Survey
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
The Value of Network Information: Assortative Mixing Makes the Difference∗ Mohamed Belhaj† and Frédéric Deroı̈an‡ October 6, 2016 † ‡ Centrale Marseille (Aix-Marseille School of Economics), CNRS and EHESS Aix-Marseille University (Aix-Marseille School of Economics), CNRS and EHESS Abstract We study the value of network information in the context of monopoly pricing under local network externalities. Under complete information, both monopoly and consumers know the network structure and consumers’ private preferences. Under incomplete information, consumers only know the joint distribution of preferences, in-degrees and out-degrees, and the monopoly knows the characteristics of each consumer. The analysis reveals that, under assortative mixing, network information increases profit and consumer surplus. ∗ For helpful comments, the authors thank Sebastian Bervoets, Renaud Bourlès, Yann Bramoullé, and participants in conferences and seminars. The authors thank the French National Research Agency (ANR) for their support through the program ANR 13 JSH1 0009 01. The authors are grateful for support from the A*Midex project (No. ANR11-IDEX-0001-02) funded by the “Investissements d’Avenir” French Government program, managed by the French National Research Agency (ANR). E-mail addresses: [email protected], [email protected]. 1 Keywords: Monopoly, Network Effects, Price Discrimination, Bonacich Centrality, Network Information, Degree Assortativity, Homophily, Assortative Mixing. JEL: C72, D85 2 1 Introduction A huge amount of information about consumer relationships is available today, thanks to digital technologies. Growing service provision by Google, Facebook, and so on, and the emergence of social-network-based business (Klout, Kred, PeerIndex) are leading firms to implement social-networkbased price strategies and to target consumers on the basis of sophisticated measures of influence or centrality.1 The consumers, too, are better informed about the social network structure and the people they interact with, thanks to online social networks. Incoming information modifies not only firms’ strategies but also consumption decisions, which may have a negative impact on profits and welfare. This raises the following question: is information about network structure beneficial to firms and consumers? In this paper we investigate the value of network information in the context of monopoly pricing under network externalities among consumers. We consider two setups. In the first, both consumers and the monopolist are fully informed about the network structure and about consumer preferences for the product. In the second, consumers know their own preference for the good, their own in-degree and out-degree, as well as the joint distribution of these characteristics. The monopolist observes these characteristics for each consumer. We compare the monopoly profit and consumer surplus under the two setups. We say that a network generates a positive information value for monopoly profit (resp. for consumer surplus) when the monopoly profit (resp. consumer surplus) is greater under full information. Our main objective is to characterize network structures with a positive information value. Assortative mixing plays a crucial role in our study. A social network exhibits assortative mixing (Newman [2002]) if there is a positive correla1 For example, Klout proposes perk campaigns, using a ‘Klout score’ measuring the influence of a consumer on the social network, based on his position on various social networks he belongs to. 3 tion in the characteristics of people socially connected with each other.2 The main contribution of this paper is to show that the property of assortative mixing guarantees a positive value of network information. We start by analyzing the benchmark case of homogeneous consumers on undirected networks, so consumers are differentiated only through their position on the network. Prices being independent of network structure in this context, outcome variations are exclusively related to demand effects. Under incomplete information, individual consumption is a function of agent degree, while under full information it is Bonacich centrality. Principally, we show that both profit and consumer surplus increase with information for all intensities of interaction, if and only if the network is assortative by degree. This result is interesting in the light of the well-known stylized fact that social networks generally exhibit degree assortativity.3 We then incorporate consumers’ heterogeneity in individual preferences for the good. Thus, agents may be differ both in position and in preference for the good. The three following conditions are shown to guarantee that network information increases profit for all intensities of interaction: degree assortativity, homophily and preference-degree assortativity, this latter property indicating the tendency for high-degree consumers to be connected to high-preference consumers. Yet these conditions do not necessarily imply increased demand, which explains how consumer surplus can fall. Last, we discuss the model, examining the value of network information under two separate modifications of the information structure, i.e. we 2 In general, the characteristics can be a personal attribute such as age, education, socio-economic status, physical appearance, and religion, or a measure of centrality, e.g., degree, betweenness, Bonacich centrality, etc. 3 See Newmann [2002], Table I, p. 2, or Serrano, Boguñá, Pastor-Satorras and Vespignani [2007]. Interestingly, degree assortativity has become a hot topic in network analyses in physics, in biology and in the social sciences. For instance, degree assortativity is known to play an important role in diffusion processes and has an impact on connectivity properties of networks. 4 modify the information structure for one setup, keeping the other setup fixed. First, we modify the full information setup, only considering partial information about the network structure, i.e. consumers and the monopoly know the number of links between each pair of types rather than the full network structure. This is consistent with the real world, where firms and consumers may not know the full details of the network due, for instance, to laws protecting privacy. Almost all findings apply. Our second modification changes the incomplete information setup: now consumers and the monopoly know the distribution of in-degrees but have no information about out-degrees (they assume no correlation between in-degrees and outdegrees). The analysis highlights the role of in-degree assortativity, i.e. the tendency for consumers to be influenced by consumers of similar in-degrees, and the positive correlation between in-degrees and out-degrees. Related literature. Our paper contributes to the classical literature on the economics of privacy4 by pointing out the role of assortative mixing in signing the value of social network data in the context of markets with network externalities. Such markets have been studied by the classical IO literature on network effects initiated by Farrell and Saloner (1985) or Katz and Shapiro (1985).5 Recently, monopoly pricing under network effect has been studied using two approaches. First, in a full information setup, both Candogan, Bimpikis and Ozdaglar (2012) and Bloch and Quérou (2013) study monopoly pricing under local network effects. Their setup incorporates an explicit network structure, and consumers are fully informed about the structure of the social network. These papers mainly establish a link between consumption levels and Bonacich centralities.6 Second, Fainmesser 4 See Acquisti, Taylor and Wagman [2015] for a survey. 5 See also Economides (1996) for an extensive survey of this literature. 6 In section 5 of their paper, Candogan et al (2012) consider both the case where the monopolist does not know network effects and the case of complete information, and examine the (positive) impact of network information on the monopolist. 5 and Galeotti (2015) consider incomplete network information in a stylized model where consumers only know the distribution of in-degrees and outdegrees in the network. The authors study how increased information held by the monopoly impacts both the monopoly’s profit and welfare. There are three main differences between FG and our work. First, in their setup, the monopoly obtains information about in- or out-degrees. It is important to point out that degree distribution does not provide a comprehensive description of the network structure. In contrast, our paper considers information about the network structure. Second, FG keep the consumers’ information structure fixed, whereas we compare setups in which consumers have distinct information sets. By doing so, we introduce the possibility of negative information value. The third difference is that we introduce consumer heterogeneity. It is worth emphasizing that our work unifies the two approaches by showing that the game of incomplete information is equivalent to a game of complete information with a corresponding network of interaction. This paper also builds on the theoretical literature on network games.7 Ballester, Calvò-Armengol and Zenou (2006) consider network effects in a game of linear-quadratic utilities under complete information, and establish a relation between equilibrium play and Bonacich centrality. Jackson and Yariv (2005, 2007) study diffusion of behavior and equilibrium properties in a network game with incomplete information. Galeotti, Goyal, Jackson, Vega-Redondo and Yariv (2010) take this a step further, discussing strategic equilibrium in a wide set of network games.8 Considering utility 7 Our paper also echoes the literature studying the efficiency of stratification under complementar- ities. See Becker (1973), Bénabou (1996), Durlauf and Seshadri (2003). Our approach mainly departs from this literature by introducing a network structure between interacting agents. 8 Charness, Fery, Meléndez-Jiménez and Sutter (2014) use experimental economics to test network games with incomplete information. Other theoretical papers on network games with incomplete information are Sundararajan (2008), Kets (2011), Acemoglu, Malekian and Ozdaglar (2013), de Marti and Zenou (2015). 6 functions concave in degrees, their paper compares outcomes from different degree distributions under positive local affiliation. Here, however, we compare networks with the same joint degree distributions, so first-order stochastic dominance is not an issue. In fact, one contribution of our study is that it incorporates network structure considerations in a model of incomplete network information. This allows us to reveal the role of degree assortativity. Homophily is now widely studied in network economics.9 However the impact of degree assortativity on economic outcomes has so far received little attention.10 Our paper emphasizes the positive impact of degree assortativity on the value on network information. Interestingly, the literature has identified network formation dynamics that generate degree assortativity. Jackson and Rogers (2007) consider a network formation process mixing random and network-based search.11 In König, Tessone and Zenou (2010), agents form and sever links based on the centrality of their potential partners, and in a context of capacity constraints on the number of links agents can maintain. The paper is organized as follows. In section 2, we present the model and characterize the Nash equilibrium of both games of complete and incomplete information. We establish a relationship between the game of incomplete information and a modified game of complete information. Section 3 introduces assortative mixing, and expresses assortativity coefficients as functions of the difference between the interaction matrices of the two games. Section 4 studies the sign of the value of information; we first 9 See Currarini, Jackson and Pin (2009) for the formation of friendship networks, Golub and Jackson (2012) in the context of learning, Galeotti and Rogers (2013) about strategic immunization incentives, or Cabrales, Gottardi and Vega-Redondo (2014) for risk-sharing networks. 10 In an unpublished note, Feri and Pin (2016) study the impact of degree assortativity on the relationship between efforts and degrees in network games under incomplete information. 11 Bramoullé, Currarini, Jackson, Pin and Rogers (2012) introduce individual heterogeneity in the framework of Jackson and Rogers (2007), and study how homophily affects network integration. 7 present homogeneous consumers’ characteristics, and then introduce heterogeneity. Section 5 discusses the model and section 6 concludes. All proofs are gathered in an appendix. 2 The model A monopolist charges linear prices in the presence of local network effects among consumers. We will consider two setups. In the complete information setup, both consumers and the monopoly know the network and consumer preferences. In the incomplete information setup, they only know the joint distribution of degrees and preferences. Under incomplete information, profit and consumer surplus can be expressed as functions of simple network statistics, whereas in the game of complete information, outcomes depend on Bonacich centralities. Because these centralities are complex objects, it is difficult to directly compare the outcomes of the two games.12 To overcome this difficulty, we establish an equivalence between the game of incomplete information and a modified game of complete information. In the modified game, each agent is influenced by all other agents, and the intensity of influence is equal to the ratio of the product of agents’ in-degrees by neighbors’ out-degrees to total number of links. Thus, rather than comparing the outcomes of the initial games directly, we compare the outcomes of two games of complete information, which are expressed as functions of Bonacich centralities (Proposition 1 thereafter). The game. We consider a two-stage game à la Candogan et al (2012). There are n consumers organized in a social network. In the first period, the 12 This difficulty has been pointed out by Fainmesser and Galeotti (2015): “There are no general results that map how adding or redistributing links in a network affects the Bonacich centralities of agents, and this is one of the reasons that the models of Bloch and Quérou (2013) and Candogan et al (2012) are less malleable in performing comparative statics.” 8 monopolist sets prices and in the second period, consumers buy a divisible quantity of the good. We let qi ∈ [0, +∞) represent the quantity purchased by consumer i. The monopolist selects a vector P = (p1 , p2 , · · · , pn ) of prices where pi ≥ 0 represents the price charged to consumer i for one unit of the good. The monopoly incurs a constant cost c for each unit of the good produced. For convenience, we define C = c1, where symbol 1 represents the n-dimensional vector of ones. In this context, the monopoly’s profit is P given by i (pi − c)qi . We let the n × n matrix G = [gij ], with gij ∈ {0, 1}, represents the network of interaction between consumers (we will refer to it as network G), with gij = 1 when agent i is influenced by agent j and gij = 0 otherwise.13 By convention, gii = 0 for all i. We introduce the following notations: I the n-dimensional identity matrix, K = G1 the profile of consumers’ indegrees, L = GT 1 the profile of consumers’ out-degrees, g = 1T G1 the sum of in-degrees (or out-degrees) in network G, d = g n the average in-degree. The utility that agent i derives from consuming the quantity qi of the good is given by: X 1 u(xi , x−i ) = ai qi − qi2 − pi qi + δ gij qi qj 2 j∈N where parameter ai represent consumer i’s private preference for the good. We let A = (a1 , a2 , · · · , an ) represent the profile of preferences. In this utility specification, introduced by Ballester et al (2006), the first three terms represent the utility that consumer i derives from consuming qi units of the good irrespective of the consumption of her peers. The last term represents the utility that consumer i derives from neighbors’ consumption. It is 13 In the real world, the nature of interactions can differ substantially according to the economic context. For instance, for communication goods such as games, mobiles devices and phones, computers, bilateral interactions between consumers are essentially symmetric. Conversely, for experience goods like cultural goods, or for fashion goods, bilateral influence may not be symmetric. While my friend’s view strongly influences my likelihood of purchasing a book or seeing a movie, it may be that my own view does not influence this friend. Our setting encompasses all these types of interactions. 9 increasing with neighbors’ consumption. Importantly, there are local complementarities: the incentive to consume increases with the consumption level of neighbors. Information structures. In the complete information setup, consumers and the monopoly know both the network G and the profile of preferences A. In the game of incomplete network information, each consumer knows the joint distribution of in-degrees, out-degrees and preferences, as well as her own private preference, in-degree and out-degree. In this situation, consumers are naturally typed by the triplet (a, k, l). We define by T = {(a, k, l)} the set of consumer types, and and we let characteristics (at , kt , lt ) corresponds to type t. The monopoly knows every consumer’s type, as well as the distribution of types. We let st represent the number of consumers of type t ∈ T in network G. Equivalence between the incomplete information game and a modified game of complete information. In the setup of incomplete information, we assume that consumers of the same type t choose the same consumption level, generically called qt (this assumption is standard in the literature, see Jackson et al [2010]). Following Fainmesser and Galeotti (2015), the expected utility of consumer i is given by EUi (qi , q−i ) = (ai − pi )qi − qi2 + δ qi ki AV (Q) 2 where AV (Q) refers to the average consumption of neighbors. We assume that consumers do not take into account the correlation between types of linked consumers and that the joint distribution of types does not provide further information on the network structure.14 In order to compute the probability of a neighbor’s type to be t, consumers should consider all networks with the same joint distribution of types as network G. When the network is sufficiently large, this probability can be approximated by 14 For instance, the degree distribution of a star network reveals the full network structure. 10 the ratio lt st /g.15 The expected average consumption level of neighbors is thus given by AV (Q) = X lt st t∈T g qt The equilibrium outcomes of this incomplete information game outcomes can be expressed as functions of the statistics of the distribution of types, and in particular consumption is an affine function of degrees (see equations (9), (10) and (11) in the appendix). As explained before, comparing these expressions to the outcomes of the complete information game is tricky. To obtain tractable comparisons, we now establish an equivalence between the incomplete information game and a modified game of complete information. Indeed, we observe that X X lt st qt = lj qj t∈T Defining matrix H = K LT g j∈N (so hij = k i lj g for all i, j), consumer i’s expected utility is written: X qi2 hij qj ui (xi , x−i ) = (ai − pi )qi − + δ qi 2 j∈N Hence, the Bayesian Nash equilibrium of the second stage of the incomplete information game played on network G generates the same consumption profile as the Nash equilibrium of the modified game with complete information played on network H, where the impact of consumer j on consumer i’s expected utility depends on agent i’s in-degree ki and agent j’s out-degree lj . Note that both G and H have the same in-degree distribution. Equilibrium outcomes and Bonacich centralities. Consider a non-negative matrix W . We let µ(W ) denote the largest eigenvalue of matrix W . We impose the following assumptions throughout the paper: 15 This result is common in the literature on incomplete information on networks. See for instance Jackson et al (2010), or recently Fainmesser and Galeotti (2015). 11 Assumption 1. δ < 1 T max µ( G+G ), µ( H+H 2 2 T ) Assumption 2. c < min {a1 , a2 , · · · , an } Together, assumptions 1 and 2 guarantee that both games admit unique and interior solutions: the latter guarantees a positive equilibrium demand, the former guarantees that optimal consumption levels are finite. For a given price vector, the first-order condition on the demand of consumer i on network W ∈ {G, H} is written: qiBR = ai − pi + δ X wij qj (1) j∈N The optimal profit and consumer surplus can therefore be expressed as functions of the position of agents on the network through unweighted Bonacich centrality under decay parameter δ, B(W, δ) = (I − δW )−1 1. The quantity bi (W, δ) represents the number of weighted paths from agent i to others, where the weight of a path of length k from agent i to agent j is δ k . The profile BZ (W, δ) = (I − δW )−1 Z represents the Bonacich centrality of network W weighted by vector Z. Assumption 1 guarantees (I − δW )−1 > 0. For convenience, we will omit reference to parameter δ in centralities, profit and consumer surplus. We also introduce the Euclidian √ norm kZk = Z T Z. We recall: Proposition 1 (Candogan et al [2012]). For network W ∈ {G, H}, prices, consumption levels, optimal profit of the monopoly, and consumer surplus are written 1 T −1 P (W ) = A − (I − δW ) I − δ W +W (A − C) 2 2 Q(W ) = 1 T −1 I − δ W +W (A − C) 2 2 Π(W ) = 1 (A − C)T BA−C 4 12 W +W T 2 CS(W ) = 1 BA−C 8 W +W T 2 2 For a given network W , both the profit and the consumer surplus depend on the Bonacich centralities of the network when W = W T , the price vector P (W ) = A+C 2 W +W T 2 . We note that, is independent of the net- work structure. For convenience, vector X (resp. Y ) will refer to the consumption profile in the game of complete (resp. incomplete) information throughout the paper. 3 Assortative mixing Assortative mixing is a cornerstone of the analysis. A social network exhibits assortative mixing (Newman [2002]) if there is a positive correlation in the characteristics of connected people. The characteristics can be a personal attribute (such as age, education, socio-economic status, physical appearance, and religion), or also a measure of centrality (e.g., degree, betweenness, Bonacich centrality, etc). In this section, we make the link between the assortative mixing coefficient and the difference between the adjacency matrices corresponding to the games of complete and incomplete information. This result reveals crucial to study the value of network information in Section 4. Newman (2003, eq. 21) defines a coefficient of assortative mixing by a characteristic, in order to measure the tendency for agents to be linked to agents with similar characteristics. Here we generalize this coefficient to two scalar characteristics. We consider two scalar characteristics of respective supports C1 , C2 , and two vectors Z ∈ C1N , Z 0 ∈ C2N . We define assortative mixing between characteristics Z and Z 0 on network G as follows: P zz 0 (ezz0 − az bz0 ) rZ,Z 0 (G) = z∈C1 ,z 0 ∈C2 σa σb 13 where ezz0 is the fraction of all edges in network G that start with a vertex of characteristic z and end with a vertex of characteristic z 0 , az represents the fraction of edges that start with characteristics z, bz0 represents the fraction of edges that end with characteristics z 0 , σa and σb the standard deviations of the distributions az and bz0 . We say that a network has the property of assortativity (resp. disassortativity) between characteristics Z and Z 0 whenever rZ,Z 0 (G) > 0 (resp. < 0). We present now an alternative expression of the coefficient rZ,Z 0 (G) as functions of the difference between the corresponding adjacency matrices of the two games. This lemma proves crucial to the analysis: Lemma 1. Consider a network G, let H = KLT g and let Θ = G − H. For any pair of scalar characteristics Z, Z 0 , we have rZ,Z 0 (G) = 1 Z T ΘZ 0 g σa σb (2) Assortative mixing by a single characteristic corresponds to the case where Z = Z 0 , and we denote rZ (G) = rZ,Z (G) for convenience. Four coefficients, all of which apply to undirected network, will play a key role in the paper: • The first coefficient, rD (G) (where D = G1 represents the profile of individual degrees), measures the level of (dis)assortative mixing by degree (Newman [2002]). Degree assortativity holds whenever rD (G) > 0, and indicates that consumers are more likely to be linked to consumers with similar degrees.16 By Lemma 1, we have rD (G) > 0 whenever DT ΘD > 0. This means that the number of paths of length 3 in network G exceeds the number of (weighted) paths of length 3 in network H.17 Moreover, 16 As extreme cases, the correlation coefficient of a complete bipartite network, including the star network, takes the value −1 (however, in general non-complete bipartite networks can be assortative). By contrast, the Pearson coefficient of the union of two regular components with at least two distinct degrees takes the value 1. 17 We did not identify any such characterization of degree assortativity in the literature. 14 assortative mixing by degree can be characterized in terms of paths in network G only. Letting g (k) = 1T Gk 1 represent the number of paths of length k ≥ 1 in network G, we get rD (G) > 0 if and only if g (1) g (3) > g (2) 2 i.e., the product of the number of paths of lenght 1 by the number of paths of length 3 exceeds the square of the number of paths of length 2. • The second coefficient, rA (G), measures the level of (dis)assortative mixing by characteristic A. Homophily then refers to the case in which rA (G) > 0 (i.e., AT ΘA > 0), and indicates that consumers are more likely to be linked to consumers with similar preferences.18 • The third coefficient, rA,D (G), measures the tendency of high-preference consumers to be linked to high-degree consumers. When rA,D (G) > 0 (i.e., AT ΘD > 0), there is preference-degree assortativity. • The fourth coefficient, rA,B(G) (G), measures the tendency of highpreference consumers to be linked to high-Bonacich centrality consumers. When rA,B(G) (G) > 0 (i.e., AT ΘB(G) > 0), there is preference-Bonacich centrality assortativity. 4 The value of network information In this section, we compare both the monopoly’s profit and the consumer surplus in the game with complete network information and the game under incomplete network information. Generally speaking, under incomplete information, consumers do not know the true type of their neighbors, simply inferring expected neighbors’ consumption levels from their knowledge about the distribution of types. Once consumers and monopoly obtain information about the structure of the network of interaction, consumers 18 The notion of assortative mixing by individual characteristics such as age, gender, ethnicity, etc, is also called homophily - see Lazarsfeld and Merton [1954], McPherson, Smith-Lovin and Cook [2001]. 15 modify their decisions and the monopoly may change prices. This results in a variation in both the profit and the consumer surplus. To understand the role of the network structure, we start with the benchmark case of homogeneous consumers. Then we incorporate heterogeneity. 4.1 Homogenous preferences In this subsection, we consider homogenous preferences and we set A = 1. In this setting, the monopoly’s profit is proportional to the sum of Bonacich centralities, and consumer surplus is proportional to the sum of squares of centralities. To determine the sign of the value of network information, we have to compare Bonacich centralities on networks G and H, both of which have the same degree distribution. In general, both positive and negative information values are possible outcomes. We start by examining the case of undirected networks, i.e. we assume GT = G. We note that prices are identical for all, and independent of the network structure since network G is undirected, which implies that outcome gaps are the result of a pure demand effect. As a first observation, it is easily seen that the value of information is null on regular networks (where all agents have the same degree), because centralities are homogeneous and identical in both networks. Figure 4.1 depicts two networks with the same degree distribution. Black nodes represents consumers with degree 3, white nodes consumers with degree 2. For δ = 0.2, network G1 represented in Figure 4.1-Left (resp. G2 in Figure 4.1-Right) generates a negative (resp. positive) profit gap. In network G1 (resp. G2 ), consumers with the highest degrees decrease (resp. increase) their consumption level with information, while consumers with the lowest degrees increase (resp. decrease) their consumption level. In total, in network G1 (resp. network G2 ) information generates a decrease 16 Figure 1: Two networks with the same number of consumers and the same degree distributions. (resp. increase) in aggregate consumption and profit. It can be seen that in network G1 , high-degree consumers tend to be linked with low-degree consumers, while in network G2 consumers with equal degrees are exclusively linked with each other. The example suggests that degree assortativity matters. Actually, when there is degree assortativity, central consumers tend to underestimate their neighbors’ consumption levels under incomplete information while peripheral consumers tend to overestimate their neighbors’ consumption levels. Therefore, by complementarities, central consumers increase their consumption level with information, while peripheral consumers decrease their consumption level. However, it is unclear which effect dominates, although the example suggests that information is beneficial for the network satisfying degree assortativity. We will see that, indeed, the sign of rD (G) is crucial in determining the sign of the profit gap. To grasp an intuition, we begin with the case where the intensity of interaction is close to zero. Recall that in order to 17 assess the variation in consumption we need to compare aggregate Bonacich centralities in the two networks G and H. Given that the numbers of paths of length 1 and 2 in networks G and H are identical, the sign of the gap in aggregate centralities is the same as the sign of the difference between the numbers of paths of length 3 in networks G and H when the intensity of interaction is sufficiently low. Now, as explained above, this difference is precisely equal to DT ΘD.19 Therefore, for an undirected network G, when the intensity of interaction is sufficiently low, when rD (G) > 0 we have an increase of demand, and thus Π(G) > Π(H). The same reasoning applies for consumer surplus. Does this result hold for higher intensities of interaction? Paths of lengths greater than 3 can no longer be ignored. But degree assortativity is still relevant: Theorem 1. When ΘD 6= 0, we have both Π(G) > Π(H) and CS(G) > 1 CS(H) for all δ ∈]0, µ(G) [ if and only if rD (G) ≥ 0. When ΘD = 0, we have both Π(G) = Π(H) and CS(G) = CS(H) for 1 [. all δ ∈]0, µ(G) Theorem 1 is powerful because the assortativity condition is independent of the intensity of interaction. Moreover, it is worth mentioning that it is not possible to obtain a finer condition that is independent of the intensity of interaction, because the sufficient condition becomes necessary too when the intensity of interaction is sufficiently low. For the class of networks satisfying ΘD = 0, the two games have the same outcomes, so this class corresponds to the degenerate case in which network information does not affect decisions. A network satisfies ΘD = 0 if the average neighbors’ degree is the same for all consumers. Moreover, in such networks there is no assortative mixing by degree. This class of 19 Actually, 1T (G3 − H 3 )1 = DT ΘD because H1 = G1. 18 networks includes regular networks, but also some other network structures, as illustrated by the twelve-consumer sixteen-link network depicted in figure 4.1: Figure 2: A non-regular network such that ΘD = 0. Black consumers have degree 4, white have degree 2. Theorem 1 is silent about networks such that rD (G) < 0. For a sufficiently low intensity of interaction, degree disassortativity involves a negative information value. But the sign of the information value on the same network differs according to the intensity of interaction. Generally speaking, for high intensity of interaction, a disassortative network can generate a positive outcome gap. Let λmin (G) represent the minimum eigenvalue of network G. This eigenvalue is useful to establish a negative threshold on degree assortativity above which the value of network information is positive for profit and consumer surplus. Indeed, we obtain: Proposition 2. Consider a network such that ΘD 6= 0. We have both Π(G) > Π(H) and CS(G) > CS(H) if rD (G) ≥ rc with 2 (4) δν 2 g g + (g (2) )3 − 2gg (2) g (3) P rc = − 1 − δλmin (G) g i d3i − (g (2) )2 19 We also examine how the profit gap varies with parameter δ. This comparative statics analysis yields an unambiguous conclusion under homogenous preferences: Proposition 3. Consider a network such that ΘD 6= 0. When rD (G) ≥ 0, the profit gap is increasing in parameter δ. Hence, for all network structures, the higher the intensity of interaction between consumers, the higher the profit gap. We have shown that, under degree assortativity, network information increases welfare. We examine the incidence on the variance of consumption levels: Proposition 4. Consider a network such that ΘD 6= 0. When rD (G) ≥ 0, network information increases the variance of consumption levels. Hence, degree assortativity increases profit and consumer surplus, and also induces a raise in the variance of consumptions. We turn to the general case of directed networks. We introduce the intermediary network of averaged interactions G̃ = we define D̃ = K+L . 2 We let matrix H̃ = D̃D̃T g G+GT 2 . For convenience, denote the matrix of in- teraction of the game with incomplete information on network G̃. First, we observe that, under complete network information, outcomes are identical on networks G and G̃. Second, we show that, for all intensities of interaction, outcomes are larger on the game played on network H̃ than the game played on network H. Elaborating on these two points, the next theorem emphasizes the role played by degree assortativity on the network of averaged interactions: Theorem 2. Assume (G̃ − H̃)D̃ 6= 0. Then Π(G) > Π(H) and CS(G) > 1 [ if rD̃ (G̃) ≥ 0 (i.e., D̃T (G̃ − H̃)D̃ ≥ 0). CS(H) for all δ ∈]0, µ(G) 20 Theorem 2 generalizes Theorem 1 to directed networks. Shortly speaking, the theorem states that under positive correlation between the average degree of connected consumers, both profit and consumer surplus increase with information. However, it is important to point out that, because we introduce the intermediary network G+GT 2 , the condition is no longer nec- essary, in contrast with the case of undirected networks. 4.2 Heterogenous preferences In this section, we take into account heterogeneous private preferences for the good. This adds complexity to the model, because now agents may be distinct both in their position on the network and in their private preference. We assume here GT = G, for simplicity. To get some intuition, we begin with the two polar cases of low and high intensities of interaction. We start with a low intensity of interaction. Here, network effects are mainly driven by preference parameters. The following proposition shows the positive role played by homophily: Proposition 5. Assume that δ is sufficiently small. If rA (G) > 0, we have both Π(G) > Π(H) and CS(G) > CS(H). We turn to the case where the intensity of interaction is sufficiently high. We have shown that the condition rD (G) > 0 guarantees that the sum of Bonacich centralities is strictly larger on network G than on network H for all intensities of interaction. Moreover, for network G (resp. H), Bonacich centralities tend to infinity when δ tends to 1 µ(G) (resp. 1 µ(H) ). Thus, we have µ(G) ≥ µ(H). A direct consequence is that, when parameter δ tends to 1 µ(G) , both profit and consumer surplus tend to infinity on network G, but are still finite on network H, irrespective of the distribution of vector A. We therefore obtain the following proposition: 21 Proposition 6. If rD (G) > 0, we have µ(G) > µ(H), and when δ tends to 1 , µ(G) we have both Π(G) > Π(H) and CS(G) > CS(H). Now, we consider an arbitrary intensity of interaction. We first consider profit. A legitimate question is whether having both degree assortativity and homophily guarantees that profit increases with information. The answer is, it doesn’t: when high-preference consumers are rather connected to low-degree consumers, there can be a negative information value, as illustrated in example 1: Example 1. In this example, we have both rA (G) > 0, rD (G) > 0 but Π(G) − Π(H) < 0. We set n = 5, δ = 0.2, c = 0, and we consider the network and preferences depicted in Figure 1. We find rA (G) ' 0.06, rD (G) = 1, Π(G) − Figure 3: The network, preferences and consumption levels of the two games in example 1. Π(H) = −0.1997. The next theorem shows that the coefficient of assortative mixing between preferences and degrees20 does matter: 20 Assortative mixing between preferences and degrees may in particular exist for types of good such 22 Theorem 3. When ΘA 6= 0 or ΘD 6= 0, we have Π(G) > Π(H) for all p 1 [ if rD (G) ≥ 0, rA (G) ≥ 0 and rA,D (G) ≥ − rA (G) · rD (G). δ ∈]0, µ(G) 1 When ΘA = ΘD = 0, we have Π(G) = Π(H) for all δ ∈]0, µ(G) [. In short, the three assortative mixing conditions21 guarantee that degrees and preferences reinforce each other in such a way that the average increase in the consumption level of central consumers dominates the decrease of peripheral consumers. Conversely, when the disassortativity between preferences and degrees is too strong, preferences and degrees are misaligned, which can produce a decrease in profit. To sum up, under low intensity of interaction, homophily (rA (G) > 0) guarantees that profit increases with information. Under very high intensity of interaction, degree assortativity (rD (G) > 0) guarantees a positive information value. For intermediate intensity of interaction, not only do these two conditions matter, but in addition, preferences and degrees need to be not too disassortatively mixed (of course, preference-degree assortativity fills this latter condition). We turn now to consumer surplus. Actually, the three conditions of Theorem 3 do not guarantee an increase in consumer surplus. Example 2 illustrates the point: Example 2. In this example, we have rA (G) > 0, rD (G) > 0, rA,D (G) > p − rA (G)rD (G) but CS(G) − CS(H) < 0. Consider n = 6, δ = 0.1624, c = 0, and consider the network and preferences depicted in Figure 2. Then, we have rA (G) = 0.228, rD (G) = 0.333, that part of the preference is increasing in the ability to use them socially or to display them to others (fashion, gaming, etc). To our knowledge, the economic literature is silent about this coefficient. Closely related, although distinct, is the correlation between valuations and number of friends (see for instance Campbell (2013) for comparative statics exercise with respect to this coefficient). 21 Note that the three conditions rD (G) > 0, rA (G) > 0 and rA,D (G) > 0 do not involve a positive correlation between preferences and degrees. 23 Figure 4: The network and preferences in example 2. Black nodes have degree 3, and white have degree 2. p rA,D (G) = −0.258 > − rA (G) · rD (G) = −0.275 and CS(G) − CS(H) = −0.0087. We also have Π(G) − Π(H) = 0.1190 and 1T (X − Y ) = −0.0119. In the above 6-consumer example, aggregate demand decreases with network information because high-preference consumers are rather linked to low-degree consumers. This in turn originates a decrease in the consumer surplus. We give now conditions under which network information increases the consumer surplus. Recall that rA,B(G) (G) measures assortative mixing between Bonacich centralities and preferences. We obtain: Theorem 4. Consider an undirected network G. When ΘA 6= 0 or ΘD 6= 0, we have CS(G) > CS(H) if the following p conditions hold: rA (G) ≥ 0, rD (G) ≥ 0, rA,D (G) ≥ − rA (G) · rD (G), and rA,B(G) (G) ≥ 0. When ΘA = ΘD = 0, we have both CS(G) = CS(H) for all δ ∈ 1 ]0, µ(G) [. Key in Theorem 4 is that preference-Bonacich centrality assortativ24 ity guarantees increased demand, which in turn, combined with increased profit, guarantees an increase in the consumer surplus. It should be stressed that the condition rA,B(G) (G) ≥ 0 depends on the intensity of interaction. This means that, as parameter δ varies, the sign of the coefficient rA,B(G) (G) can change. We explored whether the three conditions rA (G) ≥ 0, rD (G) ≥ 0, rA,D (G) ≥ 0 guarantee an increase in consumer surplus (for networks such that either ΘA 6= 0 or ΘD 6= 0). They do, under both sufficiently low and sufficiently high intensities of interaction. However, for intermediate intensities, the question remains open. One difficulty is that demand can decrease under these three conditions, as shown by example 3: Example 3. In this example, we have both rA (G) > 0, rD (G) > 0, rA,D (G) > 0 but 1T (X − Y ) < 0. Consider n = 9, δ = 0.05, c = 0, and consider the network and preferences depicted in Figure 3. We find rA (G) ' 0.0196, rA,D (G) ' 0.0087, Figure 5: The network and preferences in example 3 - Black nodes have degree 4, red have degree 3, and white have degree 2. rD (G) ' 0.0233, and 1T (X − Y ) ' −1.18e − 04. Furthermore, we have 25 CS(G) − CS(H) = 0.0048. Remark: networks satisfying ΘD = 0 and ΘA 6= 0. When the network satisfies ΘD = 0 (e.g., regular networks), we have rD (G) = rA,D (G) = rA,B(G) (G) = 0. Proposition 4 and Theorem 3 then show that, when ΘA 6= 0, homophily guarantees a positive network information value. We note that the sum of consumption levels is identical in the two games. Remark: ex post consumer surplus. The consumer surplus describes the sum of equilibrium ex ante utilities, i.e. utilities derived from consumption levels Y on expected network H. Ex post utilities, say CS ex post derived from consumption levels Y on real network G, also deserve attention. We can easily show that CS ex post = CS(H)+δY T ΘY . Therefore, the conditions guaranteeing a positive profit gap, as given in Theorem 3, also involve that CS ex post > CS(H).22 As a consequence, the conditions given in Theorem 4 not only guarantee increased (ex ante) consumer surplus, but also increased ex post consumer surplus. 5 Discussion In this section, we discuss two separate modifications of the information set. First, we compare the outcomes of the game of incomplete information and the outcomes of a game of a partial information, where agents know the number of links between each pair of types instead of having full information. Second, we compare the outcomes of the game with complete information and the outcomes of a game in which agents only know the in-degree distribution instead of the distribution of in- and out-degrees. Partial information. In many circumstances, the monopolist and consumers do not know the full detail of the network, for instance due to laws 22 These conditions guarantee that Y T ΘY > 0. 26 , protecting privacy.23 Here we relax the assumption of full information, assuming instead that agents only know the number of links between each pair of types. A before, consumers know own degree and the monopoly knows each consumer’s type. To fix ideas, we assume an undirected network G. We let ψtt0 represent the total number of links between pairs of types t and t0 (where a type refers to a pair (a, d)). We can show that the corresponding matrix of interaction by agent is Ξ, with ξij = ψtt0 , st st0 t is the type of consumer i, t0 the type of consumer j and st the number of consumers of type t.24 Then, matrix Ξ has the same degree distribution and assortativity coefficients as network G, i.e. rA (G) = rA (Ξ), rD (G) = rD (Ξ), rA,D (G) = rA,D (Ξ), so all corresponding results stay valid. Partial information allows for a second interpretation of our results, where the network is formed after consumer decisions (as in Jackson et al [2010]), Acemoglu et al [2013] or Fainmesser and Galeotti [2015]). In the first setup, agents only know the joint distribution of types and assume no correlation between types of linked consumers; in the second setup, they know both the joint distribution of types and public information about the process of network formation summarized by the matrix [ptt0 ], where ptt0 represents the probability that the type of a neighbor of a t-type consumer is t0 . The corresponding interaction matrix by agent is therefore given by matrix Ξ, where ξij = dt ptt0 25 . st0 We can therefore apply our results to com- pare outcomes of the games played on networks Ξ and H. Note that the 23 Current legislation regarding the protection of privacy on Internet markedly differs across nations, and is under constant debate. For instance, legal protection against private institutions is rather weak in the US (outside the Children’s Online Privacy Protection Act), while it is stronger in the EU; e.g., European Convention number 108 for the Protection of Individuals with regard to Automatic Processing of Personal Data, or the role of the Article 29 Data Protection Working Party. 24 For consumer i with degree di , the probability that the type of a neighbor is t0 is given by ψtt0 . di st In order to obtain the system of interaction by agent, we multiply this quantity by di and divide by st0 , the number of agents of type t0 . 25 t0 . Note that ξij = dt st ptt0 s t s t0 and dt st ptt0 represents the expected number of links between types t and Therefore, matrix Ξ is undirected. 27 consumption profile of the game played on network Ξ is a Bonacich centrality and can no longer be characterized by simple network statistics. Knowing in-degrees. We compare the full information game and a game in which agents know the in-degree distribution of the network. Consumers know their own in-degree and the monopolist knows each consumer’s indegree. Agents assume that there is no correlation between in-degrees and outdegrees. To simplify the analysis, we assume that consumers are homogeneous. As in the above cases, we build a matrix of interaction by agent for the game of incomplete information. Since each consumer considers all consumers in the society as potential partners with equal probabilities, the matrix of interaction becomes H̄ = K1T n (so, h̄ij = ki n for all i, j, including the diagonal). The tendency of consumers to be influenced by consumers of similar in-degrees affects the value of information. We call rK (G) the coefficient of in-degree assortativity. We also let ρk,l represent the correlation between in-degrees and out-degrees in network G. We obtain: Proposition 7. We have Π(G) ≥ Π(H̄) if both rK (G) ≥ 0 and ρk,l ≥ 0. Proposition 7 shows that in-degree assortativity, combined with a positive correlation between in-degrees and out-degrees, guarantees a positive profit gap. Essentially, positive correlation guarantees high transmission of influence on the network, because big influencees are also more likely to be big influencers. Note that if in-degrees and out-degrees are independent, only in-degree assortativity matters. 28 6 Conclusion In this paper we considered monopoly pricing in a context where consumers are organized in a network of local complementarities. We explored whether network information is valuable to firms and consumers. Our analysis yields clear-cut results on how network structure impacts the value of network information, showing the key impact of degree assortativity, homophily, preference-degree assortativity and preference-Bonacich centrality assortativity. These results are interesting in the light of the empirically documented properties of social networks: degree assortativity and homophily. Several questions related to this paper remain open. First, competition among firms deserves attention. For instance, it could be valuable to explore how the fierceness of competition affects the value of information in the presence of network effects.26 Second, network evolution is an issue. Firms often try to influence the network formation, for instance by trying to create opinion leaders or by fostering social relations. Finally, information acquisition may be endogenous. How does the network drives the incentives for firms to invest in information acquisition, and for consumers to invest in data protection, is an interesting issue. References [1] Acemoglu, D., A. Malekian and A. Ozdaglar, 2013, Network Security and Contagion, NBER Working Paper No. 19174. [2] Acquisti, A., C. Taylor and L. Wagman, 2015, The economics of privacy, forthcoming in the Journal of Economic Literature. 26 For multiproduct oligopolies, Chen, Zenou and Zhou (2015) show that, in the presence of substi- tutable products and under complete information, firms offer lower prices to more central consumers, and firms’ profits can decrease when network effects are higher. 29 [3] Ballester, C., A. Calvò-Armengol and Y. Zenou, 2006, Who’s who in networks. Wanted: the key player, Econometrica, vol. 74(5), 14031417. [4] Becker, G., 1973, A theory of marriage: Part I, Journal of Political Economy, vol. 81, 813846. [5] Bénabou, R., 1996, Heterogeneity, stratification, and growth: macroeconomic implications of community structure and school finance, American Economic Review, vol. 86, 584-609. [6] Bloch, F. and N. Quérou, 2013, Pricing in Social Networks, Games and Economic Behavior, vol. 80, 263-281. [7] Bramoullé, Y., S. Currarini, M. Jackson, P. Pin and B. Rogers, 2012, Homophily and Long-Run Integration in Social Networks, Journal of Economic Theory, vol. 147(5), 1754-1786. [8] Cabrales, A., P. Gottardi and F. Vega-Redondo, 2014, Risk-Sharing and Contagion in Networks, CESifo Working Paper No. 4715. [9] Campbell, A., 2013, Word-of-mouth communication and percolation in social networks, American Economic Review, vol. 103(6), 2466-2498. [10] Candogan, O., K. Bimpikis and A. Ozdaglar, 2012, Optimal Pricing in the Presence of Local Network Effects, Operations Research, vol. 60(4), 883-905. [11] Charness, G., F. Feri, M. Meléndez-Jiménez and M. Sutter, 2014, Experimental Games on Networks: Underpinnings of Behavior and Equilibrium Selection, Econometrica, vol. 82(5), 1615-1670. [12] Chen, Y.-J., Y. Zenou and J. Zhou, 2015, Competitive Pricing Strategies in Social Networks, mimeo. 30 [13] Currarini, S., M. Jackson and P. Pin, 2009, An Economic Model of Friendship: Homophily, Minorities and Segregation, Econometrica, vol. 77(4), 1003-1045. [14] de Marti, J. and Y. Zenou, 2015, Network Games with Incomplete Information, Journal of Mathematical Economics, vol. 61, 221-240. [15] Durlauf, S. and A. Seshadri, 2003, Is Assortative Matching Efficient?, Economic Theory, vol. 21, 475-493. [16] Economides, N., 1996, The Economics of Networks, International Journal of Industrial Organization, vol. 14(6), 673-699. Hungar. Acad. Sci 5, 17-61. [17] Fainmesser, I. and A. Galeotti, 2015, Pricing Network Effects, forthcoming in the Review of Economic Studies. [18] Farrell, J. and G. Saloner, 1985, Standardization, Compatibility and Innovation, RAND Journal of Economics, vol. 16, 70-83. [19] Galeotti, A., S. Goyal, M. Jackson, F. Vega-Redondo and L. Yariv, 2010, Network Games, Review of Economic Studies, , vol. 77(1), 218244. [20] Galeotti, A. and B. Rogers, 2013, Strategic Immunization and Group Structure, American Economic Journal: Microeconomics, vol. 5(2), 1-32. [21] Golub, B. and M. Jackson, 2012, How homophily affects the speed of learning and best-response dynamics, Quaterly Journal of Economics, vol. 127(3), 1287-1338. 31 [22] Jackson, M. and B. Rogers, 2007, Meeting Strangers and Friends of Friends: How Random Are Social Networks?, American Economic Review, vol. 97(3), 890-915. [23] Jackson, M. and L. Yariv, 2005, Diffusion on Social Networks, Economie Publique, 16(1), 3-16. [24] Jackson, M. and L. Yariv, 2007, Diffusion of Behavior and Equilibrium Properties in Network Games, American Economic Review, vol. 93(2), 92-98. [25] Katz, M. and C. Shapiro, 1985, Network Externalities, Competition and Compatibility, American Economic Review, vol. 75, 424-440. [26] Kets, W., 2011, Robustness of Equilibria in Anonymous Local Games, Journal of Economic Theory, vol. 146(1), 300-325. [27] König, M., C. Tessone and Y. Zenou, From Assortative to Dissortative Networks: The Role of Capacity Constraints, Advances in Complex Systems, Vol. 13(4), 483-499. [28] Lazarsfeld, P. and R. Merton, 1954, Friendship as a social process: A substantive and methodological analysis. In Freedom and control in modern society, ed. M. Berger, T. Abel, and C. Page, 18-66, New York: Van Nostrand. [29] McPherson, M., L. Smith-Lovin and J. Cook, 2001, Birds of a Feather: Homophily in Social Networks, American Review of Sociology, vol. 27, 415-444. [30] Newman, M., 2002, Assortative mixing in networks, Physical Review Letters, vol. 89, 208701. 32 [31] Newman, M., 2003, Mixing patterns in networks, Physical Review Letters, vol. 67, 026126. [32] Pin, P. and F. Feri, 2016, The Effect of Externalities Aggregation on Network Games Outcomes, mimeo. [33] Pin, P. and B. Rogers, 2015, Stochastic Network Formation and Homophily, forthcoming in the The Oxford Handbook on the Economics of Networks. [34] Serrano, M., M Boguñá, R. Pastor-Satorras and A. Vespignani, 2007, Correlations in complex networks, Structure and Dynamics of Complex Networks. From Information Technology to Finance and Natural Science World Scientific, Singapur. [35] Sundararajan, A., 2008, Local Network Effects and Network Structure, B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics, vol. 7(1). 33 Appendix: Proofs Proof of Proposition 1. We consider W ∈ {G, H}. For clarity, we write P, Q for P (W ), Q(W ). Assumptions 1 and 2 guarantee the existence of a unique and interior consumption profile. We provide now a characterization of the equilibrium (these results are known - see Candogan et al [2012]). The first-order conditions associated with consumers’ utilities, for price P , give the relationship between optimal consumer consumption levels and prices: P = A − (I − δW )Q (3) The monopoly’s profit is written Π(W ) = (P − C)T Q Plugging equation (3) into equation (4), we get h i Π(W ) = (A − C)T − QT (I − δW )T Q The first order conditions with respect to Q give W + W T −1 1 I −δ (A − C) Q= 2 2 (4) (5) (6) Plugging Q into the profit and exploiting QT (I − δW )−T Q = QT (I − T −1 δ W +W Q, we find 2 Π(W ) = W + W T −1 1 (A − C)T I − δ (A − C) 4 2 (7) i.e., using equation (6), Π(W ) = 1 (A − C)T Q 2 We turn to consumer surplus. Consumer i’s utility is written uBR = i 1 2 · qi2 . Summing all utilities, we find 1 CS(W ) = QT Q 2 34 (8) Plugging equation (6) into equation (8), we find 1 W + W T −2 T CS(W ) = (A − C) I − δ (A − C) 8 2 Outcomes in the game of incomplete information. Recall that in-degree profile K = G1 and out-degree profile L = GT 1. We define for P P P convenience τk = p kp2 , τl = p lp2 , τkl = p kp lp . We can easily show that the vector of consumptions on network H is written: Y = A−C + νK K + νL L 2 with δ (1 − νK = 2g δ τ ) 2g kl δ (1 − νL = 2g δ τ ) 2g kl (1 − A−C 2 δ τ )2 2g kl and (1 − T A−C 2 T L+ A−C 2 T K δ 2 − ( 2g ) τl τk K+ δ τ )2 2g kl δ τ 2g l (9) δ τ 2g k A−C 2 T L δ 2 − ( 2g ) τl τk Then, profit and consumer surplus are given by: 1 1 Π(H) = (A − C)T (A − C) + (νK K + νL L)T (A − C) 4 2 (10) and 1 1 CS(H) = (A − C)T (A − C) + (νK K + νL L)T (νK K + νL L + A − C) (11) 8 2 Note that, when G is undirected, the vector of consumption is given by: Y = A−C +ν D 2 (12) ν= δ DT (A − C) 2 g − δDT D (13) with 35 Proof of Lemma 1. For a given network G, the assortativity coefficient rZ,Z 0 (G) is defined as follows (this is a direct generalization to two characteristics of the assortativity coefficient of Newman (2003, eq. 21): rZ,Z 0 (G) = X 1 zz 0 (ezz0 − az bz0 ) σa σb z∈C ,z0 ∈C 1 2 We let I(.) denote the indicator function. We note that P P ezz0 = (i,j)∈N 2 gij I(zi =z,zj0 =z 0 ) gij I(zi =z) , az = g (i,j)∈N 2 g , and bz = P (i,j)∈N 2 gij I(zj0 =z 0 ) . g It follows that rZ,Z 0 (G) = X gij zi zj0 X gij zi X gij zj0 − g g g 2 2 2 1 σa σb (i,j)∈N (i,j)∈N ! (i,j)∈N or equivalently 1 rZ,Z 0 (G) = σa σb Letting matrix H = KLT g Z T GZ 0 Z T K LT Z 0 − g g g ! and recalling that Θ = G − H, we obtain finally rZ,Z 0 (G) = 1 Z T ΘZ 0 σa σb g We present two useful lemmatas. We consider an undirected network G and we define M = (I − δG)−1 . The respective consumption profiles under complete and incomplete information are X = 12 (I − δG)−1 (A − C) and √ Y = 21 (I − δH)−1 (A − C). For every vector V , we let kV kM = V T M V denote the M -norm of vector V (this is a norm as matrix M is positive definite), and we let kV k represent the Euclidian norm. Lemma 2. We have Π(G) − Π(H) = δ 2 kΘY k2M + δY T ΘY 36 (14) Proof of Lemma 2. We have (I − δG)X = (I − δH)Y that is, (I − δG)(X − Y ) = δΘY or equivalently, given that M = (I − δG)−1 , X = Y + δM ΘY (15) Thus, 1 (A − C)T (X − Y ) = δX T ΘY 2 that is, Π(G) − Π(H) = δX T ΘY (16) Plugging equation (15) into equation (16), we obtain Π(G) − Π(H) = δY T ΘY + δ 2 Y T ΘT M ΘY Lemma 3. We have δ2 CS(G) − CS(H) = kM ΘY k2 + δY T M ΘY 2 (17) Proof of Lemma 3. Recalling that X = Y + δM ΘY , we deduce that X T X − Y T Y = δ 2 (M ΘY )T (M ΘY ) + 2δY T M ΘY The gap in consumer surplus being CS(G) − CS(H) = 21 (X T X − Y T Y ), we obtain CS(G) − CS(H) = δ2 kM ΘY k2 + δY T M ΘY 2 37 Proof of Theorem 1. We recall that A = 1, X = # δ 1−c 1+ D . DT D 2 1−δ 1−c B(G), 2 and Y = g • If ΘD 6= 0: I. Monopoly’s profit. We prove that the condition rD (G) ≥ 0 is sufficient: Note that ΘD 6= 0 implies ΘY 6= 0. By equation (14) in Lemma 2, Π(G) − Π(H) > 0 if Y T ΘY ≥ 0 (18) Plugging equation (12) into condition (18) and recalling that Θ1 = 0, we get DT ΘD ≥ 0, which is equivalent to rD (G) ≥ 0. We prove that the condition rD (G) ≥ 0 is also necessary: Suppose that rD (G) < 0. We introduce e = 1−c 2 for convenience. We have, for δ small enough, 1 X = 1 + δG1 + δ 2 G2 1 + δ 3 G3 1 + o(δ 3 ) e 1 Y = 1 + δH1 + δ 2 H 2 1 + δ 3 H 3 1 + o(δ 3 ) e We recall that Π(G) − Π(H) = e(X − Y ), and that, because networks G and H have same degree profile, Θ1 = 0 and 1T (G2 − H 2 )1 = 0. We thus obtain Π(G) − Π(H) = e2 δ 3 1T (G3 − H 3 )1 + o(δ 3 ) Now, we observe that, because G1 = H1, we have 1T (G3 − H 3 )1 = DT ΘD By Lemma 1, rD (G) < 0 involves DT ΘD < 0, and therefore Π(G) − Π(H) < 0 for δ sufficiently low. 38 II. Consumer surplus. We prove that the condition rD (G) ≥ 0 is sufficient: By equation (12), Y = Y T M ΘY = 1−c 1 2 + νG1. Hence, 1−c T 1 M ΘY + ν1T GM ΘY 2 We note that 1−c T 1 M ΘY = X T ΘY 2 Moreover, because X − we have 1−c 1 2 = δGM 1 and GM = M G (since GT = G), T 1 1−c 1 GM ΘY = 1 ΘY X− δ 2 T In the end, we obtain T ν 1−c Y M ΘY = X ΘY + X− 1 ΘY δ 2 T T Exploiting now that ΘT 1 = Θ1 = 0 (where 0 represents the vector with entries equal to 0), we obtain δY T M ΘY = (ν + δ)X T ΘY (19) Now, by equation (16) we have X T ΘY = Π(G) − Π(H) δ (20) Combining equations (17), (19) and (20), we get CS(G) − CS(H) = δ2 ν kM ΘY k2 + 1 + Π(G) − Π(H) 2 δ (21) where ν > 0. Since ΘY 6= 0, we have M ΘY 6= 0. The condition rD (G) ≥ 0 involving a positive profit gap, we conclude by equation (21) that this also entails a positive consumer surplus gap. We prove that the condition rD (G) ≥ 0 is also necessary: 39 Suppose first that rD (G) < 0. Reacalling that e = 1−c 2 and that CS(G) − CS(H) = 12 (X T X − Y T Y ), we obtain CS(G) − CS(H) = 2e2 δ 3 1T (G3 − H 3 )1 + o(δ 3 ) Note that, because G1 = H1, we have 1T (G3 − H 3 )1 = DT ΘD and thus, rD (G) < 0 implies CS(G) − CS(H) < 0. • If ΘD = 0, we have that ΘY = Θ(1 + νD) = 0. By equation (15), we have that X = Y . Thus we obtain that Π(G) = Π(H) and CS(G) = CS(H). Proof of Proposition 2. We observe from equation (15) that 1T (X − Y ) > 0 if δkΘY )k2M > −Y T ΘY We note that M is a symmetric positive definite matrix, with a spectrum deduced from the spectrum of G as follows: if λi is an eigenvalue of G, then 1 1−δλi is a positive eigenvalue of M . Letting λmin (G) denote the smallest eigenvalue of G, the following standard inequality applies: ∀Z, Z T M Z ≥ We have that (ΘY )T M ΘY ≥ 1 ZT Z 1 − δλmin (G) 1 (ΘY )T ΘY 1−δλmin (G) . Therefore, T 1 (X − Y ) > 0 if Since Y = 1−c 1 2 δ 1 − λmin (G) kΘY k2 > −Y T ΘY + νD and Θ1 = 0, we have ΘY = νΘD 40 Noting that XX i gij dj 2 = kG2 1k2 = 1T G4 1 = g (4) j we obtain g (2) g2 3 g 2 g (4) + (g (2) )3 − 2gg (2) g (3) P g i d3i − (g (2) )2 g (2) g (3) + g (4) kΘY k = ν −2 g P (g (2) )2 3 − Exploiting Y T ΘY = rD (G) d , we obtain i i g 2 rD (G) > − 2 δν 2 1 − δλmin (G) To finish, from equation (21), increased profit entails increased consumer surplus. Proof of Proposition 3. We differentiate the system of first order conditions (I − δG)X = 1−c 1 2 with respect to δ. We denote by X 0 the derivative of vector X with respect to parameter δ. We obtain: (I − δG)X 0 = GX that is, with M = (I − δG)−1 , X 0 = M GX Thus, we get 1T X 0 = Given that δGX = X − 1−c 1, 2 we obtain δ1T X 0 = and since CS(G) = XT X 2 2 X T GX 1−c 2 X T X − 1T X 1−c and Π(G) = δ1T X 0 = 1−c T 1 X, 2 2 (2CS(G) − Π(G)) 1−c 41 Hence, we are in position to characterize the sign of the variation in profit gap with δ. Indeed: (1 − c)δ T 0 1 (X − Y 0 ) = 2(CS(G) − CS(H)) − (Π(G) − Π(H)) 2 By equation (21), and given that ΘY 6= 0, CS(G)−CS(H) > Π(G)−Π(H), so that (1 − c)δ T 0 1 (X − Y 0 ) > Π(G) − Π(H) 2 and since rD (G) ≥ 0, we have Π(G) − Π(H) > 0, so 1T (X 0 − Y 0 ) > 0. Proof of Proposition 4. The variance of vector X is written: V ar(X) = X T X − (1T X)2 n As X = Y + δM ΘY (and thus 1T X = 1T Y + δ1T M ΘY ), we get # 1 T 1 T 2 2 T T 2 T V ar(X)−V ar(Y ) = δ Y ΘM ΘY − (1 M ΘY ) +2δ Y M ΘY − (1 Y )1 M ΘY n n | {z } | {z } =φ1 =φ0 we have φ0 > 0: indeed, let Z = M ΘY . Then, φ0 = Z T Z − (1T Z)2 = V ar(Z) > 0 n we have φ1 > 0 when A = 1 and rD (G) ≥ 0: indeed, we have φ1 = Y T M ΘY − 1 T (1 Y )X T ΘY n Since Y = 1 + αD, Y T M ΘY = (1 + αD)T M ΘY i.e., given δGM = M − I Y T M ΘY = X T ΘY + α1T M −I ΘY δ i.e., given Θ1 = 0, Y T M ΘY = X T ΘY + 42 α T X ΘY δ so in the end Y T M ΘY = 1 + Therefore, given 1T Y n α T X ΘY δ = 1 + αd φ1 = 1 + α − 1 − αd X T ΘY δ i.e., φ1 = α 1 − δd T X ΘY δ Since δd < 1 (because d ≤ µ(G)), we conclude that φ1 > 0 whenever X T ΘY > 0. This is guaranteed by the condition rD (G) ≥ 0. Proof of Theorem 2. We let e = 1−c . 2 We let X = e(I − δ G̃)−1 1 and Y = T −1 e(I − δ H+H ) 1 represent respectively the equilibrium demand profiles in 2 the games of complete and incomplete information. We start with the monopoly’s profit. By Proposition 1, Π(G) = Π(G̃). We let matrix H̃ = D̃D̃T g denote the matrix of interaction of the game with incomplete information on network G̃. By Theorem 1, (G̃ − H̃)D̃ 6= 0 and rD̃ (G̃) ≥ 0 involve Π(G̃) > Π(H̃). It is therefore sufficient to show that T Π(H̃) ≥ Π( H+H ) for all δ. Now, define MH̃ = (I − δ H̃)−1 . Similar simple 2 computations as in Lemma 2 entail Π(H̃) − Π Recalling that H+H T 2 H+H T 2 = δ 2 k H̃ − = KLT +LK T 2g H+H T 2 Y k2MH̃ + δY T H̃ − H+H T 2 Y , few computations entail 1 H + HT = (L − K)(L − K)T H̃ − 2 4g T This means that matrix H̃ − H+H is positive definite. Therefore, we have 2 T Y T H̃ − H+H Y > 0, which shows the result. 2 We turn to consumer surplus. We use the same overall strategy as with monopoly profit. First we note that CS(G) = CS(G̃). Moreover, 43 (G̃ − H̃)D̃ 6= 0 and r K+L (G̃) ≥ 0 implies CS(G̃) > CS(H̃). It is therefore 2 T sufficient to show that CS(H̃) ≥ CS( H+H ). 2 To proceed, we examine the sum of squares of centralities given by equation (9). We write α = νD̃ , β = νK , γ = νL for convenience. The square of consumer i’s consumption for network H̃ is [1 + δα(ki + li )]2 = 1 + 2δα(ki + li ) + δ 2 α2 (ki2 + li2 + 2ki li ) while the square of agent i’s consumption for network H is [1 + δβki + δγli ]2 = 1 + 2δβki + 2δγli + δ 2 (β 2 ki2 + γ 2 li2 + 2βγki li ) Summing over all agents, note that P i αki > P i βki +γli since α > β+γ . 2 Hence, it is sufficient to show that all terms before the quantities τkl , τl , τk are larger in the former situation than in the latter. We get: for τkl , it must be that γβ ≤ α2 . But we know that γ+β ≤ α, and it 2 2 is true that γβ ≤ γ+β because this means (β − γ)2 ≥ 0. 2 for τk and τl , it is sufficient to prove that τk (α2 − β 2 ) + τl (α2 − γ 2 ) ≥ 0. Now, exploiting that γ+β 2 ≤ α, we have i γ − βh τk (α − β ) + τl (α − γ ) ≥ (γ + 3β)τk − (β + 3γ)τl 4 2 2 2 2 Assume w.l.o.g. that γ ≥ β, that is τk ≥ τl . Then we have i γ − βh τk (α2 − β 2 ) + τl (α2 − γ 2 ) ≥ (γ + 3β)τk − (β + 3γ)τl 4 Now, we have βτk −γτl ≥ 0: replacing β and γ, we get that this quantity is proportional to τk − τl . Hence, τk (α2 − β 2 ) + τl (α2 − γ 2 ) ≥ 0 T We thus obtain CS(H̃) ≥ CS( H+H ). 2 Proof of Proposition 5. We introduce E = A−C 2 for δ small enough, X = E + δGE + o(δ) Y = E + δHE + o(δ) 44 for convenience. We have, Recall that Π(G) − Π(H) = E T (X − Y ) and CS(G) − CS(H) = 21 (X T X − Y T Y ). We obtain Π(G) − Π(H) = δE T ΘE + o(δ) CS(G) − CS(H) = 2δE T ΘE + o(δ) We note that E T ΘE = 41 AT ΘA, which entails 1 Π(G) − Π(H) = δAT ΘA + o(δ) 4 1 CS(G) − CS(H) = δAT ΘA + o(δ) 2 Thus, when rA (G) > 0, i.e. AT ΘA > 0, outcome gaps are positive. Proof of Theorem 3. There are two cases: • ΘA 6= 0 or ΘD 6= 0: in this case ΘY = Θ(A + νD) 6= 0, so kΘY kM > 0. Then, by Lemma 2, we have that Y T ΘY ≥ 0 implies Π(G) − Π(H) > 0 We exploit Y = A−C 2 f (t) = + νD (see equation (12)). Define A − C 2 + tD T A − C + tD Θ 2 The sufficient condition is thus expressed as f (ν) ≥ 0. Note that parameter ν is increasing with δ, and when δ goes from 0 to its maximal bound, ν goes from 0 to infinity. Now, rA (G) ≥ 0 implies f (0) ≥ 0. Moreover, rD (G) ≥ 0 implies f (+∞) ≥ 0. For intermediate values of parameter ν, note that rD (G) ≥ 0 entails that f (.) is U-shaped. The minimum is attained at ν ∗ = p and f (ν ∗ ) ≥ 0 if rA,D (G) ≥ − rA (G) · rD (G). −( A−C )T ΘD 2 , T D ΘD • When ΘA = ΘD = 0, we have ΘY = 0. Lemma 2 then involves Π(G) = Π(H). 45 Proof of Theorem 4. There are two cases: • ΘA 6= 0 or ΘD 6= 0: assume that rD (G) ≥ 0, rA (G) ≥ 0, rA,D (G) ≥ p − rA (G) · rD (G), and rB(G),A (G) ≥ 0. We have ΘY = Θ(A + νD) 6= 0, so kM ΘY k > 0. Then, by Lemma 3, Y T M ΘY > 0 guarantees that CS(G) > CS(H). Since Y T M ΘY = X T ΘY + ν 1T GM ΘY , we need to show that X T ΘY > 0 and 1T GM ΘY > 0. X T ΘY > 0: recall that Π(G) − Π(H) = δX T ΘY . Therefore, under the three first conditions, X T ΘY > 0. M −I , δ 1T GM ΘY > 0: Note that GM = so 1T GM ΘY > 0 whenever B(G)T ΘY > 0 (with B(G) = M 1). Since Y = (A − C)/2 + νD, B(G)T ΘY > 0 is implied by B(G)T ΘA > 0 and B(G)T ΘD > 0. Now, on the one hand, rB(G),A (G) ≥ 0 means AT ΘB(G) ≥ 0. On the other hand, rD (G) > 0 implies DT ΘB(G) > 0. This stems from Theorem 2: indeed, this theorem states that profit gap is positive when DT ΘD > 0, and in the homogenous case, profit gap is proportional to B(G)T Θ(1 + νD), i.e., to B(G)T ΘD. • When ΘA = ΘD = 0, we have ΘY = 0. Lemma 3 then involves CS(G) = CS(H). Proof of Proposition 7. We set c = 0 for convenience as it plays no role in the proof. We let H̄ = K1T n . For convenience, we denote by Y = B( H̄+2H̄ T , δ) the consumption profile under incomplete information and we define Φ = G+GT 2 − H̄+H̄ T 2 . We will first characterize Y . Second, we apply Lemma 2, which still holds in this scenario. Step 1: We characterize the vector Y . For consumer i, the probability of being influenced by any consumer j is yi = 1 + δ ki . n X k +k i 2n j 46 j yj Therefore, vector Y satisfies Setting y = 1T Y , we get after simple development y= 4n P (2 − δd)2 − δ 2 i ki2 and consumer i’s consumption is written yi = 4 + 2δ(ki − d) 2 P (2 − δd)2 − δn p kp2 (22) Step 2: By equation (14), Y T ΦY ≥ 0 guarantees a positive profit gap. Exploiting equation (22), we find XX φij (2 − δd + δki )(2 − δd + δkj ) ≥ 0 i j That is, given that 1T Φ1 = 0 and simplifying by δ, XX g +g XX g +g ki +kj ij ji ij ji 2(2 − δd) − k + δ − i 2 2n 2 i j that is, XX g ij +gji 2 i j i 2 − δd ki kj ≥ n δ ki +kj ki kj 2n ≥0 j X 1X 2 d − d ki li + ki2 n i i T )K, we get Noting that K T GK = K T ( G+G 2 X XX 1X 2 − δd 2 d − ki li + d ki2 (23) gij ki kj ≥ n δ n i i i j P Remembering that ki li = n(Cov(k, l) + d2 ) (where Cov(k, l) is the co- i variance between in-degrees and out-degrees), we obtain 2 − δd XX X gij ki kj − d ki2 + n Cov(k, l) ≥ 0 δ i j i P P We add and substract the term g1 kp2 kp lp , and we note that p P ki li g p Cov(k,l) . d =d+ The above equation is then equivalent to XX P 2 2 − δd 1 X 2 X i ki gij ki kj − k kp lp + Cov(k, l) +n ≥ 0(24) g p p d δ p i j i T The first term is equal to K T (G− KLg )K and is non-negative if rK (G) ≥ 0 (in-degree assortativity). The second term is non-negative if in-degrees and out-degrees are positively correlated (ρk,l ≥ 0). 47