* Your assessment is very important for improving the workof artificial intelligence, which forms the content of this project
Download Morphemes in Competition
Ojibwe grammar wikipedia , lookup
Macedonian grammar wikipedia , lookup
Kannada grammar wikipedia , lookup
French grammar wikipedia , lookup
Malay grammar wikipedia , lookup
Proto-Indo-European verbs wikipedia , lookup
Navajo grammar wikipedia , lookup
Modern Hebrew grammar wikipedia , lookup
Latin syntax wikipedia , lookup
Comparison (grammar) wikipedia , lookup
Georgian grammar wikipedia , lookup
Old Norse morphology wikipedia , lookup
Yiddish grammar wikipedia , lookup
Ancient Greek grammar wikipedia , lookup
Swedish grammar wikipedia , lookup
Agglutination wikipedia , lookup
Portuguese grammar wikipedia , lookup
Icelandic grammar wikipedia , lookup
Ukrainian grammar wikipedia , lookup
Hungarian verbs wikipedia , lookup
Spanish grammar wikipedia , lookup
Polish grammar wikipedia , lookup
Old Irish grammar wikipedia , lookup
Russian grammar wikipedia , lookup
Modern Greek grammar wikipedia , lookup
Old English grammar wikipedia , lookup
Serbo-Croatian grammar wikipedia , lookup
Pipil grammar wikipedia , lookup
Lexical semantics wikipedia , lookup
Sanskrit grammar wikipedia , lookup
Scottish Gaelic grammar wikipedia , lookup
Basque verbs wikipedia , lookup
Morphemes in Competition Complementarity effects in which specific items or rules supersede general ones are ubiquitous in phonology (the Elsewhere Condition), morphology (blocking), syntax (e.g. in many formulations of Binding Theory, Müller & Sternefeld 2001), semantics (e.g. strongest meaning, maximize presupposition), and pragmatics (e.g. scalar implicature). In spite of a widely shared pretheoretical intuition that these diverse phenomena are somehow related, no formal principle that ties them together has as yet been discovered. Even within morphology, the existence of a unified blocking principle remains controversial. Morphological theories that adopt blocking as a fundamental principle include Paradigm Function Morphology (Stump 2001) and Minimalist Morphology (Wunderlich & Fabri 1994). To make blocking formally tractable and to avoid empirically unwanted globality, they specify the space of competing alternatives (in technically very different ways) as a paradigmatic grid of productive functional categories, where a category is productive if and only if it has a default exponent. Defaults and blocking then together ensure that every feature bundle corresponds to one and only one form. Thus, worse blocks *badder and *worser, and quicker blocks *quicklier and *quickerly. But glory does not block gloriosity, since nominalizations do not compete in a paradigm; still less is there blocking among unproductive categories, such as English diminutives: birdlet „ birdie „ birdikin, princekin „ princelet „ princeling, essayette „ essaylet. A controversial consequence of this approach is that in paradigms where periphrastic forms appear just where corresponding synthetic forms are missing, morphology must block syntax (Poser-blocking). This is sharply at odds with the approach taken in Distributed Morphology. DM has no general blocking principle other than the Subset Principle, which resolves competition between morphemes (Vocabulary Items) at single nodes, e.g. ox-en vs. box-es, bett-er vs. *good-er. It deals with complementarity between larger expressions not by blocking but by merger and movement operations at various points in the derivation, so that competing formations are just different spellouts of the same syntactic structure. For example, pre-spellout Head Movement, Lowering, and Local dislocation derive synthetic forms from the same syntactic structures that underlie the corresponding periphrastic forms. Fusion of distinct unlinearized feature bundles generates portmanteaux, such as Swahili si-, which supersedes Negative ha- + 1.Sg. affix ni- in the verb paradigm. Whole-word portmanteaux are treated by root suppletion plus zero allomorphs: e.g. worse has a suppletive allomorph of bad and a zero allomorph of -er). I provide two arguments that the derivational machinery of DM, despite this considerable richness, cannot account for the full range of morphological complementarity phenomena, and necessarily loses generalizations that are straightforwardly captured by blocking approaches. The first argument involves competition among morphemes within a word that are not inserted at the same node, and therfore cannot be dealt with by merger operations. Vedic Sanskrit has two agent noun suffixes, (1) preaccenting 1 -tar-V , which forms nouns that, like verbs, assign structural case to their objects and get adverb modifiers, and (2) accented -tár-N , which forms nouns that have genitive objects and adjective modifiers (Kiparsky 2016, likewise Avestan, Lowe 2015). The former is only attached directly to verb roots, the latter is attached high in the structure to arbitrarily complex verbs. They form a privative semantic opposition: the low 1 -tar-V denotes habitual or professional agency in ongoing time, the high -tár-N simply denotes agency in general (like English -er). The generalization is that the structurally high semantically nondescript -tár-N is used when and only when the structurally low 1 -tar-V suffix is unavailable, namely: (1) to denote past or future agency, or occasional agency, and (2) when the verb is morphologically complex (causative, intensive, desiderative, denominative, or prefixed), to denote any kind of agency whatever. The problem for DM is this. Suppose a high agent is introduced in a derivation. The derivation must crash if and only of a low agent can be successfully introduced in a competing derivation. But DM allows only rules to compete, and high and low agents can’t be introduced by the same rule, since they are not inserted at the same node and do not realize the same syntactic features bundles. A second set of arguments that supports blocking over DM-style movement comes from cases where a morpheme is excluded in a phonological context and the gap is supplied by periphrasis. The severity of the problem depends on the particular assumptions that are made about the phonology/morphology interface, but no version of DM can do full justice to it. If merger and movement operations precede Vocabulary Insertion, they have no access to the phonology. The phonological constraints on the synthetic comparative -er are then not expressible in the grammar. Bobaljik (2012) suggests suggests that they “reflect statistical regularities in the input to the language learner”. This is perhaps defensible for English in view of the overlap between the synthetic and periphrastic comparative in disyllabic adjectives, but it cannot be seriously maintained is cases where the synthetic morpheme is subject to a categorical phonological restriction. For example, Sanskrit verbs regularly form their perfect stems by reduplicating the root. Instead, a periphrastic perfect consisting of “be” or “do” plus a nominal form of the verb is required if the root is (1) superheavy (V̄C or VCC), e.g. ı̄ks. ‘see’ Ñ ı̄ks.-ām . ca-kr-e, or (2) morphologically complex, e.g. cint-ay- ‘think’ Ñ cint-ay-ām ās-a. There is nothing statistical about these conditions. Versions of DM which allow late operations such as Local Dislocation to access phonology (Embick 2010), could deal with restriction (1). However, another constraint on the Sanskrit root perfect is (3) that it may not have a present meaning, hence bibhayām . ca-kār-a ‘has feared’ (vs. bibhāya ‘fears’). So the merger operation must be late (Local dislocation) because it must see the syllable weight of the root, but it must must be early (Lowering) because it must see the semantics – a contradiction. Worse, there are cases where the synthetic form must be derived by an early operation but is blocked by derived phonological properties of the base. The Classical Greek perfect mediopassive is obligatorily periphrastic when the stem+ending would yield a phonologically irreparable consonant cluster (Smyth 1920): (1) Sg. 1. 2. 3. Du. 2,3. Pl. 1. 2. 3. lélumai lélusai lélutai lélusthon lelũmetha lélusthe léluntai ‘loosen’ gégrammai ‘write’ gégrapsai gégraptai gégraph th on gegrámmetha gégraph th e gegramménoi eisí (for unpronouncable *gegráph ntai) Blocking the Lowering operation here would require access not only to the output of Vocabulary Insertion, but to the phonological computation that it feeds. This distribution is readily accounted for in a lexicalist model where morphology and phonology interact cyclically and synthetic forms block periphrastic forms, but appears to be incompatible with the basic architectural commitments of DM. References Jonathan D. Bobaljik. 2012 Universals in Comparative Morphology: Suppletion, Superlatives, and the Structure of Words. Cambridge: MIT Press. Embick, David. 2010. Localism and globalism in morphology and phonology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Kiparsky, Paul. 2016. The agent suffixes as a window into Vedic grammar. In Dieter Gunkel, Brent Vine, Joshua Katz, and Michael Weiss (edd.) Sahasram Ati Srajas: Indo-Iranian and Indo-European Studies in Honor of Stephanie W. Jamison. Ann Arbor: Beech Stave Press. Müller, Gereon & Wolfgang Sternefeld. 2001. The Rise of Competition in Syntax. In G. Müller & W. Sternefeld, Competition in Syntax, Berlin: Mouton. Stump, Gregory 2001. Inflectional morphology. Cambridge: CUP. Wunderlich, Dieter & Ray Fabri. 1994. Minimalist Morphology: An approach to inflection. Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft 20: 236-294.