Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Democratic Theory and the Problem of Rights: Reflections on Labor Regimes.* Reproaching Prussian parliamentary liberals in 1862 for imagining that they could rely on a liberal reading of constitutional rights to counter arbitrary action by the Prussian regime, Lasalle said: "Constitutional issues are not at bottom juristic issues, but questions of power. The real national constitution has its being only in the actual power relations subsisting in the nation. Written constitutions have value and durability only when they accurately represent the prevailing power relations." Die Verfassungsreden. Eduard Bernstein, ed. Berlin: Cassirer, 1919 vol. 2, p. 60. Lasalle insisted that effective constitutions are to be taken as nothing more than written statements of power relations. The rulers of a state can freely ignore things written in the constitution so long as they have the power to do so and find it in their interest. The power, in turn, is a function of their control over coercive machinery and, ultimately, their command over the means of physical violence. When opponents of a regime wrap themselves in constitutional assurances, they bare their weakness. The servants of power do not require such poor disguises: "The royal regime, gentlemen, has practical servants, not orators, such practical servants as one wishes you." (Ibid.) But Lasalle's vigorous statements do not really make the case against the "actions" of jurists and the political pertinence of legal argument as clear as all that. Already in the first of his two speeches on constitutions, he had indicated that the effectiveness and bias of the regime's administrative and judicial law-enforcement machinery are as important as its control over arms, contrasting the readiness with * Paper presented at Centre of Criminology, University of Toronto, February 16, 1988 1 which Englishmen, as he supposes, take arms against usurping magistrates, with German docility. Moreover, he cites the overwhelming potential for power possessed by the people and maintains that it can be made actual and decisive by means of organization. In his second address, then, given a few months later, he treated the power of the regime and of its opponents as importantly determined by the distribution of legitimacy. On the premise that the spectacle of interplay between parliament and ministers had become an important support for the regime's legitimacy, he urged the oppositional parliamentarians to boycott parliament, as a counter to the regime's unauthorized military policy. Once the legitimating impact of legal forms is given substantial weight and the possibility is raised that power relations may be changed by means of levers internal to the legal order, the relevance of what jurists do when they engage in the contest to establish law appears much more substantial. I begin with two very general questions: (1) How do demands made on legal institutions work back on the design of legal institutions? (2) How do changes in the design of legal institutions work back on the general design of political institutions, what A.D. Lindsay called the effective constitution? The most familar modern theoretical approaches to these questions are: (1) Liberal theories, centered since Dicey's time on the concept of "rule of law.” The generality, concreteness, universality of law are undermined by the demands on law characteristic of the regulatory and/or welfare state. The decline of the rule of law in this sense corresponds to a rise in arbitrary rule and the transformation of the political 2 system (e.g., Friedrich Hayek, Theodore Lowi). (2) Progressive theories of legal development, often associated with evolutionary theories, treat changes in forms as adaptations to changing demands generated by changing social needs (or expectations) and the central problem is to keep changing legal principles and procedures to make them serviceable to law as a principal instrument of orderly social change. Failures in these respects undermine democracy as a method of collective problem solving for the public (e.g., Phillip Nonet and Philip Selznick, Lawrence Friedman, J. Willard Hurst). (3) Marxist theories of law as bourgeois ideology, masking and/or actualizing class domination through the state. This conventional classification scheme only hints at the available range of sophisticated and richly elaborated versions of these respective approaches, and it ignores important differences within each category. Present purposes are sufficiently served if this familiar material helps to situate our more detailed analyses of narrower issues within the wider context to which they belong. Two representative contemporary formulations will be compared below. This examination will show, I hope, why I prefer to explore these sweeping questions in the more densely differentiated settings of specific issue-areas. Our interest is in political theory; our work requires legal politological analyses. The relations between power and law are matters of patterned nuances, not sweeping assertions. The legal regulation of labor relations is often accorded a special status in both law and political theory. Its special status in law arises from the difficulties of reconciling the principal instruments and institutions of private law (whether common law or 3 codified) with the demands, conflicts, and social innovations generated by the interplay between dependent labor and employers. Accordingly, the field has been governed at least in important part by distinctive "labor codes" legislatively setting down norms and procedures to regulate certain aspects of these relations. A striking feature of much of this legislation, however, is first, that it exemplifies regulation by very imprecise principles, leaving much to the discretion of administrators or courts, and, second, that it is often designed to give legal effect to shifting bargains struck among contending social actors whose legally recognized diverse social identities, resources and functions differ markedly from the general attributes of personality that modern legal systems normally claim to make central, especially in the law of contract. These aspects appear, for example, in the persistent attention to status in legally-set standards of "fairness" in wages, hours, and other conditions of employment and conditions of work. They appear even more strikingly in legal treatment of the activities and organizations surrounding collective bargaining between organized employees and employers, as exemplified, for instance by the diverse legislative innovations that have been used to deal with the difficulties that most most modern legal systems have had in comprehending the legal effects of collective agreements in relation to individual contracts of employment. As both Max Weber and Emil Durkheim pointed out nearly a century ago, the law of employment puts special pressure on the legal system that the former characterized as formally rational in principle and tendency. For political theorists whose conception of "rule of law" approximates closely to Weber's model of formal rationality, with its Kantian background, -- and this includes most thinkers oriented to 4 continental Liberalism (Hayek, Lowi, Neumann) -- these aspects of labor law make it a matter of considerable concern. Converging with this are analyses grounded on conceptions of individual substantive rights of free contract. There has been a century of resourceful speculation within both mainstreams of liberal political thought, seeking to mitigate or overcome this stubborn pervasive anomaly, and we will return to some contemporary efforts. But the problems cannot be said to have been rendered obsolete from the liberal point of view. What law does with regard to labor relations has a major impact on the kind of law prevailing in the civil sphere and it has a major impact on the kinds of collective actions and achievements that are accepted as helping to shape the social context of the political constitution. The demands on legal institutions first arise most evidently in the context of court actions -- some prosecutions (e.g., criminal conspiracy), civil litigation in torts and contracts, and actions in various magisterial courts. Then comes legislation and, now the preponderant contexts of administrative and regulatory law. Throughout, the developments are importantly played out through institutions of non-state law. We can leave aside for now the question of whether to consider these as part of the "legal institutions" in the sense of our first basic question or as manifestations of demands. Periodically, the demands (and their consequences) expressly become matters of constitutional law, as in the contexts to be discussed. Because of the special ambiguities attaching to constitutional law, its intermediate position between questions of power and questions of law, such constitutionalizing can also be understood as a locus of new political demands on the labor regime. To sort through this welter of possibilities, then, I use the concept "labor regime" 5 to characterize the pattern of juridified institutions established within a given labor market at any given time, serving to orient expectations and actions in the relationships among state and non-state actors. As employed here, the term "regime" draws on two distinct usages. While lawyers often use it to refer to the complex of juridified regulations governing some issue domain, recent international relations theory has broadened and deepened the concept. The distinctive feature of "regime" in that context, and the feature that makes it of interest to us, is that it emphasizes not only the quasi-legalistic "principles, norms, rules and decision-makers" around that the expectations of the relevant political actors converge in a given issue area over an identifiable period of time but also the power constellation that conditions the effectiveness of the institution in question. The institution is not reduced to the power factors and the power factors are not idealistically denied. Among students of international relations, the point of the concept has been to qualify the monistic "realism" that has dominated their study during the past generation, to facilitate inquiry into the causal importance of quasi-legalized institutions where and when they can be discerned, without denying the general force of power-oriented systemic theory (Keohane, 1986). In adapting the regime concept to the constitution and development of institutions in certain intranational issue-areas, the point is to conceptualize institutions that have an important irreducible legal component but that are shaped in important measure by the non-legal power resources that participants bring into play. The lawyer's "regime" thus provides the starting point for analysis, but the complex of norms and regulations is understood "realistically,” in conjunction with the competing political designs at work in the field. 6 As a constituted pattern, a regime embodies a measure of resistance to disruptive change; it places constraints upon the forms and exercises of power deployed; but these characteristics differ significantly in degree from regime to regime and from time to time in the life of a regime. A regime may be said to intend a preferred type of outcome, but this design will be established in a structural tendency, subject to even quite important exceptions, and not in a purely instrumental machinery. Regimes differ as to complexity, flexibility, and tolerance of inner inconsistency or conflict, but all display that visible blend of legal manner and power factors that mark the theory of international law that is the paradigm for the concept itself (cp. Korsch, 1972). The reconstitution of a regime -- i.e., a change in its structural tendency -- implies a shift in the underlying power constellation. In the study of labor, then, regime refers to the institutionalized political organization of labor markets, comprising the patterned interactions among state agencies and collectivities of workers and employers. When applied to the current scene in Canada or the United States, the concept recombines the elements that are conventionally distinguished as the industrial relations system and its public policy environment. Without denying the possibility of a type of regime in which a collective bargaining system is governed by a state-maintained settlement, the conceptual shift facilitates inquiry into the political dynamics of such a regime, as well as into historical sources and alternatives. When I speak of "demands" on the law in this context, then, I mean demands on such a regime arising either from outside of its institutions or from developments within its institutions that change their social functions and effects. All three of the theoretical traditions broadly characterized above have paid 7 special attention to developments in the labor regime and have assigned them importance beyond the immediate policy consequences for the organization of the labor market. If we take Max Weber and Emile Durkheim as offering alternative twentieth-century formulations relevant to liberal legal politology, it is worth noting that both identify anomalies and innovations in labor law as posing unique challenges to the liberal legal order, especially to the institution of contract. Von Mises and Hayek simplify the liberal response, rejecting central features of most advanced labor regimes on high political grounds. For progressives, as witness the historically important themes of industrial democracy and labor legislation, the emergence of collective bargaining and related demands provides a decisive opportunity for reconstituting the "bundle of powers" comprehended by the institution of property so as to orient the law to the needs of persons under modern conditions. John R. Commons and Philip Selznick would be representative Americans, while Lujo Brentano and Hugo Sinzheimer are the most important German names. Whether to include McKenzie King in this company is very debatable, but there is no shortage of Canadians. In Marxist thought, the labor regime is of course the locus of the decisive relationships within the capitalist order. This is where the exploitation of labor takes place and where the class conflict is ultimately grounded and reproduced. Accordingly, questions about the kinds of changes that can take place within this domain without revolutionary overthrow have been especially stimulating and divisive in this tradition, as have conflicting interpretations of developments. To illustrate analytical problems and to suggest some of my own substantive 8 theses, I propose to compare two treatments of a similar new factor in the constitution of two labor regimes. The factor is the introduction of a constitutional bill of rights, with the concommitant question about judicial review of legislation. The first case involves Part II of the Weimar Constitution (enacted in 1919), and the representative response to be considered is that of the Socialist labor lawyer, Franz L. Neumann; the second case deals with David Beatty's recent writings on the effects of the Canadian Charter of Rights upon Canadian labor law. A principal reference point common to both is the relationship between the respective constitutional guarantees of equality (RV 109 and Charter Section 15(1)["Every individual is equal before and under the law and has the right to equal protection and equal benefit of the law without discrimination ..."]) and the powers of labor unions within the respective labor regimes. In terms of our simplistic trifurcation of approaches, both must be treated as hybrid cases, with Neumann representing a Marxism that is very strongly tinged by progressivism and Beatty representing an ingenious mix of liberal and progressive elements. Any deeper analysis of the issues, however, must abandon these preliminary heuristic schematizations. I promise you that I will not engage in the pointless exercise of debating whether Neumann is "really" a Marxist or Beatty "merely" a liberal. It is pointless to reify such ideal types. The illuminating theoretical issues between them concern the contrasts between predominantly collectivist (or institutionalist) and individualist readings of basic constitutional guarantees affecting social rights, and between two theories of democracy. My own view is that Beatty's analysis is shown by the comparison to be seriously flawed, but that it suggests important correctives to Neumann's historically 9 dated and radically incomplete design. There are obvious objections to the comparison between Neumann and Beatty. The constitutional provisions at issue are very different, as are the legal systems and the labor regimes. Most difficult, political theory treatment of juristic texts must bear in mind the performative or forensic dimensions of such interventions: legal discourse is directed to legal doctrine and attempts to reshape doctrine. Its theorizing must be constrained within that frame of reference if it is to work as legal discourse. A politicaltheory-grounded critique of such texts, accordingly, involves a measure of translation and thus distortion and cannot presume to provide more than a critical perspective for the legal theorist. But I think that it is possible to learn by putting the hardest of these difficulties aside, and factoring out the others. The respective bills of rights are very different. Among other varied details, the Weimar charter of rights and duties expressly guarantees labor the right to unionization and to an organized voice in certain vaguely delimited economic matters, while it also guarantees the right to private property, as defined by law. The Canadian Charter is silent on both points. The fundamental differences between the two legal systems matter perhaps less than might be expected, in the respects of interest here, since Weimar constitutional jurisprudence was surprisingly oriented to American developments, including some appropriations of the emerging sociological jurisprudence (with paradoxical effects). Two contrasts must be noted, however. The Weimar Constitution, unlike the Canadian Charter, makes no express provision for judicial review (and arguably assigns special responsibilities to the President as "guardian of the constitution"). More strikingly, the 10 German legal system, and especially the higher courts, accepted the demands of the Weimar Constitution only selectively, treating many of them as barely binding in law or construing them in terms of a judge-made higher law of the German state, built upon the more general clauses in the Civil Code (especially important with regard to the substantive rendering of the equality clause: RV 109). These points are important because they doubtless enter into Neumann's rejection of judicial review in defense of equality claims. But they don't explain the argument away, in my view. The two labor regimes share general features. In both, the central institutional design comprises self-regulation through collective bargaining between autonomous organizations of employers and workers, aiming at collective agreements superior to individual contracts of employment with regard to the norms and procedures laid down in them. In both cases as well, this autonomous design is massively limited by state intervention and regulation, that is only partially qualified in turn by neo-corporatist mechanisms of consultation and negotiation and by electoral organizations of the labor movements. But the labor regimes differ in many respects, including aspects of special importance to Beatty. Specifically, the Weimar labor regime provides for works' councils in larger enterprises, and it eschews the familiar North American rule of exclusive representation for administratively determined bargaining units. These differences are not relevant to the logic of Neumann's analyses, however, because he is hostile to works' councils as anything other than local agencies of unions and because he aspires to a unified union movement, that would enjoy monopoly of representation. In other words, they do nothing to explain the contrasting approaches. It might be objected finally that it is rather absurd to seek instruction from 11 arguments designed to bolster the Weimar system, except perhaps as object lessons of things to avoid at all costs. I will proceed, however, on the assumption that responsibility for the failure of Weimar lay elsewhere. Neumann and Beatty are alike in that both employ teleological constitutional analyses to ground their interpretations of the demands made by constitutionally guaranteed rights. All specific provisions of their respective constitutions, they maintain, must be interpreted by reference to a central purposive design (or sovereign commitment). For both, the highest normative principle concerns the advance of social egalitarianism. Neumann speaks of actualizing a social Rechtstaat -- an order that institutionalizes processes of progressive social democratization, while Beatty finds a "right to equality of liberty,” (cp. Dworkin) a principle that first of all empowers action in behalf of individual autonomy for the most dependent. Applied to the labor regime, these similar-sounding fundamental norms have quite different consequences. Neumann argues that the actualization of social rights depends primarily on the inner dynamics of the institutions that have been achieved in the struggle for such rights. The principal actors within those institutions are collective ones, and the decisive constitutional guarantees are those that give optimal safeguards to the effective actors whose dynamism inclines them towards the normative goal. The constitutional guarantee of equality, accordingly, must either be very narrowly construed to deal with the most essential safeguards of legal procedure or it must be construed as a non-justiciable regulative principle for collective actors. It must never be usable as a basis for individual claims against the institutions and forces of progressive change. Parliament is important here, but no less important are socially generated institutions 12 that serve social right without legislative juridification. His analysis is specified by reference to arguably discriminatory regulations and proposals in labor law that favor unions over employers in certain respects, such as asymmetrical rights of legal representation and standing to sue for enforcement of collective agreements, as well as challenges to the proposition that the right to strike somehow implies a balancing right to lock out: unions represent great collective interests, Neumann maintains, while employers represent nothing except the private interests of the proprietors. Beatty contends that Charter rights must be understood as progressive levers of change in the labor regime. Because of the special character of Section 1 of the Canadian Charter ["The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms guarantees the rights and freedoms set out in it subject only to such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society"], his argument proceeds in two stages. He argues for a very wide interpretation of the acts and sources of power to which the guarantees of individual freedom in Section 2 ["Everyone has the following fundamental freedoms: a) Freedom of conscience and religion; b) freedom of thought, belief, opinion and expression, including freedom of the press and other media of communication; c) freedom of peaceful assembly; and d) freedom of association."] apply: so, for example, he treats all actions by unions as instances of the state actions that the Charter limits, because of the role of state regulation in the labor regime through the certification of unions, the legal enforcement of the universal agency shop, the recognition of legislative powers in collective agreements, and the like. He also argues that the "reasonable limits" clause of Section 1, authorizing exceptional legislated incursions on guaranteed individual rights if they can be "demonstrably 13 justified in a free and democratic society" should be read as a charter for revising the power relations between strong and weak in society. With "equal rights to liberty" as the basic principle of the Charter, he maintains, the incursions permitted -- and in fact promoted -- are primarily those that make for greater equality, provided also that standards of proportionality are met -- i.e., that the gains in individual empowerment are sufficient and that the losses in established individual rights are minimal. He applies this line of analysis to a number of issues in Canadian labor law, including mandatory retirement and the exclusion of certain classes of workers from the principal labor regime, but ends up by denying the constitutionality of a central feature of the labor regime, viz., the concept of exclusive representation by the union certified for a given bargaining unit. This denies individual choice in matters of association without a proportional compensation in the empowerment of the least advantaged. To achieve the valid ends of the legislation entering into the labor regime, he maintains, it must be reoriented in the direction of works' councils, where the workers' collectivity is formed on lines more egalitarian than in the exclusive collective bargaining agent model. I don't have the time to attempt an immanent critique of the legal arguments adduced by the authors to defend their positions, although I have difficulties with both. Instead, I want to call attention to two points of contrast. The first is that Neumann conceptually links rights to historically differentiated collective actors in institutions, making that a central feature of what he calls socialist jurisprudence and grounding his position in the Marxist critique of individual property rights, while Beatty introduces social considerations only at the point of balancing competing individual claims of right, although he also thinks that the design as a whole somehow introduces a dynamism 14 tending towards such occasions, construing Section 1 less as a statement of exceptions than as a mandate for change. The second is that Beatty treats the labor regime as wholly juridified, by virtue of the important part that law plays in its operations, while Neumann expressly treats it as constituted by changing constellations of interactions between socially autonomous and state regulative factors. The historical differences do not explain this contrast. It is above all this difference in the ways that the authors treat the composition of power and law in this field that makes the comparison especially theoretically fruitful. The differences in the interpretations of rights gain their full meaning only in the context of the contrasting political theories, specifically in contrasting theories of democracy. Writing in Germany in 1929, when he was still a practicing Socialist labor lawyer and not yet the academic political theorist he was to become in exile, Franz L. Neumann (1929) warned against impending legislation designed to authorize and regulate the emerging Weimar practice of judicial review. Letting judges assay the constitutionality of legislative acts would threaten the collective gains already achieved by labor, he maintained, and impede the movement towards industrial and social democracy. The rights and duties laid down in the second part of the Weimar Constitution can contribute to democratization, as they are meant to do, only if their actualization is left under the ultimate control of democratic political and social processes (Neumann, 1930). At the modern stage of development, according to Neumann, liberal guarantees of individual rights against the state, especially as these are construed by courts, are ideological camouflage for the power of proprietors who are in fact no longer individuals in any important sense. While the inner logic of the constitution's guarantees, positive and 15 social, clearly points beyond such ideological individualism, the constitution's language still reflects the element of compromise in the republic's foundation and leaves ample room for the old anti-social jurisprudence. Moreover, for the judiciary to become the final arbiters of the constitution would contradict the socially democratic design of the constitution itself. The only way of reading the guarantees of fundamental rights in the Weimar Constitution consistent with either democratic theory or socialist jurisprudence, in his view, is to take them as formative commitments to self-rule, governed above all by an egalitarian social ideal, i.e., as recognitions and constitutive empowerments of ongoing democratic political and social processes. According to Neumann, these processes comprise institutional developments in the social sphere as much as public policy in law and administration, and they spawn patterns of collective mobilization and assertion against the vested powers of property, as well as partially legalized provisional collective bargains with it. But many of these dearly bought and still embattled achievements are juristically vulnerable to challenges based on individual rights and equality before the law in the liberal sense. In this context, judicial review would simply reinforce the uses of the legal system as a prime instrument of arbitrary control in the service of the class interests and class forces that have been otherwise thrown on the defensive by the advances of collective democracy (Fraenkel, 1930; see Luthardt, 1986; Kettler and Meja, 1988). According to this socialist jurisprudence, the actualization of the rights decisive to labor depends on the vitality of popular social movements, their penetration into authoritative institutions, including the specialized legal forums for labor law, and the responsiveness of lawmakers and the legal system to these social achievements. 16 Behind Neumann, of course, there is the whole Marxist tradition, whose central tenet is its distinctive critique of the liberal doctrine of the individual labor contract. More narrowly, there is the reformist pluralist current within that tradition, that looks to collectivization of relations between labor and capital as a series of strategic steps in the progressive expropriation of capital through an expropriation of its functions (Sinzheimer, 1927; Renner, 1929; Kettler, 1984; Kettler, 1986). For Neumann, democracy is collective popular power articulated through historically apt designs for action, principally through majoritarian parliamentary rule and social organization for the displacement of property-grounded power. Institutions are construed on the model of collective agreements: they give a measure of stability for a time, reflecting the balance of forces at that time. The rationality of the whole can only be shown by a characterization of the whole epoch, since it is impossible to do more than to minimize the role of power in its more arbitrary forms in a development inherently marked by conflict and uncertainties. A constitutional commitment to the democratic process is not empty, since it represents a collective agreement of substantial weight, but it cannot be left in the safekeeping of a high court that is structurally distant from if not hostile to this dynamic reality. Consequently, judicial review is wrong not only because it is likely to result in regressive judgments but also because it removes key issues out of the democratic process, misleadingly obscuring their political character and thus contradicting by its operations even the most favorable decisions. Beatty deprecates politics. Democracy means a maximum of individual autonomy for all. Politics allocates values on the basis of power, that is unequally 17 distributed and dependent on factors that politics cannot attack, unless it is controlled by reason. Social reason undergoes a progressive development over time, but political representation does not adequately reflect it. Law must do so. The constitutional settlement embodies the new substantively democratic social ethics. A legal process centered on "constitutional conversation" gives virtual representation to the politically unrepresented; it institutionalizes substantive reason. Jurisprudence oriented to judicial review is the centerpiece of democratic development because it produces and reproduces authoritative constitutional conversation. Stated so baldly, both positions appear extremist and implausible; and we know that neither author lacks the ingenuity to subtilize their analyses so that they can comprehend details and distinctions in interesting ways. Political theoretical models encompass legal theories in loose ways, as I have noted earlier, and the question of their proper logical relations cannot be further explored here. I simply want to acknowledge that we are dealing with two sharp lawyers here, as well as political theorists whose work is questionable at important points. Beatty's challenge to the collective labor regime in Canada wrongly abandons already jeopardized collective rights to an individual rights analysis and to a judicialized process that cannot perform as he wishes. A jurisprudence informed by democratic political theory should rather build on potentialities in the Charter for protecting/strengthening institutionalized democratic relations and democratizing forces, following Neumann's line of thinking. The fundamental freedoms of Section 2 must be understood to address individuals in the concrete relations that give actuality to these abstractions: these are more likely to be collective and institutional than individual. 18 To counteract unwanted conservative implications of institutionalism, it is necessary, first, to avoid false harmonistic theories of institutions, and, second, to develop a lean theory of minimal participation rights and "principles of fundamental justice" (Section 7: "Everyone has the right to life, liberty and security of the person and the right not to be deprived thereof except in accordance with the principles of fundamental justice" [explicated in sections 8-14]) for actors within institutions. The case study illustrates some general problems of legal politology. In the end, the question about the effects of new demands proved to be a contested question whose answer depends in important part on political choices. My response to the question about the impact of constitutional demands on the labor regime derives from a political position that distrusts the total juridification of social issues that is implicit in Beatty's response, not merely because of distrust of judicial intervention at all levels but also because I think that questions of law are better answered when questions of democratic power are given their due. 19 The Reconstitution of the Welfare State: A Latent Social-Democratic Legacy* 1. The "Crisis" of the Welfare State and the Law The great challenge to contemporary political analysis and theoretical reflection is posed by the much-discussed "crisis" of the welfare state in the wealthy nations of western Europe and North America, by the attendant dramatic reversals of public policy in several of the leading nations, and by the widespread loss of confidence and political initiative among the welfare state's dedicated partisans (Dunn, 1984). Although it is historically accurate enough to say that "the essence of the welfare state is government-protected minimum standards of income, nutrition, health, housing, and education, assured to every citizen as a right, not as a charity" (Wilensky, 1975, p. 1), a broader use of the term seems justified by usage in the literature (Lowi, 1985), as well as by analytical considerations. The new classes of expenditures and guarantees to which the historical definition refers have been everywhere closely intertwined with regulatory and planning measures, as well as with characteristic developments in the organization of government and the constitution of the political process. As Luhmann has pointed out, the welfare state utilizes law as well as money in the attempt to compensate all citizens for disadvantaged interests (Luhmann, 1981: pp. 25-32). Fiscal problems doubtless have fueled the allegations of "crisis,” but the debate is by no means limited to issues directly affecting the public budget. The contemporary attack is aimed against the whole complex of developments associated with the great "push" in *Law & Society Review, 21:1 (1987), pp. 9-47 20 the direction of the welfare state, that Jürgen Habermas correctly identifies as the central political development of the twentieth century in these nations (Habermas, 1981). According to many journalistic and merely ideological treatments, this "crisis" refers mainly to the presumed excesses and consequent failures of redistributive fiscal policies and regulatory interventions in autonomous social processes, especially economic ones. The troubling manifestations of "crisis,” it is argued, can be readily overcome by replacing the defective policies with ones that restore earlier emphases on non-governmental mechanisms of distribution and social control. Cutbacks and deregulation are the easy answer. More serious analyses of recent developments, however, recognize that much more than policies are being tested. The disappointment of well-established expectations as a result of fiscal retrenchment, for example, shakes the foundations of complex social interdependencies (Glendon, 1981). Similarly, de-regulation implies reallocations of power among organized collective social actors, as well as changes in its forms. The progressive dismantling of the "neo-corporatist" arrangements, that have only recently been identified as constitutive of the most developed welfare states (Berger, 1981), affects important sources of integration and legitimacy. In sum, the issues raised by the debate concerning the welfare state are constitutional, in a functional sense, if not always in a legal one. They affect the forms and contents of the rules that in fact define the norms for authoritative rule-making; they point towards that intersection of legalized standards and publicly effective power that constitute the order of the state. Correspondingly, welfare state malfunctionings have often been measured by 21 such signs of legitimacy deficit as the surprising dimensions of an "unobserved economy" outside the law (Feige, 1980), the increasing recourse to direct action by hitherto quiescent groups (from blockades by private truckers to doctors' strikes), and -most importantly -- selective non-enforcement and extensive disobedience of regulatory law (Reidegeld, 1980; Voigt, 1980; Weiler, 1983; Reich, 1984; Teubner, 1984). The welfare state involves more than just an institutionalized complex of priorities and commitments in public policy and a concommitant structure of corporate access to and participation in public power. It also entails some shift in the predominant character of law and in the effective constitutional framework that defines it. Most remarked over the years have been the rising importance of administrative regulatory law governed by statutes laying down only the most general purposive principles, and the consequent narrowing of the domain of ordinary judge's law, whether civil or common (Hedemann, 1934; Jones, 1958; Unger, 1976; Nonet and Selznick, 1978; Mitnick, 1980; Hayek, 1973, 1976, 1979; Bernier and Lajoie, 1986). With this attenuation of the older pattern of "legalism," historically important in the traditional constitutional designs of all these nations (Shklar 1964), multi-partite consultation and negotiation had become an increasingly important underpinning for decisions and adjudications that would otherwise appear one-sidedly politicized (Harter 1982). For over a generation, such structures and processes appeared to ground a new constitutional consensus and to provide a framework for a stable legitimation of incrementally-rising expectations (Lindblom 1966). The most recent years, however, have seen a sequence of forceful political challenges to this system, resistance movements, delegitimation, and now claims that earlier legalistic forms of constitutionalism can and must be restored (Lowi, 22 1979). In the context of legal discussion, issues are often formulated as problems of "(hyper-)legalization," and countermeasures are presented as steps to de-regulate or de-juridify, so as to restore individual autonomy (Tribe, 1979, Seibel, 1980, Mitnick, 1980, Wilson, 1980; cp. Friedman, 1985). The legal dimension commands attention because much of the contemporary debate about responses to the "crisis" of the welfare state turns on the precise character of its legal and constitutional features and their consequences. When the welfare state could be taken as established beyond fundamental questioning, several influential writers argued that this development should be legally confirmed by giving the most secure legal recognition possible to the new "social rights" (Marshall, 1949: 1965; Reich, 1964; Glendon, 1981) that the political settlements of the welfare state had been thought to give social standing equivalent to constitutional rights. As the factual premises of these arguments are undermined by current shifts in policy, supporters of institutionalized welfare guarantees decry the abandonment of essential experiments in social justice, rational planning of social development, and democratization, while conceding that there has been something seriously wrong with the constitutional and legal order of established welfare states, and that changes can therefore not be avoided (Voigt 1980; Voigt, 1986; Mishra, 1984). Many proponents of the welfare state, in short, agree that the contemporary "crisis" is a symptom of substantial shortcomings in the design and not merely a function of transitory swings in political opinion or unfavorable economic conjunctures. They often acknowledge that the welfare state poses the problem of the limits of law, and that the problem has broad constitutional ramifications, but they will not accept an abandonment of the larger political aspirations (Görliz and 23 Voigt, 1985; Bernier and Lajoie, 1986). Their opponents, as noted, have no such reservations. They charge that the demands and procedures imposed on the legal system by welfare state developments inevitably disrupt its capacity to function in a way consonant with constitutionalism (Lowi, 1979; Lowi, 1985). For them the most recent developments substantiate forty-year-old claims that the emerging pattern of state interventions would be antithetical to the legal and constitutional systems presupposed by representative democracy (Hayek, 1944). They accordingly welcome steps away from the welfare state as movement towards restoration of "constitutionalism,” and they minimize their social or political costs. The primary objections to this position begin with the maldistribution of the ensuing costs and benefits, especially since measures of "de-legalization" cannot but be designed in a highly selective way. Almost fifty years ago, Karl Mannheim (1940; Kettler, Meja, and Stehr, 1984) pointed out that the integration and steering of modern societies has become dependent on highly complex and powerful social techniques. Methods of organization, communication and direction have become available whose operations profoundly disturb such mechanisms as the market and parliamentary government, upon which the constitution of social order and the direction of public policy had rested during the classical liberal era. Since these methods are concentrated in the hands of powerful social actors, a measure of control over the uses of these techniques appears indispensable to the maintenance of a public interest or commonwealth. There must be adequate control over controls. And that means, of course, a measure of control over the actors whose power these techniques so greatly enhance. Mannheim 24 imagined that "planning" provides a master technique that can coordinate and control all these effects for the sake of a common purpose that it is also competent to define and to legitimate. We have good reason not to share his faith in such a universal solvent (Dunn, 1984). But the insufficiencies of the institutional responses projected two generations ago or implemented in the interim do not detract from the soundness of his basic social observation, reaffirmed repeatedly since. While it is possible and indeed desirable to make shifts and changes among the steering and allocation mechanisms deployed by governments, perhaps even quite radical ones, it is impossible to suppose that all purposive attempts to orient, coordinate and steer the enormous social powers generated by contemporary social technology can be simply abandoned. Nor are the proponents of "de-legalization" seriously proposing to do so. Public authority and power are to be realigned so as to make them work in closer accord with institutions of social control different from the presently influential neo-corporatist and public administrative ones, that are to be weakened. That these alternative institutions, misleadingly apostrophized as "markets" or "spontaneous social order" (Hayek, 1978-81; Loewe, 1935; cp. Schumpeter 1950; Coe and Wilber, 1985) are more exclusively grounded in the social domain of the "economy" and less susceptible to influences from the "polity," (to adopt Charles Lindblom's helpful renewal (1977) of a still useful simplification) means that vital social interests without weight in the calculus institutionalized in the economy's social technology will be neglected. For my present purposes, the interest at issue first of all is the interest in legality itself, that may be aptly epitomized in the language of the American constitution, as a 25 social interest in "due process" (Selznick, 1969: 1980). The defense of legalism by de-legalization results in the subjection of more people to more arbitrariness, quite apart from questions of social justice. While present-day structures of legalization may fail to provide adequately for this interest, the proposals for "de-legalization" would further enhance the power of institutions whose commitments to due process are slight, uncertain, and at present dependent on the operation of the larger regulations and designs proposed to be dismantled. The measures supposed to reduce undue pressures of law upon certain social actors are likely to subject others to arbitrary powers. The characteristic combination of proposals for the "de-legalization" of some social relationships with "neo-conservative" proposals for the strengthening of criminal and moral policing suggests, moreover, that the changes proposed will not even lead to a society less subject to coercive state control, but rather to a re-legalized society that is increasingly dependent on punitive rather than on regulative law (Lukes and Scull, 1983). The real contemporary debate is a debate about the direction that re-legalization can take (Galanter, 1976; Voigt, 1980; Simitis, 1983; Willke, 1983; Teubner, 1983; Teubner 1984), given the present spreading evasion and selective non-enforcement of law, that must be taken as a sign of the welfare state's real problems. Is there a possibility of solving present pressing difficulties in a way that will actualize the promise of social rights that are made but too often frustrated by present legal designs, or must reordering proceed by suppressing the expectations? At one important level, both lines of argument concern the impact of the past three generations on the legal and constitutional character of property, the central 26 contested concept in discussions of rights, rule of law, and constitutional order. Both lines eventually move the discussion from the context of private to that of public law. The issue is increasingly joined over the question whether the achieved complex of regulative and constitutive law can be rendered legally viable and constitutionally coherent or whether its scope and objectives are such that it cannot but render all regulation and adjudication a matter of merely political "justice.” My primary purpose in this paper is to provide a wider context for thinking about some recent legal thinking, initiated in America but elaborated in Germany, that projects a strategic conception initially formulated as a theory of legal evolution, and that claims to see the emergence or promise of a new type of legalism and constitutionalism adequate to the welfare state (Nonet and Selznick, 1978; Teubner, 1982; Teubner, 1983 cp. Blankenburg, 1983; Rottleuthner, 1986). It is my contention that this tendency represents an attempt to revive and to elaborate an undercurrent within social democratic thinking, latently present underneath the stronger statist and regulation-centered socialist mainstream, and historically more closely tied to the legal practice associated with the trade union movement than to the ideological or theoretical activities oriented to political parties. The analysis has three stages: 1) I shall begin with recent questions about property and the order of the socially-minded state, and specifically with two inquiries into the possibilities of securing that order by broadening the scope of that best-protected legal good to cover the decisive claims and expectations comprising the "social rights" of contemporary citizenship (Marshall 1949: 1965). The two legal studies selected for review, one Dutch and the other American, converge in tracing the key problems to the structure of public 27 law, and thus in denying that the old predominant "civil right" of property can be adapted so as to make it central to the structures distinguishing the contemporary welfare state. The categories of private law can neither comprehend (in dogmatic legal analysis) nor ground (in normative constitutional theory) the decisive relationships (Raiser 1971:1977). But the problem is that the predominant public law itself appears to be in crisis, seemingly stretched beyond its technical and legitimating capacities by the overload of judgments it is asked to order. The welfare state regime seems no longer viable. The debate about property must be left behind. 2) Yet there is a theory of the public law, substantiated by reference to a key dimension of its effective working, that purports to see an evolutionary way out of the decisive difficulties that are commonly summarized under the heading of "(hyper-)legalization" (Teubner, 1982; Teubner, 1984; Voigt, 1980; Voigt, 1983). The key dimension of existing law that provides this theory a model and point of reference proves to be collective labor law. 3) As an historical matter, however, this law owes its character as much to the organized force of labor as it does to the facilitating framework established by public law. (Simitis, 1983) Like other law that is "constitutional" in effect, it is intrinsically a compound of power and legality. Because the welfare state as a whole can be understood as being in important measure a complex of responses to the mobilization and organization of labor (Pryor, 1968; Martin, 1986, p. 160; Hay, 1975; Piven and Cloward, 1977; Offe 1972, 1980; Bureau, Lippel, Lamarche, 1986; Schmitter, 1977; cp. Orloff and Skocpol, 1984), at present no less than in the past, that finding seems to leave the proposed solution to the "crisis" paradoxically dependent on an agent 28 profoundly weakened by the problems that are now to be solved (Huxley, Kettler and Struthers, 1986). Viewed more theoretically, the model of a new type of law appears founded on analogy to a most uncertain case and therefore misleadingly incomplete (Teubner, 1984; Kettler, 1986). But no conclusion in such general terms can be allowed to dismiss so interesting a theory (Conference, 1983). The conclusion of my paper, should serve as a troubling starting point for more detailed study of historical experiences and present prospects. Its present purpose is less a refutation of the "evolutionists'" thesis than a proposal about the historical and theoretical contexts within which these theses can best be examined. 2. The Problem with New Property In connection with the ongoing discussions about a new codification of civil law in the Netherlands (Burgelijke Wetboek), F.W. Grosheide has recently reopened the question of extending the legal concept of property to include claims to a variety of powers and entitlements that do for those who claim them many of the things that recognized property does for its possessors, and that similarly rest on stable expectations reasonably aroused by long-continued public policy (Grosheide, 1982). Grosheide weighs two fields of application. First, he cites claims that inhere in certain legally recognized social positions and are essential to them, like the authority pertaining to a given office (e.g., a professor's power over grades) or access to indispensable information. Secondly, and more importantly, he considers claims generated by established social policies and other public programs (e.g., welfare, education, health-care, housing subsidy, etc.). In the modern welfare state, with its 29 massive transfers and uncertain finances, complex specialization and impenetrable interdependencies, such interests appear as precarious as they are essential, since they seem subject to quite arbitrary decisions by public and private bureaucracies. Indeed, the emphasis on welfare policies in a narrow sense could be somewhat misleading. Much of the planning, regulation, and public funding characteristic of the contemporary welfare state have to do with designs for agriculture or industry or art, as well as with regulatory public care for the social effects of non-public actions. The problems turning on security of expectations, that are central to the historical rationale for property, arise here as well. It might well be asked, accordingly, whether some or all of the claims arising in these broader domains might also be construed as property rights, if any expansion in the legal concept is undertaken. Such a question implies, of course, that public and private agencies would have to overcome new kinds of juristic obstacles (or at least entertain new kinds of juristic considerations) before making changes in policy, even in accordance with parliamentary decisions regarding general policy objectives or budgetary allocations, if those changes would prejudice claims that have been transformed into vested property rights. Arising as an issue in technical juristic inquiry for Grosheide, the possibility of redefining property quickly proves to have wide ramifications for the theory and practice of contemporary politics. The point of any such reinterpretation of property would be to place the claims affected under the protection of the same legal mechanisms that protect proprietors against arbitrary incursions. The idea of such a doctrine of "new property" was originated by Charles Reich twenty years ago, in the United States (Reich, 1964), and was actually cited in a few American decisions during the 'seventies. But it would mean 30 something quite different, of course, in a legal system like that of the Netherlands. In the American context, the idea promised not only the superior legal defenses available to property rights in all legal systems based on the common law (Samuel, 1983), but it also seemed to provide quite categorical constitutional protection for the most basic of the interests at stake, in view of the provisions in the American constitution denying to the federal government (5th Amendment) as well as to the several state governments (14th Amendment) the power of depriving individuals of "life, liberty or property" without "due process of law." The proposal gained influence among advocates of expanded protection for social rights by a surprising tendency for the courts, during the 'sixties and into the 'seventies, to return to the earlier constitutional doctrine of "substantive due process." The courts appeared inclined once again, though in an historically novel way, to interpret the constitutional guarantees to mean that some acts are impermissible, even if duly authorized by legislation, if they are found to be incompatible with substantive principles held to be inherent in the concept of "due process.” In the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, the doctrine of "substantive due process" had served to deny governments the power to interfere with freedom of contract. This freedom was taken as an absolute and as a decisive attribute of "liberty" and "property" in the sense of the constitutional guarantees, and the constitutional guarantee had been utilized to invalidate social legislation. When the Supreme Court changed direction in 1937, in the so-called constitutional revolution that upheld the constitutionality of a new generation of social legislation, the doctrine was abandoned. But as revived a generation later, "substantive due process" appeared to promise a 31 defense of quite different social values, and even possibilities for new active judicial initiatives on their behalf. The leading case (Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965)) invalidated laws against the sale of contraceptives on grounds that suggested a new right of privacy and autonomy. The Court's broad reading of the concept of "state action," in related contexts, to include actions by private parties that depend on public means for their effects (e.g., the use of the legal sanctions of contract to support a design for racial discrimination, as in "restrictive covenants") promised applications to situations where powerful non-governmental actors interfere with protected rights (Cox, 1976). At the extreme was the example of the Alabama judge who was administering all the state mental hospitals in the jurisdiction and who was legally requiring the state government to fund the improvements he was imposing. He grounded his actions on the argument that this was the only remedy available to secure the constitutional rights of the patients, including a "right to treatment" in view of their deprivation of liberty. (Wyatt v. Aderholt , 503 F2d 1305 (5th Circ., 1974); Note, 1975; Special Project 1978). This action suggested that "new property" might be judicially supported in an active way and not merely defended against interferences deemed to be inherently arbitrary. Such expectations have proved very exaggerated in the United States, in the light of the more recent constitutional jurisprudence of the Supreme Court (Funston, 1977). In a legal system like the Dutch, where the courts cannot invalidate procedurally correct acts of state, hopes could not in any case take this form. Nevertheless, the conception of "new property" is hardly pointless, because the legal status of property is a strong one. The protection of property by such actions as damage suits against 32 "impermissible conduct" (onrechtmatige daad) in private law and by analogous actions for compensation in public law do add up to a more secure and developed complex of legal remedies than anything now available for the protection of "personal" entitlement claims, the strongest legal status to which the claims sometimes proposed for reclassification as "new property" can at present pretend. In one respect, indeed, the legal import would be greater under Dutch law than under American, since there would be a considerable strengthening of the claims against "horizontal" challenges, i.e., from other private parties, that would only rarely be a factor in the American case. Under the civil code, as in common law, property has long had a legal effectiveness denied all other sources of rights or obligations. So, although the stakes are naturally very much lower in the absence of the American legal ground in an activist constitutional jurisprudence, the notion of "new property" is not without its appeals to some Dutch jurists. Nevertheless, Grosheide does not believe that it is either feasible or desirable to assimilate the claims comprehended as "new property" to the old legal concept. The substantive or functional legal criteria for property that have been developed by Dutch courts are clearly not met. Moreover, he finds it hard to imagine alternative juristically sound criteria that would be inclusive enough to cover the new claims and still fit into anything like the old systematization interrelating the law of property with the law of contracts, torts, and so on. If the move to "new property" does not work by extending to the new claims the security and standing of the old, the strategy must be altogether reconceived. Grosheide's main point is that the old concept requires critical analysis and 33 de-absolutizing. Claiming superior social realism and legal subtlety for the doctrine of property as a "bundle of powers," first articulated by Oliver Wendell Holmes, Grosheide maintains that this concept, although originally at home in the common law, can be adapted to Dutch requirements. He suggests that the multiple functions bundled together in the old substantial property concept should be separately considered. Due weight could then be given to the extent to which a number of these functions have already been "socialized," in the sense of being put under the regulation and care of public law -- as in labor law, for example. Such reanalysis would make it possible, on the one hand, to identify the modes of property that should continue to be treated legally in more or less the old way, and, on the other, to connect the other facets of property expressly with their functional counterparts among the claims that some would want to see reformulated as "new property," most of which arise under public law (cp. Raiser, 1971: 1977). Grosheide maintains that this would enhance the legal standing of the newer claims while opening the opaque old concept to juristic analysis and ethical assessment (cp. Van den Bergh, 1983). He agrees with Reich about the need to show that the justifications that underlie the privileged status of property in the old law now apply to many claims generated in what had been deemed the domain of public law, and to strengthen the legal positions of claimants dependent on the newly "socialized" dimensions of property. Instead of attempting to broaden the scope of private law to cover major constituents of civic status in the welfare state, however, he finds it necessary to reconsider the division between private and public law, and to acknowledge that the assumptions underlying their mutual isolation have been rendered 34 obsolete in important respects by modern developments. Writing in a legal context premised on the welfare state, Grosheide demonstrates the impossibility of escaping from the difficulties of public and constitutional law in such a state to the doctrines and instrumentalities of private law. This critique of the "new property" conception, as it was originally proposed, converges with the argument of the American constitutional theorist, Jennifer Nedelsky (Nedelsky, 1982, 1983). Not sharing Grosheide's need to break down an absolute property concept in a codified system of private law, she rather points out that the "new property" concept is in fact anachronistic, since American courts have long ceased to regard property, except in the law of compensation, as a substantially unified legal entity. The categorical protection it is sought to extend by bringing the newer claims within the defenses supposed to safeguard property has actually come to lack a legal object, since property in the sense of those defenses has virtually ceased to have any legal existence (cp. Unger, 1983, 290). Regardless of the isolated returns to "substantive due process," the legal developments that broke down the "freedom of contract" as obstacle to wages-and-hours legislation fifty years ago also undermine the possibility of depending on "right to welfare" as security against changes in public policy that might be experienced as arbitrary disappointments of reasonable expectations. The right of property hardly stands in the way of any regulation deemed reasonable by a competent public authority, Nedelsky points out, and the law of property transactions has been adapted to differentiate among the most diverse analytical units. Holmes' conception of property as a bundle of powers, with its implication that different powers merit different legal treatment, has been thoroughly established in the law. 35 Unlike Grosheide, who would welcome such a development for the Netherlands, however, Nedelsky views this situation with some alarm. The difference in perspectives has to do with differences in the theoretical frame of reference. While Grosheide is interested in fairly specific questions about the relationship between the law of property and a number of other important justiciable claims within the legal system (i.e., questions of legal dogmatics and legal policy) Nedelsky is preoccupied with fundamental meta-juristic questions about constitutionalism and the respect for individual autonomy. That brings her work expressly closer to the larger questions of political thought that are only implicit in Grosheide's doctrinal analysis. Her perspective, accordingly, cautions against overconfidence about the course of public legislation and policy in welfare states under stress. She contends that if the American constitutional design is to have any structural limitations at all, it requires the postulation of a domain absolutely protected against exercises of public power, as she maintains was once the case with property, The sweep of democratic legitimation provided elsewhere in that design could not be restrained in any other way. A government understood as the embodiment of the people's will cannot be brought otherwise to respect the autonomy of individuals. This is not to say that she imagines that either democracy or the absolutism of property rights ever existed in actual fact as they were postulated in the American authorizing myth. But the practice of the state, and especially the judicial practice of the courts, could reasonably be understood as oriented to the legitimizing constitutional beliefs. Moreover, she maintains, a measure of limitation was actually achieved, albeit at cost to other social values. Now, she contends, the situation has drastically changed. 36 While the absolute concept of property retains its hold on the collective political imagination of the people, perhaps because of its psychologically satisfying concreteness of reference, the judicial dissolution of the legal concept increasingly jeopardizes the integrity of the constitutional myth and consequently threatens unrestricted democratically-sanctioned incursions upon individual autonomy, freely taking what is now understood as having been freely given. Nedelsky is far from thinking that the focus on private property ever provided a sufficient basis for a fully adequate doctrine of individual autonomy, but she does insist that it was precisely this inadequate myth that has made constitutionalism possible under the conditions of a commercial society, and with it, such protection as there has been for the individual. The doctrine of "new property," if it were more influential in the courts, could actually increase the danger, she argues, since it would render the concept of private property still more vague and still more distant from the experiential popular intuition of property as something finite, concrete, and graspable in a literal way. Talk of protecting "property" in that sense --especially since it is then likely also to extend to goods with regard to which there are deep political divisions, like those at stake in the decriminalization of abortion -- can discredit the whole concept. Yet she does not think that restoration of the old property concept in law is either feasible or desirable. The social interests invested in the newer welfare-state developments are too great. The costs in social values that even a futile attempt to proceed in this direction would exact are incalculable, since the reassertion of anything like the old property concept, with its concomitant categorical "freedom of contract," would call into question, could it be achieved, the very social claims that the proponents of "new property" mean to 37 strengthen. She calls instead for some functional equivalent to the absolute property right, possessing comparable psychological plausibility, to give legal support to the autonomy of the individual and to satisfy the requirement she deems integral to constitutionalism, a secure reference point for tension between state power and individual rights. As she acknowledges, her position is paradoxical. Like Grosheide, she is glad to see many of the social effects of the legal breakdown of the old property concept, since it has meant some weakening of the frequently oppressive power of proprietors, as well as the legal vindication of some public counter-forces against the frequently destructive human consequences of domination by market processes. The interest that originally brought her to her paradox, in fact, was inquiry into the extent to which change in the law could bring about far more basic social change in a socialist direction. But she is sufficiently impressed by the historical arguments advanced by Friedrich A. Hayek and his followers, concerning the constitutional importance of the old property doctrine, to inquire anew into the political kernel of truth that she considers to be embedded in their fallacious legal theory. Nedelsky and Grosheide do not meet at the same level of argument and thus cannot be said to disagree. Nedelsky's analysis is expressly restricted to the American constitutional experience, that has, in her judgment, given distinctive political importance to property rights and that therefore implies the need for a functional equivalent if property rights are recognized as having been in effect legally dismantled, as they rightfully ought to be. She does not address herself to the relationship between property rights and individual autonomy in other constitutional designs. Grosheide in 38 turn, given the juristic parameters of his argument, does not entertain questions about the constitutional implications of changes in property doctrine. Nor would he be likely to hit upon the broad sense of "constitutional implication" invited by the characteristic functioning of American constitutional law as a pivot between technical issues in private and public law and fundamental questions in the ideological and institutional politics of constituting the republic, since modern Dutch legal thought does not typically link the issues in this way. Yet there is value in thinking about the two arguments together, quite apart from their converging scepticism about "new property.” The juxtaposition suggests that the sometimes quite technical uncertainty about the law of property is a sign of a deeper set of internationally-shared concerns about the character of law and constitution in the contemporary welfare state. Problems about the security of "social rights" (i.e., claims upon collectivized goods, services. and responsibilities upon which individual existences and vital social relationships are constructed), as well as their separation from claims properly left to the play of political forces and environing conjunctures, open questions about the whole system of legalized securities and the place of individual rights within it. Grosheide's analysis serves as a reminder that the powers that have been legally devolved from property by changed legal doctrine and regulative public law have been subjected to new norms and relocated in other institutional forms. If there are now new interests to be protected that are said to resemble these powers in important respects, as the doctrine of "new property" points out, then we should scrutinize the protective and empowering capabilities inherent in the new situation with care before despairingly setting out in search of functional equivalents for absolute property rights. Grosheide 39 suggests that claims like those that are proposed for inclusion under the concept of "new property" might better be assimilated to the appropriate location within this new complex, once its character is made more evident. Complementarily, a prominent Dutch public lawyer has stressed the importance of not treating the new practical assurances and the new provisions for reciprocity and adjustment within the welfare state complex as if they were merely administrative or political devices (Donner, 1979). He insists on the need to specify their legal character, despite the strain they put on the old categories of public and constitutional law. In a manner reminiscent of American legal theorists early in the present century, he calls for a dynamic redefinition of the constitutional limits of public law. A contemporary Dutch illustration of the approach that Grosheide thinks can be usefully comprehended within doctrinal legal analysis, instead of being taken as nothing more than positive legal or administrative enactment or mere political fact, is the linkage between the procedure for negotiating the annual framework for collective wage agreements and the determination of levels and policies with regard to welfare programs (van Peijpe, 1985). The former is a repository of deductions from property rights achieved over several generations by judicial recognition of collective agreements and by labor law; the latter is the result of fairly recent social legislation and ministerial practice. Precisely because the powers and functions originating in property affect important interests most directly and visibly, the connection established in practice tends to take welfare benefits out of the unilateral and discretionary control of bureaucratic or even parliamentary authority. By virtue of established arrangements, the comparatively strong organizations oriented to the regulative process affecting wage 40 levels cannot disregard the process concerned with welfare levels. While it is impossible to speak of guaranteed rights, in the sense associated with judicial process, it is nevertheless equally implausible to speak of the structure of institutionalized constraints as if it were a mere political conjuncture. Constitutional usages seem to be emerging; a new regime appears to have been taking shape in this domain. And press reports show that the parties on the defensive with regard to this design at the time of writing clearly state their claim as a "constitutional" one -- as is also the case in comparable controversies raging at the moment in France and Italy. If the example is fairly chosen, it suggests that the development projected in Grosheide's analysis may have its own constitutional consequences, even though its legal meaning has not been thoroughly assimilated by the legal doctrine of the civil code or public law. The powers abstracted from private property are not simply -- or at least not necessarily --taken over by the existing and ordinary organs of "the state." In this case, and in some others, at least, they involve a measure of "collegiality,” in Max Weber's sense,1 with intermediate organizations and other institutional forms. These in turn, as in the example, may importantly influence the exercise of other powers that had belonged to government alone; and they may generate and protect new functions. This is the development that has been widely studied from a different point of view as the emergence of "neo-corporatism" (Schmitter and Lehmbruch, 1979; Berger, 1981; Lehmbruch and Schmitter, 1982; Streek and Schmitter, 1985; cp. Mishra, 1984). 1 Weber omits a general definition of the concept, but he uses this heading to classify a variety of special social relationships and groups that have the function of limiting authority, with all varieties displaying mechanisms for reaching decisions by mutual adjustment among actors with an important measure of autonomy. (Weber, 1978, pp. 271-282.) 41 It is not my present concern to inquire into the dynamics of such development or the difficult questions it raises about parliamentary and other constituents of political democracy. Nor am I about to engage in debate about the economic wisdom of the policies generated by such structures. The question now is whether Nedelsky's reading of the American "paradox of property" has overlooked comparable re-constitutive trends, with their own deep roots in American political consciousness -- hidden complexities within the general phenomenon that was characterized as "pluralism" in the debates of the 'sixties and early 'seventies (Connolly, 1968). If so, such trends would not solve the basic problem she raises, concerning the dangers to individual autonomy. But attention would properly shift from the contemplation of paradoxes to an assessment of strengths and weaknesses, trends and possibilities within an emergent constitutional order that limits and channels state power by powers that are not decisively dependent on either the law of property or its myth. 3. Welfare States as a Response to Labor Movements The example derived from the linkage between Dutch industrial relations and welfare policy was not randomly chosen, because the history of reflections on the possibility of such constitutional evolution, in the United States as in western Europe, largely coincides with attempts to think through the implications of the labor movements that have so strongly influenced the public agenda during the past century. For more than half of that century, much of that thinking had to do with fears or hopes of social revolution. Financial or regulatory welfare state measures were promoted as prophylactic devices by the one side and as strategic transitional stages by the other 42 (Preller, 1949; Adams, 1966). Then came several decades during which the large questions appeared obsolete, but during which the institutionalization of welfare state programs was widely accepted as the price for such a cooling of social threat and conflict. In the past decade, then, in the debate about the presumed crisis of the welfare state, there has been grave unease about the adjustments that were then made. The compromises between "conservative" and "progressive" designs that were embodied in the welfare state are everywhere threatened with a loss of legitimacy (Habermas, 1973; Luhmann, 1981; Mishra, 1984). Not coincidentally, the most recent period has also seen a weakening of organized labor (Roberts, 1984; Panitch and Swartz, 1984; Wedderburn, Lewis and Clark, 1983; Block and McLennan, 1985; Troy and Sheflin 1985). The unions themselves have suffered from sustained unfavorable market conditions in their areas of greatest concentration, from increasingly restrictive regulation, from effective resistances to organization in the newer areas of employment growth, and from declining memberships (Kochan, 1985; Lipset, 1986). Where social democratic parties have not lost greatly in electoral strength, they have increasingly shifted their orientations away from the symbols and designs that bound them to the labor movement, as witness the political developments in France and Spain during the early 1980's. These trends have profound implications for the political prospects of the welfare state. The reciprocal interdependencies between organized labor and the complex of laws, policies, and institutions comprising the welfare state are well-established, although the direction of causality with regard to new spending programs is the subject of an interesting recent debate (Pryor, 1968; Orloff and Skocpol, 43 1984). If due regard is paid to the intricacies of actions and reactions, not to speak of anticipatory and preemptive actions, there is little doubt that trade union movements and the political parties close to them have been the major initiators and/or targets at the initiation of the programs in question. And there is no doubt at all that they have been decisive in the subsequent institutionalization of many of them. At one level, the correlation between the strength of labor and the elaboration of the welfare state seems easily accounted for. Both developments appear to be dependent on the strength of social democratic or laborist political movements. High levels of trade union membership and loyalty are then seen as an expression of the same "class consciousness" that sustains parties with "revolutionary" or radically reformist programs. The institutionalization of welfare state programs and the "neo-corporatist" political arrangements that have sustained them has been recognized as a direct or indirect result of the influence of those parties (Aaron, 1982; Schmitter and Lehmbruch, 1983; Lipset, 1983). Political labor movements themselves did not necessarily originate the eventually implemented designs for welfare, security, public health, industrial democracy, environmental protection, social and regional equalization, and economic planning that are variously comprehended by the term welfare state as it used here. Much in these designs embodies resistance to labor's claims to political power. There is something absurd about the debate concerning the "real" social and political meaning of the welfare state, whether it represents a design for "social welfare" or "social control.” The welfare state forms a contested complex of compromises and arbitral resolutions, often initiated in fact by religious parties or secular social reformers in and out of state office who were expressly aiming at a "third way" between 44 socialist-oriented organized labor and its opponents, and its "meanings" are perpetually in contest (Trattner, 1983). In any case, the striking general feature in the political formations under consideration remains the high correlation between the strength of organized labor and the extent to which public agencies honor the claims and expectations comprising the "social rights" of contemporary citizenship (Martin, 1986), as these have been given a status plausibly construed as functionally equivalent to constitutional guarantees (Marshall, 1949: 1965; Preuss, 1973; Preuss, 1983). For the labor movement, as for many of the other state and non-state actors involved in the formation and institutionalization of the welfare state, the concerns around which all others revolve are naturally centered in the labor market (Offe, 1985). The interrelationship between the actions of labor (or expectations concerning them) and the welfare state, accordingly, is most evident in the domain of labor law. I maintain that developments in this sphere are, first of all, influential in shaping the other aspects of the welfare state, and, second, representative of constitutional patterns and alternative possibilities for the design as a whole. A striking indicator of the link between labor law and the broader changes under discussion is the extent to which purposive, "sociological" approaches to law -- without which the law of welfare states can hardly be imagined -- receive their paradigmatic judicial formulations in labor law cases within legal systems as disparate as the American and the German. If Holmes, Brandeis, and Frankfurter are taken as the principal practical representatives of this tendency in the United States, the formative importance of labor issues on their jurisprudence is evident from the record (Mason, 1956; Frankfurter, 1961; Hirsch, 1981; Irons, 1982). In the German case, the interplay 45 can conveniently be studied in connection with the "social" legal doctrine of "works community" (Kettler, 1984; Simitis, 1957). Especially important for reflections on the paradigmatic significance of labor law are the developments in the sphere of collective labor law, the law of labor organization, collective agreements, and collective actions. Because such developments commonly reflect or react to actions (and litigation) by unions and are not limited to changes in legislation, they also point to a line of connection between labor movements and the legal constitution of the welfare state that is interestingly separate from the line through political parties and parliaments (cp. Simitis, 1983). The standpoint of comparative collective labor law helps to bring into focus the distinction between the predominant social-democratic themes of welfare-oriented regulation by the democratic state and the often latent themes of non-state collective interactions, sometimes characterized as the "syndicalist" dimension of the labor movement. It was the composite (and not rarely discordant) effects of both these elements that comprised labor's stimulus to and mode of integration into the welfare state. In the history of collective labor law, the main theme is the struggles of trade union movements for some form of legal recognition (or acknowledgement) of their characteristic modes and forms of social power. Of special interest here are the contested legal ramifications of the recognition variously gained, the implications of the diverse collective labor regime for the constitutional designs of the various welfare states. Without denying that the initial designs of these regimes were often out of the hands of the labor movements, that were in any case frequently divided among themselves on key issues, I am especially interested here in the aims and 46 achievements of what German political analysis would call the "legal and constitutional policy" (Martiny, 1976) of the trade union wings of a number of labor movements, because certain common features in those achievements provide a model that bears on problems more fundamental than those to which those policies were primarily addressed. During much of the history of organized labor, these policies have been under attack from two sides. On the one hand, they have been taken as challenges to the fundamental character of liberal law, somehow legitimating collective and coercive challenges to property in some of its vital aspects and undermining the sovereignty of parliaments and the legalism of the judicial process (von Mises, 1949). On the other, they have been seen as betrayals of the political activism and larger social objectives of the labor movement, accepting a conditionally sheltered but dependent position within a social system whose principal direction will be determined by others (Erd, 1977; Klare 1978; Klare, 1982; Rogers, 1985; Tomlins, 1985; Panitch and Swartz 1985). The former analysis is integral to the general legalistic critique of the welfare state, and I have already given my reasons for putting that aside. The latter presupposes a range of alternatives for labor and a measure of potential labor control over events that do not accord with my reading of the situation (Simitis, 1983; Huxley, Kettler and Struthers, 1986). In their political outlines, both lines of attack have changed remarkably little since they were articulated, for example, in the Hearings of the American Commission on Industrial Relations before the First World War. The characteristic defenses of the policies, in turn, might be called "pragmatic,” in both the banal sense and in the more 47 complex and interesting one. A major new social reality was there to be accommodated. Both policy and law had to be adapted in some suitable way. But the divisions that that Commission uncovered within the workings of the pragmatists' major accomplishment of the time, Brandeis' "Protocols of Peace" in the New York garment industry, as well as the divisions manifested in the majority and minority reports of that Commission, indicate a characteristic cleavage within the legal and constitutional policy of labor. On the one side are some for whom accommodation and adaptation are a matter of social pacification under state regulation. On the other, are others for whom they are a matter of institutionalizing non-violent social conflict and change, within structures that limit the role of state regulation (Adams, 1968; U.S. Commission on Industrial Relations, 1916: 10453-10815). This distinction will prove relevant to our assessment of contemporary legal-constitutional designs that model a law competent to give the welfare state its proper constitution upon the collective self-regulation under law achieved in industrial relations. 4. The Socialist Labor Law Project in Weimar: Collective Agreement and Cumulative Social Change Notwithstanding the reductionist theory of law proclaimed by the orthodox socialist doctrine of the Second International (Engels/Kautsky 1892), there did exist jurists who were attracted to organized social democracy in Germany. Since Lasalle (1864:1919), they sought to specify and demystify the dramatic transformations symbolized by the concept of revolution, relating these transformations strategically to the systems of law and political constitution. Such juristic speculation interacted 48 reciprocally both with the practical juristic strategies governing the legislative work of socialist parliamentarians and the legal work of labor organizations to project a conception of legal restructuring that could comprehend the social rights that the socialist-oriented labor movement demanded and the social power that this movement deployed without resort to violence or dictatorship (Anon., 1890). Curiously enough, in the light of recent "new property" discussions, Anton Menger, the first important academic jurist in the German-speaking world sympathetic to socialist ideas, proposed amendments to the draft of the German civil code (BGB) that would have extended the protection accorded property to workers' capacity for work (Arbeitskraft), so that, for example, an action against "impermissible conduct" could be initiated where an employer fails to provide adequate safety or requires excessive labor (Menger, 1890, 1903). Such adaptation of property concepts had already been commonplace in the English labor movement during the Chartist period (Jones, 1983), and it was repeatedly taken up later elsewhere as well, if only for tactical purposes (Radbruch, 1930). But the most profound Socialist juristic study of the time to deal with the legal status of property emphasized the stability of the formal legal concept together with the decisive change in its function brought about as economic relationships were increasingly defined by legal institutions such as contract and corporation, technically ancillary to property but effectively superceding it (Renner, 1905: 1949). This de-centering of the property concept, together with the emphasis on alternate institutions, including public law institutions, for the legal reconstitution of the employment relationship, bears a certain resemblance to Grosheide's analysis. At the 49 beginning of the century, Karl Renner's conclusion was that the transfer of the primary organizational and regulatory functions to these "complementary" institutions would happen adaptively in the course of social development long before the actual abolition of private property. The formal legal category of property, in his view, cannot be an obstacle in the way of increasing practical acknowledgment of the social character of production. The social functions of property would be socialized first. Renner's ideas were adapted and refined in the German literature of labor law, especially during the first ten years of the Weimar Republic. Hugo Sinzheimer, an important labor lawyer who became a Social Democrat in the last years of World War I and served as a leading Social Democratic contributor to the drafting of the Weimar Constitution, developed a functionalist theory of the emerging collective labor law. Ultimately, he projected this law as simultaneously the model and the dynamic source of a fundamental change in the whole legal system, as well as in the effective constitution of social life (Kahn-Freund 1976: 1981; Kettler 1984a). According to Sinzheimer, the most important "complementary" institution, capable of absorbing the organizing and directive functions that property had carried out, is the collective agreement between employers and trade unions, an institution that has social reality before it is given legal recognition and that embodies a dynamism and flexibility that the legal code cannot provide (Sinzheimer 1927, Sinzheimer 1976). Working at first only through doctrinal analysis and the promotion of legislation and later also through his work on the constitution and on the various governmental commissions charged with the design of the new labor law promised in the constitution, as well as his performances as principal legal advisor to the (Socialist) Free Trade Unions, he sought 50 to secure a form of legalization for the collective agreement that would allow it to retain the openness of a social invention created to meet experienced social need, while retaining its connection to the dynamic and transformative social force that had created it. For Sinzheimer, the collective agreement is so significant, first, because it is a spontaneous product of an authentic search for order between collectivities with conflicting interests, a balancing of active social forces, and not simply a formal design that must be imposed by the coercive powers of the state apparatus. The order and balance presupposes the continued existence of the two major collective social actors in the employment relationship, but the design is imposed by the newly organized working class. The nature of this imposition, moreover, implies further re-orderings in the future, with the initiative remaining with the workers (Kettler 1984). It is this implication that vitally distinguishes Sinzheimer's mature views from the more static pragmatism with that he was often perforce politically allied and with which his position is accordingly often confused (Cp. Korsch, 1922: 1980; Fraenkel, 1958:1973; Kahn-Freund, 1976:1981). Secondly, the collective agreement represents a response to fundamental anomalies in the relationship between the buyers and sellers of work, the relationship that, with Renner and the whole Marxist tradition, Sinzheimer considered decisive for the order of a given society. Its emergence, he thought, signals and speeds the growing social obsolescence of the individual contract of employment, which stands in fact for the actual rightlessness of the worker. The individual contract of employment is so profoundly misleading in industrial 51 organization, according to Sinzheimer, because it fails to acknowledge the dependence that constrains the worker and the power to which it subjects him. As long as laborers are isolated in mutual competition, as they are when labor is first made free, their total dependence upon employment requires them to accept these legal fictions, or to contest them only in unrealistic ways. But when they organize for collective action, they achieve some corrections. Some of the first achievements, Sinzheimer thought, are only indirectly their own. Fear of their growing power and a measure of humanitarian concern lead to some legislation that directly or indirectly protects the labor power they must employ, constantly risk, and in time exhaust, and that insures minimally against its loss. In his view, however, the collective agreement that establishes norms for the terms and conditions binding upon an entire sector of economic life is a far more significant and revelatory accomplishment than such welfare regulations and compensations, because it periodically gives temporary form to the balance between the power of employers and the organized resistance of workers, and because it provides a procedure for lessening the dependency of workers. The effect is to create an expandable measure of power-sharing with regard to controls that had earlier been considered inherent in proprietorship. After the Revolution of 1918, Sinzheimer, active in support of the reformist wing of Social Democracy and closely tied to the socialist-oriented Free Trade Unions, elaborated his idea of the limitations that can be exercised by institutions of labor law into a conception of progressive stages that would re-enact in the economic sphere what had already taken place in the political sphere (Sinzheimer, 1923). First, corresponding to the collective agreement and the legal arrangements needed to give it 52 full recognition, is the "constitutional order of labor.” Here, the entrepreneur's power over the labor he hires is limited by certain rights that they are guaranteed and by some collective participation with regard to conditions of employment and welfare. Sinzheimer's examples include jointly managed social insurance schemes, the joint work groups set up between the top levels of labor and industry in the last days of the war, and the post-war works councils. Next was to come a "constitutional order of the economy," where the common interests of all participants in the economy would find ever clearer expression in institutions forming a common will, as in the post-war co-management schemes in coal and potash and in the never-implemented constitutional provision for a pyramid of consultative economic councils. This would be marked by steadily increasing common control over production. Finally complete democratization of economic relationships would follow, where the leadership functions required by the rational organization of production would no be connected in any way with property. The abolition of that right by legal enactment, marking the establishment of mature socialism, would then be a solemn ceremonial formality. Sinzheimer thought that this sequence was implicit in the core institution of the collective agreement under conditions of political democracy, and that each successive step, although it may require some legislative action, builds on the social integration and shifts in power achieved at the step preceding. The "social provisions" of the second part of the Weimar Constitution, themselves the result of compromise (Schmitt 1928; Nipperdey1930), exemplify the principle of collective agreement even while codifying it. Sinzheimer argued that they laid down the framework for social constitution, as well as principles to guide judicial doctrine in the direction of the development he projected (cp. 53 Neumann 1930: 1981). The electoral and parliamentary institutions of political democracy are presupposed at every stage, but Sinzheimer's analysis emphasizes the fundamental transformation in the meaning of the political framework when its social substance and legal instruments are changed by the course of social development (cp. Simitis, 1983). During the three or four comparatively prosperous years culminating in the Social Democratic electoral victory in 1928, as the labor movement recovered from its grave setbacks during the hyper-inflation, it did not appear unreasonable, though certainly controversial, to assert with Karl Renner (1929) that the complex welfare institutions in the course of being generated by labor were achieving a state of things recognizably on the way towards an actualization of economic democracy, and to celebrate a new era of social rights. At least, it made good sense for Sinzheimer and his effective younger associates to build this reading of developments into labor's legal theory in the doctrinal contests concerning key outstanding issues in collective labor law. But the jurisprudence of the courts, including the new labor courts after 1927, for which Sinzheimer had fought so hard, indicated that these legal theses were not to prevail (Kahn-Freund, 1930: 1981). The devastating events following the onset of the Great Depression showed that the neo-corporatist balance that had been struck was profoundly unstable, dependent as it was on labor's uncertain access to certain parts of the state bureaucracy and upon unreliable temporary alliances (Maier, 1975; Preller, 1949; Hartwich, 1967). Even the formal outlines of the design projected by Sinzheimer disappeared with the National Socialist accession to power. Labor ceased to be an independent force for more than twenty years, and all of the substantive achievements 54 of labor that were not destroyed were transmuted into privileges at the disposition of the "leaders" of "works-communities," i.e., they became almost always a matter of patronage by the proprietors. What had been conceived as the "constitutional" structure of work- and welfare-relationships proved to be even more quickly vulnerable to the stress of the Depression and to the hostility of its adversaries than the political constitution of parliamentary democracy itself. Sinzheimer acknowledged in 1933 (Sinzheimer, 1933) that his conception of labor law could not withstand massive unemployment. The theoretical works he wrote in exile nevertheless continued to speculate about democratization of economic relationships as the transformative way towards a legal order congruent with the social character of humankind (van Peijpe, 1984). His somewhat younger close collaborators turned more sharply against the legal strategy they had shared with Sinzheimer. Franz L. Neumann, for example, concluded in the aftermath of defeat, that the labor movement had been credulous about law and the state and that the legal development of the Weimar period had in fact seen an aggrandizement of arbitrary power in bureaucracies and courts structurally tied to labor's social antagonists. The legal doctrines associated with labor law (i.e., shifting from individual persons to institutionalized collective legal personality and granting discretion to judges to make decisions in accordance with very imprecise normative principles) he now analyzed as indistinguishable from legal instruments of control generated by a monopoly capitalism no longer served by the standards of legality appropriate to earlier phases. The period of neo-corporatism between 1924 and 1928 appeared to him in retrospect as a scene of unequal conflict between interest groups increasingly overshadowed by armed bands, 55 with organized socialist-oriented labor in fact more and more dependent on a less and less legitimate state (Neumann, 1937, 1944, 1980; see also Kahn-Freund, (1979:1981) "Postscript,"). Some such assessment, if not always with all the Marxist arguments adduced by Neumann, predominates in the more recent literature on the Weimar labor law experience (Martiny, 1979; Kaiser, 1980; Kaiser, 1981), where the distinctive attempts associated with Sinzheimer are not altogether neglected. Even Thilo Ramm, who first renewed interest in these writings, concluded that the practical failure of the conception stemmed in important measure from inner defects (Ramm, 1966). 4. From Industrial Justice to Reflexive Law Some recent German literature in legal theory has cast key institutions of labor law in a role similar to that envisioned by Sinzheimer, as an instance and model of a form of legalization that can provide an alternative to the forms now widely criticized as hyperdeveloped and that can effectively safeguard social rights otherwise at risk (Voigt, 1980, 1983; Teubner, 1982; Ronge, 1980, Ronge, 1983). Most of these writers have drawn direct inspiration from American rather than German sources. Gunther Teubner has been the most innovative among them and, although his most recent formulations depend increasingly on systems theory, he has also paid special attention to the evolutionary design of Philip Selznick (Nonet and Selznick, 1975; cp. Teubner, 1983; Teubner, 1984). In abandoning the rather shaky reformist Marxist framework that characterized the older German work, Teubner and the others have brought out the more general implications of the legal conception. At the same time, they have run the risk of losing the awareness of power variables that the Social Democratic legacy 56 contains in its imagery of class struggle, however tamed and attenuated. This is not to say that the American progressivist-pragmatic tradition, that provides the background for American expansions upon the model of labor law, does not have its own version of the classical Social-Democratic awareness of the interplay between questions of law and might. However, the development of that tradition has tended to obscure this awareness, especially where it has focused on the progressive evolution of collective problem-solving mechanisms rather than on the critique of domination by "special interests." Selznick and Nonet distinguish three evolutionary "stages" or ideal-types, but indicate that the "evolution" in question is intended as a heuristic model rather than as a theory of natural development. The first stage, called "repressive," finds law passively and opportunistically in the service of predominant social and political forces, acting above all as a means of coercion. In the second stage, "autonomous" law, the legal system approximates to Max Weber's conception of formally rational law. To establish and preserve institutional integrity, Nonet and Selznick claim, law "insulates itself, narrows its responsibilities, and accepts a blind formalism as the price of integrity" (p. 77). At the third stage, then, to the extent that it can actually be attained, law once again responds to the social environment, as in the first stage, but now it is geared to meet Roscoe Pound's demand that law be "responsive to social need.” It is much more likely to be engaged in regulation than in adjudication, and it has the cognitive capacity to comprehend social pressure as "sources of knowledge," while facilitating the achievement of common purposes. Although Selznick describes the stages in that evolution in quite general, sometimes hortatory terms, the work clearly rests on Selznick 57 and Nonet's impressions of the socially constructive administrative programs that they have studied over the years (Selznick, 1949; Selznick, 1969). The first dimension in "responsive law" involves a conception of substantive justice. It is linked theoretically to legal philosophers who place principle above rules in law. Since the philosophical argument itself is slight, however, it seems more firmly grounded in Selznick's conviction that the major social programs since the American New Deal have been responsive to real problems and that the practice of an important subset among administrators and judges can be seen as effectively dedicated to "the progressive reduction of arbitrariness in positive law and its administration." In this connection, Selznick expressly challenges the most fundamental categories of formal law. "In the context of responsive law, "he writes, "claims of right are understood as opportunities for uncovering disorder or malfunction, and hence may be valued as administrative resources. But the resolution of controversies cannot remain the paradigmatic concern." This, he asserts, "is to demand a system of law that is capable of reaching beyond formal regularity and procedural fairness to substantive justice" (p. 108). With this, the whole conception becomes very uncertain, or at least dependent on a strong political consensus, and the pragmatist-progressivist provenance of Selznick's ideas becomes evident. But the striking thing about the conceptions of substantive moral and political knowledge developed in this intellectual tradition is the rich elaboration of its concept of problem-solving intelligence into procedures or methodologies for decision- making, that are in turn oper in distinctive patterns of organization. For John Dewey (1927) this reasoning generates a radical theory of populist democracy; for Charles Lindblom, a 58 "post-ideological" theory of "partisan mutual adjustment" (1965; cp. Kettler, 1967, Kettler, 1969). As in these cases, Selznick's undertheorized account of methods for adequate social self-management proves to be analytically separable from the philosophical characterization of outcomes as substantively rational. In his adaptation of Selznick's ideas, Teubner accordingly distinguishes between the notions of a law governed by substantive justice contained in Nonet and Selznick's stage of "responsive law" and an implicit second dimension, where the distinctiveness of "responsive" law derives from its structure and its inner connection with problem-generating and problem-engaging organized social actors. Teubner calls this "reflexive" law and characterizes it as law that puts in place autonomous and self-legitimating "constitutions" for diverse domains, each having its own distinctive principles and appropriate mechanisms, with the overall legal framework providing for mutual respect among the spheres. This law, he maintains, is essentially a law of organization. It is self-limiting because it addresses itself to mechanisms and processes of subsystem conflict-resolution, rather than imposing solutions. His primary case in point is labor law, understood in a way more directly reminiscent of Selznick's earlier work on "industrial justice" (Selznick, 1967) than of the Weimar Socialist formulations, with their Marxist points of reference. Selznick had argued, first, that contemporary trends in economic organization themselves already incline towards internal legality, institutionalizing a system of rules and reasonableness that is progressively removed from arbitrariness and open to corrective contestation. The "social foundations of industrial justice," he maintains, are already present in a tendency towards rules and reasonableness inherent in modern 59 organization, as it advances beyond the simplicities of bureaucratic hierarchy. Nevertheless, he finds, despite the "human relations" movement in personnel administration that he prizes, that this system is still too much inclined to instrumentalize participants. Decisively reorienting this incipient rationality in economic organization and giving it a human face, Selznick contends, implies the transformation of the employment relationship. In a distinction analogous to Sinzheimer's, he contrasts the "prerogative" contract that subordinates the individual employee to the command of his employer with the collective "constitutive" contract. The latter, he maintains, is not a contract in the older legal sense at all, but the establishment of a scheme of internal governance on the basis of negotiations between parties whose interests conflict at least in important part, and that are equipped with some autonomous power resources through their organization and capacities for collective action. The collective agreement, then, reorients the organization of economic activity so as to provide autonomy and due process in this domain at least, subject to constraint by regulative principles democratically established by public authority. The major jurisprudential issue, he finds, concerns the theory of association. Selznick argues above all against attempts to construe corporate organization with the help of the individualist contract theory of common law. He welcomes instead the turn towards a new institutionalism, with status as a source of rights (cp. Simitis, 1956, Kettler, 1984). Within the state's legal system, the constitutive contracts provide a reference point for comprehensive public policy, so that disputes arising under such contracts that go beyond the internal arbitration system will be resolved by courts taking 60 guidance from relevant statutes and not from the common law of contracts. They provide a framework, moreover, to sustain due process, a framework that can be judicially monitored to assure minimum standards. The presence of lawyers in the negotiations and arbitrations involved in constitutive contracts, Selznick contends, will make available the analytical habits and concepts of the common law. However the constitutive and political character of the deliberations will prevent the abandonment of substance for form. He finds here a pattern of legalization, in short, that brings the central value of legality, its negation of arbitrariness, into social relationships especially subject to abuses of power, without subjecting them to formalized, largely retrospective and unreasonably uniform standards or procedures, and without adding unmanageably more functions and uncontrollably more power to the central institutions of the state. Selznick thinks that this adaptability and flexibility provides as much assurance of intelligent collective judgment as can be secured. Selznick does not claim that this complex and contradictory process, as it has been institutionalized in the practice of business organization and labor law, already adds up to industrial justice or to the accomplishment of the principled public purposes often merely enshrined as ineffective ideals in symbolic legislation. But he thinks that it might be legally nudged closer to due process. In a parallel to some of Sinzheimer's larger hopes, he thinks that the principle of contestation intrinsic to due process may generate real democratic participation and in time bring the association to "polity" in Aristotle's sense, as an uncoerced association for the good life. This is the vision, it seems, that captured the imagination of Teubner and other contemporary commentators looking for ways of re-legalization able to move beyond present grave 61 difficulties in the law without abandoning great masses of people to the arbitrary social powers that were in some measure controlled and compensated for by the regulations of the welfare state (cp. Luhmann, 1985). 5. Functionalism and the Politics of Constitution Whatever the doctrinal merits of Sinzheimer's and Selznick's analyses of the collective labor law (cp., e.g., Kaskel, 1922, Kaskel, 1932; Cox ,1960: 1983; Simitis, 1983), it is by no means obvious, first, that the model can be applied to different issue domains, and, second, that the experience can be abstracted from the historical and political contexts to which it belongs. Both questions come back to the forms, purposes, and powers of the labor movement. Comparative historical study seems to suggest that the effectiveness of the autonomous labor organizations depends heavily on their success in gaining the support of political authorities. Sinzheimer concluded in 1929, for example, that the Weimar system of compulsory arbitration at the discretion of the Minister of Labor was essential to the regime of collective agreements, even though it made the social actors more dependent on the state than his initial theory of the collective agreement would have allowed (Sinzheimer, 1929, Hartwich, 1967). Franz Neumann was not alone in his conviction that such dependency, either in the Weimar period or in more recent history, disables the labor movement from pursuing precisely the lines of development that Sinzheimer projects (cp. Erd, 1979). Similar arguments have been made with regard to constraints imposed on the American labor movement in return for the support it receives from the National Labor Relations Board (Klare, 1982). The question, however, is not only whether such linkage between movement 62 and state represents a threat to the integrity of the movement; the question is also what happens when the state's agencies break the link or turn against the regime to which the movement has been central. Then the prospects for the "evolution" that Selznick projects appear dim indeed. In his recent elaborations of the argument on behalf of "reflexive law," Teubner (1984 and 1986; Teubner and Willke, 1984) has conceded the limited applicability of the collective labor law example and has subsumed this case under a much wider class of procedural or constitutive legislation designed to steer the "self-steering" mechanisms of social subsystems by legitimating and reforming their internal organizations. One of his major interests, in fact, has been the restructuring of organizations so as to revise their internal "logics" (the norms, priorities, and cognitive methods according to which they act). Most recently, he has addressed himself to the reform of corporate law so as to bring about internal weighing of considerations relating to social interests not ordinarily comprehended within corporate rationality (Teubner 1984a), a legally sanctioned institutionalization of "corporate social responsibility." Without presuming to dismiss the interesting analyses that Teubner presents and develops in his recent work, it is nevertheless fair to note that this direction removes him further from an understanding of the political dimension in constitution and reconstitution. His "subsystems" now have "reproductive mechanisms" that hardly accord with the realities of powers and resistances that empirical research uncovers. They possess "rationalities" that leave little room for intra-systemic ideological divisions (cp. Jörges, 1983, Münch, 1985, Kettler 1986). In his earliest formulations, Sinzheimer too was fascinated by theories of "organization" and "function" that promised to supercede 63 political conflict. However it was precisely his recognition of the power dimension in the ordering of social relations that marked his turn to the social democratic movement and his commitment to increase the power of labor organizations. This is not to be confused with a reductionist treatment of law as simply equivalent to power in other modes. The distinctive achievement of social democratic legal thought from Renner through Sinzheimer, Fraenkel, and Neumann was precisely their work on a political-social theory of the legalistic mode and its development in a state thought to be inclining towards social democracy. Teubner counts on the power of the political system to provide the sanctions required for use of reflexive law to reconstitute autonomous, self-regulating social subsystems in the public interest. But that begs too many questions about the structural determinants of state action. American labor policy has allowed the constituted collective labor regime to be marginalized (Huxley, Kettler and Struthers 1986). Similarly, recent British legislation in the field of collective labor law might be thought to exemplify perfectly Teubner's conception of "reflexive law," since it concerns itself exclusively with procedural requirements for organization and collective action. Yet the design and effect have been to lessen subsystem autonomy drastically and to introduce massive, punitive, and largely arbitrary judicial regulation where non-state interaction processes had prevailed (Wedderburn, Lewis and Clark, 1983; Davies and Freedland: Kahn-Freud, 1983). Some might argue that the new "logic" is more in the "public interest" than the old, but the argument would be a political one, subject to political rejoinder (Simitis, 1983). In the meantime, there are signs that this legal remedy seriously threatens primary social actors in the older constitutional design. 64 A counter-example does not refute a complex argument, but it may call attention to a vital missing dimension. Teubner's theory cannot be satisfactorily developed within the unpolitical framework of abstract functionalist theory; it requires the context of an adequate political theory of constitution. Social democratic political thought can hardly claim that distinction, but it is at least open to the central issues. That is why the recollection of its dual legacy is offered as a constructive contribution to the contemporary debate. But the study has barely begun. The major purpose of this introduction to the inquiry has been to indicate the inner connections between past achievements in the reconstitution of labor relations and the conception of an evolutionary alternative to "de-legalization" schemes for the welfare state. The second point was to identify the difficulties raised for this alternative approach by the historical record of political preconditions for the effectiveness of the "new labor law." There are excellent reasons for wanting to pursue the ways of re-legalization derived from Sinzheimer and Selznick, but appearances are powerfully against them. Such a recognition has classically been the starting point for careful reconsideration of the facts. 65 Works Community and Workers' Organizations: A Central Problem in Weimar Labour Law* 1. The Problem of Institutionalism: Is Labor’s Legal Theory Self-Destructive? In the analyses of the juristic symptoms of fascism that Franz L. Neumann wrote in exile, he includes his former close associate, the prominent Social Democratic labour lawyer, Hugo Sinzheimer, among the proponents of the "institutionalism" that supplied fascist jurisprudence with rationales for the destruction of free trade unions. "Institutionalism," as Neumann presents it, constructs a legal model in which the individual persons, whose wills constitute the primary legal relationships in liberal legal systems, are replaced by members of constituted communities, whose legal claims and duties somehow derive from the objective character of those communities (1937). 1 Contract gives way to status. Free legal subjectivity is displaced by the objective legalities supposed to inhere in organic community and fellowship. One fiction gives way to another. But they are not equally good. The latter does away with legal claims to equality before the laws, Neumann maintains, and the visibility (even if only in * " Economy and Society 13:3 (August, 1984) 278-3032. Based on a lecture presented at the commemoration of the 50th anniversary of Hugo Sinzheimer's inauguration as Extraordinary Professor of Legal Sociology at the University of Amsterdam. Agnietenkapel, 7 November 1983. The research of which this is a first product, on "Labor and the Law in Germany and the United States, 1912-1937" is indebted to the Netherlands Institute for Advanced Study in the Social Sciences and Humanities, Bard College Center, Trent University Research Committee, and the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. 1 "Rights and duties are no longer to be connected to the wills of legal persons equal before the law but rather to objective facts." (1937, p. 590) 66 disguised form) of the powers of property. The critique of liberal legalism eventuates in the justification of powerful new techniques of repression. According to Neumann, the legal conceptions that he calls "institutionalist" were most strikingly deployed during the Weimar years in the labor law, where the relationship between workers and entrepreneurs was characterized in the works-council legislation (Betriebsrätegesetz) and construed in numerous cases as association in a works-community (Betriebsgemeinschaft) having a common works-objective (Betriebszweck) that imposed privileges and obligations on the participants. Neumann points out that this conception ignores the fundamental social divisions between labor and capital and provides a central ideological theme for the National Socialist legislation on the organization of national work, establishing the "Führer"-principle in all enterprises and reducing workers to the status of dutiful vassals. Paradoxically and tragically, he maintains, all reformist socialist and trade-union-oriented legal thinkers incline towards "institutionalism," without of course meaning to help bring about their own liquidation. Neumann contends in these writings of the mid-30's that when Hugo Sinzheimer adapted ideas from his teacher, Otto Gierke, in order to justify the claim that collective labor agreements (Tarifverträge) are a social source of law superior to the individual contracts of employment of the German civil code (Sinzheimer 1907/8; 1916; 1976, 1/ pp. 35-69, 402-422, 2/ pp. 3-41), he laid the theoretical basis for institutionalism and prepared an influential support for the legitimacy of such ideas in the labor movement (Neumann 1944, pp. 440-458; 1980, pp. 260-280, pp. 298-313). Neumann is doubtless right in his assessment of the important place that the 67 legal fiction of the works-community assumed in National Socialist labor law and in the connection between the "institutionalist" legal doctrine that sustained that fiction and themes pervading Weimar labor law2. A younger contemporary of his, Otto Kahn-Freund, had already pointed out in 1932 the affinities between fascist ideology and the doctrine implicit in the decisions of the Weimar labor courts, and he had also voiced his misgivings about the effects of Sinzheimer's recourse to notions of "social law" and the consequent determination of legal claims and obligations by the functional requirements of institutionalized collectivities (1981). And on the ceremonial occasion marking the incorporation of the German legal profession into the National Socialist Association of Jurists in the fall of 1933, the long-time president of the highest labor court proudly told Hitler's justice-commissioner that the labor court, with its doctrine of the works-community, had led the judicial system in pursuing the objectives now so brilliantly embodied in the great National Awakening, under the banner of the Führer (Wrobel 1982, p. 342).3 But Justice Oegg, speaking a month before Sinzheimer took up 2 Paragraph 1 of the Works-Councils Law of 4 February 1920 states as one of the two basic objectives of the Works-Councils: fulfilling the works-objectives. Paragraph 1 of the 1934 Law for the Ordering of National Work provides: "The entrepreneur, as leader of the works, and the employees and workers, as his following, work together in the works for the advancement of the works-objectives and for the common service of people and state." W. Mansfeld/W. Pohl, 1934. 3 See also the editorial on 1. Mai 1933 in the journal of the labor court association , Das Arbeitsgericht: "A new day has broken for Germany, stirring the German people to its deepest depths. Great joy possesses German labor-court judges, professional judges and lay judges upon this occasion. That for which we strove and longed now has prospects for quick realization. The fateful chasm between the givers and takers of work is to be closed. German workers are to be led back to social peace, the German worker is to be taken up as fully enfranchised member in the community of the people and in the state. And thus we have come substantially closer to the highest aim of German labor law and the high purpose of the labor court association, to solidify the bands among law, economy, and the people's life, to bring about the feeling among the 68 in exile an academic post with little prestige or influence, did not cite Hugo Sinzheimer as an inspiration. And this was not only because Sinzheimer was already an outcast, as a Socialist and a Jew. Sinzheimer was a founder of the Association of Republican Justices and Editor of its journal, Die Justiz, a stubbornly dissenting voice, detested by the conservative legal profession (1968). Sinzheimer had, moreover, forcefully objected to the doctrine of the works-community since the time of its first enunciation by the German High Court (Reichsgericht) in 1923. A major objective of his book on the fundamental principles of labor law is to show the profound difference between his conception of such law, that he presents as a social and collectivistic advance on the obsolete individualism of the German civil code, and the ideological distortions of this basic idea (1927). If Sinzheimer's conception of the law can be said to have been "institutionalist" at all, it was so in a sense very different from that of the courts; it presupposed the organized different levels of the people that they belong together and thus the unity of the German people." 38 Jg., Nr. 5. More startling, perhaps, is the enthusiasm voiced a year later by one of the most brilliant of the Weimar civil and labor jurists in his commentary on "Das Gesetz zur Ordnung der nationalen Arbeit." Justus Wilhelm Hedemann, whose warning against the "threat to law and state" posed by the abandonment of rigorous legal norms in favor of general clauses had just appeared in early 1933, now concludes: "There are no more hate-filled partisans stubbornly struggling for every penny, but only the will to 'order,' order in the works as in the wage scale. A firm band of law is to forge together all those associated with an enterprise, even with regard to the hardest questions. Belonging together is not merely one of the values of the new German labor law; it is its basic value. This distinguishes the new German labor law from the partially related Italian one. Because Mussolini's Carta del Lavoro is still deliberately and emphatically built upon the existence of the two formed groups, givers and takers of work, but this is no longer the case in Adolf Hitler's national labor statute." 39 Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung 3 (1. February 1934) Cp. Hedemann 1933, esp. pp. 16-18. But Hedemann, despite his occasional misgivings, had already welcomed the legal doctrine of "works-community" in earlier works: see, for example, "Betriebsgemeinschaft als Rechtsproblem," in Potthoff 1925, pp. 17-36. A footnote indicates, by the way, that the notorious Roland Freisler wrote his dissertation in support of this doctrine. 69 labor resistance that the Weimar courts sought to hamper and that their successor tribunals, often with the same membership, brutally repressed. The question before us is by no means, absurdly, whether Sinzheimer was in any sense politically allied with National Socialism; it is whether Neumann is mistaken in his contention that Sinzheimer's conception of the law and his legal strategy are to be understood as nothing more than a preliminary and yet contributory symptom of the crisis in liberal law and capitalist society that was most malignantly expressed, in Neumann’s judgment, by National Socialism. Did Sinzheimer have a legal theory distinguishable from proto-fascist "institutionalism" in more than political intention? Do his theory and, more generally, his approach to the law deserve a more discriminating and more favorable assessment ? These questions have more than historical interest. Contemporary debates about "legalization" (Verrechtlichung) of the labor movement, especially in Germany, England, and the United States, take up the issues not far from where Neumann left them almost fifty years ago. When, for example, Rainer Erd in Germany (1977, 1979, 1983; cp. Moritz 1980 and Ronge 1983) or Karl Klare in the United States (1978, 1982) claim that the practical legal doctrine of the labor movement undermines that movement's capacities for promoting the interests of the working class, let alone serving as a force for progressive social change, their analyses, rich as they are in detailed treatment of recent events and legal judgements, follow along the lines that Neumann took up in the mid-thirties.4 And when Gunther Teubner (1982) or Rüdiger Voigt (1980, 4 The belated and limited post-war reception of these Weimar labor law discussions was initiated by Thilo Ramm, with a source book (1966). See also his authoritative 70 1983), in contrast, explore the possibilities of a "reflexive jurisprudence" to provide for multiple self-governing constitutions within the framework provided by a democratic state, in place of the opaque administrative arbitrage found ever more oppressive and ineffective by critics of all political persuasions, their thinking is reminiscent of Sinzheimer --and susceptible to the criticism of being "institutionalist.” It is the objective of the present historical study to show that Sinzheimer’s strategy is properly understood only when his legal analysis of labor law is viewed together with his political assessment of the labor movement. The interdependence between the two dimensions is not reducible to the terms of analysis at home in either domain; there is a complementarity between the legal and political theories. As a practical jurist, Sinzheimer does not address the reflexive meta-theoretical problem of review of the record, a number of years later, "Die Arbeitsverfassung der Weimarer Republik," in Franz Gamillscheg, et al., In Memoriam Sir Otto Kahn- Freund (Munich, 1980). A major source is Fraenkel (1973), representing original contributions to the Weimar discussions, written as a student and then colleague of Sinzheimer and his successor as chronicler in Die Justiz, as well as subsequent re- interpretations of the experience. For an influential if brief early utilization, see Hartwich 1967, pp. 14f. Forthcoming in a Sonderband of Ius commune is a valuable contribution by a distinguished living scholar, who was Sinzheimer's last assistant in Frankfurt: Franz Mestitz, "Zur Wirkungsgeschichte des Arbeitsrechts." Contrasting and illustrative recent interpretations of the story are Andreas Kaiser, "Kollektives Arbeitsrecht und gewerkschaftlicher Funktionsverlust in der Weimarer Republik," Demokratie und Recht, 8. Jg., Heft 4, 1980, 444-451, and Henryk Skrzypczak, "Zur Strategie der Freien Gewerkschaften in der Weimarer Republik," in Heinz Oskar Vetter, ed., Vom Sozialistengesetz zur Mitbestimmung, Cologne, 1975, pp. 201 ff. An outstanding specialist on Kahn-Freund, Neumann, et al. is Wolfgang Luthardt. See, for example, "Kontinuität und Wandel in der Theorie Franz L. Neumanns," Internationale wissenschaftliche Korrespondenz zur Geschichte der deutschen Arbeiterbewegung, (September, 1983) 329-373. There are usefully contrasting viewpoints in two papers in Zeitschrift für Rechtssoziologie 1/81, indicating the present state of the German debate: contributions by Michael Kittner/Axel Breinlinger and by Wolfgang Däubler. The corresponding American debate, much cruder, is in 4 National Labor Relations Law Journal 450 (1981) 71 such an intellectual composite, but the record of his practice on the issue of the workscommunity poses the question in a productive way. 2. The Doctrine of Works-Community in Weimar Labor Law The German courts during the Weimar years employed the concept of "works-community" most notably in decisions relating to the payment of wages during temporary closures of enterprises. The German Civil Code (BGB) provides for an exception to the rules normally governing reciprocal contracts (gegenseitiger Vertrag) when those contracts are contracts of employment. While a failure to perform the contracted services that is due to factors making the employee unable to perform will normally simply excuse the performance (323), an inability on the part of the employer to utilize the services (Annahmeverzug) renders him liable for the payment of wages, without requiring the employee to make up the omitted performance (615). In the new period of labor activism after the First World War, the courts confronted a series of cases in which they were asked to decide whether clause 323 or 615 applies where the performance is rendered impossible by the effects of labor conflicts in which the claimant for wages is not directly involved. In a series of decisions, beginning with a judgment of the highest court (Reichsgericht) and continuing through decisions of the labor court (Reichsarbeitsgericht), after its establishment in 1927, the German courts came to hold that the issues should not be decided by technical legalistic explication of the two clauses but by reference to the sweeping general code provisions concerning "good faith" (Treu und Glauben, 242). The decision of the highest labor court doctrinally culminating this line of development said, "The 72 individualistic point of view that was determinative of employment relationships at the enactment of the German Civil Code cannot claim today the significance that it had at that time, because the idea of a social labor-and works-community has in the meantime been recognized and established in legislation as well as in juristic science." (Reichsarbeitsgericht decision of June 20, 1928) The initial case in the sequence involved non-striking trolley car employees whose workplace was shut down by a strike in the company's power plant. Unlike later cases, when the courts will use sweeping general clauses, the court still attempted in this case to cast its decision in the form of an interpretation of the clauses on inability to perform, but the reasoning depended on the notion of a works community. All of the contracts of employment are held to be grounded upon the collaborative effort of all members of the works community; when this necessary precondition is not met, the contracts are to be taken as unperformable by reason of the kind of inescapable circumstance that the German Civil Code subsumes under its paragraph 323, and the employers is to be excused from performance.5 5 Decision of the Reichsgericht, 6 February 1923, Reichsgerichts Zeitung 106, 272. The general clause concerning "good faith" is thus used as an auxiliary to the construction of 323 BGB. It may be of some relevance that the same court in that year culminated a series of cases in which it used this doctrine of underlying commercial precondition (geschäftliche Grundlage) by actually revaluating a contract whose face value had been rendered meaningless by the German mega-inflation, in disregard of legal tender legislation and universally accepted doctrine (Decision of November 28, 1923), and that its members in effect threatened to rule in disregard of the legislation that was enacted in 1925 in order to set limits to such revaluation. The doctrinal history we are considering cannot be separated, as will become clear, from questions about the forms and limits of judicial authority. The influential decision in this area by the Reichsarbeitsgericht was the decision of 20 June 1928, Bensheimer Sammlung, vol. 3, No. 35, p. 116. For discussion of the cases, and a complete list of related cases up to July 2, 1930, see Otto Kahn-Freund, "The Social Ideal of the Reich Labor Court," in 73 Kahn-Freund 1981, pp. 126 f. and footnote 42 on p. 158. Later cases can be located with the help of the index in the annual compilation of supplements to Das Arbeitsrecht: Rechtsprechung des Arbeitsgerichts. For the "prevailing doctrine (herrschende Lehre)," past and present, see, for example, Alfred Hück and H.C. Nipperdey, Lehrbuch des Arbeitsrechts (Mannheim, 1928), pp. 194-201; same (1970), pp. 81-84. Justus Wilhelm Hedemann, Schuldrecht des Bürgerlichen Gesetzbuches, Berlin, 1949, pp. 266-269; Walter Kaskel, Arbeitsrecht Neubearbeitet von Hermann Dersch, Berlin, 1932, pp. 188190; O. Jaümig et al., Bürgerliches Gesetzbuch, Munich, 1981, pp. 622-624. Startling continuities in the immediate post-world-war-two period are suggested by the following excerpt from the leading commentary for 1953: (After the first world war), basic principles concerning dependent work took form, that steadily departed from the character of the contract of employment as part of the law of contracts, finding their basis in the mutual bonds arising out of cooperation in the enterprise and in the collective shaping of the work-relationship. This development was not interrupted while the Law for the Ordering of National Work of 1934 was in effect, since this law, as far as the essence of the dependent service-relationship is concerned, simply took over the basic principles already developed, and the leadership-principle that it introduced made no substantial difference in this. The new conception of the workrelationship as a community-relationship in personal rather than material law definitively asserted itself and still prevails today .... While the earlier jurisprudence required employer and worker each to bear the risk falling in his own ambit of responsibility -- the employer, the interruption of work due to technical or economic causes affecting the enterprise, and the worker, the interruption brought about by his own conduct or by that of his comrades, with the risk to be divided between them in the event of general disturbances -- the Reichsarbeitsgericht, after the Law for the Ordering of National Work came into effect, concluded from the leading position of the entrepreneur in the affairs of the enterprise and from his duty of caring for the welfare that he alone had in principle to bear the full risk and that only jeopardy to the continued existence of the enterprise, taken together with the worker's duty of fealty, could justify an occasional partial or even complete extinction of the wage claim. This principle continues to be recognized after the suspension of this law, although it is now also derived from the position of the employer as entrepreneur who has the direction and responsibility for the leadership of the enterprise, derives the gains from the work and must therefore also bear the losses. (RGR Komm. zum BGB, 1953, pp. 304, 308) Subsequent developments reinstated the doctrine of "spheres." The commentator does not consider it worth remarking that "while the Law for the Ordering of National Work was in effect," as he tactfully characterizes the Nazi regime, the "leader" of the "works-community" did not have to worry about independent labor 74 organizations, let alone the risk of strikes. But the turn of events recorded in the commentary underlines the fact that it is not the substantive outcomes of these cases that are politically significant, but the twists of doctrine. . 75 As a practical matter, the subsequent judgments were more often controlled by matter, the subsequent judgements were more often controlled by reasonings associated with the so-called labor-community, involving a notion of imputed solidarity between strikers and non-strikers and exempting employers from liability for wages where the inability to accept the services of employees willing to work was due to a strike or other labor-action, but the linkage between this concept and the notion of the works-community was everywhere in the language of the decisions. It helped to obscure the curious imposition of class-solidarity on all workers regardless of their subjective dispositions or individual interests and to provide a generalized ideological justification for this refusal to apply legal provisions precisely intended to deal with the issues. The German courts swept wide. An especially striking decision by a provincial court, some years later, denied the claims for wages made by higher office and supervisory personnel rendered unable to work by a lockout of the production workers in a textile plant, where the lockout came about on instruction of the trade association, combating strikes elsewhere in the industry. The angry objections to these decisions from Clemens Nörpel, the labor law specialist who was a leading functionary of the small clerical and managerial employees’ union allied to the socialist-oriented labor movement (ADGB), indicate something about the conflict generated among different groups of workers by this doctrine: Of course, it is progress in principle when the courts hammer it into white collar employees, above all, that there are bonds of solidarity between them and the workers. Unions also carry on this essential work of enlightenment. But the 76 practical conclusions that the courts are drawing are as yet altogether without a basis in actual developments. The unions first have to adjust themselves to this. The workers' unions would have to reach an agreement with the employees' unions in every strike. That would soon make common demands inescapable. Preconditions, in a word, that are so far only in their earliest beginnings. The courts can't go on this way, forcing life to make an abrupt, total turnabout. We'd come to catastrophic conditions (Nörpel 1926, p. 102,cp. Nörpel 1925). 6 But characteristic and suggestive as Nörpel’s pragmatic objections may be, our interest in the problems of assigning liability in these cases is not limited to their direct effects on the state of labor relations. The decisions assumed importance by virtue of their rationales more than by virtue of their immediate legal outcomes. In the general crisis of legitimacy of the Weimar republic, where concepts of pluralism and democratically-controlled group conflict were seen by many as breaches of public order and a threat to the state, the 6 The issue was attentively followed in the Korrespondenzblatt of the General Council of the Free Trade Unions; consistently pressing the case for wage payments. Of course, the situations often involved closures having nothing to do with partial strikes, and there was a general union interest in preventing judicial innovations that would make it impossible to claim wages when plants were closed by shortages, transportation problems, or breakdown of energy supplies. See Arbeiterrechts-Beilage Nrs. 1 and 6, 32 Korrespondenzblatt (1922) and Arbeiterrechts-Beilage Nr. 6, 1923. In the former of these, the newsletter calls attention to the lower-court decision in the tramway case, in an article bitterly noting that the whole problem is one where the legal outcome depends on chance. In Berlin, for example, courts in the North and West of the city, rule against wage claims, while the rest tend to rule in their favor. The last cited article covers the High Court decision of February 6, 1923, sarcastically jibing at the "social" interest of a court that rules against those with the only real "social" claim and charging it with having done nothing more than to throw up a defense of large entrepreneurs faced with strikes. For Nörpel's overall conception of labor law, see Nörpel/Gusko 1932. 77 generalized reasonings of the court were read for their larger ideological implications and had effect at that level, especially when taken together with such related legal doctrines as those laid down in decisions holding all strikes on behalf of organizational objectives, including attempts to secure reinstatement of employees dismissed for union activities, as counter to good morals and therefore illegal. The unspecific concepts of "community" and the related "communal" criteria of good morals were deployed to weaken the legitimacy of class-organization. The emphasis on organization by "works" rather than by collective union-management relations, moreover, was a primary theme among employers' organizations and their allies (Hartwich 1967, 314 f.)7 3. The Ambiguity of Weimar Labor Law A leading proponent of the Weimar labor law promoted by Sinzheimer took strong issue, however, with Nörpel's objections to the high court's doctrine. Heinz Potthoff wrote: Nörpel is in the midst of the practical activity of union struggles and, he sees with special urgency anything that might hamper or endanger the unions and their campaign for the advancement of the mass of workers. For me, the reform of labor law comes first, and I see this objective as no less embracing, difficult, and urgent. In order to push it forward, I am willing to accept a temporary worsening 7 See also contributions by Josef Winschuh and Hermann Meissinger in Potthoff 1925. The non-striking "yellow" unions in Germany referred to themselves as the "works-community" movement (Werksgemeinschaften), and the major employers, at least in heavy industry, broke their 1918 agreement with the genuine unions to end their support for these associations, usually company-unions, as soon as the employers regained the ascendancy after the stabilization of 1923-4. Hartwich 1967, pp. 314 f. A more thorough examination of the ideological significance of "Betrieb" and "Betriebsgemeinschaft" would have to consider in some detail the conflict over works-councils that began in 1919 (Crusius/Schiefelbein/Wilke 1978). 78 of the workers' position. Because it is simply true that progress in legal policy is more easily made against the workers than for them (Potthoff 1926, pp. 106-107). Potthoff could well feel that he had earned the right to weigh such alternatives and to speak in this manner to the trade unions, since he was one of the outstanding supporter of a conception of labor law that assigned the highest importance to the interests of workers and to the organizations of labor. With Hugo Sinzheimer, he had founded the journal Arbeitsrecht in 1914, and like him, he assigned a special weight to the concept embodied in the title. Labor law, in that view, is not simply the aspect of the legal system that covers the relationships and claims pertaining to employment. It is, rather, an integral system, at least in principle, for establishing the terms upon which the interpersonal relationships comprising the organization of work can be justly and peacably maintained. It is, moreover, a system of organization destined to replace and not merely to supplement the objectified and impersonal formalisms of the legal system that modern states have established under the influence of liberalism and capitalism. And its basic actors are collective legal personalities, not the individuals of liberal legalism. Accordingly, Potthoff strongly supported the rights of coalitions of workers, as well as employers, and the principles of collective bargaining. He shared Sinzheimer's views about the normative effects of collective agreements and their superordination over individual contracts of employment, and he campaigned for systems of workers' representation long before the establishment of works-councils. And yet he insisted that the court's decision on the matter of entrepreneurial risk, although he disagreed with the specific ruling, represented an "historic" breakthrough for this novel conception of labor 79 law. The crucial thing, as he saw it, was that the Court had announced that it would rule on the basis of "social conditions" and not the rules of the German civil code. Since the occasions on which the court acceeded to this principle of interpretation involve strikes, the immediate rulings have been inimical to the interests of workers, as the unions see them. But all this will look quite different, he asserts, once a "social economy" has been achieved, since strikes will not be allowed then anyway: Now it is quite true that we do not have socialism today, but capitalism, and that the attitude of the unions must adapt itself to this legal and economic order, But the reform efforts must nevertheless go in the direction where the goal comes into view. Valid developmental ideas must not be rejected simply because they are in advance of the situation to which one is adjusted (Potthoff 1926a). Potthoff devoted a whole issue of Arbeitsrecht to this issue, significantly called "Implementation of the Collective Idea.” After the opening article by Nörpel cited above, Potthoff offered not only his own reply but also two more articles by close associates, reviewing recent works on the question of the collective identity of the enterprise and the distribution of entrepreneurial risk in the event of interruptions in production. All three of these articles agreed that the court had erred in its 1923 decision when it suggested that the works-community exempted the employer from his responsibility for paying wages without giving due weight to the facts of his proprietorship and profits, but all three welcomed the suggestion that there was a collective responsibility among employees, so that none of them as individuals could escape the consequences of actions taken by the collectivity. Above all, the articles celebrated the principle of 80 interpretation introduced, welcoming it as a major step towards rendering the enterprise legally independent of the congeries of individual contracts usually used to characterize it, towards giving it its own legal personality. For Potthoff, the central point is that workers enter into a collective venture, with collective norms and obligations, when they enter upon work, and they can only assert collective rights within functionalized organs of production. "As long as we do not achieve this organic-social attitude towards labor law," he maintains,"labor law cannot attain its most important cultural objective." "The individuals must feel like members of a whole, not merely like associates but like collaborators in a common venture," he continued, "what hinges on this psychic reorientation is the very possibility of vocational satisfaction and thus of the people's culture of work and everyday life (Potthoff 1926, p. 108)." 8 Potthoff argued that the ultimate legal justification for the court's initiative in 8 The other articles in the special issue, in addition to Nörpel's and Potthoff's, are Else Buddeberg, "Der Betrieb als Kollektivbegriff der modernen Arbeiterverfassung," pp. 117-124, and H. Philipp, "Lohnanspruch bei Betriebsstockung und Teilstreik. Entwicklung von Individualrecht zu Sozialrecht", 127-134. Elsewhere in the same volume, Potthoff criticizes several decisions that take up the mistaken aspect of the high court's decision, assuming a community of interests between employers and workers rather than recognizing the collective responsibility of workers. In short, Potthoff tries to separate the doctrines of "Arbeitergemeinschaft" from "Betriebsgemeinschaft," although the courts consistently linked them. "Fehlurteile," Heft 4, (April, 1926), 314-317. See also the articles by Potthoff in Potthoff 1925. For an indication of similar thinking in Socialist circles, see, for example, Hermann Muttutat, "Die Neugestaltung des Arbeitsrechts," Sozialistische Monatshefte, 29. Jg. Bd. 60, 406- 411 (1923) Potthoff puts this "collectivist" decision at the center of his wider treatment of "Die Verselbständigung des Betriebes," 55 Juristische Wochenschrift 533 (Heft 5, 1926). For a fascinating treatment of Potthoff and other outstanding jurists active between 1920 and 1950, putting the key issues in a different methodological and theoretical context than the one presented here, although one that would have to be considered in more extensive work, see Spiros Simitis, Die faktischen Vertragsverhältnisse als Ausdruck der gewandelten sozialen Funktion der Rechtsinstitute des Privatrechts, Frankfurt, 1957. ." 81 moving away from the individualistic doctrines of the civil code derives from the Weimar Constitution. He does not claim that that constitution lays down binding and effective direct norms rendering the law of labor relations collectivistic, but rather that the change is dictated by the "spirit of the constitution," that is "social" as well as "democratic.” "That means the spirit that speaks out of the constitution as well as the spirit that gave birth to it, the underlying idea of the fundamental law, as well as the spirit of the age that created it." While the letter of the law remains the same, he asserts, the meaning must be changed, if it is not to run counter to the foundations of the legal order and of the state itself (Potthoff 1925a, p. 4).9 Although the Weimar constitution does not make a commitment to the abolition of the wage system, he maintains, it does set in train the end of individualism in law, as social reality has long ended it in most spheres of life. The interplay between the courts and the legislature will achieve this design, formalizing a constitutional structure to comprehend the actual tendency in the shape of things. And in this process, he asserts, the courts must be the pioneers. "As someone who knows his times and their social needs, the judge is the best reformer of the law," he maintains (Potthoff 1925a). If the outcomes are imperfect or even incorrect, the need is to work on litigation and legal doctrine to move developments in the right direction. Any attempt to assert individual claims instead, however tempting the immediate advantage, is reactionary and vain. The day of the collectivity has come. 9 For a similar reading of the constitution, in this connection, see Edgar TatarinTarnheyden, "Artikel 165. Recht der Berufsverbände und Wirtschaftsdemokratie," in Hans Carl Nipperdey, Die Grundrechte und Grundpflichte in der Verfassung 3. Bd. (1930. Despite Tatarin-Tarnheden's blatantly corporatist treatment of this and other questions, Neumann praises him in his review of Nipperdey’s volumes (1929: 1981). 82 Sinzheimer vehemently disagreed with Potthoff's assessment of the issues. First of all, he opposed the doctrine of "works-community" in a number of professional opinions for trade unions . His basic argument in the opinions is that the courts had mistaken the law by applying an implausible social analysis under cover of the general clause on "good faith" to something that should properly be treated as a straightforward case in contracts. He denied that the parties associated within a works could be considered as being in community with regard to anything to do with wealth (Vermögen). The co-participation established by the works-council-legislation has only to do with questions concerning the treatment of labor; wider moves towards economic community have been aborted, and they could not, in any case, affect the point at issue here, unless they had actually progressed to the point where they eliminated the conflict of economic interests between workers and those for whom they work. The reciprocal obligations concerning the exchange of wages for work arise out of a reciprocal contract (gegenseitigen Schuldvertrag) as provided in the civil code; there is no contract of association (Gesellschaftsvertrag). In consequence, there is no more reason for a wage-earner to bear any part of the risk involved in the entrepreneur's pursuit of profit than for a supplier who delivers goods as per contract at a time when the goods cannot be utilized. As for as the supposed work-community among the employees, Sinzheimer maintains that they are unified in law only by being subject in common to the authority of their employer; they have no common legal obligations in the sense of the civil code. It is the power of the employer that forms the whole that the court mistakenly treats as a collective legal actor. The workers cannot control one another at work and they cannot 83 be held responsible for one another's actions. A fortiori, workers cannot be held responsible for the conduct of employees in other works or even industries. At most, he was prepared to concede the principle embodied in the legislation covering unemployment compensation, that workers who would benefit directly from the changed terms of employment being sought by the strikers might be excluded from wage payments. There, at least, there was a community of interests. In sum, Sinzheimer rejected the doctrine of imputed solidarity and "spheres" as well as the doctrine of "works-community." And he warned: One can see . . . the upshot of adjudication that no longer orients itself to the law and its principles, but to social relationships as the judge imagines them to be . . . . If this development continues, it will soon be possible to say that we have labor law indeed, but that it is only valid to the extent that the judge considers it to be reconcilable with the principle of good faith, as he understands it (Sinzheimer 1929, pp. 42 and 45)10 These are intelligent legal arguments. But Sinzheimer was syndicus for the Free Trade Unions (ADGB) and it was his job to deliver effective legal arguments on issues affected the vital interests of unions. One of the professional opinions attacking the court's doctrine in these cases was provided by him to a union facing shop-closures as a result of the breakdown of markets during the Ruhr-Boycott and wanting to claim wages notwithstanding the doctrine of works-community, and the other was given to the 10 Reprinted, in part, in 16 Arbeitsrecht 4 (April 1929), 223-227 and 16 Arbeitsrecht 5 (May, 1929) 297-303. See also Hugo Sinzheimer, "Absatzstockung und Arbeitsvertrag," (1924) in Sinzheimer 1976 1/ pp. 207-215. Similar: Franz L. Neumann, "Betriebsrisiko," 1 Arbeitsrechts-praxis, Heft 10 (1928), pp. 219-223 ." 84 trade union of supervisory office-workers, interested in being excused from the supposed labor-community when there is a strike of production-workers. Neumann, moreover, was working together with Sinzheimer during a number of these years, as he indicates in dedicating his 1932 book on the legal status of trade unions to Sinzheimer, and certainly knew Sinzheimer’s position on this specific controversy. So the agreement between Sinzheimer and Nörpel on the specific issues need not be decisive for the theoretical questions we are exploring. The question remains whether Sinzheimer's advice on these matters rests on a coherent position different in principle from the vague invocation of "social" reasoning whose consequences he so vigorously attacks here, or whether his insistence in these cases on the contract law of the German civil code and his dismay at the liberties taken by the judge simply confirms the more general thesis advanced by Neumann after the collapse of Weimar, that the type of jurisprudence characterized by institutionalism and the recourse to general clauses is completely politicized and opportunistic, devoid of all inner rational structure. 4. Sinzheimer’s Theory of Collective Labor Law Sinzheimer's social analysis of the civil law in its effective functioning took over from Gierke the conception of the employment relationship having more in common with an institution of interpersonal dependency and domination than with a contract of exchange (Gierke 1868, 1914). This is common ground with Pothoff. But his theory of the institution Sinzheimer derived from Marx, by way of Karl Renner (1904: 1949, 1929). The power of domination inherent in property in a capitalist society is acknowledged as the decisive fact concerning work, but the authority associated with that power is seen 85 as provisional, loosening as property loses its directive functions in modern industry and as labor organizes its collective opposition. The authentic law of the relationship is increasingly generated by the resistance of those subjected to the power in question. It manifests itself as a provisional constitutional structure established by collective agreement, either for a stated time or in an intermittent process. As it changes over time, it registers the various stages towards the full democracy that is to come, when the functions of direction and coordination will be performed altogether without reference to rights of property. This authentic law is the labor law. Its center and paradigm is the collective agreement. Its terms consequently depend on the comparative weights of the contesting powers at a given stage, taking into account all of the resources pertinent to a power contest within an institution whose productive functioning is essential to the survival, let alone the well-being, of society. As long as the organization of labor is not strong enough to organize production, it must deal with an employer who is a proprietor. As long as it must deal with such a proprietor, it must have full benefit of all safeguards provided by the formalizations of contract law, the old formalizations of the civil code, now performing new kinds of functions, as well as the new laws of participatory councils and collective agreements. The social constitution of work, like the political constitution of the state, must comprehend a diversity of relationships among the same set of actors, and there is no rule of consistency about the structures of these relationships. Simmel's brilliant inventory of the plurality of social figures is contemporaneous with Sinzheimer's first interest in sociology. Gierke's treatment of early law, and especially his work on 86 Althusius, also illuminates the possibilities of pluralism. What Sinzheimer adds to this is the notion of a dynamic constitution, integrating the mix from time to time but also encouraging it to change. This is certainly not Marx's theory of social or political change, since it stresses successive and cumulative reorganizations of ongoing social functions, including production and legal ordering, rather than revolutionary break and a new starting point. Nor is it, however, a theory taken in by illusory homogenizations and romantic spiritualizations of exploitative power relationships. At least not as a rule.11 Sinzheimer is enthusiastic about the new labor law and about the potentialities of the social and political constitutions established in 1919. But he never loses sight of the fact that they are possibilities and not completed achievements. That's what made him a tough 11 There are some indications that Sinzheimer's 1919 design for "anchoring the councils in the constitution," that eventuated in Article 165 of the Weimar Constitution, although ostensibly meant to accommodate the demands of the radicalized workers in the council movement (Sinzheimer 1919), may have been concerted with Rudolf Wissell's Ministry of Economic Affairs, where there was scathing contempt for radicals and for any socialization measures that might damage entrepreneurial leadership. The conception of "Gemeinwirtschaft" promulgated there was expressly conceived by some in the ministry as continuous with the views of those who had been most committed to national victory in the war, placing the general good above that of individuals. A departmental press spokesman vehemently praised Sinzheimer's proposals while claiming departmental parentage for them, during a remarkable confidential press briefing on the day on which Sinzheimer first presented them to the S. P. D. Parteikonferenz in Weimar. The spokesman remarked that it was high time that the government "threw the people a bone.” (Transcript in Nachlass Arnold Brecht, Bundesarchiv Koblenz) In June of 1919, Wissell twice wrote the chief author of the ministry's ideas, Wichard von Möllendorf, in terms that suggest full agreement between themselves and Sinzheimer (Wissell 1983, pp. 265-266; cp. Miller 1978). But socialization and council discussions within government, Social Democratic Party, and Free Trade Unions were in such an ambiguous and confused state in the Spring and Summer of 1919 that Sinzheimer's closeness to Wissell at that time, notwithstanding all the talk of community between industry and labor, also brought him close to the only influential insider force pressing concretely for measures to transform the structure of the economy. Bieber 1981, pp. 685-695 87 lawyer committed practically to the organizations whose power he considered essential to the actualization of the constitution--what in American labor law is called "managing the agreement"--and preparing for further movement. This commitment to the power of the trade unions and, to a lesser extent, the Social Democratic Party, increasingly distinguished him from the liberal socially-minded reformers who were often his allies against Left and Right in his constitutional designs. His political alignments form an essential complement to his conception of those designs and his hopes about their eventual consequences (Sinzheimer 1927).12 4. Complementarity and the Labor Courts 12 For a contrasting assessment of Sinzheimer's work and of the legal policies of the labor movement in Weimar, see the well-researched work by Martiny (1976). On the central place of "organization" in the ADGB's political strategy, see Gerhard Beier, "Autonome Transformationspolitik der Gewerkschaften," Horst Heimann/Thomas Meyer, Hrsg., Reformsozialismus und Sozialdemokratie (Berlin, Bonn, 1982) 301-316. Sinzheimer's conception of constitutional development derives in part from Georg Jellinek 1906. See Hugo Sinzheimer, "Georg Jellinek," (1938). The question whether the growing power of labor can be "cashed in" from time to time in the form of constitutional change and reform of the law is matter for interesting discussion among social democrats during the debate on the BGB in the last decade of the nineteenth century. Thomas Vormbaum 1977. It also occasions a thoughtful but heretical rejoinder to Engels'/Kautsky's treatment of Menger's "Juristen-Sozialismus", by an anonymous writer uncharacteristically given space in Neue Zeit by Kautsky. The writer distinguishes two views of the power of labor, one taking it as "latent" and the other as "actual.” Those who hold the former think that labor's increasing power can only assert itself in a revolutionary moment; the others, that the power steadily changes the social equation and makes possible continuous and cumulative assertion by way of legal changes. Anon., "Die soziale Frage und die Rechtsordnung," Neue Zeit, XI/2 (1890-91) Nr. 40, pp. 430- 438; Nr. 41, pp. 476-480; Nr. 43, pp. 539-544. For an introductory overview of the competing conceptions of "Sozialpolitik" and especially the widespread disillusionment among social reformers with the "class-selfishness" of organized labor in Weimar, useful as a contrast to Sinzheimer, see Preller 1949, pp. 204ff. 88 Sinzheimer’s view of the new labor courts offers a striking illustration of the complementary relationship between his theoretical conception and political activity in the broad sense, and it bears directly on the issues raised by Neumann's critique. Even if it is granted that Sinzheimer's social analysis of institutions differs from the institutionalism easily adapted to denials and suppression of social conflict and that the difference is by no means simply a matter of political or organizational opportunism, it seems even more clear from the presentation of his curious "constitutionalism" that much law will have to be made by judges. And the conception of judges free to make laws is inseparable from the flight from specific legal norms, comparatively constraining upon judicial procedure and decision, to "general clauses" concerning procedure and substance, a feature that Neumann correctly identifies as a hallmark rationalization of National Socialist jurisprudence. Sinzheimer did accept the shift from norms to principles, if also with mounting discomfort. He vigorously fought, first, for informal proceedings in labor courts, based on the practice of the pre-war commercial courts, a mix of administrative hearing and mediation, and, second, in his regular column in Die Justiz, he repeatedly supported Ernst Fuchs' enthusiastic version of the "free-law" doctrine, propogated at great length in the earlier years of the journal. Yet he qualified his agreements in both instances. His campaign with regard to labor courts concentrated on the need to separate them completely from the judicial system at the level of first instance and to give a major role on the courts to lay assessors drawn from the respective organizations of both labor and ownership, and this familiar trade union demand is a far cry from the mythical judge as wise voice of the Acommunity.” In association with successive ministers of labor and with the 89 representatives of the ADGB he carried this fight through years of deliberations in the ministerial committee on the unification of the labor law, of which he was a member, and he also played a leading part in opposing attempts by Gustav Radbruch, during his brief tenure as Minister of Justice, to sway the Social Democratic Party from this antilegalistic position. His support for free-law in general was qualified, first, by a constant if not always consistent insistence that rigorous legal-scientific analysis of doctrine had to precede any consideration of larger social considerations that might properly be invoked in a legal case, and, second, by the requirement that the makeup and dominant ideology of the judiciary would have to be rendered more consistent with the newly-established democratic constitution before their range of free discretion could reasonably be expanded. That was the point of his leading role in the Association of Republican Justices and his determined campaign to require governments to counter the "crisis of confidence in justice" by democratization of legal education and the courts. The Association of German Justices (Deutscher Richterbund) fought Sinzheimer on both complexes of issues. The contest more directly pertinent to our present interests concerns the character of the labor court. This was the issue that delayed enactment of the legislation for six years, as judicial officials and groups combined with representatives of business interests to demand incorporation of the labor law into the work of the ordinary courts, or at least the full integration of labor courts into the judicial system, with its professional judiciary. The legislation finally secured by the stubborn insistence of Brauns, the priest who was minister of labor for most of the years of the Weimar Republic, the trade unions, and the small group led by Sinzheimer satisfied the 90 most important demands of organized labor. In a furious, last-minute attempt to block its enactment, the head of the Association of German Justices, a judge of the high court, maintained that the division being created between civil law and the law of labor was coming "at a time that needs synthesis between them more than any in the past" and at a time that gives the most promising signs that the legal profession, as well as the general public, is coming to recognize "that work does and must represent the kernel and essence of all life." Labor cases are making the courts in general more social-minded, the conservative judge argued, presumably with an eye to the workscommunity decisions. To separate labor jurisprudence would impede the development towards organicism and Acommunity.” He wrote: We have abandoned the overly logical and abstract way of thinking, influenced by a misunderstood Roman law; we are moving towards an understanding of law as something biological, a segment of life as it is lived, and towards a comprehension that law and equity are inseparable. With this, we are leaving the narrowly civilistic point of view and granting the social idea its rightful place. . . . The spirit of all-German fellowship is about to take the place of Romanist individualistic egoism.13 All this is being disrupted by the decision to give labor its own separate courts, in which 13 Juristenwochenschau, 55. Jg. Heft 28, 4 Dez 1926. For Sinzheimer's role in governmental deliberations on the labor courts, see "Reichskanzlei Akten betreffend Einheitliches Arbeitsrecht (Arbeitsgerichtsgesetz)", Bundesarchiv Koblenz, R43 I/ 2062-2063. The first item in the file is a "Programm für die Neuregelung des Arbeitsrechts in Deutschland," by Sinzheimer. Paul Umbreit, the editor of the Korrespondenzblatt of the Free Trade Unions, represented that organization in these discussions. Note the paralellism between his intervention in the meeting of 20/21 February 1922 (f. 188) and Sinzheimer's written response to the agenda (f. 178). Cp. Martiny 1976, pp. 99-114. 91 the narrow class interests of labor, according to Justice Reichert, are bound to predominate. The judge, in short, never confused Sinzheimer’s critique of liberal formalism in labor law with his own proto-fascist position. The whole vocabulary of the "social" interpretation of the labor relationship and "works-community", as well as the shining example of the 1923 decision on entrepreneurial risk are turned loose against the legislation that Sinzheimer, mistakenly as it unfortunately proved, welcomed as the beginning of a new day for labor, a triumphant confirmation of his overall conception about labor and the law: Out of the dark corners of a law indifferent to the masses of working people, a law and a way of proceeding have now emerged, that shed the light of full legal worth upon the masses. This law would never have come about without the struggle, the effort, the sacrifices, and the growing power of the labor movement. The developments in labor law show more clearly than any other legal field that the dynamic approach to law is correct. The new state of the law has not come out of juristic theories and dogmatic learning. The new state of the law is the precipitate of the mighty social movement, it is the formal recognition of an actual power (Sinzheimer 1976, 1/ p. 112). Changed conditions undermined that power, and Sinzheimer's hopes proved illusory. We do not contend that Sinzheimer's political judgment was unerring or that his theory is infallible. A theory that respects the freedom that prevails in the political domain cannot offer prophecy. The question is whether it provides insight. The answer suggested here is that Sinzheimer's legal theory cannot be considered apart from his legal, publicistic, pedagogical, and political practice, because 92 his theory itself presupposes continuous action to shift the balance of social power; it rests ultimately upon a theory of constitutional change that recognizes that constitutional questions involve an interplay between questions of law and questions of might. This is not to suggest some dialectical unification of theory and practice: the relationships are those of complementarity rather than synthesis. But the rendering of legal structures and relationships provided by the theory is expressly context-dependent, and the context is understood to be shaped by contests among social and political actors, contests whose outcomes cannot be determined by the theory. Accordingly, Sinzheimer never promulgated a universal theory of "institutionalism;" he saw certain institutionalist modes of legal interpretation becoming increasingly pertinent to certain issues within a new constellation of social forces. He was almost always eminently clear about the limiting conditions upon which such proposals rested, and he knew what it meant to lose the fight to secure those conditions and the consequent need to rethink. His theory might best be construed as a strategic conception, whose concrete meanings are presented to us more reliably in specific legal arguments than in the most general theoretical utterances. 5. Neumann and Sinzheimer Neumann knew all this, because he was intimately associated with Sinzheimer during the later Weimar years, and shared his strategic conception in most respects. When Neumann himself wrote on the sharing of entrepreneurial risk in 1928 and 1929, he repeatedly cited Sinzheimer in support of his argument. First, he insisted that the general clause on "good faith" can be used to supplement the more rigorous norms of the civil code but not to supecede them. Secondly, on a more methodological level, he 93 distinguished between legal sociology as a positive, value-free science and sociological analysis as an auxiliary science for jurisprudence; and he insisted that such analysis is in order only after "technical jurisprudence" has done its work, to check whether social change had subjected the applicable legal norms to a change in function to the extent that their literal application would make no sense. And third, he argued that when such a controlling analysis is performed with regard to the questions in dispute in these cases, it shows the continuing social relevance of the minimal safeguards for workers built into the provisions on employers' liability when they are unable to utilize the services duly offered in compliance with a contract of employment. In answer to Ludwig Bendix, who agreed with his conclusions but challenged him for relying on technical legal analysis and for rejecting the free-law method of judicial discretion and social interpretation of general clauses acknowledged by the court-- as the social movement had been urging it for decades to do (Bendix 1929)--Neumann insisted that such "free-law" approaches become reactionary in their effects once the working class succeeds in translating some of its demands into legal institutions. For Neumann, more simply than for Sinzheimer, at least at this time, the question of judicial discretion appeared to be a strictly political question. The jurists who had insisted on positivist rigor when bourgeois control over law was secure now plead for free-law and institute a judicial regime of American-style judicial review, as well as manipulative deployment of general clauses and analyses that purport to be social. The working class, that had made some gains before the war,when there was nothing like a democratic constitution, with the help of some social-minded judges using informal methods, now must solidify the newer legislative achievements and back the 94 constitutional structure that made them possible by drawing on the defensive capabilities of legal formalism. Although liberal in provenance and ideologically obscurantist, Neumann contends, these forms are neutral in their effects and can be employed on behalf of workers' power. Everything possible must now be done to bind judges to the letter of the law and to a rigorous logic of legal inferences, because they will use any discretionary power they are granted on behalf of their social class. In the course of arguments that are more tactical than strategic, Neumann probably goes further in the direction of Hans Kelsen’s positivism than Sinzheimer, notwithstanding broad areas of agreement between them. Like Heinz Potthoff and some others usually allied with Sinzheimer and Neumann, Bendix welcomed the "collectivist" arguments and free-law methods in the decisions of the High Court, while deploring their specific contents in these cases, and he maintained that the logic of social events would lead to a reversal of the objectionable conclusions, now that the judges had begun on the course of recognizing the need to orient themselves to social realities and social outcomes (Bendix 1929). Neumann dismissed this contention, but not because he saw some general dangers inherent in "collectivist" -- or what he would later designate as "institutionalist" -- legal thinking as such. Rather, he insisted once again on the merely political character of the judges' choice of methods and arguments. He noted, for example, that the courts were overwhelmingly refusing to credit the real solidarity manifested by workers in refusing to work on May Day, and that they were everywhere approving dismissals without notice, on the basis of a strict reading of the relevant clauses in the civil code. Neumann, like Sinzheimer, was perfectly willing to see a more "institutionalist" reading of the workplace 95 situation, even on the matter of sharing entrepreneurial risk, after there had been "a thoroughgoing implementation of the ideas of economic democracy." On the wider methodological issue of the relations between legal and social analyses, then, Neumann wrote: The incredible difficulty of explicating the institutes of labor law lies precisely in the discrepancy between the economic base and legal superstructure. Sociological jurisprudence has the task of restoring a correspondence between them, so far as possible, although, needless to say, this must not involve dismissal of clearly applicable compelling legal norms, regardless of whether such disregard would promote or harm the interests of workers (Neumann 1929). "The great significance of Sinzheimer's Foundations of Labor Law," he concludes, writing in 1929, "consists in its full understanding of this complex of problems." Neumann's own methodological reflections, it seems, displayed the same uncertainties as Sinzheimer's, indicating the "incredible difficulty" of the problems. His frankly political justification for positivist rigor brushed aside theoretical difficulties with even greater facility than Sinzheimer's more interesting design (Neumann 1929). As a participant in the legal and political struggles of the Weimar period, Neumann had no methodical, theoretically-grounded solutions to propose. Under conditions of defeat and exile, however, Neumann became intrigued with the possibilities of an integral, dialectical theory that could read univocal meanings in developments and project necessary next steps. That theory, influenced more by Harold Laski's confident renditions of Marxist generalizations than by the more subtle forms of Marxism with which Neumann had been acquainted earlier, inclined towards 96 simplifications cast in terms of structurally constrained ideological stages that were in turn reflections of socio-economic ones (Neumann 1980). As Neumann himself eventually came closer to seeing once again, such theory could also be deeply misleading, precisely because of its excessive ambition (Neumann 1957). While it may be possible to formulate "institutionalism" as a single coherent theory by abstracting certain common features from several sorts of arguments and showing their similarity to certain French legal theories, it is by no means clear that such a theory was held in Germany in that way. Potthoff's position depended on the special importance he assigned to work as the constitutive activity of culture. Nazi "institutionalism" makes no sense without the conception of the "Führer;" and Sinzheimer's "institutionalism" depends equally on the conception of organized worker's resistance to domination by property. These fundamentally different contexts give very different meanings to the elements generalizable from both. We need a greater appreciation for ambiguity and complexity, as well as curiosity about the detailed treatment of particular problems, to appreciate Sinzheimer's achievement -- and to build the kind of legal theory to which he aspired.14 5. Conclusion 14The present reconsideration of Neumann’s challenge to Sinzheimer is not intended to suggest that Neumann had no cause for concern about ambiguities in his own earlier thought as well as Sinzheimer’s. Carl Schmitt’s subtle apologia for National Socialist jurisprudence was the prime cause of uneasiness, in view of his own earlier respect for Schmitt’s work. In his theory of concrete order (Konkretes Ordnungsdenken), published in 1934, Schmitt distinguished between settled domains appropriate to technical, positivist jurisprudence and dynamic, political domains, subject to regulation in accordance with inner principles articulated in "concrete norms," a distinction not unlike the one that both Sinzheimer and Mannheim made. 97 Duncan Kennedy has offered an attractive theory of the relationships between the forms and substance of law, working with American private law. He finds inner structural connections between "rule”-jurisprudence and "individualism," on the one hand, and between "standards-" jurisprudence and "altruism," on the other. While questioning the plausibility of the methodological program of the former structure, as well as the ethical viability of its substantive norms, he nevertheless insists that no legal thinker can avoid some measure of divided loyalties between the two structures, finding himself abruptly shifting his commitments from one to another on some issues or at some point in a pattern of argument (Kennedy 1976, 1979, 1980). Up to that surprising outcome, Kennedy's analysis parallels the arguments of Ludwig Bendix among the Weimar jurists, the writer who had criticized Neumann's recourse to legal positivist method. Bendix contrasts conceptualist, positivist jurisprudence, comparable in the German legal context to Kennedy's rule-jurisprudence, to free law method, relying on general clauses and social analyses of outcomes, very close to Kennedy's "standards." He sees these methods linked, respectively, to liberal individualism and collectivist social thinking. This too is like Kennedy's analysis. But Bendix has no doubt about the choice to be made, although he thinks that it is more likely to be governed by irrational psychological and social factors than by rational determination (Bendix 1929b).15 The troubled experience that Sinzheimer and Neumann, and the others of their generation, had with such a straightforward commitment underlines the importance of deepening the analysis before drawing conclusions from it. Although Kennedy's analysis avoids 15 Bendix also criticized Potthoff's theoretical grounding of his position, viewing the reliance on constitutional doctrine as dangerously rationalistic and unpolitical. See 13 Arbeitsrecht 4 (April, 1926) 257-276. 98 comparative reference, his closing contentions about ambivalence can be given depth by reflection on the struggles of Weimar socialist jurists to comprehend the repressive "altruism" and manipulative deployment of general standards to break organization and destroy solidarity that marked labor adjudication in the Weimar Republic. The fact that Neumann and some others subsequently treated their own efforts to deal with these complexities as woefully and obviously deluded cannot be the last word on their experiences. The brilliant refugee generation, desolate in their isolation, left us one unfortunate legacy, along with many riches. Probing the agonizing nerve of what they took to be their own failures, they inclined towards a perversely teleological reading of German intellectual history. All thinking was reinterpreted as pointing towards Nazi ideology (or painstakingly exempted from the stigma). Often this included their own past thought and led to a tragic loss of depth and subtlety (Kettler/Meja/Stehr 1984).16 Neumann's Behemoth remains a classic. But the problems of constituting cumulative social change cannot be superceded by generalized invocations of revolutionary politics. And the end of what came after Weimar did not obviate questions of legalized social reform. 16 Sinzheimer was largely exempted from this tendency to blame the victims alongside of the oppressors, as witness his sad, ironic, but ultimately triumphant affirmation of the rich variety of German legal thinking in his book on "Jewish classics of German legal science." (1938) But he could not escape the consequences of being deprived of his craft. If his theorizing depended on the complementarity of his practice, and if forced exile denied him that crucial resource, the Netherlands never received his most vital, living thought. Even the reflections of such a mind can be stimulating; but they can't replace the thinking lawyer (Sinzheimer 1935; cp. Taco van Peijpe, "Hugo Sinzheimer en het nederlandse arbeidsrecht," 10 Recht en Kritiek 7 (1984)). 99 References Aaron, Benjamin. 1982. "Labor Relations in the United States from a Comparative Perspective," Washington and Lee Law Review, 39: (Fall) 4: 1247-1265. Abel, I.W. 1975 Collective Bargaining. Labor Relations in Steel: Then and Now. New York: Columbia University Press (Carnegie Mellon University) Adams, George W.1982. "Labor Law Remedies,” Pp. 56-78 in Swan. Kenneth P./Swinton1982. Adams, Graham. Jr. 1966., Age of Industrial Violence, 1910-1915: The Activities and Findings of the U.S. Commission on Industrial Relations, New York and London:Columbia University Press Anonymous 1890-91. "Die soziale Frage und die Rechtsordnung," Neue Zeit, XI/2, Nr. 40, pp. 430- 438; Nr. 41, pp. 476-480; Nr. 43, pp. 539-544 Arbeiterrechts-Beilage, Korrespondenzblatt .1922/3. Atleson, James B. 1983 Values and Assumptions in American Labor Law, Amherst, Mass: University of Massachusetts Press Bain, George Sayers/Price, Robert, Profiles of Union Growth. Oxford: Blackwell. Beatty, David M. 1987. Putting the Charter to Work. Kingston and Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press Beetham, David. 1989. "Max Weber and the Liberal Political Tradition," European Journal of Sociology, XXX.1989.:311-323 Beier, Gerhard .1982. "Autonome Transformationspolitik der Gewerkschaften," Horst Heimann/Thomas Meyer, Hrsg., Reformsozialismus und Sozialdemokratie. Berlin/Bonn Bendix, L. .1929. "Das Betriebsrisiko," 16 Arbeitsrecht 129 Bendix, L. .1929a. "Mehrdeutige Tatsachen, mehrdeutige Gesetze und die Aufgabe des Richters," 16 Arbeitsrecht 673 100 Bensheimer Sammlung .1928. Reichsarbeitsgerichtrechtsprechung, 20 June 1928. 3. Bd., Nr. 35, S. 116 Berger, Suzanne. 1985. Organizing Interests in Western Europe. Pluralism, Corporatism, and the Transformation of Politics. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press. Bergh, G.C.J.J. van den .1983. "Schijnbewegingen, Hercodificatie en eigendomsdefinitie in historisch perspectief," in Liber Amicorum John Gilissen, Antwerpen: Kluwer Rechtswetenschappen, n.d., pp. 389-404 Berman, Harold J. 1983. Law and Revolution. Cambridge and London: Harvard Bernstein, Irving. 1972. The Lean Years: A History of the American Worker, 1920-1933. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Best, Michael H. 1990 The New Competition: Institutions of Industrial Restructuring. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press Bieber, H.-J. .1981. Gewerkschaften in Krieg und Revolution. Hamburg: Hans Christian Blankenburg, Erhard. 1984 "The Poverty of Evolutionism: A Critique of Teubner's Case for 'Reflexive law'" Law and Society Review 18. 2, 273-301 Brecht, Bertolt. 1967. "Weite und Vielfalt der realistischen Schreibweise," Schriften zur Literatur und Kunst. 1934 bis 1938. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Brecht, Bertolt. 1974. "The Caucasian Chalk Circle" in Brecht, Collected Plays. 7:135-229. New York: Random House Brody, David 1992 "The Breakdown of Labor's Social Contract," Dissent, Winter 1992 Brody, David. 1971. "The Expansion of the American Labor Movement: Institutional Sources of Stimulus and Restraint," in Brody, David ed., The American Labor Movement. New York: Harper & Row. Brody, David. 1980. Workers in Industrial America: Essays on the Twentieth Century Struggle. New York: Oxford University Press. Brousseau, Robert. 1980. "Toward a Theory of Rights for the Employment Relation,” Washington Law Review 56: 1 Brown, Lawrence D. .1983. New Policies, New Politics: Government's Response to Government Growth, Washington:The Brookings Institution Buddeberg, Else .1926. "Der Betrieb als Kollektivbegriff der modernen Arbeiterverfassung," 13 Arbeitsrecht (Sonderheft: Durchsetzung des Kollektivgedankens) Budget Paper E. 1991 Ontario in the 1990s--Promoting Equitable Change. Toronto: Ontario Budget Papers Buroway, Michael. 1985. The Politics of Production: Factory Regimes Under Capitalism and Socialism. London: Verso. Cella, G. and T. Treu. 1982 "National Trade Union Movements," Chapter 10 of R. Blanplain, ed., Comparative Labour Law and Industrial Relations, Deventer, Netherlands: Kluwer CIR. 1916. U.S. Commission on Industrial Relations. 1916. Final Report and Testimony Submitted to Congress by the Commission on Industrial Relations created by the Act of Congress August 23, 1912. 64th Congress, 1st Session, Senate Document No. 415. Clune, William H. 1983 "The Political Origins and Political Process of Regulation: What We Can Learn From A Positive Political Analysis," David Trubek, ed., Reflexive Law and the Regulatory Crisis, papers of a conference at the University of Wisconsin-Madison, July 18-21, 1983. Madison: Disputes Processing Research Program, University of Wisconsin Law School Conference on Regulatory Law and the Regulatory Crisis .1983. Disputes Processing Research Program, University of Wisconsin Law School, July 18-21, 1983 (Unpublished Compilation of Papers edited by David Trubek) 101 Commons, John R./Andrews, John B. 1916. Principles of Labor Legislation.[Prepared in Co-operation with the American Bureau of Industrial Research]), New York, London: Harper and Bros. Connolly, William E. .1969. The Bias of Pluralism, New York: Atherton Press Cox, Paul N. 1985. “On Debunking Labor Law Doctrine: A review of James Atleson's Values and Assumptions in American Labor Law" Utah Law Review 1:101-130 Cox, A. .1960: 1983. Law and the National Labor Policy, Westport, Con. Cox, A. .1976. The Role of the Supreme Court in American Government, Oxford: Oxford University Press Crusius, R./Schiefelbein, G./Wilke, M. .1978. Betriebsräte in der Weimarer Republik. Berlin: Olle und Wolter Cumming, Robert D. 1969. Human Nature and History. A Study of the Development of Liberal Political Thought, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1969. vol. 1. Dahl, Robert A./Lindblom, Charles E. 1953. Politics, Economics, and Welfare. New York: Harper and Row Daintith, Terence and Gunther Teubner, eds. 1986 Contract and Organisation. Legal Analysis in the Light of Economic and Social Theory, Berlin and New York: DeGruyter Das Arbeitsgericht .1933. 38 Jg., Nr. 5 Davies, P.and Freedland, M. : Kahn-Freud, O. .1983. Labour and the Law, Third Edition, London: Stevens and Son Davis, Mike. 1986. Prisoners of the American Dream. London: Verso,. Dewey, J. .1927. The Public and Its Problems, New York: Henry Holt & Co. Dick, William M. 1972 Labor and Socialism in America. The Gompers Era. Port Washington, New York: National Universities Press Donner, A.M. .1979. Bestending en Wederkering. Over het Verband van Staat en Staatsrecht, Zwolle: W.E.J. TjeenkWillink Donner, A.M. .1981. "Grondwetsherziening en statsrechtsdogmatiek. Iets over het materiel wetsbegrip," Mimeo. Dunn, John .1984. The Politics of Socialism. An Essay in Political Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Dworkin, Ronald. 1979. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge: Harvard Dworkin, Ronald. 1985. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge: Harvard Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Law's Empire. Cambridge: Belknap Dyzenhaus, David. 1989. "The New Positivists," University of Toronto Law Journal, 39:361-379 Engels, Friedrich and Karl Kautsky. 1887. "Juristen-Sozialismus," Die Neue Zeit, 22:491-509 England, Geoffrey. 1982. "Some Observations on Selected Strike Laws." Pp. 221-298 in Swan/Swinton 1982. Erd, R. .1977. 'Verrechtlichte Gewerkschaftspolitik. Bedingungen ihrer Entwicklung und Veränderung," in Joachim Bergmann, Hg., Beiträge zur Soziologie der Gewerkschaften, 143-182. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Erd, R. .1979. Verrechtlichung industrieller Konflikte. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Erd, Rainer. 1983. "Gesetzgebung oder Machtpoker? Das Beispiel der amerikanischen Gewerkschaften." in Ruediger Voigt, ed., Abschied vom Recht? Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. 102 Erd, R. .1977. "Verrechtlichte Gewerkschaftspolitik. Bedingungen ihrer Entwicklung und Veränderung", in Joachim Bergmann, ed., Beiträge zur Soziologie der Gewerkschaften, Frankfurt: Edition Suhrkamp, pp. 143-82 Feige, E.L. .1980. "A new perspective on macroeconomic phenomena. The theory and measurement of the unobserved sector of the United States economy: causes, consequences and implications" Paper presented to the August 1980 meetings of the American Economics Association in Denver, Colorado Fisher, Roger, William Ury and Bruce Patton. 1991. Getting to Yes. Negotiating Agreement Without Giving In. New York: Penguin Fox, Alan. 1974. Beyond Contract: Work, Power and Trust Relations. London: Faber. Fraenkel, E. .1973. Reformismus und Pluralismus. Hamburg: Hoffmann und Campe Fraenkel, Ernst. 1929. "Kollektive Demokratie." Die Gesellschaft, 6:8: 103-18 Frankenberg, Günter. 1989. "Down by Law," in Joerges and Trubek 1989. Freeman, Richard B. 1985. "Why Are Unions Faring Poorly in NLRB Representation Elections?" in Kochan, Thomas ed., Challenges and Choices Facing American Labor, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Fricke, Werner, Karl Krahn, Gerd Peter. 1985 Arbeit und Technik als politische Gestaltungsaufgabe. Ein Gutachten aus sozialwissenschaftlicher Sicht. [Der Senator für Bildung, Wissenschaft und Kunst der Freien Hansestadt Bremen (Hg.)] Bonn: Verlag Neue Gesellschaft: Forschungsinstitut der Friedrich-Ebert-Stiftung Friedman, Lawrence M., 1975. The Legal System: A Social Science Perspective. New York: Simon and Schuster Friedman, Lawrence M. 1985. Total Justice. New York: Russell Sage Fügen, N. 1985. Max Weber. Reinbek: Rowohlt Funston, R.Y. .1977. Constitutional Counter-Revolution?, Cambridge, Mass.: Schenkmann Publishing Co. Galanter, M. .1976. "Legalization and Delegalization" Mimeo., New York: American Political Science Association. Gerth, Hans and C. Wright Mills. 1958. From Max Weber. New York: Oxford (Galaxy) Gierke, O. .1868. Rechtsgeschichte der deutschen Genossenschaft. Bd. 1. '' 11-15, 19-23, 70. Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung Gierke, O. .1914. "Die Wurzeln des Dienstvertrages," Festschrift für Heinrich Brunner. München und Leipzig: Duncker und Humblot Glendon, Mary Ann. 1981. The New Family and the New Property. Toronto: Butterworth's. Godard, John. 1990 "Managerial Interests and Union Power: A Theory and Analysis of Structural Variation in Bargaining Outcomes Using Firm-Level Survey Data," Queen's Paper in Industrial Relations, 1990-5. Kingston, Ontario: Industrial Relations Centre, Queen's University Goldfield, Michael.1987. The Decline of Organized Labor in the United States. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Görlitz, Axel and Voigt, Rüdiger .1985. Rechtspolitologie, Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag, 1985. Gourevitch, Peter/ Lange, Peter/Martin, Andrew "Industrial Relations and Politics: Some Reflections," in Doeringer, Peter Industrial Relations in International Perspective. New York: Holmes & Meier Publishers, Inc. Gregg, P.A./ Machin, J.S. 1988. "Unions and the Incidence of Performance Linked Pay Schemes in Britain," International Journal of Industrial Organization 6: 91-107. 103 Grosheide, F.W. .1982. Eigendom in de Overgang?, Amsterdam Habermas, Juergen. 1987. "Wie ist Legitimität durch Legalität möglich?.” Kritische Justiz 20.1:1-16 Habermas, Jürgen. 1992. Faktizität und Geltung. Beiträge zur Diskustheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Habermas, Jürgen. [1981] 1987. Theory of Communicative Action. Volume Two. Lifeworld and System: A Critique of Functional Reason. Boston: Beacon Press Habermas Juergen .1969. Legitimation Crisis, Boston:Beacon Press Hart, Dieter. 1983 "Contract and Consumer Protection: Organizing Countervailing Power. On the development of Substantive and Reflexive Elements in Modern Contract Law", in David Trubek, ed., Reflexive Law and the Regulatory Crisis, Madison: Disputes Processing Research Program, University of Wisconsin Law School Hartwich, Hans-Hermann 1967 Arbeitsmarkt, Verbände und Staat, 1918-33. Die öffentliche Bindung unternehmerische Funktionen in der Weimarer Republik, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1967. Hay, J.R. .1975. The Origins of the Liberal Welfare Reforms, 1906-1914, London and Basingstoke: The Macmillan Press Ltd. Hayek, Friedrich. 1960. The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Hayek, Friedrich. 1973, 1976, 1979. Law, Legislation and Liberty. 3 vols. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hayek, F.A. .1944. The Road to Serfdom, London: Routledge Hecker, Steven and Margaret Hallock, eds., Labor in a Global Economy. Eugene: University of Oregon Labor Education and Research Center Hedemann, J.W. .1933. Die Flucht in die Generalklauseln. Eine Gefahr für Recht und Staat. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck) Hedemann, J.W. .1934. "Zum Gesetz zur Ordnung der nationalen Arbeit," 39 Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung 3 (1. Februar 1934) Hedemann, J.W. .1949. Schuldrecht des Bürgerlichen Gesetzbuches. Berlin Heindl, Hermann. 1928. [Editorial] Zeitschrift für Soziales Recht 1:1. Horowitz, Morton J. 1992. The Transformation of American Law. new York and Oxford: Oxford Hück, Alfred and H.C. Nipperdey .1928:1970. Lehrbuch des Arbeitsrechts. Mannheim Hume, David. [1777] 1987. "Of the Rise and Progress of the Arts and Sciences," in Hume, Essays. Moral Political and Literary. Indianapolis: Liberty Classics Irons, Peter.1982. The New Deal Lawyers, Princeton: Princeton University Press Jacoby, Sanford M. 1985 Employing Bureaucracy. Managers, Unions and the Transformations of Work in American Industry, 1900-45, New York: Columbia University Press Jaümig, O. et al. .1981. Bürgerliches Gesetzbuch. München Jellineck, Georg. 1906 Verfassungsänderung und Verfassungswandlung, Berlin: Verlag von O. Häring Joerges, Christian and David M. Trubek. eds., 1989. Critical Legal Thought: A German-American Debate. Baden-Baden: Nomos 104 Joerges, Christian. 1987. "Die Überarbeitung des BGB-Schuldrechts, die Sonderprivatrechte und die Unbestimmtheit des Rechts," Kritische Justiz, 20:2: 166-182 Joerges, Christian, "Regulatory Law. Private Government and Self-Government" in Conference on Regulatory Law and the Regulatory Crisis, Disputes Processing Research Program, University of Wisconsin Law School, July 18-21, 1983 (Unpublished Compilation of Papers edited by David Trubek) Jones, G. S. .1983. Languages of Class, 1832-1982, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Juristenwochenschau .1926. 55. Jg. Heft 28, 4 Dez Kahn-Freund, O. .1932: 1981. "The Social Ideal of the Reich Labour Court," Labour Law and Politics in the Weimar Republic, ed. by Roy Lewis and John Clark, Oxford: Oxford University Press Kahn-Freund, O. .1981. Labour Law and Politics in the Weimar Republic. edited by Roy Lewis and Jon Clark. Oxford: Blackwell Kaiser, Andreas .1980. "Kollektives Arbeitsrecht und gewerkschaftlicher Funktionsverlust in der Weimarer Republik," Demokratie und Recht, 8. Jg., Heft 4, 1980, 444-451 Kaiser, Andreas .1981. "Arbeitsrechtswissenschaft und Gewerkschaften gegen Ende der Weimarer Zeit", in Udo Reifner, ed., Das Recht des Unrechtstaates, Frankfurt und NewYork: Campus Verlag Kaskel, W. 1922 "Buecher-Kommentar", Recht und Wirtschaft 1:70 Kaskel, W. 1932 Arbeitsrecht, Fourth edition, ed. by Herman Dersch, Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer Kennedy, D. .1979. "The Structure of Blackstone's Commentaries," 28 Buffalo Law Review 205 Kennedy, D. .1980. "Towards an Historical Understanding of Legal Consciousness: The Case of Classical Legal Thought in America, 1850-1940," 3 Research in Law and Sociology 3. Kennedy, Duncan. 1976. "Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication". Harvard Law Review, 89: 1685ff. Kennedy, Duncan. 1979. "The Structure of Blackstone's Commentaries". Buffalo Law Review, 28:2: 211-382 Kennedy, Duncan. 1982. "Distributive and Paternalist Motives in Contract and Tort Law, with Special Reference to Compulsory Terms and Unequal Bargaining Power" Maryland Law Review, 41:4:563ff Kettler, David and Peter Warrian. 1994. "American and Canadian Labor Law Regimes and the Reflexive Law Approach." Ralf Rogowski and Ton Wilthagen, eds., Reflexive Labour Law. Deventer and Cambridge: Kluwer, 1994 Kettler, David and Volker Meja. , 1988. "The Reconstitution of Political Life: The Contemporary Relevance of Karl Mannheim's Political Project". Polity, 20:4:623-647 Kettler, David and Volker Meja. 1990 "Social Progress after the Age of Social Democracy: The End of Trade Unionism in the West?" Jeffrey C. Alexander and Piotr Sztompka, eds., Rethinking Progress, London and New York: Unwin Hyman Kettler, David, James Struthers and Christopher Huxley. 1990. "Unionization and Labour Regimes in Canada and the United States: Considerations for Comparative Research," Labour/Le Travail 25 (Spring, 1990), 161-187 Kettler, David. 1984 "Works Community and Workers' Organizations: A Central Problem in Weimar Labour Law," Economy and Society 13:3 (August) Kettler, David. 1984a. "Sociological Classics and the Contemporary State of the Law," Canadian Journal of Sociology, 9:447-458 Kettler, David. 1987. "Legal Reconstitution of the Welfare State: A Latent Social Democratic Legacy". Law & Society Review, 21(1): 9-47 105 Kettler, David. 1989. "Figure and Ground in Collective Labor Regimes," in Axel Goerlitz and Ruediger Voigt, eds., Limits of Law, Pfaffenweiler: Centaurus. Kettler, D. .1967. "Political Science and Political Rationality," in David Spitz, ed., Political Theory and Social Change, New York Kettler, D. .1969. "The Politics of Social Change: The Relevance of Democratic Approaches," in William E. Conolly, ed., The Bias of Pluralism, New York Kirchheimer, Otto .1964. Politik und Verfassung, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Klare, K. .1982. "Critical Theory and Labor Relations Law," in David Kairys, ed., The Politics of Law. New York Klare, Karl E. 1978. "Judicial Deradicalization of the Wagner Act and the Origins of Modern Legal Consciousness, 1937-1941" Minnesota Law Review 62:265. Klare, Karl E. 1985. ATraditional Labor Law Scholarship and the Crisis of Collective Bargaining Law: A Reply to Professor Finkin.” Maryland Law Review. 44.3:731-840. Klare, Karl E. 1989. "Workplace Democracy & Market Reconstruction: An Agenda for Legal Reform," Catholic University Law Review, 38:1: 1-68 Klare, K. .1982. "Critical Theory and Labor Relations Law" in David Kairys, ed., The Politics of Law, New York: Pantheon Books Kochan, Thomas A./ Katz, Harry C./McKersie, Robert B. 1986. The Transformation of American Industrial Relations, Boston: Beacon Press Kochan, Thomas ed. .1985. Challenges and Choices Facing American Labor, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press Korsch, Karl. 1972. "Jus belli ac pacis im Arbeitsrecht," Kritische Justiz 5. 2: 142ff. Korsch, K. .1922:1980. "Der tote Sinzheimer und der lebende Marx," Gesamtausgabe: Raetebewegung und Klassenkampf, Bd. 2, pp. 537-541, Frankfurt: Europäische Verlagsanstalt Kreuder, Thomas. 1991 [Buchbesprechung] Joachim Weyand, Die tarifverträgliche Mitbestimmung unternehmericher Personal- und Sachentscheidungen, Kritische Justiz, 24, 1, 117 Lasalle, Ferdinand. 1919. Die Verfassungsreden. in Eduard Bernstein, ed. Gesammelte Reden und Schriften. vol. 2. Berlin: Dietz Legien, Carl. 1914. Aus Amerikas Arbeiterbewegung. Berlin: Verlag der Generalkommission der Gewerkschaften Deutschlands Lehmbruch, G. and Schmitter, P.C., eds. .1981. Patterns of Corporatist Policy-Making, Beverly Hills and Lo ndon: Sage Publications Lenhoff, Arthur. 1951. "Some Basic Features of American and European Labor Law: A Comparison," Notre Dame Lawyer 26 (Spring) 3: 389-428. Lindblom, C. .1965. The Intelligence of Democracy, New York: The Free Press Lindblom, C. .1977. Politics and Markets: The World's Political-Economic Systems, New York: Basic Books Loewe, Adolph .1935. Economics and Sociology, London: George Allen & Unwin Lorwin, Lewis L. 1924. The Women' Garment Workers. New York: B.W. Huebsch. Lowi, Theodore S. .1987. "The Welfare State, the New Regulation, and the Rule of Law" in Allan C. Hutchinson and Patrick Monahan, The Rule of Law: Ideal or Ideology? Toronto: Butterworths 106 Lowi, Theodore S. 1979. The End of Liberalism: The Second Republic of the United States. Second Edition, New York: W.W. Norton & Co. Luhmann, Niklas. 1981. Politische Theorie im Wohlfahrtsstaat. Munich and Vienna: Guenter Olzog Verlag Luhmann, Niklas. 1984. Soziale Systeme. Grundrisse einer allgemeinen Theorie. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Luhmann, Niklas. 1985. "Einige Probleme mit reflexivem Recht,” Zeitschrift für Gunther Rechtssoziologie (June) pp. 1-17. Luhmann, Niklas. 1985. "The Self-Reproduction of Law and Its Limits,” in Gunther Teubner, ed., Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State. Berlin and New York, De Gruyter. Luhmann, Niklas. 1990. Political Theory in the Welfare State. Berlin and New York: De Gruyter Lukes, S.and Scull, A., .1983. Durkheim and the Law, Oxford: Martin Robertson Luthardt, Wolfgang. 1983 "Kontinuität und Wandel in der Theorie Franz L. Neumanns," Internationale wissenschaftliche Korrespondenz zur Geschichte der deutschen Arbeiterbewegung, (September) 329-373. Luthardt, Wolfgang. 1986. Sozialdemokratische Verfassungstheorie in der Weimarer Republik. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag. Maier, C. .1975. Recasting Bourgeois Europe, Princeton: Princeton University Press Mannheim, Karl. [1925] 1986. Conservatism. A Contribution to the Sociology of Knowledge. David Kettler, Volker Meja, and Nico Stehr, eds. London and New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Mannheim, K. .1940. Man and Society in an Age of Reconstruction, London: Kegan and Paul Mansfeld, W./Pohl W. .1934. Die Ordnung der nationalen Arbeit. Berlin: Deutsches Druck- und Verlagshaus Markovits, Andrei S. 1985 The Politics of the West German Trade Unions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Marshall, T.H. .1949: 1965. "Citizenship and Social Class," in Class, Citizenship, and Social Development, New York Martiny, M. .1976. Intetgration oder Konfrontation? Studien zur Geschichte der sozialdemokratischen Rechts- und Verfassungspolitik. Bonn/Bad Godesberg: Neue Gesellschaft Menger, Anton. 1886. Das Recht auf den vollen Arbeitsertrag in geschichtlicher Darstellung. Stuttgart: Cotta Menger, Anton. [1903] 1927. Das bürgerliche Recht und die besitzlosen Klassen. Tübingen: Verlag der H. Laupp'schen Buchhandlung. Mestitz, Franz .1980. "Probleme der Geschichte des Arbeitsrechts", Zeitschrift für Neuere Rechtsgeschichte", Volume no. 1/2, . Mestitz, Franz .1984. "Zur Wirkungsgeschichte des Arbeitsrechts," in Harald Steindl, Wege zur Arbeitsrechtsgeschichte, Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann Miller, S. .1968. Die Bürde der Macht. Die deutsche Sozialdemokratie, 1918-1920. Düsseldorf: Droste Mises, Ludwig von. 1949. Human Action. New Haven: Yale University Press. Mishra, Ramesh .1984. The Welfare State in Crisis, New York: St. Martin's Press Mitnick, Barry M. .1980. The Political Economy of Regulation, New York: Columbia University Press Mommsen, Wolfgang. 1984. Max Weber and German Politics, 1890-1920. Chicago and London: University of 107 Chicago Press Moore, Barrington. 1978. Injustice: The Social Bases of Obedience and Revolt. White Plains, New York: M.E. Sharpe Inc. Moritz, K. .1980. Begrenzung gewerkschaftlicher Politik durch Arbeitsrecht. in R. Voigt, Hg., Abschied vom Recht?. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Mückenberger, Ulrich 1991 "Neue Beschäftigungsformen, EG-Charta der Arbeitnehmerrechte und Ansätze europäischer Normsetzung," Kritische Justiz, 24, 1, 1 Münch, Richard .1985. "Die sprachlose Systemtheorie. Systemdifferenzierung, reflexives Recht, reflexive Selbststeuerung und Integration durch Indifferenz", Zeitschrift für Rechtssoziologie, (June, 1985) pp. 19-28 Muttutat, Hermann .1923. "Die Neugestaltung des Arbeitsrechts," Sozialistische Monatshefte, 29. Jg. Bd. 60, 406411 Nachlass Arnold Brecht Bundesarchiv Koblenz Nedelsky, J. .1982. "American Constitutionalism and the Paradox of Private Property," Mimeo: Law and Society Association, Toronto Nedelsky, J. .1983. "Individual Autonomy in the Bureaucratic State: Toward a Reconception," Mimeo: American Political Science Association, Chicago Neumann, F. .1928. "Betriebsrisiko," 1 Arbeitsrechts-praxis, Heft 10 Neumann, F. .1929: 1981. "The Social Significance of the Basic Laws in the Weimar Constitution," 10 Economy and Society 329 Neumann, F. .1929. "Richterliches Ermessen und Methodenstreit im Arbeitsrecht," 16 Arbeitsrecht 320 Neumann, F. .1932. Koalitionsfreiheit und Reichsverfassung. Die Stellung der Gewerkschaften im Verfassungssystem. Berlin: Heymanns Neumann, F. .1937. "Die Funktionswandel des Gesetzes im Recht der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft," 6 Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung, 542 Neumann, F. .1944. Behemoth, Second Revised Edition, New York: Oxford Neumann, F. .1957. The Democratic and the Authoritarian State. Glencoe: The Free Press Neumann, F. .1980. Die Herrschaft des Gesetzes. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Neumann, F.L. .1930: 1981. "The Social Significance of the Basic Laws in the Weimar Constitution," Economy and Society, 10:329 Neumann, F.L. .1937: 1957. "The Change in the Function of Law in Modern Society," The Democratic and the Authoritarian State, Glencoe, Illinois: The Free Press Nipperdey, Hans Carl, ed. .1930. Die Grundrechte und die Grundpflichten der Reichsverfassung, Berlin: Verlag vonReinar Hobbing Nonet, Phillippe and Selznick, Philip. 1978 Law and Society in Transition, New York, Hagerstown, San Francisco, London: Harper Colophon Books Nörpel, C./Gusko, K. .1932. Gewerkschaften und Kollektives Arbeitsrecht. Berlin: ADGB Note .1975. "The Wyatt Case: Implementation of a Judicial Decree Ordering Institutional Change," Yale Law Review, 84:138 108 O'Grady, John. 1990a "Coming in from the Cold: Canadian Labour Market Policy in the 1990s," International Business and Trade Law Program Conference on Global Competition and Canadian Federalism, Faculty of Law, University of Toronto, September 15, 1990 O'Grady, John. 1990b "Labour Market Policy and Industrial Strategy after the Free Trade Agreement: The Policy Debate in Ontario," Labor Law Journal, August O'Grady, John. 1990c "Beyond the Wagner Act?" (Unpublished) Offe, Claus. 1984. "Social Policy and the Theory of the State," Pp. 95ff. in Contradictions of the Welfare State, ed. by John Keane, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, . Offe, Claus .1972. "Advanced Capitalism and the Welfare State," Politics and Society, 2:479-488 (Summer) Offe, Claus .1985. Disorganized Capitalism, Cambridge: Polity Press Ogorek, Regina 1989. "Inconsistencies in 19th Century Legal Theory," in Joerges and Trubek 1989, 13-37 Orloff, Ann Shola and Skocpol, Theda .1984. "Why Not Equal Protection? Explaining the Politics of Public Social Spending in Britain, 1900-1911, and the United States, 1880's-1920", American Sociological Review, vol. 49 (December) pp.726-750 Panitch, Leo/Swartz, Donald. 1984. ATowards Permanent Exceptionalism: Coercion and Consent in Canadian Industrial Relations," Labor/Le Travail 13: 133-157. Panitch, Leo/Swartz, Donald. 1988. The Assault on Trade Union Freedoms: From Consent to Coercion Revisited, Toronto: Garamond. Peijpe, Taco van .1984. "Hugo Sinzheimer en het nederlandse arbeidsrecht", Recht en Kritiek, vol. 10, No. 1, pp.7-32 Peijpe, Taco van .1985. De ontwikkeling van het loonvormingsrecht, Nijmegen: Ars Aequi Libri Philipp, H. "Lohnanspruch bei Betriebsstockung und Teilstreik. Entwicklung von Individualrecht zu Sozialrecht", 13 Arbeitsrecht (Sonderheft: Durchsetzung des Kollektivgedankens) Poggi, Gianfranco. 1978. The Development of the Modern State. A Sociological Introduction. London: Hutchinson. Pope, Jim. 1993. "The Transformation of Labor Rights Consciousness." Paper presented to the 1993 Annual Meeting of the Law and Society Association. Unpublished. Porter, Michael E. 1990 The Competitive Advantage of Nations. New York: The Free Press. Potthoff, H. .1925. Die sozialen Probleme des Betriebes. Berlin: Industrieverlag Spaeth & Linde Potthoff, H. .1925a. Die Einwirkung der Reichsverfassung auf das Arbeitsrecht. Leipzig/Erlangen: A. Deichert Potthoff, H. .1926. "Die Verselbständigung des Betriebes," 55 Juristische Wochenschrift 533, Heft 5 Potthoff, H. .1926b. "Rechtsfortschritt durch Rechtssprechung," 13 Arbeitsrecht (Sonderheft: Durchsetzung des Kollektivgedankens.) 106 Potthoff, H. .1926c. "Sozialismus, Gewerkschaften, Arbeitsrecht," 13 Arbeitsrecht 833 Preller, L. .1949. Sozialpolitik in der Weimarer Republik. Stuttgart: Mittelbach Preller, Ludwig .1949. Sozialpolitik in der Weimarer Republik, Stuttgart: Franz Mittelbach Verlag Preuss, Ulrich K. .1973. Legalität und Pluralismus. Beiträge zum Verfassungsrecht der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, 109 Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Preuss, Ulrich K. .1983. "The Concept of Rights in the Welfare State" in Conference on Regulatory Law and the Regulatory Crisis (1983) Disputes Processing Research Program, University of Wisconsin Law School, July 18-21, 1983 (Unpublished Compilation of Papers edited by David Trubek) Priore, Michael and Charles F. Sable. 1984 The Second Industrial Divide: Possibilities for Prosperity. New York: Basic Books Pryor, F.L. .1968. Public Expenditure in Communist and Capitalist Nations Radbruch, G. .1930. "Arbeitskraft," in Hans-Carl Nipperdey, ed., Die Grundrechte und die Grundpflichten in der Reichsverfassung, vol. 3, Berlin: Verlag von Rainer Hobbing Raiser, L. .1971: 1977. "Die Zukunft des Privatrechts," in Die Aufgabe des Privatrechts. Aufsaetze zum Privat- und Wirtschaftsrecht aus drei Jahrzenten, Kronberg/ Ts. Ramm, T. .1966. Arbeitsrecht und Politik. Neuwied: Luchterhand Ramm, T. .1980. "Die Arbeitsverfassung der Weimarer Republik," in Franz Gamillscheg, et al., In Memoriam Sir Otto Kahn- Freund. München. Ratz, Ursula. 1980. Sozialreform und Arbeiterschaft. Berlin: Colloquium Verlag Regini, Marino. 1984. "The Conditions for Political Exchange: How Concertation Emerged and Collapsed in Italy and Great Britain,” Pp. 124-144 in Goldthorpe, John H. ed., Order and Conflict in Contemporary Capitalism: Studies in the Political Economy of Western European Nations. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Reich, Robert B. 1991 The Work of Nations: Capitalism in the 21st Century. New York: A.A. Knopf Reich, C. .1964. "The New Property," Yale Law Journal, 73:733 Reichsgerichts Zeitung .1923. Reichsgerichtsrechtsprechung, 6. Februar 1923 106, 272. Renner, Karl [1905, 1929] 1949. The Institutions of Private Law and their Social Functions, transl. and ed. by Otto Kahn-Freund, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul Renner, K. .1929. Wege der Verwirklichung, Berlin: Verlag von J.H.W. Dietz Nfg. RGR Komm. zum BGB .1953. Rogers, Joel .1984. Divide and Conquer: The Legal Foundations of Postwar U.S. Labor Policy, Unpublished Dissertation, Princeton University Rogowski, Ralf and Ton Wilthagen. 1994. Reflexive Labour Law. Deventer and Cambridge: Kluwer. Ronge, V. .1983. "Rechtsetzung durch Tarifvertrag? Zur Koexistenz von staatlichem und nichtstaatlichem Recht," in R. Voigt, Hg., Abschied vom Recht?. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Ronge, V. .1980. Am Staat vorbei, Frankfurt/New York: Campus Verlag Rottleuthner, Huber. 1986. "Theories of Legal Evolution: Between Empiricism and Philosophy of History,” Rechtstheorie Beiheft 9. Rottleuthner, Hubert. 1987 "Biological Metaphors in Legal Thought" in Gunther Teubner, ed., State, Law, Economy as Autopoietic Systems, Berlin: DeGruyter Samuel, G. .1983. "Public and Private Law: A Private Lawyer's Response," The Modern Law Review, 46:58 Savelsberg, Joachim. 1992. "Law That Does Not Fit Society: Sentencing Guidelines as a Neoclassical Reaction to 110 the Dilemmas of Substantivized Law," American Journal of Sociology, 97: 5 (March 1992): 1346-81 Schmitt, Carl .1928. Verfassungslehre, Munich and Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot Schmitter, Philippe C. 1983. "Democratic Theory and Neo-Corporatist Practice," Social Research 50 (Winter) 885-928. Schmitter, P.C. and Lehmbruch, G., eds. .1979. Trends Towards Corporatist Intermediation, New York and London: Sage Publications Schuchardt, Wilgart. 1985a "Innovatorische Handlungspotentiale abhängig Beschäftigter zur Veränderung und Gestaltung ihrer Arbeitsbedingungen gemäß ihren Zielen und Interessen -- ein Problemüberblick," Werner Fricke/Wilgart Schuchardt (Hrsg.) Innovatorische Qualifikationen, eine Chance gewerkschaftlicher Arbeitspolitik: Erfahrungen aus den Niederlanden, Italien, Schweden und der Bundesrepublik. Bonn: Verlag Neue Gesellschaft: Forschungsinstitut der Friedrich-Ebert-Stiftung Schuchardt, Wilgart. 1985b "Technisch-organisatorischer Wandel. Beteiligung der Arbeitnehmer und gewerkschaftliche Arbeitspolitik. Notwendigkeit, Möglichkeit und Perspektiven für die Entwicklung und Anwendung innovatorischer Qualifikationen." Werner Fricke/Wilgart Schuchardt (Hrsg.) Innovatorische Qualifikationen, eine Chance gewerkschaftlicher Arbeitspolitik: Erfahrungen aus den Niederlanden, Italien, Schweden und der Bundesrepublik. Bonn: Verlag Neue Gesellschaft: Forschungsinstitut der Friedrich-Ebert-Stiftung Schumpeter, Joseph A. .1947. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, 2nd ed. New York: Harper & Brothers Seibel, W. .1980. "Abschied vom Recht -- eine Ideologie?," in Rüdiger Voigt, ed., Verrechtlichung, Koenigstein:Athenäum Selznick, Philip. 1969 Law, Society, and Industrial Justice, New York: Russell Sage Foundation Selznick, P. .1949. TVA and the Grass Roots, Berkeley: University of California Press Shklar, Judith N. 1987. "Political Theory and the Rule of Law," in Allan C. Hutchinson and Patrick Monahan, eds., The Rule of Law. Ideal or Ideology. Toronto, Calgary, and Vancouver: Carswell Shklar, Judith N. 1990. The Faces of Injustice. New Haven and London: Yale University Press Shklar, Judith N. [1964] 1986. Legalism. Laws, Morals, and Political Trials. Cambridge MA and London: Harvard University Press. Simitis, Spiros. 1984. "Zur Verrechtlichung der Arbeitsbeziehungen," Pp. 74-165 in Friedlich Kübler, ed., Verrechtlichung von Wirtschaft, Arbeit und Sozialer Solidarität. Vergleichende Analysen, Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft. Simitis, S. .1957. Die faktischen Vertragsverhältnisse als Ausdruck der gewandelten sozialen Funktion der Rechtsinstitute des Privatrechts, Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann Sinzheimer, H. .1907/8. Der korporative Arbeitsnormenvertrag. Eine privatrechtliche Untersuchung. 2 Bänder. Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot Sinzheimer, H. .1916. Ein Arbeitstarifgesetz. Die Idee der sozialen Selbstbestimmung im Recht. München und Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot Sinzheimer, H. .1919. Das Rätesystem. Frankfurt Sinzheimer, H. .1920. "Programm für die Neuregelung des Arbeitsrechts in Deutschland,""Reichskanzlei Akten betreffend Einheitliches Arbeitsrecht (Arbeitsgerichtsgesetz)", Bundesarchiv Koblenz, R43 I/ 2062-2063. Sinzheimer, H. .1927. Grundzüge des Arbeitsrechts. 2. verbesserte Auflage. Jena: Gustav Fischer Verlag Sinzheimer, H. .1929. "Zur Frage des Betriebsrisikos nach der arbeitsgerichtlichen Rechtssprechung," Schriften der 111 VELA, Vereinigung der leitenden Angestellten. Heft 5, Berlin Sinzheimer, H. .1935. Rechtssociologie. Amsterdam Sinzheimer, H. .1938. Jüdische Klassiker der deutschen Rechtswissenschaft. Amsterdam: Hertzberger Sinzheimer, H. .1968. Die Justiz in der Weimarer Republik. Thilo Ramm, Hg. Neuwied/Berlin: Luchterhand Sinzheimer, H. .1978. Arbeitsrecht und Soziologie. 2 Bänder. Otto Kahn-Freund, Hg. Frankfurt/Köln: Europäische Verlagsanstalt Sinzheimer, Hugo. 1929 "Die Reform des Schlichtungswesens", Bericht über die Verhandlungen der 11. Generalversammlung der Gesellschaft für soziale Reform, Mannheim, October 24 and 25, 1929 112 Sinzheimer, Hugo. [1919] 1976 "Die Räte," Arbeitsrecht und Rechtssoziologie. Gesammelte Aufsätze und Reden. 2 vols., Otto Kahn-Freud and Thilo Ramm, eds. Frankfurt: Europäische Verlagsanstalt Sinzheimer, Hugo. [1933] 1976 "Die Krisis des Arbeitsrechts" in Arbeitsrecht und Rechtssoziologie, 2 vols., Otto Kahn-Freund and Thilo Ramm, eds. Frankfurt: Europäische Verlagsanstalt Sinzheimer, H. .1923. "Das neue Arbeitsrecht in Deutschland", Die Internationale Gewerkschaftsbewegung, Vol. 1, No. 3 (January/February, pp. 12-20 Sklar, Martin J. 1988. The Corporate Reconstruction of American Capitalism, 1890-1916. Cambridge: CUP Skocpol, Theda. 1979. States and Social Revolutions, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Skocpol, Theda. 1980. "Political Responses to the Capitalist Crisis: Neo-Marxist Theories of the State and the Case of the New Deal," Politics and Society 10:2 Skrzypczak, Henryk .1975. "Zur Strategie der Freien Gewerkschaften in der Weimarer Republik," in Heinz Oskar Vetter, ed., Vom Sozialistengesetz zur Mitbestimmung. Köln. Special Project .1978. "The Remedial Process in Institutional Reform Litigation," Columbia Law Review, 78:788 Streeck, Wolfgang. 1981 Gewerkschaftliche Organisationsprobleme in sozialstaatlichen Demokratien. Königstein/Ts.: Athenäum Verlag Streek, Wolfgang/Schmitter, Philippe 1985. "Community, Market, State -- and Associations?” in W. Streek and P.C. Schmitter, eds., Private Interest Government: Beyond Market and State. Beverly Hills and London: Sage. Streek, Wolfgang and Schmitter, Philippe C. .1985. Private Interest Government, London, Beverly Hills, New Delhi: Sage Publications Sugarman, David and Gunther Teubner, eds. 1990 Regulating Corporate Groups in Europe. BadenBaden: Nomos Verlaggesellschaft (European University Institute, Firenze) Swinton, Katherine E./ Swan, Kenneth P. 1982b."The Interaction between Human Rights Legislation and Labor Law." Pp. 112-142 in Swan/Swinton 1982 Tatarin-Tarnheyden, Edgar .1930. "Artikel 165. Recht der Berufsverbände und Wirtschaftsdemokratie," in Hans Carl Nipperdey, Die Grundrechte und Grundpflichte in der Verfassung 3. Bd. Taylor, Charles. 1985. "Alternative Futures. Legitimacy, Identity and Alienation in Late Twentieth Century Canada" in: Constitutionalism, Citizenship and Society in Canada. Vol. 33 of the Research Studies Prepared for the Royal Commission on the Economic Union and Development Prospects for Canada. Toronto: University of Toronto. Teubner, G. .1982. "Reflexives Recht," 68 Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 13 Teubner, Gunther. 1987, "Juridification. Concepts, Aspects, Limits, Solutions," in Gunther Teubner, ed., Juridification of Social Spheres. Berlin: DeGruyter. Teubner, Gunther and Helmuth Willke. 1984. "Kontext und Autonomie: Gesellschaftliche Selbststeuerung durch reflexives Recht", Zeitschrift für Rechtssoziologie, 6 Heft 1, 4-35 Teubner, Gunther ed. 1985. Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State, Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter Teubner, Gunther, ed. 1988c, Autopoietic Law: A New Approach to Law and Society, Berlin: DeGruytTeubner, Gunther. 1982/3. "Substantive and Reflexive Elements in Modern Law," Law and Society Review 17: 401f. Teubner, Gunther. 1986 "Industrial Democracy Through Law? Social Functions of Law in Institutional Innovation", Terence Daintith and Gunther Teubner, eds., Contract and Organisation. Legal Analysis in the 113 Light of Economic and Social Theory, Berlin and New York: DeGruyter, 261-273 Teubner, Gunther. 1986. "After Instrumentalism?" in Gunther Teubner, ed., Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State. Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter. Teubner, Gunther. 1987 "Juridification. Concepts, Aspects, Limits, Solutions," in Gunther Teubner, ed., Juridification of Social Spheres. A Comparative Analysis in the Areas of Labor, Corporate, Antitrust, and Social Welfare Law. Berlin: DeGruyter Teubner, Gunther. 1988a "Evolution of Autopoietic Law," in Gunther Teubner, ed., Autopoietic Law: A New Approach to Law and Society, Berlin: DeGruyter Teubner, Gunther. 1988b "Hypercycle in Law and Organization: The Relationship between SelfObservation, Self-Constitution and Autopoiesis," European Yearbook in the Sociology of Law, 3 Teubner, Gunther. 1988b. "Social Order from Legislative Noise? Autopoietic Closure as a Problem for Legal Regulation" in Gunther Teubner, ed., State, Law, Economy as Autopoietic Systems. Berlin: De Gruyter. Teubner, Gunther. 1988c. "Enterprise Corporatism, New Industrial Policy and the 'Essence' of the Legal Person," The American Journal of Comparative Law 36: 401 Teubner, Gunther. 1989. Recht als autopoietisches System. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Teubner, Gunther. 1989a "How the Law Thinks: Towards a Constructivist Epistemology of Law," Law & Society Review, 23, 5 Teubner, Gunther. 1989b "'And God Laughed...: Indeterminacy, Self-Reference and Paradox in Law," in Christian Joerges, ed., Critical Legal Thought. An American-German Debate. Baden-Baden: Nomos, Teubner, Gunther. 1990 "Unitas Multiplex: Corporate Governance in Group Enterprises." David Sugarman and Gunther Teubner, eds., Regulating Corporate Groups in Europe. Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlaggesellschaft (European University Institute, Firenze) 104 Teubner, G. .1984. "Verrechtlichung -- Begriffe, Merkmale, Grenzen, Auswege," in Friedrich Kuebler (Hrsg.) Verrechtlichung von Wirtschaft, Arbeit und Sozialer Solidaritaet, Baden-Baden: Nomos, 1984, pp. 289-344 Teubner, G. .1984a. "Corporate Fiduciary Duties and their Beneficiaries: A Functional Approach to the Legal Institutionalization of Corporate Responsibility" in Klaus J. Hopt and Gunther Teubner, Corporate Governance and Directors' Liabilities: Legal, Economic and Sociological Analyses of Corporate Responsibility, Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1984 Teubner, Gunther and Willke, Helmuth .1980. "Dezentrale Kontextsteuerung im Recht intermediärer Verbände," in Voigt, ed., Verrechtlichung, Koenigstein: Athenäum Verlag Tomlins, Christopher L. 1985 The State and the Unions. Labor Relations, Law, and the Organized Labor Movement in America, 1880-1960. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Towers, Brian 1989. "Running the Gauntlet: British Trade Unions under Thatcher, 1979-1988," Industrial and Labor Relations Review 42:2 (January) 163-188, at 179f. Trattner, Walter I., ed. .1983. Social Welfare or Social Control?, Knoxville: The University of Tennessee Press Tribe, Lawrence H. .1979. "Too Much Law, Too Little Justice:An Argument for Delegalizing America", The Atlantic, July 10, 1979, p. 25 Tronto, Joan. 1984. "Law and Modernity: The Significance of Max Weber's Sociology of Law". Texas Law Review, 63:3:565-577 Troy, Leo L. and L. Sheflin. 1985 Union Sourcebook: Membership, Structure, Finance, Directory. West Orange: IRDIS 114 Troy, Leo. 1986. "The Rise and Fall of American Trade Unions: The Labor Movement from FRD to RR,” Pp. 75-109 in Lipset, Seymour Martin ed., Unions in Transition: Entering the Second Century, San Francisco: Institute for Contemporary Studies. Troy, Leo. 1990 "Is the U.S. Unique in the Decline of Private Sector Unionism?" Journal of Labor Research, Volume XI, No. 1 (Spring) 111-143 Trubek, David. ed. 1983. Reflexive Law and the Regulatory Crisis. Unpublished papers of a conference at the University of Wisconsin-Madison, July 18-21, 1983. Madison: Disputes Processing Research Program, University of Wisconsin Law School Tushnet, Mark V. 1983. "Following the Rules Laid Down: A Critique of Interpretivism and Neutral Principles," Harvard Law Review, 96:4:781-827 U.S. Commission on Industrial Relations. 1916. Industrial Relations. Final Report and Testimony submitted to Congress by the Commission on Industrial Relations created by the Act of August 23, 1912. 64th Congress, 1st Session, Senate Document No. 415, II: "A.F. of L., Socialists, and Industrial Workers" and XI: "Labor and the Law" Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1976. Law in Modern Society. New York: The Free Press Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. 1983. "The Critical Legal Studies Movement," Harvard Law Review, 96:3: 563-675. United States Bureau of Labor Statistics 1989. Employment and Earnings 36 (No. 1, January). United Steel Workers of America: Basic Steel Industry Conference. 1988 Economics of the Steel Industry under the Reagan Administration (mimeo) Vardaro, Gaetano. 1990 "Before and Beyond the Legal Person: Group Enterprises, Trade Unions and Industrial Relations." David Sugarman and Gunther Teubner, eds., Regulating Corporate Groups in Europe. Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft (European University Institute, Firenze) 217-251 Verma, Anil. 1991 "Restructuring in Industrial Relations and the Role for Labor," Steven Hecker and Margaret Hallock, eds., Labor in a Global Economy. Eugene: University of Oregon Labor Education and Research Center Vieux, Steve 1988. "Containing the Clas Struggle: Skocpol on Revolution," Studies in Political Economy 27: 87-111. Voigt, R. .1980. Verrechtlichung Königstein/Ts: Athenæum Voigt, R. .1983. Abschied vom Recht? Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Voigt, Rüdiger. 1980. "Verrechtlichung in Staat und Gesellschaft" in Voigt, ed., Verrechtlichung. Königstein: Athenaeum Voigt, Rüdiger. 1989. Limits of Legal Regulation - Grenzen rechtlicher Steuerung. Pfaffenheimer: Centaurus Verlag Voigt, R. .1983. "Verrechtlichung und Entrechtlichung: Entwicklungslinien Regulativen Rechts im Wohlfahrtsstaat," in Voigt, ed., Abschied vom Recht?, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Voigt, R., ed. .1986. Limitations of Law. An Interdisciplinary Symposium, Discussion Papers, No. 65/85 Center for Studies on Changing Norms and Mobility, Siegen University Vormbaum, T. .1977. Sozialdemokratie und Zivilrecht. Berichterstattung und Kritik der sozialdemokratischen Partei und Presse während der Entstehung des bürgerlichen Gesetzbuches. Berlin/New York: De Gruyter Wagner, Gerhard and Heinz Zipprian. 1989. "Wertfreiheit. Eine Studie zu Max Webers 115 kulturwissenschaftlichem Formalismus," Zeitschrift für Soziologie, 18:1:4-15 Weber, Max. 1902. Review of the first volume of Philipp Lotmar, Der Arbeitsvertrag. Nach dem Privatrecht des Deutschen Reiches. Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, 17:723-734 Weber, Max. 1923. Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Religionssoziologie. Das Antike Judentum. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck) Weber, Max. 1968. Economy and Society. An Outline of Interpretive Sociology. Edited by Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich. New York: Bedminster Press Weber, Max. 1976. Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Grundriss der verstehenden Soziologie. Fifth Revised edition. Edited by Johannes Winckelmann. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck) Weber, Max. 1978. Economy and Society. edited by Gunther Roth and Claus Wittich, Berkeley and Los Angeles, California: University of California Press. Wedderburn, Lewis, Roy, and Clark, J. .1983. Labour Law and Industrial Relations: Building on Kahn-Freund, Oxford: Weiler, Joseph. 1986."The Role of Law in Labor Relations" Pp.1-65 in Labor Law and Urban Law in Canada, volume 51 of the Research Studies prepared for the Royal Commission on the Economic Union and Development Prospects for Canada, University of Toronto Press, . Weiler, Paul. 1983 "Promises to Keep: Securing Workers' Rights to Self-Organization Under the NLRA," Harvard Law Review, 98, 2, 1796 Weiler, Paul. 1984 "Striking a New Balance: Freedom of Contract and Prospects for Union Representation," Harvard Law Review, 98, 2, 351. Weiler, Paul. 1988 The Transformation of the Law at Work. Cambridge: Harvard University Press Weinstein, James. 1969. The Corporate Ideal in the Liberal State, 1900-1918. Boston: Beacon Press. White, Morton. 1949. Social Thought in America: The Revolt against Formalism. New York: VikingWhite, Robert. 1984 "Report of UAW Director for Canada and International Vice President Robert White," (December 1 and 2) Unpublished Wilensky, Harold L. .1975. The Welfare State and Equality: Structural and Ideological Roots of Public Expenditures, Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press Williams, C.B. 1964. "Notes on the Evolution of Compulsory Conciliation in Canada," Relations Industrielles 19 Willke, Helmuth.1983. Entzauberung des Staates. Koenigstein: Athenaeum. Wilson, J. Q., ed. .1980. The Politics of Regulation, New York: Basic Books Wissell, R. .1983. Aus meinen Lebensjahren. Ernst Schräpler, Hg. Berlin: Colloquium Wrobel, H. .1982. "Der deutsche Richterbund im Jahre 1933," 15 Kritische Justiz 323. 116