third World. New York: Harper and Row. Diamond, Larry. 1995. "Democracy and Economic Reform: Tensions, Compatibilities. and Strategies for Reconciliation." In Lazear 1995. Dutt, Amitava Krishna and Kwan S. Kim. 1994. "Market Miracle and State Stagnation? The Development Experience of South Korea and India Compared. In Dutt, Kwan, and Singh1994. Dutt, Amitava Krishna, Kwan S. Kim, and Ajit Singh, editors. 1994. The State, Markets and Development: Beyond the Neoclassical Dichotomy. Aldershot, U.K.: Edward Elgar. Easterly, W. 1993. "How Much Do Distortions Affect Growth?" in Journal of Monetary Economics 32 (November):187-212. Economist. 1997. "Crime and Parliament." 27 September, 1997, 45. ---. 1996. "Muck and Money." 15 June 1996, 57. ---. 1996. "Muck Spreads." 2 March 1996, 36. Efron, Sonni. 1998. "Corruption Charges Taint Agency Responsible for Regulating Banks and Extricating Nation From its Fiscal Crisis." Los Angeles Times, 28 January. Ekpo, Monday U., editor. 1979. Bureaucratic Corruption in Sub-Saharan Africa: Toward a Search for Causes and Consequences. Washington, D.C.: University Press of America. Fatton, Robert, Jr. 1992. Predatory Rule: State and Civil Society in Africa. Boulder, C.O.: Lynn Rienner Publishers. Feichtinger, Gustav, and Franz Wirl. 1994. "On the Stability and Potential Cyclicity of Corruption in Governments Subject to Popularity Constraints." Mathematical Social Sciences 28 (October):113-131. Fiorentini, Gianluca, and Sam Peltzman, editors. 1995. The Economics of Organised Crime. Cambridge: The Cambridge University Press. Gallagher, Mark. 1991. Rent Seeking and Economic Growth in Africa. Boulder, C.O.: Westview Press. Giglioli, P. P. 1996. "Political Corruption and the Media: The Tangentopoli Affair." International Social Science Journal 48 (September):381-391. Goettingen, University of, and Transparency International. 1996. Internet Corruption Rankings. June, online document at http://www.uni-goettingen.de/~uwvw/icr.htm. ---. 1995. Internet Corruption Rankings. April, online document at http://www.uni-goettingen.de/~uwvw/icr.htm. 28 Gould, David J. 1980. Bureaucratic Corruption and Underdevelopment in the Third World: The Case of Zaire. New York: Pergamon Press. Gould, David J, and Jose A. Amaro-Reyes. 1983. The Effects of Corruption on Administrative Performance: Illustrations From Developing Countries. World Bank Working Paper No. 580. Washington D. C.: The World Bank. Granovetter, Mark. 1978. "Threshold Models of Collective Behavior." American Journal of Sociology, 83(6):1420-1443. Granovetter, Mark. 1973. "The Strength of Weak Ties." American Journal of Sociology, 78(6):1360-1380. Haggard, Stephan, and Steven B. Webb. 1994. Voting For Reform: Democracy, Political Liberalization, and Economic Adjustment. Washington, D.C.: The World Bank. Hallet, Jean-Pierre. 1968 [1964]. Congo Kitabu. Reprint, NY: Random House. Heidenheimer, Arnold J., Michael Johnston, and Victor T. LeVine. 1989. Political Corruption: A Handbook. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. Hong, C. S., and K. A. Conrad. 1998. "Bandwagon Effects and Two-Party Majority Voting." Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 16 (May-June):165-172. Hope, Sr., Kempe Ronald. 1996. Development in the Third World: From Policy Failure to Policy Reform. Armonk, N. Y.: M. E. Sharpe. Huang, Peter H, and Ho-Mou Wu. 1994. "More Order Without More Law: A Theory of Social Norms and Organizational Culture." Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 10 (October):390-406. Huntington, Samuel P. 1979. "Modernization and Development." In Ekpo 1979. ---. 1968. Political Order in Changing Societies. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Huther, Jeff, and Anwar Shah. 2000. Anti-Corruption Policies and Programs: A Framework for Evaluation. World Bank Working Paper No. 2501. Washington D. C.: The World Bank. Jabbra, J. G. 1976. "Bureaucratic Corruption in the Third World." Indian Journal of Public Administration 22 (October-December):673-91. Johnston, Michael. 1996. "The Search for Definitions: The Vitality of Politics and the Issue of Corruption." International Social Science Journal. 48(September):321-335. ---. 1982. Political Corruption and Public Policy in America. Monterey, CA: Cole. Kaufmann, Daniel and Shang-Jin Wei. 1999. Does Grease Money Speed Up the Wheels of Commerce? World Bank Working Paper No. 2254. Washington D.C.: The World Bank. Khan, Mustaq H. 1996. "A Typology of Corrupt Transactions in Developing Countries." Institute of Development Studies Bulletin. 27 (April):12-18. Kiser, Edgar, and Xiaoxi Tong. 1992. "Determinants of the Amount and Type of Corruption in State Fiscal Bureaucracies: An Analysis of Late Imperial China." Comparative Political Studies 25 (October):300-331. Klitgaard, Robert. 1991a. Adjusting to Reality: Beyond "State versus Market" in Economic Development. San Francisco: ICS Press. ---. 1991b. "Gifts and Bribes." In Zeckhauser 1991. ---. 1988. Controlling Corruption. Berkeley: University of California Press. Kong, Tat Yan. 1996. "Corruption and its Institutional Foundations: The Experience of South Korea. Institute of Development Studies Bulletin. 27 (April):48-55. Krueger, Ann O. 1974. "The Political Economy of the Rent-seeking Society." American Economic Review, 64 (June):291-303. Kuran, Timur. 1995. Private Truths, Public Lies: The Social Consequences of Preference Falsification. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ---. 1991. "Now Out of Never: The Element of Surprise in the East European Revolution of 1989." World Politics. 44 (October):7-48. 29 ---. 1989. "Sparks and Prairie Fires: A Theory of Unanticipated Political Revolution." Public Choice. 61 (April):41-74. ---. 1988. "The Tenacious Past: Theories of Personal and Collective Conservatism." Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization. 10 (September):143-171. ---. 1987. "Preference Falsification, Policy Continuity and Collective Conservatism." Economic Journal. 97 (September):642-665. Lambsdorff, Johann Graf. 1998. "An Empirical Investigation of Bribery in International Trade." European Journal of Economic Development. 10 (June):40-59. Lazear, Edward P., editor. 1995. Economic Transition in Eastern Europe and Russia: Realities of Reform. Stanford, CA: The Hoover Institution Press. Leff, Nathaniel. 1989 [1964]. "Economic Development Through Bureaucratic Corruption." American Behavioral Scientist. 8 (November):8-14. Reprinted in Heidenheimer et al 1989. Leys, Colin. 1989 [1965]. "What is the Problem About Corruption?" Journal of Modern African Studies. 3 (1965):215-230. Reprinted in Heidenheimer et al 1989. Los Angeles Times. 1996. "World Bank Steps Up Attack on Global Corruption." 4 October, page D8. Lui, Francis, T. 1986. "A Dynamic Model of Corruption Deterence." Journal of Public Economics. 31 (Nov):215-236. Macrae, John. 1982. "Underdevelopment and the Economics of Corruption: A Game Theory Approach." World Development. 10 (Aug):677-687. Manion, Melanie. 1996. "Corruption by Design: Bribery in Chinese Enterprise Licensing." Journal of Law, Economics and Organization. 12 (April):167-195. Mauro, Paulo. 1995. “Corruption and Growth." Quarterly Journal of Economics, 3 (August):681-712. ---. 1994. The Composition of Government Expenditure: The Good Guys and the Bad Guys. Harvard: Harvard University, unpublished manuscript. Mbaku, John Mukum. 1996. "Bureaucratic Corruption in Africa: The Futility of Cleanups." Cato Journal. 16 (Spring):99-118. Meny, Yves. 1996. "'Fin de Siecle' Corruption: Change, Crisis and Shifting Values." International Social Science Journal. 48 (September):309-320.. Monshipouri, Mahmood, and Amjad Samuel. 1995. "Development and Democracy in Pakistan: Tenuous or Plausible Nexus?" Asian Survey. 35 (November):973-989. Mookherjee, Dilip, and I. P. L. Png. 1995. "Corruptible Law Enforcers: How Should They Be Compensated?" The Economic Journal. 105 (January):145-159. Mueller, Dennis C. 1993 [1989]. Public Choice II: A Revised Edition of Public Choice. Reprinted, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Myrdal, Gunnar. 1989a [1968]. "Corruption: Its Causes and Effects." In Asian Drama: An Enquiry into the Poverty of Nations. Vol. 2. New York: The Twentieth Century Fund, pp.937-951. Reprinted in Heidenheimer et al 1989. ---. 1989b [1968]. "Corruption as a Hindrance to Modernization in South Asia." In Asian Drama: An Enquiry into the Poverty of Nations. Vol. 2. New York: The Twentieth Century Fund, 951-958. Reprinted in Heidenheimer et al 1989. Noonan, John T., Jr. 1984. Bribes. New York: Macmillan. North, Douglass C. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance. Cambridge, UK: The Cambridge University Press. Nye, J. S. 1989 [1967]. "Corruption and Political Development: A Cost-Benefit Analysis." American Political Science Review, (June):417-27. Reprinted in Heidenheimer et al 1989. 30 Olsen, T. E. and G. Torsvik. 1998. Collusion and Renegotiation in Hierarchies: A Case of Beneficial Corruption. University of Bergen Economics Department Working Paper. Bergen, Norway: University of Bergen. Olson, Mancur. 1982. The Rise and Decline of Nations. New Haven: Yale University Press. Ostrom, Elinor, Larry Schroeder, and Susan Wynne. 1993. Institutional Incentives and Sustainable Development: Infrastructure Policies in Perspective. Boulder, C.O.: Westview Press. Pavarala, Vinod. 1996. Interpreting Corruption: Elite Perspectives in India. New Delhi: Sage Publications. Pritchett, Lant. 1995. Where Has All the Education Gone? World Bank Discussion Paper. Quah, Jon S. T. 1989. "Singapore's Experience in Curbing Corruption." In Heidenheimer et al 1989. Rasmusen, E, and J. M. Ramseyer. 1994. "Cheap Bribes and the Corruption Ban: A Coordination Game Among Rational Legislators." Public Choice. 78 (March):305-327. Root, Hilton. 1996. "Corruption in China: Has it Become Systemic?" Asian Survey, 36 (August):741-757. Rose-Ackerman, Susan. 1996. "Democracy and 'Grand' Corruption". International Social Science Journal. 48 (September):365-380. ---. 1978. Corruption: A Study in Political Economy. New York: Academic Press. Sandler, Todd. 1992. Collective Action: Theory and Applications. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press. Schelling, Thomas C. 1978. Micromotives and Macrobehavior. New York: W. W. Norton & Co. Scott, James C. 1985 Weapons of the Weak: Everyday Forms of Peasant Resistance. New Haven, C.T.: Yale University Press. ---. 1972. Comparative Public Corruption. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall. Shah, Anwar. 1997. “Fostering Responsive and Accountable Governance: Lessons from Decentralization Experience." Paper presented at the World Bank Conference on Evaluation and Development: The Institutional Dimension in Washington. Shleifer, Andrei, and Robert W. Vishny. 1993. "Corruption." Quarterly Journal of Economics. 108 (August):599-617. Stevens, Mike, and Shiro Gnanaselvam. 1996. "The World Bank and Governance." Institute of Development Studies Bulletin. 26 (April):97-105. Sturzenegger, Federico, and Mariano Tommasi. 1994. "The Distribution of Political Power, the Costs of Rent-Seeking, and Economic Growth." Economic Inquiry. 32 (April):236-248. Tanzi, Vito. 1995. "Corruption: Arm's-Length Relationships and Markets." In Fiorentini and Peltzman 1995. Tanzi, Vito, and Hamid Davoodi. 1998. Roads to Nowhere: How Corruption in Public Investment Hurts Growth. Economic Issues #12. Washington, D.C.: The International Monetary Fund. Tharoor, Shashi. 1997. India: From Midnight to the Millennium. New York: Arcade Press. Theobald, Robin. 1990. Corruption, Development and Underdevelopment. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press. Thompson, D. F. 1993. "Mediated Corruption: The Case of the Keating Five." American Political Science Review. 87 (June):369-381. Tirole, Jean. 1996. "A Theory of Collective Reputations (With Applications to the Persistence of Corruption and to Firm Quality). Review of Economic Studies. 63 (January):1-22. Tollison, Robert D.1982. "Rent Seeking: A Survey." Kyklos. 35(4):575-602. Tullock, Gordon. 1996. "Corruption Theory and Practice." Contemporary Economic Policy. 14 (July):6-13. ---. 1967. "The Welfare Costs of Tariffs, Monopolies and Theft." Western Economic Journal. 5 (June):224-232. Van Rijckeghem, Caroline, and Beatrice Weder. 1997. Corruption and the Rate of Temptation: Do Low Wages in the Civil Service Cause Corruption? International Monetary Fund Working Paper #WP/97/73. Washington DC: International Monetary Fund. Wade, Robert. 1989. "Politics and Graft: Recruitment, Appointment, and Promotions to Public Office in India." In Ward 1989. 31 ---. 1985. "The Market for Public Office: Why the Indian State is not Better at Development." World Development 13 (April):467-497. Ward, Peter, editor. 1989. Corruption, Development and Inequality: Soft Touch or Hard Graft? London: Routledge. Waterbury, John. 1973 [1989]. "Endemic and Planned Corruption in a Monarchical Regime." World Politics 25(4):533-555. Reprinted in Heidenheimer et al 1989. Wei, Shang-Jin. 1999. Corruption in Economic Development: Beneficial Grease, Minor Annoyance, or Major Obstacle? World Bank Working Paper No. 2048. Washington D. C.: The World Bank. ---. 1997. Why is Corruption so Much More Taxing Than Tax? Arbitrariness Kills. National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper #6255. Wilson, James, Q. 1993. The Moral Sense. New York: The Free Press. Wilson, Peter J. 1967. A Malay Village and Malaysia. New Haven, CT: Hraf Press. Whitehead, Laurence. 1989 [1983]. "On Presidential Graft: The Latin American Evidence." In Clarke 1983. Reprinted in Heidenheimer et al 1989. Witt, Ulrich. 1989. "The Evolution of Economic Institutions as a Propagation Process." Public Choice. 62 (August):155-172. Zeckhauser, Richard, editor. 1991. Strategy and Choice. Cambridge M.A.: The MIT Press.