Download Positive functionals and the axiom of choice

Survey
yes no Was this document useful for you?
   Thank you for your participation!

* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project

Document related concepts
no text concepts found
Transcript
R ENDICONTI
del
S EMINARIO M ATEMATICO
della
U NIVERSITÀ DI
PADOVA
N ORBERT B RUNNER
Positive functionals and the axiom of choice
Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico della Università di Padova,
tome 72 (1984), p. 9-12
<http://www.numdam.org/item?id=RSMUP_1984__72__9_0>
© Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico della Università di Padova, 1984, tous
droits réservés.
L’accès aux archives de la revue « Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico
della Università di Padova » (http://rendiconti.math.unipd.it/) implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www.numdam.org/legal.
php). Toute utilisation commerciale ou impression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit
contenir la présente mention de copyright.
Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme
Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques
http://www.numdam.org/
Positive Functionals and the Axiom of Choice.
NORBERT BRUNNER
In this note
tion theory, is
we
prove, that
to
equivalent
a
a
(*)
proposition which is useful in integraweak axiom of choice.
THEOREM. The axiom
of countable multiple choice is equivalent to the assertion, that every positive linear functional on a
B-lattice is continuous.
Our set theory is Z.F°, the Zermelo-Fraenkel system minus the
axioms of choice and foundation. MCw says, that a countable sequence of nonempty sets (Sn)nEw contains a sequence of nonempty
finite subsets
In ZF’°
is not provable, and MOro does
not imply the countable axiom of choice A COD. It is unknown, whether
in ZF ( --. ZF° + foundation)
AOro.
A B-lattice (AB-lattice in [4]) is a vector lattice together with a
Frechet-complete (Cauchy sequences are convergent, c.f. [3] for a
discussion of diverse completeness properties) Riesz-norm 1 1 (c.f. [7],
p. 61 and p. 101), i.e. (i) - y x s y implies 11 x ~~ ~ 11 y I and (ii) if
11 x 1 there is a y &#x3E; 0 such that - y x y and 11 y 1. A positive
0
linear functional for X is a linear mapping f : X - R such that
Whenever x &#x3E; 0.
j)
PROOF OF THE THEOREM. « ~ »: Assume
Let f : X - R
be positive and linear. If f is not continuous, the standard argument
f is not bounded. We observe, that Sn =
proves, that in
(*) Indirizzo dell’A.: N. BRUNNER: Purdue
West Lafayette, Indiana 47907, USA.
University, Dept. Math.,
10
n, x &#x3E;_ 01 is nonempty. Since f is not bounded, there
1,
&#x3E; 2n. According to the Riesz de1, such that
x E X,
x+ + x-, where x+
sup {x, 0},
composition theorem, x x+-- x-,
a Riesz norm, lemma 9.16
x- - (- x)+,
Since
sup
11.11
is
lxl
~x, xl.
of [7] applies, which shows: Ilx+11 1, IIx-11 1. Since f is positive
2n, a confz+ &#x3E; 0. If fx+ n and
n, then lfxl
tradiction. So x+ E 8n or x- E 8n. MC~ provides us with a sequence
of finite sets .F’n ~ 0; Xn is the arithmetic mean of
0,
is
a
=
=
=
=
-
=
00
(~x~, ~)
1 and
n.
We set z
’I
As this series
con-
n=l
verges
absolutely and
n
X is
complete,
the limit z
exists;
z
=
lim yn,
n
This is
Since
i=1
a
contradic-
i
tion: The harmonic series is unbounded.
The above proof is an adaption of [6], p. 273, where this result
was proved for a class of bornological ordered vector spaces. Examples of B-lattices are the spaces Zpy p &#x3E; 1, and C(X), ..~ compact T2,
with the usual order. If the cone of a B-lattice has a base, there is
-in ZFo +
positive-, continuous-linear functional f, such
that B
C n f--(I) (B the base, C
0} the cone). In [6],
{x E
it
without
was
of
that
a positive linear
shown
the axiom
p. 272,
choice,
functional on a topological ordered vector space is continuous, if the
cone has interior points. Since this result applies to C(X), it was of
interest, whether its extension to B-lattices depends on the axiom
of choice. This is shown next. A modification of the argument in [5].
p 24, combined with «= » proves, that the following assertion is
equivalent to MC°. In a B-lattice a convex, balanced set which absorbs all order bounded sets absorbs all bounded sets, too. This
property also implies the continuity of positive linear functionals (in
=
=
ZFO).
« « »: We first observe, that MC° is equivalent to the following
weaker principle
If
is a sequence of nonempty sets,
there exists a subsequence (Sn(k»)kew and a sequence
of nonfinite
c_’
the
For
if
is
PMCA)
.E‘k 8n(k).
empty
sequence
applied to
we define a finite
Tn the set of all choice functions on
where .E’k S Tn(k) is finite and
through Fi = ~ f (i) ; f E
min
We next assume, that MCw-and hence
false and let
infinite and
be
a
of
of
(8n)nc-,
consisting
counterexample
pairwise disjoint sets. We define a B-lattice .X with a positive, un=
~j: i
11
bounded functional
00
~
~
q?. 8
=
U 8n
and X
E
8m:
.X is the
1,,-sum
of the spaces
a
Riesz-norm with
This definition is
=
{s
&#x3E;
E
respect
correct, i.e.:
! t(s)
Since
oo,
11 f
a
where
normed
The ordering
on X and 11 - 1
to this structure. We want
define ip
as
is convergent. For set
.Fn is finite. If .F U Fri,
=
now
~T={~e~:~nF~0}={~e~:~e~:/(~)~0}
otherwise
As
1,(Si).
space, X is complete, as can be proved in ZF° (c.f. [4]).
defines a vector lattice
t g, iff f (s) ~ g(s) for all s
is
oo~ ,
Iltlf
new
2
we
is
can define a partial multiple choice function
n (k) min (m : 8n n
~~ . Hence
finite,
for
=
absolutely convergent by the definition of X and hence the series which
is (unconditionally) convergent,y by completeness.
defines
That is linear and positive is obvious. But 99 is not bounded.
N
-
For otherwise we choose N
for i E N and set
so
thatn=l
21fn &#x3E;
Choose s,
Since
we
obtain
contradiction. This proves the theorem.
Axioms similar to P Maw were studied in [2]. Another application of lp-sums of y-spaces to the axiom of choice appeared in [1].
a
REFERENCES
[1] J. L. BELL - D. H. FREMLIN, A geometric form of the axiom of choice, Fundamenta Mathematicae, 77 (1972), pp. 167-170.
12
[2] N. BRUNNER, Sequential compactness and the axiom of choice, Notre Dame
Journal of Formal Logic, 24 (1983, 89-92).
[3] N. BRUNNER, Kategoriesätze und multiple Auswahl, Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 29 (1983), 435-443.
[4] M. M. DAY: Normed Linear Spaces, Ergebnisse der Mathematik 21,
Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1973.
[5] I. NAMIOKA, Partially ordered linear topological vector spaces, Memoirs of
the American Mathematical Society, No. 24, Providence, 1957.
[6] H. H. SCHAEFER, Halbgeordnete lokalkonvexe Vektorräume, Mathematische
Annalen, 138 (1959), pp. 259-286.
[7] Y.-C. WONG - K.-F. NG, Partially ordered topotogical vector spaces, Oxford
Mathematical Monographs, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1973.
Manoscritto
pervenuto in redazione
il 26 Ottobre 1982.